0916cornejo 2004 who says what words say

Upload: marimunhoz

Post on 08-Aug-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    1/25

    http://tap.sagepub.com/

    Theory & Psychology

    http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5

    The online version of this article can be found at:

    DOI: 10.1177/09593543040401962004 14: 5Theory Psychology

    Carlos CornejoPsychology

    Who Says What the Words Say? : The Problem of Linguistic Meaning in

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    can be found at:Theory & PsychologyAdditional services and information for

    http://tap.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://tap.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5.refs.htmlCitations:

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5http://www.sagepublications.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://tap.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://tap.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://tap.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://tap.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5.refs.htmlhttp://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5.refs.htmlhttp://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5.refs.htmlhttp://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5.refs.htmlhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://tap.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://tap.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.sagepublications.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/content/14/1/5http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    2/25

    Who Says What the Words Say?The Problem of Linguistic Meaning in Psychology

    Carlos CornejoPontificia Universidad Catolica de Chile

    Abstract. Currently, cognitive psychology assumes that linguistic mean-ing is based on associations between linguistic forms and semantic con-tents. This conception presents empirical as well as logical problems. Itdoes not explain the flexibility of language use and it is inconsistent withthe subject-dependence of all cognitive acts. A theoretical analysis of theseissues shows a history of confusion between linguistic and phenomeno-logical interpretations of the term meaning, and between the external andinternal perspective towards intentionality of mental life. However, ifunderstood as perspectives, both uses underline non-exclusive aspects oflinguistic meaning, namely its epistemic objectivity and its ontologicalsubjectivity. It is argued that both aspects could be integrated through thepragmatization and semiotization of meaning.

    Key Words: generativism, intentionality, meaning, pragmatics, semantics,

    semiotics, structuralism

    Introduction: Logical and Psychological Problems with the

    Notion of Linguistic Meaning

    For many authors, meaning represents the main aspect of human cognition

    and its proper theorization amounts to the key problem of cognitive

    psychology (Bruner, 1990, 1992; Glenberg & Robertson, 2000; Kitchener,

    1994). Throughout the entire intellectual history of psychology as a disci-

    pline, research programsin the sense of Lakatos (1970)have emerged

    emphasizing the fundamental role of the dimension of meaning in human

    cognitive functioning. Cases in point are the studies on memory (Bartlett,

    1932/1961), perception (Wertheimer, 1959), language (Buhler, 1934/1999)

    and developmental psychology (Piaget, 1952; Vygotsky, 1978), which, even

    before the consolidation of the so-called cognitive revolution, pointed with

    different emphases to the relevance of meaning in the configuration of

    psychological phenomena.

    Theory & Psychology Copyright 2004 Sage Publications. Vol. 14(1): 528DOI: 10.1177/0959354304040196 www.sagepublications.com

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://www.sagepublications.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://www.sagepublications.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    3/25

    The most frequent use of the term meaning in cognitive psychology and

    in the psychology of language designates the contents of linguistic con-structions (e.g. morphemes, words, clauses, etc.). According to this use of

    meaning, linguistic constructions evoke objective contents in the speakersmind. The objective nature of these representations is verified through the

    high degree of consensus in a given linguistic community. The association

    between form and content is thus independent of the subjectivity of the

    speaker/listener. These contents associated with linguistic forms constitute

    their semantic content, which has been conceptualized in varying ways in

    psychology (e.g. Bierwisch & Schreuder, 1992; Burguess & Lund, 1997;Landauer & Dumais, 1997; Rapaport, 1998), semantics (Fauconnier, 1994;

    Jackendoff, 1988; Katz & Fodor, 1963), philosophy (Putnam, 1975), semi-

    otics (Eco, 1976) and formal logic (Hintikka, 1989; Kripke, 1972).

    This common way of understanding the concept of meaning is, however,

    in conflict with some theoretical beliefs strongly shared by the cognitive

    psychologists scientific community. In order to understand this conflict, it is

    necessary to consider one of the most recurring and well-established

    findings of cognitive psychology: that subjects actively construct theirexperience. The knower is not a mere passive recipient who reproduces, in a

    quasi-pictorial manner, the information he or she receives from the environ-

    ment. Instead, there are a number of internal processes, normally automatic,

    that participate in the structuring of external reality. This thesis, known by

    some authors as cognitive constructivism (Christmann & Scheele, 2001;Neisser, 1967; Nuse, Groeben, Freitag, & Schreier, 1991), has been empiric-

    ally demonstrated in various cognitive processes (e.g. through the verifica-

    tion of top-down influences in human perception, attention and memory) andit represents a common assumption in several theoriesmany of which are

    rival in other aspects and range from Gestalt to connectionist models,

    including theories of information processing and activity theories. The basic

    idea of the knower as a (co-)constructor (Valsiner, 1994) of experienced

    reality goes across subdisciplines and theories, and has been characterized as

    belonging to the epistemological bases of the discipline (Bruner, 1992).Extending this basic constructivist idea to the realm of language

    comprehension, linguistic meaning should be the result of a subjectiveinterpretation arising from a particular context, that is, the individuals

    meaningful construal of the situation (Glenberg & Robertson, 2000, p. 383),

    based on the assumption that nothing is meaningful in itself (Lakoff, 1987,

    p. 292). However, if we claim that it is the subject using language who

    construes words or confers meaningfulness on them, it is no longer possible

    to maintain that words have an inherently associated meaning or semantic

    content. How can we reconcile the notion that a linguistic expression has asemantic content with the notion that it is the subject who understands itwho constructs its meaning? Does a linguistic expression possess a meaning

    eo ipso, or does it become meaningful only as it is constructed by the

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)6

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    4/25

    speaker/hearer? Is there a conventional content that is attached to linguistic

    constructions, which is more or less independent of who uses them and

    where they are used, or are these constructions rather a vehicle through

    which the meanings can be realized (Budwig, 1995, p. 4)? Can a mentalcontent be, at the same time, given and constructed, a priori and a

    posteriori?

    In summary, this view of linguistic meaning generates a contradiction

    between two theoretical postulates. On the one hand, cognitive psychology

    asserts that there are objective meanings attached to linguistic constructions,

    which are, by definition, independent of the subject. On the other hand,

    cognitive psychology also claims that the meaningfulness of linguistic

    expressions is the result of an interpretive and constructive process carried

    out by the speaker/listener, of whom it is therefore not independent. Thus,linguistic meaning becomes at the same time dependent on, and independent

    of, the subject.

    The (implicit) solution to this dilemma is to assume the existence of

    linguistic meanings in the head of the speaker/listener. These linguistic

    meanings are organized in some sort of mental lexicon, to which the subject

    can gain access depending on their use-contingencies (e.g. E.V. Clark, 1993;

    Jackendoff, 2002). According to this popular view, speakers possess a stock

    of lexical entries which they use in linguistic comprehension and com-

    munication. However, this account of language comprehension creates anew problem. Assuming that a given expression can be associated to more

    than one linguistic meaning, subjects must be able to decide, based on

    contextual cues, which is the appropriate meaning, that is, which lexical

    entry is required in order to understand the expression. Yet, to be able to

    make this kind of lexical decision, subjects also need to understand the

    meanings of all the alternative lexical entries. This requires additional lexical

    information if one wishes to preserve the consistency of the theory. This

    additional lexical information creates the need for a second, deeper, compre-

    hension, namely the comprehension not of linguistic expressions but oflexical entries. This creates an obvious regressus infinitus: the existence of

    linguistic meanings in the head pushes the conflict between the objective,

    conventional nature of linguistic meanings and their constructive, con-

    textual, subjective nature towards a deeper level. Thus, this solution gives

    rise to the same original questions, this time at a higher logical level: How

    can these two notions be compatible, that lexical entries possess a semantic

    content and that at the same time this content is the outcome of an active

    interpretive process on the part of the subject? Does a lexical entry possess

    a meaning eo ipso, or is it meaningful only as the speaker/listener compre-

    hends it? And so on. Summarizing, the mental lexicon hypothesis is not able

    to solve the conflict between the subject-independence of linguistic meaning

    and the subject-dependence of all forms of meaningfulness.

