accordion effect

16
What Is the Accordion Effect? Author(s): Michael E. Bratman Source: The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 10, No. 1/2 (Jan., 2006), pp. 5-19 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25115848 . Accessed: 22/12/2013 08:40 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: lamaildierica9188

Post on 04-Oct-2015

49 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

DESCRIPTION

This paper describes the discussion in action theory about the accordion effect.

TRANSCRIPT

  • What Is the Accordion Effect?Author(s): Michael E. BratmanSource: The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 10, No. 1/2 (Jan., 2006), pp. 5-19Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25115848 .Accessed: 22/12/2013 08:40

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Ethics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springerhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/25115848?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT?

    (Received 13 September 2004; accepted 13 September 2004)

    ABSTRACT. In "Action and Responsibility," Joel Feinberg pointed to an im

    portant idea to which he gave the label "the accordion effect." Feinberg's discussion

    of this idea is of interest on its own, but it is also of interest because of its interaction

    with his critique, in his "Causing Voluntary Actions," of a much discussed view of

    H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honor? that Feinberg labels the "voluntary intervention

    principle." In this essay I reflect on what the accordion effect is supposed by Feinberg to be, on differences between Feinberg's understanding of this idea and that of

    Donald Davidson, and on the interaction between Feinberg's discussion of the ac

    cordion effect and his critique of the voluntary intervention principle.

    KEY WORDS: accordion effect, action, agency, John Atwell, causation, Donald

    Davidson, Joel Feinberg, H. L. A. Hart, A. M. Honor?, Keith Lehrer, responsibility,

    transitivity of causation, voluntary intervention principle

    In an important and influential essay, "Action and Responsibility," Joel Feinberg pointed to a natural idea, one to which he gave the

    label "the accordion effect."1 Feinberg's discussion of this idea is of

    interest on its own; but it is also of interest because of its interaction

    with his critique, in his "Causing Voluntary Actions," of a much

    discussed view of H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honor? that Feinberg there labels the "voluntary intervention principle."2 In the present

    1 Joel Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (Princeton: Princeton University Press,

    1970), pp. 119-151. Prior to Feinberg's essay related ideas were famously discussed

    in G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1959), and in Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980),

    pp. 3-19. A focus of this earlier literature was on metaphysical issues of the indi

    viduation of action, issues that are not central to Feinberg's concerns. 2 Joel Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, pp. 152-186, where Feinberg discusses H. L.

    A. Hart and A. M. Honor?, Causation in the Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). The voluntary intervention principle is characterized by Feinberg by way of a

    quotation from Hart and Honor?: "the free, deliberate and informed act or omission

    of a human being, intended to produce the consequence which is in fact produced,

    negatives causal connection" (quoted in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 153).

    The Journal of Ethics (2006) 10: 5-19 ? Springer 2006 DOI 10.1007/sl0892-005-4589-3

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 6 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    essay I want to reflect on what the accordion effect is supposed by

    Feinberg to be, and on the interaction between Feinberg's discussion

    of the accordion effect and his critique of the voluntary intervention

    principle. This will also lead to a discussion of Donald Davidson's

    understanding of and use of what he takes to be the accordion effect.

    I hope in these ways to shed some light on a web of issues about

    human agency that are at the intersection of these two wonderful

    essays by Feinberg. In "Action and Responsibility," Feinberg notes that sometimes in

    saying that: "Smith is responsible for X, we can mean simply that Xis

    the result of what Smith did or, in equivalent terms, that Smith did

    something (say, turned the knob) and thereby caused X (the door's

    opening) to happen."3 Feinberg calls such a claim that "Smith did

    something ... and thereby caused X ... to happen" an ascription of

    causal responsibility to Smith. Feinberg then later goes on to note

    that: "we can usually replace any ascription of causal responsibility to

    a person by an ascription of agency or authorship."4 And he calls this

    form of replacement of an ascription of causal responsibility by an

    ascription of agency or authorship "the accordion effect." He then

    goes on to formulate this idea as follows:

    We can, if we wish, inflate our conception of an action to include one of its effects,

    and more often than not our language obliges us by providing a relatively complex

    word for the purpose. Instead of saying that Peter did A (a relatively simple act) and thereby caused X in Y, we might say something of the form "Peter X-ed Y"; in

    stead of "Peter opened the door causing Paul to be startled," "Peter startled Paul."

    Ascriptions of causal responsibility, then, are often precisely equivalent to ...

    ascriptions of causal agency.5

    Does the accordion effect depend on whether, as a matter of

    contingent fact, our language "obliges us" and has an appropriate causal verb - for example, "startle"? The first sentence in the preceding

    quotation may suggest that this is not necessary, though it is common.

    The details of this principle change a bit in the Second Edition of Causation in the Law (1985) at p. 136 (and see note 23). These changes do not touch my present discussion, however. And in this Second Edition Hart and Honor? do not explicitly

    respond to Feinberg's earlier challenge. That said, when I refer to Causation in the

    Law I will refer to the Second Edition. 3

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 130. 4

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 134. 5

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 134.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 7

    The second sentence, in contrast, formulates the underlying principle in a way that assumes there is such a verb. Which is it?

    To see the point consider a case Feinberg discusses in his

    "Rejoinder" at the end of "Causing Voluntary Actions:"

    I recently observed two young boys teasing a small child by causing him to giggle uncontrollably. Finally, one turned to the other and said (improperly): "We'd bet

    ter quit or we'll laugh him to death." The boy wanted a transitive verb that could

    be used interchangeably with "causing another to laugh"; but our language does

    not carry such a word in stock, there being little demand for it.6

    I will put aside here the point that the agent of the teasing seems to be a

    joint agent, whereas Feinberg's focus is on individual agents. What is

    important here is that the relevant agent does, according to Feinberg,

    perform the act of causing another to laugh; but there is in English no

    specific causal verb that corresponds to "causing to laugh" in the way that "startle" corresponds to "causing to be startled."

    Is this a case of the accordion effect or not? If the accordion effect

    requires that there is in fact a relevant, specific causal verb - one

    analogous to "startle" - then this is not a case of the accordion effect (at

    least in English). But in this case Feinberg does grant that the generic causal verb "causing X" does apply: the agent causes the laughter.

    Using this generic causal verb we do have a natural transition from

    saying "agent does something that causes X" to saying "agent causes

    X." Is this transition an instance of the accordion effect or not?

    Well, one philosopher who has made substantial use of this idea

    from Feinberg is Davidson, who explores the idea that "we may take

    the accordion effect as a mark of agency."7 What, according to

    Davidson, is the accordion effect? Does it require that a specific causal verb apply to the case, or is it only about the inference from

    the fact that a person's action causes an upshot to the claim that that

    person caused that upshot? The answer is: the latter. On Davidson's

    formulation of the accordion effect "an agent causes what his actions

    cause."8 Since the agent in Feinberg's laughter case is seen by

    6 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 184.

    7 Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, p. 54. One of Davidson's

    concerns is with the connection of the accordion effect to issues about the individ

    uation of actions (see pp. 55-59), but these are matters we can put to one side here.

    Our concerns here are with the truth of various statements about action and

    responsibility, not directly with the underlying principles of individuation. 8

    Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, p. 53.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    Feinberg as causing what his actions cause -

    namely, laughter -

    this

    case is an instance of the accordion effect as understood by Davidson, even in the absence of a specific causal verb that applies.

    Let us call this principle from Davidson - that "an agent causes

    what his actions cause" -principle Z>, Davidson identifies this as the

    principle associated with the accordion effect. I will return later to the

    use to which Davidson wants to put this principle. Here I want to

    note that, while Davidson seems to think he is following Feinberg

    here, and - as I have noted - there are indications in Feinberg's

    remarks that do indeed support this reading - this is not, in the end,

    Feinberg's understanding of the accordion effect.