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 7

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    5/25

    In order to understand the nature of this apparent contradiction, it is

    helpful to examine the interdisciplinary origins of the traditional concept oflinguistic meaning in psychology. In the following section I conduct a

    theoretical and historical analysis of the definition given to the termmeaning by the school of structuralism, the first great school of linguistics,

    and I discuss the ways in which the legacy of this view has produced

    (paradoxically, through the generativist school) the contradiction presented

    before. Following this, I show how the tension between meanings depend-

    ence on the subject and its independence of it is observed in linguistics as

    well, specifically in the fields of semantics and pragmatics, in the discussionabout the role played by context in the formation of linguistic meaning. In

    the following section, I discuss in greater depth the epistemological premises

    underlying the two conflicting views of linguistic meaning, and I argue that

    the problem of meaning represents a much deeper schism in the field of

    psychology, related to the epistemic value given to the intentional experi-

    ence of consciousness. In the next section, I propose the need to integrate the

    objective and subjective aspects of linguistic meaning. I argue that the

    contradiction between the subjective and objective nature of the linguisticmeaning rests on the false dichotomy, already manifest in Freges writings,

    between the (epistemic) objectivity of meaning and the (ontological) subject-

    ivity of consciousness. In the penultimate section, I argue that pragmat-

    ization and semiotization are plausible ways to integrate the subjective and

    objective aspects of meaning. Finally, I present the major conclusions thatcan be drawn from this analysis.

    Origins of Linguistic Meaning

    The Structuralist Legacy

    In the beginnings of scientific linguistics, Ferdinand de Saussure

    (1916/1966) proposed a fundamental distinction between languagelangue (p. 9)and speakingparole (p. 13). Saussure and the structural-

    ists understood langue as a superindividual system of signs, coherent and

    self-contained, which is independent of the speaker, inasmuch as it con-

    stitutes a social fact. This could and should be distinguished fromparole, the

    real use of language by specific individuals in specific situations. Saussure

    explicitly limited the object of study of the emerging field of linguistics to

    langue.Within this framework, Saussure defines meaningconcept, signifie

    (pp. 65f.)as a psychic representation appearing in the subjects con-sciousness through the quasi-physical representation of a soundimage

    acoustique, signifiant (pp. 65f.)in the speakers mind. Both elements

    constitute, for the structuralist school, the two components of any linguistic

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)8

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    6/25

    sign, which are as intimately linked as the two sides of a sheet of paper. This

    close link between them is based on the assumption that the sign belongs tothe langue, that is, to the superindividual linguistic system. This idea allows

    Saussure to account for the objectivity of linguistic signs. In ascribing thelinguistic sign to the langue system, Saussure defines and limits the semantic

    dimension of linguistics object of knowledge, assuming that the relations

    between linguistic forms and semantic contents are (socially) fixed and

    grounded at the superindividual level. Thus, in the structuralist view,

    meaning is ultimately an element of the langue, an intrinsic property of the

    linguistic sign, just like its morphology and phonology; the fact that it is apsychic representation does not impinge on its social nature. The speakers

    mind is rather the space where these superindividual creations unfold. It

    follows that linguistic meaning is part of the structure of languages social

    system, with an ontological status different from that of the subjective

    experience of the individual who uses the linguistic signs.

    Semantics displacement towards langue leads us to the distinction of

    objective units of meaning attached to linguistic signs. These are by

    definition independent of the subjects experience, since in the structuralistview the object of the study of linguistics ends precisely where the use of

    language in real contexts by actual individuals begins.

    Once the subject has been excluded, the relation between signification and

    signifier unavoidably turns into a static relation, one that is unable to account

    for the flexibility and variability of meaning in everyday uses of language.After all, metaphor, metonymy, jokes and puns are not as rare as the

    Saussurian model would suggest. This plasticity in the relation betweenform and content, according to which a word can have different meanings

    depending on the context in which it is used, is left unexplained in the

    Saussurian model.

    The Generativist Continuity

    Although Chomsky (1957, 1965) was explicit in presenting his theory as analternative approach to structuralism, some of the Saussurian schools

    essential distinctions would be recycled in the generativist model, particu-

    larly those concerning the nature of linguistic meaning.

    In Chomskys approach, syntax is conceived as a coherent system of

    logical rules operating at a mental level, which is responsible for language

    production and comprehension. This new conception requires the assump-

    tion that a logical-syntactic component of the abstract system is operating inthe head of each native speaker in the form of a dynamic system in charge

    of the generation of syntactic structures (Hormann, 1976, 1981).According to Chomsky (1965), any native speaker is an ideal speaker in

    the sense that he or she is capable of generating an infinite number of

    grammatically correct sentences, as well as being able to identify the

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 9

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    7/25

    grammaticality of any sentence in his or her native language, even though

    this speaker has never heard it before. Chomsky assigns the term com-

    petence to the linguistic knowledge that allows this capacity. When the

    speaker uses language in communicative situations, he or she is showinglinguistic performance. This performance results from the activation of the

    competence mentioned before, but it is also subject to interference from a

    number of extra-grammatical factors, which account for the possible linguis-

    tic errors which speakers actually incur. When comparing the competence/

    performance pair with the langue/parole dichotomy, it is evident that the

    latter is based on a distinction between two levels of description (social vs

    individual), while the former distinguishes between potentiality and

    realization.

    It is important to note that the pre-existence of objective and contextual

    links between lexical items and meanings is a prerequisite for the mental

    syntactic mechanism to be able to function properly. For semantic rules to

    adequately perform their interpretation of syntactic structures, there have to

    be some preordained relations between the lexical items that are generated

    and transformed, and the meanings corresponding to the contents for which

    the items stand. Thus, the Chomskian linguistic paradigm, despite presenting

    itself as an alternative to structuralism, nonetheless assumes a structuralist

    definition of sign, inasmuch as the semantically blind manipulation of

    syntactic structures is possible only if the subsequent semantic interpretation

    is guaranteed in advance. Semantic translation of syntactic structures is thussafeguarded by the assumption of meaning-in-itself (Cornejo, 2000, p. 130),

    attached to the word and independent of the speakers subjectivity.

    While the structuralist school stated that the meaning-significant union

    was a social fact, in the generativist framework this unit has psychological

    reality in the head of the native speaker. In this sense, linguistic competence

    is a sort of langue in the head which includes the knowledge of form

    content associations.1 Thus, the generativist theory brings language compre-

    hension back into the subject matter of linguistics. Such a reincorporation,

    however, assumes a redefinition of comprehension, from a subjectiveexperience to a composition of isolated meaning units.