    This is clear when we look at the remarks Feinberg goes on to make, in "Action and Responsibility," about "exceptions to the rule that

    causal ascriptions to human agency can be translated into ascriptions of causal agency"9

    - where, I take it, this is the rule associated by

    Feinberg with the accordion effect. Feinberg cites two exceptions. Here

    is the first: "It may happen, as a purely contingent matter of fact, that

    there is no single action word in the language that is precisely

    equivalent to a given causal phrase."10 So, for example, there is no verb

    "to laugh someone." But this is no exception to the rule associated with

    the accordion effect as understood by Davidson. The absence of an

    appropriate, specific causal verb in the language has no impact on

    principle D, since that principle is couched in terms of the generic

    "Agent causes upshot." In the present case, for example, the agent does

    cause laughter, though we have no specific causal verb to apply here.

    Turn now to Feinberg's second exception. In these cases "transitive

    verbs of action are available to tempt us, but they cannot be

    substituted for straightforward causal idioms without distortion of

    sense. Substitution commonly fails in cases of interpersonal causation - where one person, whether by accident or design, causes another

    person to act."11 In Feinberg's example that follows, A makes a

    remark that causes B to wiggle his finger. Feinberg says that even

    though 'A's remark causes B to move his finger, "we cannot say that

    [A] moved the finger himself. Here is an instance, then, where 'causing to move' is not the same as 'moving.'"12 In the case, then, Feinberg

    supposes that

    9 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135.

    10 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135.

    11 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135.

    12 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 9

    (i) A does something that causes B to move his finger, and that

    (ii) A causes B to move his finger;

    but, nevertheless, it is not true that

    (iii) A moves B's finger.

    The transition from (i) to (ii) is an instance of principle D\ but it is the failure in the transition to (iii) that is cited as a breakdown in the accordion effect, as Feinberg is understanding it.

    I think it is clear, then, that Feinberg is not understanding the

    accordion effect as the Davidsonian idea that "an agent causes what his

    actions cause." As Feinberg understands it, rather, the accordion effect

    involves the application of a specific causal verb. If A does something that causes X, but there is no specific causal verb associated with

    causing X, then even though A causes X, the case is an exception to the

    accordion effect, as understood by Feinberg. And, in contrast with

    principle Z>, Feinberg does not want to claim that the principle

    underlying the accordion effect is without exceptions; the claim is only that some such principle captures common and important cases.

    What is the Feinbergian principle here? Well, it is pretty much

    what Feinberg (after flirting with something closer to principle D) says it is: "Instead of saying that Peter did A (a relatively simple act) and thereby caused X'm F, we might say something of the form Teter

    X-Qd F; instead of Teter opened the door causing Paul to be

    startled,' Teter startled Paul.'"

    We can put it this way: When an agent acts and his act causes some

    change, X, in something, F, there is frequently (though not always) a

    specific, transitive causal verb, Cx, associated with causing that upshot in F, such that it is true that the agent C^-ed F When there is such a

    causal verb such that it is true that A C^-ed F, we have an instance of the

    accordion effect. But sometimes an agent will act in ways that result in

    change X in F, and yet the language does not oblige with a specific causal verb that applies. In these latter cases we do not have an instance

    of the accordion effect, as Feinberg understands it.

    Call this principle F. Principle F concerns cases in which "causal

    ascriptions to human agency" are "translated into ascriptions of causal

    agency" by way of a specific causal verb. Principle Fdoes not claim there

    is always an appropriate causal verb that applies; indeed, Feinberg is at

    pains to insist that this is not so. Principle F also involves a language

    relativity that is absent from principle D.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 10 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    I do not claim that Feinberg would reject principle Z>, only that

    principle D is not the principle associated with his understanding of the

    accordion effect. Indeed, when Feinberg is discussing causal ascriptions to human agency, and not when he is focusing on the transition from

    those ascriptions to ascriptions of causal agency, he seems to take

    principle D for granted: recall his remark that "Xis the result of what

    Smith did" is equivalent to "Smith did something... and thereby caused

    X"13 The point I want to make is that Feinberg sees the accordion

    effect not in terms of principle D but, rather, as involving a transition

    to an ascription of causal agency in terms of a specific causal verb. We

    do not have an instance of the Feinbergian accordion effect if we make

    a transition simply to an ascription of "agent causes upshot." Indeed, so long as we remain with that generic causal verb, we remain, as

    Feinberg sees it, in the domain of "causal ascriptions to human agency" rather than the domain of "ascriptions of causal agency."