    The assumption of abstract language representations in the individual

    mind has also been criticized as being illegitimate by defenders of a

    Platonist conception of the language:

    There is a distinction between a speakers knowledge of a language and the

    language itselfwhat the knowledge is knowledge of. . . . The language is

    a timeless, unchangeable, objective structure; knowledge of a language is

    temporal, subject to change, and subjective. (Katz, 1981, p. 9)

    Katz calls for a return to the langue, under the motto linguistics is not

    psychological science (p. 76). According to him, the ideal speakers

    knowledge of the language cannot be the subject matter of linguistics, since

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)10

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    8/25

    this would entail a confusion between the knowledge we have of something

    and the things that we have knowledge of. He concludes that sentences,

    meanings and language are abstract objects. What Katz forgets in his

    reasoning is the fact that Chomskys native speaker is already a Platonistconstruction, not a real one. Katzs distinction between the speakers

    knowledge of a language and the language itself holds only when the

    speaker is a real one, not a Platonic one. The abstract objects are not

    neglected in a generativist framework; they are simply supposed to be in the

    head.

    Nevertheless, the langue in the head assumption granted the Chomskian

    model a certain psychological flavor, which seduced many psychologists

    (e.g. Johnson 1965, 1966; Miller & Isard, 1963; Miller & McKean, 1964)

    and had a decisive influence in the evolution of psycholinguistics. From thispoint on, psychology appears to have assimilated the structuralist-

    generativist conception of linguistic meaning which is based on the semantic

    contents independence from the speaker/listener.

    On the Distinction between Semantics and Pragmatics

    The tension between a subject-dependent and a subject-independent mean-

    ing is also found at the point where the study of the structure of languagegives way to the study of language use. Thus, the debate about the limits of

    semantics and pragmatics can be understood as the point of conflict between

    the two ways of understanding meaning.

    Adhering to a structuralist-generativist definition of meaning, linguists

    usually understand semantics as the study of linguistic meaning, understood

    as the content conventionally linked to a given lexical item (e.g. Cruse,

    2000). The level of description of semantics, as with the other linguistics

    subdisciplines, is always structural, that is, it concerns the structure of the

    general linguistic system. With the writings of Wittgenstein (1953), Austin(1962), Searle (1969/1989) and Grice (1975), among others, the view

    emerged progressively that a description of the linguistic systems structure

    did not encompass language use phenomena.

    The division of the study of language in its structure and its use signals

    the emergence of a new linguistic subdiscipline calledpragmatics. Although

    the definition of pragmatics object of study is not altogether clear (Cruse,

    2000; Davis, 1991; Gazdar, 1979; Levinson, 1983), authors agree that it

    concerns the aspects of meaning that are derived from language use, and not

    from its semantic structure, as portrayed in the motto pragmatics =meaning minus semantics (see Levinson, 1983, p. 12). Pragmatics concerns

    itself with linguistic utterances in context, including the meaningful

    elements produced by social and contextual factors.

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 11

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    9/25

    Language use always occurs in a specific context, by a specific speaker,

    with a given communicative goal. Therefore, the pragmatic aspect oflinguistic meaning constitutes a psychological explanandum: when we

    consider the use context of a particular expression, we are referring not to ameaning-in-itself, but, rather, to the subjective experience of meaning. It is

    no longer about describing the (decontextualized) meaning of words, but

    about the online meaning that a speaker/listener constructs when using/

    hearing those words in a particular context. Thus, the study of language use

    compels us to go beyond the structural description of meaning-in-itself and

    focuses our attention on the subjective comprehension of utterances.Pragmatics quasi-psychological nature should have led it to confront the

    problem of the integration of linguistic meanings objective and subjective

    aspects. Surprisingly, this has not been the case, mainly because a large

    portion of the research that nowadays can be classified as pragmatics

    assumes, either implicitly or explicitly, a structuralist-generativist definition

    of linguistic meaning, which is always alien to the experience of meaning.

    Traditional pragmatics presumes the existence, in the head, of the utter-

    ances meaning-in-itself, while a pragmatic component is responsible foraccommodating this meaning-in-itself to the particular communicative

    situation and for extracting additional contextual inferences. In this view,

    pragmatic aspects are reduced to inferences that are subsidiary and com-

    plementary to the mental lexicons meaning-in-itself, which continues to

    be the true linguistic meaning. Paradoxically, all contextual elements influ-encing online linguistic comprehensionboth non-linguistic (e.g. non-

    verbal gestures) and paralinguistic elements (e.g. prosody, tone of

    voice)have been excluded from research in pragmatics (H.H. Clark,1996).

    Although the contextual aspect of language use is only a part of (and not

    synonymous with) the subjective experience of meaning, its absolute ex-

    clusion from pragmatics shows the incapacity of the discipline to integrate

    comprehension elements not pertaining to the langue, which, in turn, reveals

    that classic pragmatics has not abandoned the structuralist view of meaning.The language studied in pragmatics corresponds to the superindividual

    system of language. Thus, pragmatics becomes the study of the interactionalconsequences of the manipulation of superindividual prefabricated semantic

    units. The speaker/listeners experience of meaning is described, in the end,

    as a fusion of two elements belonging to two different logical realms: the

    meaning-in-itselfindependent of the subjectand the pragmatic

    inferencesdependent on both the subject and the context.

    Pragmatic theorys mixture of elements belonging to different logical

    domains seems to be the result of overlooking the fact that the study oflanguage use requires abandoning the basic theoretical assumptions thatallow us to legitimately talk about meaning-in-itself. This is so inasmuch

    as, in considering the context of language use, we are no longer dealing with

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)12

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    10/25

    a structuralist-generativist meaning-in-itself, but, rather, with a speaker/

    listeners experience of meaning, that is, with a meaning-for-somebody.

    It follows, then, that, its eventual descriptive value notwithstanding, the

    analytical distinction between semantics and pragmatics lacks psychologicalreality (Cornejo, 2000; Gibbs, 1994; Rumelhart, 1979; Shanon, 1988). The

    notion that linguistic comprehension involves the recovery of the lexical

    items predetermined semantic content, with the role of the context being the

    filter that selects the adequate semantic content, not only suffers from the

    logical problem of confounding the social and individual levels of descrip-

    tion, but is also empirically untenable from a psychological perspective, for

    at least three reasons. In the first place, it is obvious that in the microgenetic

    moment of linguistic comprehension, contextual-pragmatic information is as

    important as semantic information in order to comprehend a given ex-

    pression (Gibbs, 1984, 1994). Second, the definition of any lexical items

    linguistic meaning, regardless of how simple this item appears to be, always

    refers to some general background knowledge, without which the definition

    would become incomprehensible. A large portion of this background know-

    ledge remains implicit and is evoked by non-linguistic and paralinguistic

    contextual elements, which are therefore (strictly speaking) non-semantic.

    This is precisely the insight that inspired many fruitful theories in cognitive

    psychology, linguistics and artificial intelligence, such as the theories of

    schemata (Bartlett, 1932/1961; Rumelhart, 1980), scripts (Schank &

    Abelson, 1977) andframes (Fillmore, 1982; Minsky, 1977). Third, develop-mental psychology provides abundant evidence that language acquisition

    proceeds in a contextual and holistic fashion, as opposed to an analytical one

    (D.A. Baldwin, Markman, Bill, Desjardins, & Irwin, 1996; D.A. Baldwin &

    Tomasello, 1998).

    Interestingly, criticism of the semantics/pragmatics distinction has also

    originated from non-generativist theories, specifically from the cognitive

    linguistics theory. This theory rejects the modular view of language, which

    isolates it from the entire whole of cognitive processes and operations and

    understands meaning as conceptualization (Lakoff, 1987; Langacker, 1987,1990; Rudzka-Ostyn, 1988).

    In rejecting the notion of an autonomous linguistic faculty, cognitive

    linguistics necessarily removes the need for pragmatics as a separate

    branch of study. All meaning is, in a sense, pragmatic, as it involves the

    conceptualizations of human beings in a physical and social environment.

    (Taylor, 1995, p. 132)

    What the cognitive linguistics school understands as meaning is obviously

    not the same as the meaning-in-itself of the structuralist and generativistschools. For the former, the meaning of a linguistic construction is an

    interpretation arising out of a particular context (Geeraerts, 1993; Givon,

    1989), being, as a consequence, both context- and subject-dependent.

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 13

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    11/25

    The shift from structure to use uncovers the problem of the existence of

    two opposing ways of understanding linguistic meaning, depending onwhether it refers to superindividual regularities and conventions, or to the

    speaker/listeners experience of meaning. In what follows I would like toargue that this tension implies different metatheoretical views regarding the

    more basic issue of intentionality.

    Meaning and Intentionality

    The tension between the objectivity of what words say and the subjectivity

    of the mental construction of the subject who uses them in real contexts is

    the (psycho-)linguistic expression of a deeper division in psychology, one

    that arises from the speaker/listeners perspective towards the intentional

    experience of consciousness.

    The view of linguistic meaning as meaning-in-itself emphasizes the

    objective character of meaning: it concerns only conventionalized

    intersubjectively valid associations between linguistic form and content.

    Since the connection between form and meaning is an intersubjective one,

    what the words say is independent of their subjective use. This viewpoint

    thus adopts a superindividual perspective, located outside subjective experi-

    ence. From this standpoint, the phenomenological experience of linguistic

    comprehension becomes superfluous to the study of meaning, inasmuch assemantic content has an objective character, and either the subject possessesthis meaning or it does not. It follows that all the subtleties and deviations

    from conventional associations that are observed in daily language use have

    to be explained without altering the essential principle of linguistic mean-

    ings objectivity. On the other hand, the view of linguistic meaning as

    meaning-for-somebodye.g. that of cognitive linguisticsemphasizes the

    subjective nature of meaning and places the phenomenon within the speaker/

    listeners phenomenological experience: meaning does not reside objectively

    in the expression eo ipso, since a words meaningfulness is always asubjects contextualized construction. According to this view, the (empiric-

    ally) proven significance of the context in the definition of linguistic

    meaning is a result of the fact that meaning is always a psychological

    construction, a meaning-for-somebody.

    Thus we have two concepts of meaning, depending on whether we situate

    ourselves within or without the speaker/listeners experience of meaning. If

    we are situated outside this experience, meaning is objective, social and it

    resides in the words. If we take the perspective from inside the phenomeno-

    logical experience, meaning is a subjective, contextual construction, and itresides in the mindin the form of an intentional content of consciousness.

    It thus follows that traditional semantics term meaning puts the intention-

    ality of consciousness in parentheses, using it merely as a working hypo-

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)14

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    12/25

    thesis that justifies an inquiry into an object of linguistic knowledge. In this

    case meaning refers to a cartography of the conventional formcontentregularities existing in a linguistic community, which has nothing to do with

    the psychological explanandum of meaning as a subjective comprehension.According to this analysis, the meaning-in-itself assumed by different

    psychological schools to exist in the speakers heads is actually a unit of

    social nature, which is induced from the regularities in the linguistic

    behavior of a group of speakers. That is, it constitutes a description of the

    experience of meaning from the outside. Therefore, the psycholinguistic

    supposition that the meaning-in-itself would be stored in the memoryrepresents an illegitimate mixture of different perspectives: elements de-

    scribed from the perspective of an external observer regarding the subjects

    experience of meaning are treated as phenomenological units, whose nature

    is only accessible in the first person. The meaning-in-itself is an analysis

    unit belonging to a (macro-)social level, not to the speakers/listeners

    intentional experience. Therefore, it cannot be supposed in the head.2

    Such a standpoint could eventually lead us, however, to what Donnellan

    (1968) has called the Humpty Dumpty theory of meaning, that is, a theory of

    the kind When I use a word, it means just what I choose to mean . . ..3 Ifmeaning is by definition a meaning-for-somebody, then it becomes a purely

    subjective construction and completely variable depending on subject and

    context. Yet it is an empirical fact that linguistic expressions do not evoke

    just any content in the mind of the speaker, but a set of given objectivecontents, the presence of which provides support to the assumption of a

    meaning-in-itself independent of the subject who uses it and the context in

    which it is used. The debate about meanings constructive-subjective char-

    acter should not ignore the fact that speakers in a community are normally inagreement about the meanings of words and sentences, and when this is not

    the case, they can reach agreement without great difficulty.

    Nevertheless, it is not clear how a psychological conception of meaning,

    which approaches the phenomenon from within the experience of meaning,

    therefore emphasizing its subjective nature, can be compatible with theempirical fact that this meaning is usually objective. Is it possible for

    something to be at the same time both objective and subjective?

    Objectivity and Subjectivity of Linguistic Meaning

    It is interesting to note that the traditional conception of linguistic

    meaningas meaning-in-itselfbrings with it a particular view about the

    nature of the relation between individual and society. The idea of meaning-in-itself is always proposed in opposition to other, non-objective contents(of consciousness), assuming that there is a conceptual distinction among

    contents (of consciousness) depending on whether they are objective or

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 15

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    13/25

    subjective. In the case of Saussure, it is precisely the objectivity of linguistic

    meaning that allows it to be assigned to the social fact of langue. Thisimplicitly divides mental contents in two mutually exclusive categories: a

    meaning-in-itselfobjective and socialand a fuzzy set of other sub-jective and idiosyncratic mental contents.

    All this suggests that the idea of meaning-in-itself is based on a

    dichotomous view of the relation between individual and society, according

    to which contents of consciousness are different from the social and

    objective contents belonging to the social linguistic system. Individual

    contents (of consciousness) cannot be social, inasmuch as they are notobjective, while social meaning cannot be subjective, for it is objective. This

    reasoning can be outlined in the following way:

    P1 Meaning is a conventional content.P2 If a content is conventional, then it is objective.

    P3 A content is either objective or subjective.

    C Meaning is not subjective.

    Despite the reasoning being valid, it contains an ambiguous predicate

    which is found both in the third premise and in the conclusion: subjective.

    P3 and C are erroneous inasmuch as subjectivity is not necessarily opposed

    to objectivity. In order to make this clear, it has to be noted that the

    objectivity of meaning is based on its social conventionality and not on the

    objectivity of its referent. In fact, in semantic terms, an expression can havean objective meaning even in the absence of an observable referente.g.

    electron, accelerationor a specific referente.g.freedom,figure, blueness.

    P1 asserts the fact that, as result of social interactions, certain consensual

    soundcontent associations emerge whose validity extends to the whole

    linguistic community.4 Thus, when we talk about the objectivity of meaning,

    we are referring precisely to the conventional character of some associations

    in a given linguistic community. In other words, objectivity is understood as

    intersubjectivity. The influential Saussurian reasoning presented above is

    based on the claim that meaning cannot be individual because it is inter-subjectively valid.

    Nevertheless, the fact that some formcontent associations are inter-

    subjective does not imply that these are non-mental. This reasoning can be

    invalidated by making explicit the two different senses of subjective con-

    founded in Saussurian reasoning:

    We resist accepting subjectivity as a ground floor, irreducible phenomenon

    of nature because, since the seventeenth century, we have come to believe

    that science must be objective. But this involves a pun on the notion of

    objectivity. We are confusing the epistemic objectivity of scientificinvestigation with the ontological objectivity of the typical subject matter

    in science in disciplines such as physics and chemistry. Since science aims

    at objectivity in the epistemic sense that we seek truths that are not

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)16

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    14/25

    dependent on the particular point of view of this or that investigator, it has

    been tempting to conclude that the reality investigated by science must be

    objective in the sense of existing independently of the experiences in the

    human individual. But this last feature, ontological objectivity, is not an

    essential trait of science. (Searle, 1994, p. 5)

    According to this distinction, subjective in the third premise of the reasoning

    presented above must be understood in a strictly epistemic sense, while

    subjective in the conclusion has an ontological sense. The fallacy has ledlinguistics as well as psychology to the erroneous conclusion that meaning

    cannot be ontologically subjective (see C) given its epistemic objectivity

    (see P3). From the fact that linguistic meaning is intersubjectively valid it is

    erroneously concluded that it cannot be mental.