    I do not say this is the most natural reading of talk of "ascriptions of causal agency"

    - indeed, I find it artificial. It does seem to me

    13 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 130. I take it that in saying "thereby caused

    X" Feinberg is saying that Smith caused X. Again, in his discussion of the person

    who makes a remark and thereby causes another to move his finger Feinberg seems

    to take for granted this equivalence. Here is the full passage: "Dr. Ortho, by making

    certain learned remarks about the musculature of the forearm, may cause Humphrey

    thoughtfully to wiggle his finger. Even though it would be correct to say that Dr. Ortho's remark caused Humphrey to move his finger, we cannot say that Dr. Ortho

    moved the finger himself (Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135). Would Hart and Honor? accept principle Z>? On the one hand, they characterize "attributive inqui

    ries" as concerned with whether a "harm can be attributed to the defendant's action

    as its consequence, or whether he can properly be said to have caused it" (Hart and

    Honor?, Causation in the Law, 1985, Second Edition, p. 24). And they here seem to

    see these as two formulations of the same query, though it is not completely clear.

    Again, on p. 74 of the Second Edition they move easily from the issue of identifying an "action to be ranked the cause" to the issue of whether "B has caused the harm

    and A has not," where A and B are agents, not actions.

    On the other hand, in remarks added in the 1985 Second Edition, Hart and Honor?

    say that "a causal relation of some sort may indeed be established between the conduct

    of the person who supplies the advice or means and the death of the victim.... But the

    fact that what is here unearthed is not the central type of causal relationship but

    something more tenuous is marked by the fact that we would not happily say that the

    accomplice had either 'caused' the death or 'caused' the prisoner to kill" (Second

    Edition, pp. 42-43; the corresponding passage, without these remarks, is in the First

    Edition of Causation in the Law, at p. 40). Here they seem to contrast what the conduct

    causes with what the accomplice himself causes. So here they seem to pull back from

    principle D. In any case, in my discussion below I consider the possibility that one of the

    insights we should glean from Hart and Honor? involves a challenge to this principle.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 11

    natural to see "Jones caused her laughter" as an ascription of causal

    agency to Jones even in the absence of a transitive verb "to laugh someone." Davidson would, I think, agree. He would, I think, see

    principle D as a principle that characterizes a transition from causal

    ascriptions to human agency to ascriptions of causal agency in terms

    of the generic "agent causes upshot" But I think that even though

    Feinberg accepts principle D, he does not see this principle in this way as a principle about a transition to an ascription of causal agency. This

    is because Feinberg -

    idiosyncratically, I think - does not see a generic

    ascription of "agent causes upshot" as yet in the domain of an

    ascription of causal agency. Or anyway, this limitation in talk of

    ascriptions of causal agency is needed to make the most sense of what

    Feinberg says. This also helps us understand what Feinberg goes on to say when, in

    this paper, he turns to Hart and Honor?. Feinberg notes that Hart and

    Honor? argue that "a fully voluntary act 'negatives' causal connection

    between an earlier causal factor and some upshot."14 This is the idea

    that Feinberg, in "Causing Voluntary Actions," labels the "voluntary intervention principle." Reflecting on his example in which A's remark

    seems to cause B to move his finger, Feinberg says that this idea from

    Hart and Honor? is incorrect insofar as it denies that B's action was

    caused by A's remark.15 Indeed, Feinberg thinks, I take it, that A's

    action (his remark) causes the movement of B's finger, and that this is

    contrary to Hart and Honor?'s view. But Feinberg also says that in the

    example the intervention of the voluntary act on the part of B

    "precludes the extension of causal agency."16 For him to think this, even though he thinks that, despite that intervention, A causes B to

    move his finger, Feinberg must be thinking of the "extension of causal

    agency" as requiring that a specific causal verb - in this case, the

    transitive verb "to move something" -

    applies. Since this is supposed to be an exception to the accordion effect he is, again, understanding the accordion effect in terms of principle F9 and not in terms simply of

    principle D.