    The idea that what is ontologically subjective is epistemically subjective

    constitutes one of the essential premises of the anti-psychological thinking at

    the end of the 19th century, which constituted the origin of the elimination

    of subjective experience as a foundation for meaning. This anti-psychological thinking is clearly evident in the writings of one of the

    founders of formal semantics, namely Frege (see Levine, 1999). When

    introducing the famous distinction between referencethe object referred to

    by the signand sensethe mode of presentation of the reference (Frege,

    1892/1962, p. 39)Frege discusses whether the sense can be considered a

    mental content. His answer is a negative one, basically due to senses

    objective character, which can be a common property of many, andtherefore is not a part or mode of the individual soul (p. 42). Although the

    sense does not correspond to an element of the external world, it has,

    however, to be independent of the subject, due to its objectivity.

    The objectivization of sense through its ontological separation from thecontents of consciousness was functional to Freges goal of ensuring a non-

    ambiguous referential foundation for his Begriffschrift, the ideal language

    that would allow the linguistic unification of the analytic and synthetic

    sciences. In the logical-positivist view, where things and symbols belong

    to disjunct classes, an ideal language warranted a format of precise thoughtfor the representational mind. For this to-think-is-to-calculate conception

    to work, the class of manipulated symbols must have pre-existent relations

    with their respective referents. This condition is indeed necessary forDescartes mechanical automata, Leibnizs universal grammar, the ideal

    language of analytic philosophy, Turings machine, and certainly for

    Chomskys generative grammar. In the Fregean framework, the separation

    of the sense from the subjective mental life is indispensable to warrant the

    mentioned condition.

    The target of Freges criticism is idealistic subjectivism, which locatesmeaning in a transcendental spirit. Subjectivism does not give clear answersto the important question regarding the origin of significance or its relation

    to referential function. Freges solution to the dilemmas of subjectivism is to

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 17

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    15/25

    bind meaning to reference, in such a way that all phenomenological

    experience not related to the referential function is excluded from the

    objective conceptual domainthe sense. The individual/society dichotomy

    is also expressed in the false choice between meaning as a creation of theindividual soul and meaning as Platonic concept. In both alternatives,

    ontological and epistemic subjectivity are fused together.

    In recent decades, however, psychology has been coming closer to a

    sociocultural view of mental processes that is considerably different from

    the concept of mind that was subject to anti-psychological criticism in the

    19th century. This shift is expressed in the rediscovery of the classical

    authors in Soviet psychology (Vygotsky, 1962, 1978; Wertsch, 1985, 1991)

    and in Soviet literary science (Bakhtin, 1981; Hermans, 1996), together with

    the American pragmatists (J.M. Baldwin, 1894, 1896a, 1896b; James,

    1890/1983; Mead, 1934; Peirce, 19311935, 1958; see Dodds, Lawrence, &

    Valsiner, 1997; Joas, 1993; Shank, 1998; Smythe & Chow, 1998; Valsiner

    & Van der Veer, 2000). For different reasons, from diverse theoretical

    groundings and with a range of emphases, these authors represent the

    common idea that the self results from the internalization of externali.e.

    socialrelations. In a naturalized conception of mind, the latter is not seen

    as given beforehand, but as emerging and being formed on the basis of the

    social interactions in which human beings are involved from birth. This

    leads us to a framework in which subjectivity is seen as a social product:

    psychic life as we experience it every day would be unthinkable without the

    social processes in which the subject participates from birth. Thus, the

    intersubjective world is constitutive of the subjective world:

    The social is usually thought of in binary opposition with the individual,

    and hence we have the notion that the psyche is individual while ideology

    is social. Notions of that sort are fundamentally false. The correlate of the

    social is the natural, and thus individual is not meant in the sense of a

    person, but individual as a natural, biological specimen. The individual,

    as possessor of the contents of his own consciousness, as author of his own

    thoughts, as the personality responsible for his thoughts and feelings,

    such an individual is a purely socioideological phenomenon. . . . Every

    sign as sign is social, and this is no less true for the inner sign than for the

    outer sign. (Volosinov, 1929/1973, p. 34)

    Thus it follows that a content can be subjective, that is, can occur in a

    subjects mental domain, and be intersubjective at the same time. Further-

    more, the conceptual tools available to subjects to perceive and understand

    their world in a coherent manner are necessarily intersubjective and there-

    fore objective. From the observation that a given content is objective, thereis no reason to conclude that the same content is necessarily non-subjective

    and belongs to a Platonic superindividual world. Linguistic meanings cannot

    be anywhere else but in the speakers heads, but this does not mean that they

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)18

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    16/25

    are stored in the shape of fixed acontextual relations between form and

    content, as semantics and formal logic assert.In a dialogical view of the self (Hermans, 1996; Hermans & Kempen,

    1993), it is not hard to understand that, epistemically, the dichotomybetween individual and society on which the concept of meaning-in-itself

    is based does not exist. Peirce and Vygotskys hypotheses about the social

    formation of subjectivity weaken the implicit synonymy between epistemic

    subjectivitysubjectivity in the sense of a knowledge that cannot be

    generally validand ontological subjectivitythe fact that mental pro-

    cesses can only be experienced within the private realm. As a consequence,although linguistic comprehension is an undeniably private experience and

    therefore subjective, it is also undeniable that the subject cannot understand

    this experience as such unless he or she has internalized a conceptual set of

    tools that are intersubjectively constructed.

    Overcoming the dichotomous view of the relation between individual and

    society, a goal pursued both by Peirces pragmatism and by sociogenetic

    theory, puts into question the theoretical basis that caused linguistic meaning

    to be taken out of phenomenological experience and reified as a structuralproperty of linguistic signs. If meanings ontological subjectivity is not

    opposed to its epistemic objectivity, then psychology is now able to

    reformulate the concept of linguistic meaning in a way that integrates both

    aspects of the concept: objectivity and subjectivity.

    Pragmatization and Semiotization of Meaning as Methods for

    Integration of Objectivity and Subjectivity

    So far, it can be concluded that it is necessary to correct the traditional

    definition of meaning in a double sense: (1) it should be understood as a

    phenomenon that takes place inside the subjects experience; and (2) its

    epistemic objectivity should be considered compatible with the ontological

    subjectivity of experience. The first correction implies the pragmatization ofmeaning, that is, its reconceptualization as a meaning-for-somebody, a

    subject- and context-dependent construction. Meaning is no longer seen as a

    pre-existent abstract entity which is activated whenever language is used, but

    it is rather an ongoing construction which therefore depends on a myriad of

    factors, such as paralinguistic and non-linguistic cues, corporal and emo-

    tional arousal, comprehension background, and so on.