    Again, this also helps us understand Feinberg's reply in his

    "Rejoinder," appended to "Causing Voluntary Actions," to Keith

    14 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135.

    15 Though, strictly speaking, what is challenged at this point in the discussion is

    the closely related idea that, in "Causing Voluntary Actions," Feinberg labels the

    "first cause principle" (see below). In my next sentence I note the challenge to the

    voluntary intervention principle, strictly speaking. 16

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 135.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 12 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    Lehrer's comments on Feinberg's original paper. One of the purported

    counter-examples to the voluntary intervention principle that Fein

    berg sketches in his original paper involves someone I will call

    "lago."17 lago tells a "coldly jealous husband" about his wife's love

    affair with Horner, hoping thereby to get the husband to kill Horner.

    After due consideration, the husband does indeed shoot and kill

    Horner. The husband's killing is free and deliberate, even though, as

    Feinberg sees it, caused by Iago's action. So this is, Feinberg alleges, a

    violation of a principle from Hart and Honor? that precludes the

    causation of fully voluntary action, a principle Feinberg labels "the

    first cause principle."18 Further, since we "might well judge that

    the cause of Horner's death was [Iago's] disclosure of the facts to the

    cuckolded husband"19 this is also, at least potentially, a violation of

    the voluntary intervention principle. Or so Feinberg argues. Lehrer is unconvinced: "it is quite clear that the death of Horner is

    to be attributed to the husband ... and to no one else."20 Feinberg

    replies: "I do not see how the facts of the case would logically foreclose the judgment that the cause of Horner's death was [Iago's]

    spilling the beans or that the death is to be attributed jointly to [lago and the husband]."21 But Feinberg goes on to concede that in

    17 The example is in Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 157. It occurs as one of a

    quartet of purported counter examples. A fifth purported counter example is in the

    "Rejoinder" at p. 177. As Feinberg notes, Hart and Honor? acknowledge two

    general lines of qualification to the voluntary intervention principle [see Hart and

    Honor?, Causation in the Law (Second Edition), p. 75]. However, Feinberg claims

    that his counter-examples do not fit into either of these two categories. 18

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 152. Feinberg describes this principle by

    quoting from an earlier essay of Hart and Honor? where they say that "a [free and

    deliberate] human action is never regarded as itself caused" (this quote appears in

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 152). Hart and Honor?, Causation in the Law, is a

    bit more nuanced than suggested in this quotation from the earlier essay (see e.g.,

    pp. 42-43 in the Second Edition). But these are not matters we need to discuss here. 19

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 157. 20

    Keith Lehrer, "Comments," in W. H. Capit?n and D. D. Merrill (eds.),

    Metaphysics and Explanation (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966), pp. 52-53. Let me note that one of Lehrer's criticisms is that in his original discussion

    Feinberg did not do justice to the point that Hart and Honor? were interested

    primarily in attributive causal statements, not in explanatory causal statements.

    Feinberg concedes the point, but claims that his counter examples challenge Hart

    and Honor?'s principles even interpreted explicitly as principles about attributive

    causal statements. 21

    Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 183. Feinberg presumably intends a dis

    tributive reading, not a shared agency reading of "jointly."

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 13

    supposing that the death might be attributed to lago he is not making a claim of "causal agency," he is only pointing to a "causal

    citation."22 This concession would make no sense if "lago caused the

    death" were a claim of "causal agency." After all, Feinberg explicitly

    envisages that we might correctly judge that "the cause of Horner's

    death was [Iago's] spilling the beans." And, as we have seen, Feinberg does accept principle D (though not in the same spirit as Davidson), and so in this case the inference to "lago caused the death." So

    Feinberg must be thinking that a claim of causal agency requires the

    application of a specific causal verb - in this case, say, shooting

    Horner or, perhaps, killing Horner. And Feinberg is noting that he

    might be right about the possibility that lago causes the death even if

    no such specific causal verb applies. lago, after all, certainly does not

    shoot Horner, and many will find it strained to say he kills Horner.