    It is important to note that pragmatization of meaning is a consequence of

    any theory that is distanced from a computational or mechanistic view of the

    mind. Examples are current research programs like embodied cognition(Lakoff & Johnson, 1999; Thompson & Varela, 2001; Varela, Rosch, &

    Thompson, 1991) and affective neurosciences (Damasio, 1999). In both

    cases, the radical foundation of mental processes on neurobiological and

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 19

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    17/25

    basic corporal processes leads to the replacement of the disembodied

    meaning-in-itself by a pragmatized meaning. Similarly, within the boundedrationality research program (Gigerenzer & Goldstein, 1996), there are

    interesting attempts to deal with the categorization problem, which leads toabandoning the view of meaning as abstract representation. In this direction,

    a categorization model has been proposed which is based on a simple

    heuristic that stops looking for features to categorize a particular stimulus as

    soon as there is sufficient information to make a specific categorization, so

    that it is not necessary to compare all of the stimuluss features to ideal

    profiles stored in memory in order to make a categorization (Berrety, Todd,& Martignon, 1999). Aside from the advantages of the model in terms of

    psychological plausibility, it shows that categorization can occur without the

    activation of an abstract representation, on the basis of a few cues.

    Categorization is in this sense contextually guided. Furthermore, consistent

    with an ecological view of rationality, concepts should be contextually

    sensible in the stronger sense, that is, the correctness of the categorization

    should be judged considering the environment in which the concept is used.

    Thus, a particular object could, in principle, be categorized in different waysaccording to the present ecological needsin this regard see Olsons (1970)

    classical work.

    The second correction involves solving the problems of idealistic subjectiv-

    ism. If human individuality is formed in society, an ontological difference

    does not exist between subjective and intersubjective forms of meaning-fulness. Subjective consciousness is not transcendental, but rather it

    develops in the play of intersubjectively determined meaning constructions.Now, if we ask for the material of the social constructions which constitute

    consciousness, we arrive at the concept of sign, whose social, but at the

    same time experiential, nature allows an adequate access to meaningfulness.

    This movement implies the semiotization of meaning, that is, its revision as

    a complex subjective construction which employs a diversity of semiotic

    (and consequently intersubjective) elements, and which is permanently

    modified in communicative use. Meaning also requires an interpretationprocess, and therefore an interpreting subject. From this fact it does notfollow, however, that meaning is an interindividually different content.

    Rather, internal comprehension processes are based upon socially shared

    interpretive possibilities. Although to mean and to understand are internal

    processes, they are supported by many social elements, whose relative

    weight can vary interindividually depending on the context of use. From this

    point of view, subjective comprehension always occurs through the use of

    the internalized social instrumental, and hence the subjective space remains

    at all times within the limits and possibilities of intersubjectivity.Approaches like the epidemiology of representations (Sperber, 1996)

    and memetic theory (Blackmore, 1999; Dawkins, 1976; Dennett, 1995)

    have also defended a socialized view of the mind. Although with different

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)20

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    18/25

    nuances, they all propose gene-like or virus-like units of information

    (memes or mental/public representations), characterized by a tendency toself-reproduction or self-spreading. Individual minds are seen as an optimal

    medium where these can subsist. Fashion, scientific theories, gestures andideas are all examples of self-replicators. The framework undoubtedly

    overcomes the false dichotomy between mental contents and social contents.

    Nevertheless, these theories are not capable of explaining the individual use

    of language; diachronic variability of meanings and the contextual flexibility

    of language use are questions that cannot even be formulated within this

    framework. The reason is the exclusion of ontological subjectivity from theclass of natural phenomena.5 The naturalization of the mind proposed by

    memetic theory and its variants implies the reconceptualization of the mind

    as a receptacle of elements that are meaningful in themselves, described

    from a third-person perspective, and therefore decontextualized. Thus, thestructuralist/generativist hard core remains the same. The price to pay for the

    elimination of subjectivity is the creation of a metaphysical realm inhabited

    by representations that are intrinsically meaningful.6

    It could be counter-argued that the second proposed correction leads to the

    negation of subjectivityin the sense of individuality. However, properly

    considered, subjectivity as an attribute of psychic life is not neglected byarguments against an individual/society dichotomization; rather, what is

    abandoned is the very idea that consciousnesss subjectivity consists of a

    dominium proprium, apart from the objective, and is therefore unable to beapproached for scientific inquiry. It is still undeniable that the contents of

    consciousness are in a sense private, that is, that thoughts, feelings, pains,

    and the like, are accessible to the thinking, feeling subject in a way which is

    completely different from that of an eventual external observer. What is to

    be questioned, however, is the conclusion, reached from the qualitativecharacter of such phenomena, that they constitute an epistemically non-

    objective domain.

    The pragmatization and semiotization of meaning allow us to account for

    both its variability and its objectivity. On the one hand, meaning is alwayscontextually determined, because it is a content of consciousness and

    consequently it is construed within the experience of a subject, which is

    always contextualized. On the other hand, the comprehension process

    utilizes multiple conventionalized cues. Even though their degree of con-ventionalization can vary, semiotic elements are always the result of

    internalizations of language games with others.

    Conclusions

    I have tried to show that the way in which cognitive psychology and

    psycholinguistics use the concept of linguistic meaning is empirically

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 21

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    19/25

    dubious and inconsistent with basic psychological knowledge shared by

    these very disciplines. Most cognitive psychologists claim that linguisticmeaning is in some way contained in linguistic forms and, at the same time,

    that the meaning of an expression is the final product of an active andconstructive process on the part of the subject. Thus, a linguistic signs

    meaning is, at the same time, dependent on and independent of the subject.

    This contradiction has its origins in the illegitimate introduction into

    psychological language of distinctions coming from the realm of linguistics

    (where they were valid). Many cognitive models are based on two assump-

    tions: (a) that the scholastic maxim aliquid stat pro aliquosomethingstands for something elseexhaustively defines the sign; and (b) that this

    dyadic unitusually in the form of signification/signifieris stored in the

    mind and is recovered every time the sign is used. Besides the empirical

    anomalies of this kind of model when trying to use a static model of sign to

    account for the contextual flexibility of meaning in daily use, this way of

    understanding linguistic meaning confounds two different logical levels,

    namely the structural description of the intersubjective form/content regu-

    larities and the phenomenological experience of meaningful comprehension.This confusion often goes unnoticed by psychologists, who frequently use

    the term semantics to refer to experiential meaningfulness and not to

    linguistics superindividual meaning-in-itself.

    This is not to say that the concept of meaning-in-itself is totally without

    basis. Actually it is based on empirically observable regularities betweenlinguistic forms and mental contents. However, based on its objectivity,

    linguists, philosophers and psychologists have concluded that meaningcannot be a content of consciousness. The mental contents of consciousness

    that are conventionally associated with given linguistic forms are thus taken

    out of subjective experience and fixed within a dyadic model of the sign,

    which leaves subject and context in parentheses. When placed outside

    the head, the meaning-in-itselfreified and de-psychologizedleads

    towards the creation of a Platonic third realm (Ryle, 1957/1990, p. 371);

    inside the head, it produces two kinds of entia mentalis(epistemically)objective contents and (ontologically) subjective contents.

    I have argued that overcoming the contradiction between the two uses of

    meaning requires us to realize the perspective taken towards the intention-

    ality of consciousness in both language games: when using linguistic

    meaning referring to meaning-in-itself, one observes the phenomenon from

    outside the intentional experience of the subject who understands; when one

    talks about meaning-making or making sense, one observes the phenomenon

    from within the experience of meaningfulness of the subject who under-

    stands. Both perspectives emphasize different aspects of the same phenom-enon: on the one hand, the intersubjectively valid regularities of some

    formcontent associations; on the other, the intrinsically individual quality

    of the linguistic comprehension process. Throughout this paper I have

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)22

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    20/25

    questioned the ubiquitous idea that the subjective and objective aspects of

    meaning are mutually exclusive. Quite the opposite: both aspects can beintegrated once we go beyond a Robinson Crusoe view of the human

    being, that is, the Cartesian idea of logical pre-existence of the subject oversociety.

    Notes

    1. Currently, the clearest instance of the assumption of the langue in the head is

    the hypothesis of a mentalese or language of thought (Fodor, 1975).

    2. In this sense can the famous dictum of Putnam be understood: Cut the pie any

    way you like, meanings just aint in the head! (Putnam, 1975, p. 227).

    3. From Lewis CarrollsAlice in Wonderland.

    4. Conventional in P1 refers to the descriptive fact that the same word produces

    similar contents; it does not allude to the prescriptive determination of how and

    when a word is to be used. The determination of the correct use of a language

    is always historically and ontogenetically posterior to the spontaneous use of

    language.

    5. This point is already explicit in Dennetts (1987) theory of intentional systems,

    where intentionality is understood as an attribution made by an external

    observer about the behavior of an organism or system. Hence, it is an observer-

    relative property, not a factual one, as physical states are. According to this view,

    the sentence The child forgot to do her homework has exactly the same

    referential status as This clock forgot how to work; both of them refer to non-

    factual properties.6. Sperber strictly represents the marriage of Durkheimian structuralist thought

    expressed by the concept of social representation (Sperber, 1989)with the

    functionalist philosophy of mind through the concept of mental representation.

    Since both viewpoints propose characteristically third-person descriptions, Sperb-

    ers theory cannot account for intentionality and ontological subjectivity: Be-

    cause of these interactions [physical interactions with the environment], mental

    representations are, to some extent, regularly connected to what they represent; as

    a result, they have semantic properties, or meaning, of their own (Sperber,

    1996, p. 80).

    References

    Austin, J.L. (1962). How to do things with words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

    University Press.

    Bakhtin, M. (1981). The dialogical imagination. Austin: University of Texas

    Press.

    Baldwin, D.A., Markman, E.M., Bill, B., Desjardins, R.N., & Irwin, J.M. (1996).

    Infants reliance on a social criterion for establishing wordobject relations. Child

    Development, 67, 31353153.

    Baldwin, D.A., & Tomasello, M. (1998). Word learning: A window on earlypragmatic understanding. In E.V. Clark (Ed.), The proceedings of the Twenty-

    Ninth Annual Child Language Research Forum (pp. 323). Stanford, CA: Center

    for the Study of Language and Information.

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 23

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    21/25

    Baldwin, J.M. (1894). Imitation: A chapter in the natural history of consciousness.

    Mind, 3, 2655.

    Baldwin, J.M. (1896a). Heredity and instinct I. Science, 3(64), 438441.

    Baldwin, J.M. (1896b). Heredity and instinct II. Science, 3(67), 558561.

    Bartlett, F.C. (1961). Remembering. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    (Original work published 1932.)

    Berrety, P.M., Todd, P.M., & Martignon, L. (1999). Categorization by elimination:

    Using few cues to choose. In G. Gigerenzer, P.M. Todd, & the ABC Research

    Group, Simple heuristics that make us smart (pp. 235254). Oxford: Oxford

    University Press.

    Bierwisch, M., & Schreuder, R. (1992). From concepts to lexical items. Cognition,

    42, 4360.

    Blackmore, S. (1999). The meme machine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Bruner, J.S. (1990).Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Bruner, J.S. (1992). Another look at new look 1. American Psychologist, 47,

    780783.

    Budwig, N. (1995). A developmental-functionalist approach to child language.

    Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Buhler, K. (1999). Sprachtheorie [Theory of language] (3rd ed.). Stuttgart: Lucius &

    Lucius. (Original work published 1934.)

    Burguess, C., & Lund, K. (1997). Modelling parsing constraints with high-

    dimensional context space. Language and Cognitive Processes, 12, 177210.

    Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Christmann, U., & Scheele, B. (2001). Kognitive Konstruktivitat am Beispiel von

    Ironie und Metapher. In N. Groeben (Ed.), Zur Programmatik einer sozial-

    wissenschaftlichen Psychologie, Band II: Objekttheoretische Perspektiven, 1.

    Halbband: Sozialitat, Geschichtlichkeit, Erlebnisqualitaten, Kognitive Konstruk-

    tivitat(pp. 261326). Munster: Aschendorff.

    Clark, E.V. (1993). The lexicon in acquisition. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press.

    Clark, H.H. (1996). Using language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Cornejo, C. (2000). Sprache, Geist und Gesellschaft: Grundlagen einer psycho-

    logischen Theorie der Bedeutung [Language, mind and society: Foundations of apsychological theory of meaning]. Aachen: Shaker.

    Cruse, A. (2000). Meaning in language: An introduction to semantics and prag-

    matics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making

    of consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Davis, S. (1991). Introduction. In S. Davis (Ed.), Pragmatics: A reader (pp. 313).

    New York: Oxford University Press.

    Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Dennett, D.C. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Dennett, D.C. (1995).Darwins dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life.New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Dodds, A.E., Lawrence, J.A., & Valsiner, J. (1997). The personal and the social:

    Meads theory of the Generalized Other. Theory & Psychology, 7, 483503.

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)24

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    22/25

    Donnellan, K. (1968). Putting Humpty-Dumpty together again. Philosophical

    Review, 76, 203215.

    Eco, U. (1976).A theory of semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Fauconnier, G. (Ed.). (1994). Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in

    natural language. Cambridge: Cambridge Unversity Press.

    Fillmore, C.J. (1982). Frame semantics. In the Linguistic Society of Korea (Ed.),

    Linguistics in the morning calm (pp. 111137). Seoul: Hanshin Publishing.

    Fodor, J.A. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Crowell.

    Frege, G. (1962). Sinn und Bedeutung [Sense and reference]. In G. Patzig (Ed.),

    Funktion, Begriff, Bedeutung: Funf logische Studien [Function, concept, meaning:

    Five logical studies] (pp. 3863). Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. (Original

    work published 1892.)

    Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition, and logical form. New

    York: Academic Press.

    Geeraerts, D. (1993). Vaguenesss puzzles, polysemys vagaries. Cognitive Lin-

    guistics, 4(3), 223272.

    Gibbs, R.W. (1984). Literal meaning and psychological theory. Cognitive Science, 8,

    275304.

    Gibbs, R.W. (1994). The poetics of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D.G. (1996). Reasoning the fast and frugal way:

    Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 103, 650669.

    Givon, T. (1989). Mind, code, and context: Essays in pragmatics. Hillsdale, NJ:

    Erlbaum.

    Glenberg, A.M., & Robertson, D.A. (2000). Symbol grounding and meaning: A

    comparison of high-dimensional and embodied theories of meaning. Journal of

    Memory and Language, 43, 379401.

    Grice, H.P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J.L. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax

    and semantics: Vol. 3. Speech acts (pp. 4158). New York: Academic Press.

    Hermans, H.J.M. (1996). Voicing the self: From information processing to dialogical

    interchange. Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3150.

    Hermans, H.J.M., & Kempen, H.J.G. (1993). The dialogical self: Meaning as

    movement. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

    Hintikka, J. (1989). Degrees and dimensions of intentionality. In J. Hintikka & M.B.

    Hintikka, The logic of epistemology and the epistemology of logic: Selected essays(pp. 183204). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Hormann, H. (1976). Meinen und Verstehen: Grundzuge einer psychologischen

    Semantik [To mean and to understand: Features of a psychological semantics].

    Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Hormann, H. (1981). Einfuhrung in die Psycholinguistik [Introduction to psycho-

    linguistics]. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Jackendoff, R. (1988). Conceptual semantics. In U. Eco, M. Santambrogio, & P.

    Violi (Eds.), Meaning and mental representations (pp. 8197). Bloomington:

    Indiana University Press.

    Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of language: Brain, meaning, grammar, evolu-tion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    James, W. (1983). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

    University Press. (Original work published 1890.)

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 25

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    23/25

    Joas, H. (1993). Pragmatism and social theory. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago

    Press.

    Johnson, N.F. (1965). The psychological reality of phrase structure rules. Journal of

    Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 4, 469475.

    Johnson, N.F. (1966). On the relationship between sentence structure and the latency

    in generating the sentence. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 5,

    375380.

    Katz, J.J. (1981). Language and other abstract objects. Totowa, NJ: Rowman &

    Littlefield.

    Katz, J.J., & Fodor, J.A. (1963). The structure of a semantic theory. Language, 39,

    170210.

    Kitchener, R.F. (1994). Semantic naturalism: The problem of meaning and natural-

    istic psychology. In W.F. Overton & D.S. Palermo (Eds.), The nature and

    ontogenesis of meaning (pp. 279293). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.),

    Semantics of natural language (pp. 253355). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research pro-

    grammes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of

    knowledge (pp. 91196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about

    the mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and

    its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Landauer, T.K., & Dumais, S.T. (1997). A solution to Platos problem: The latent

    semantic analysis theory of acquisition, induction, and representation of know-

    ledge. Psychological Review, 104, 211240.

    Langacker, R.W. (1987). Foundations of cognitive grammar: Vol. 1. Theoretical

    prerequisites. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Langacker, R.W. (1990). Concept, image, and symbol: The cognitive basis of

    grammar. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Levine, A.T. (1999). Scientific progress and the Fregean legacy. Mind & Language,

    14, 263290.

    Levinson, S.C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Mead, G.H. (1934). Mind, self, and society from the standpoint of a socialbehaviorist. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Miller, G.A., & Isard, S. (1963). Some perceptual consequences of linguistic rules.

    Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 2, 217228.

    Miller, G.A., & McKean, K.O. (1964). A chronometric study of some relations

    between sentences. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16, 297308.

    Minsky, M. (1977). Frame-system theory. In P.N. Johnson-Laird, & P.C. Wason

    (Eds.), Thinking: Readings in cognitive science (pp. 355376). Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

    Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Nuse, R., Groeben, N., Freitag, B., & Schreier, M. (1991). Uber die Erfindung/endes Radikalen Konstruktivismus: Kritische Gegenargumente aus psychologischer

    Sicht [On the invention/s of radical constructivism: Critical counterarguments

    from a psychological point of view]. Weinheim: Deutscher Studien.

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)26

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    24/25

    Olson, D.R. (1970). Language and thought: Aspects of a cognitive theory of

    semantics. Psychological Review, 77, 257273.

    Peirce, C.S. (19311935). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vols. 16; C.

    Hartshorne, & P. Weiss , Eds.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Peirce, C.S. (1958). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce: Vol. 8: Reviews,

    correspondence, and bibliography (A.W. Burks, Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard

    University Press.

    Piaget, J. (1952). La psychologie de lintelligence [The psychology of intelligence]

    (3rd ed.). Paris: Colin.

    Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In H. Putnam (Ed.),Mind, language

    and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 215271). Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Rapaport, W.J. (1998). Understanding understanding: Syntactic, semantics, and

    computational cognition. In J. Toribio & A. Clark (Eds.),Language and meaning

    in cognitive science: Cognitive issues and semantic theory (pp. 7388). New

    York: Garland.

    Rumelhart, D. (1979). Some problems with the notion of literal meanings. In A.

    Ortony (Ed.),Metaphor and thought(2nd ed., pp. 7182). Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Rumelhart, D. (1980). Schemata: The building blocks of cognition. In R. Spiro, B.

    Bruce, & W. Brewer (Eds.), Theoretical issues in reading comprehension (pp.

    3358). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Rudzka-Ostyn, B. (Ed.). (1988). Topics in cognitive linguistics. Amsterdam: John

    Benjamins.

    Ryle, G. (1990). The theory of meaning. In G. Ryle, Collected papers, Vol. 2:

    Collected essays (pp. 407414). Bristol: Thoemes. (Original work published

    1957.)

    Saussure, F. de (1966). Course in general linguistics. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    (Original work published 1916.)

    Schank, R.C., & Abelson, R.P. (1977). Scripts, plans, goals and understanding: An

    inquiry into human knowledge structures. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Searle, J.R. (1989). Speech acts (15th ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

    Press. (Original work published 1969.)

    Searle, J.R. (1994). The problem of consciousness. In R. Casati, B. Smith, & G.White (Eds.), Philosophy and the cognitive sciences (pp. 110). Vienna: Holder-

    Pichler-Tempsky.

    Shank, G. (1998). The extraordinary ordinary powers of abductive reasoning. Theory

    & Psychology, 8, 841860.

    Shanon, B. (1988). Semantic representation of meaning: A critique. Psychological

    Bulletin, 104, 7083.

    Smythe, W.E., & Chow, S.L. (1998). The formal and mental structures of semiotic

    processes. Theory & Psychology, 8, 783803.

    Sperber, D. (1989). Letude anthropologique des representations: Problemes et

    perspectives. In D. Jodelet (Ed.), Les representations sociales (pp. 115130).Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Oxford:

    Blackwell.

    CORNEJO: LINGUISTIC MEANING IN PSYCHOLOGY 27

    at UNIV DE SAO PAULO BIBLIOTECA on August 18, 2010tap.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/http://tap.sagepub.com/
  • 8/22/2019 0916cornejo 2004 Who Says What Words Say

    25/25

    Taylor, J.R. (1995). Linguistic categorization: Prototypes in linguistic theory (2nd

    ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Thompson, E., & Varela, F.J. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and

    consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5, 418425.

    Valsiner, J. (1994). Culture and human development: A co-constructivist perspect-ive. In P. Van Geert & L. Mos (Eds.), Annals of theoretical psychology (Vol. 10,

    pp. 247298). New York: Plenum.

    Valsiner, J., & Van der Veer, R. (2000). The social mind: Construction of the idea.

    Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Varela, F.J., Rosch, E., & Thompson, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive

    sciences and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Volosinov, V.N. (1973).Marxism and the philosophy of language. Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press. (Original work published 1929.)

    Vygotsky, L.S. (1962). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Vygotsky, L.S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychologicalprocesses (M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner, & E. Souberman, Eds.).

    Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Wertheimer, M. (1959). Productive thinking. New York: Harper & Row.

    Wertsch, J.V. (1985). Vygotsky and the social formation of mind. Cambridge, MA:

    Harvard University Press.

    Wertsch, J.V. (1991). Voices in the mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

    Press.

    Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Acknowledgements. Preparation of this manuscript was supported byGrant C-13680/3 from the Fundacion Andes. I would like to thankKatherine Strasser, Luke Moissinac and three anonymous reviewers fortheir comments on an earlier version of this manuscript.

    Carlos Cornejo (PhD, Cologne University, 2000) is Assistant Professorin psychology of language and theoretical psychology at the PontificiaUniversidad Catolica de Chile. His research interests include theoreticaland empirical aspects of meaning construction/processing, figurative lan-guage and pragmatism in psychology. Address: Escuela de Psicologa, P.Universidad Catolica de Chile, Vicuna Mackenna 4860, Santiago, Chile.[[email protected]]

    THEORY & PSYCHOLOGY 14(1)28