    This does not mean that, indeed, no such specific causal verb does

    apply; it only means that Feinberg's challenge to Hart and Honor?, and his reply to Lehrer, is seen by him as independent of this issue, even though Feinberg also holds that if indeed there is no such

    specific causal verb that applies, the case is an exception to the

    accordion effect.

    Let us step back a bit. Feinberg's main challenge to the voluntary intervention principle is by way of purported counter-examples. If we

    agree that these counter-examples work - and I myself find them

    largely persuasive - then we must conclude that sometimes a

    voluntary intervention does not negative relevant causal attributions.

    It does not follow from this, however, that the existence of a

    voluntary intervention does not in some cases block, or help block, the casual attribution.

    Feinberg himself seems unwilling to say this, however, since he

    offers a substitute for the voluntary intervention principle: "the more

    expectable human behavior is, whether voluntary or not, the less likely it is to 'negative causal connection."22. But we could acknowledge the

    significance of expectability without dismissing the voluntariness of

    an intervention as of no significance at all to relevant causal

    attribution. One way to read Lehrer is to see him as suggesting that at

    least in some cases along these lines the fact that the husband acts

    fully voluntarily and deliberately supports the judgment that it is the

    husband, and not lago, who causes Horner's death. After all, even

    22 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 184.

    23 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 166.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 14 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    Feinberg grants that we will sometimes make this causal attribution

    to the husband and not to lago.24 And we can see Lehrer as

    suggesting that when we do this it can be at least in part because of

    the fact that the husband's relevant acts are voluntary and deliberate

    and they intervene between Iago's acts and the death. We can reason

    in this way even if we are convinced by Feinberg that the voluntary intervention principle errors in supposing that such a voluntary and

    deliberate intervention always blocks the causal attribution.

    Indeed, Hart and Honor? point to a very general ground for such

    reasoning:

    [Our] sense of respect for ourselves and others as distinct persons would be much

    weakened, if not dissolved, if we could not think of ourselves as separate authors

    of the changes we make in the world. If we had to share the authorship of such

    changes with numerous prior agents, of whom it could be said that, had they not

    acted as they did, we should not have been able to bring about the change, we

    could no longer think of ourselves as separate authors in the way we now do.25

    We can agree with Feinberg that his counter-examples show that the

    voluntary intervention principle errs in its generality, while still

    seeing, in these remarks from Hart and Honor?, a potential ground for the idea that the voluntariness of an intervention can sometimes

    matter to a causal attribution.

    Consider, then, the idea that the voluntariness of an intervention

    can block or help block, not only the applicability of a specific causal

    verb (which Feinberg himself emphasizes), but also, in some cases, a

    causal attribution by way of the generic "Agent causes upshot." As I

    have said, this is compatible with Feinberg's example-driven criticism

    of the voluntary intervention principle, since this criticism is that this

    principle errs in its generality. Indeed, this idea is to some extent in

    the spirit of Feinberg's acceptance of the idea that certain causal

    verbs impose conditions on causal process that are violated by

    voluntary interventions - the idea now is just that this can sometimes

    be true even for the generic causal verb "Agent causes upshot." And

    this idea is also compatible with Feinberg's principle F, since that

    principle only says that there are common cases involving a

    Feinbergian accordion characterized in terms of the application of

    a specific causal verb. But since principle D is, like Hart and Honor?'s

    24 Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, p. 184.

    25 Hart and Honor?, Causation in the Law (Second Edition), pp. lxxx-lxxxi.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 15

    voluntary intervention principle, a purportedly general principle, it

    may be threatened by this idea.

    Consider the following sequence of thoughts:

    (1) lago performs voluntary action A.

    (2) The husband performs voluntary action B.

    (3) B is a causal consequence of A.

    (4) B causes Horner's death.

    (5) A causes Horner's death, (from (3), (4), and the transitivity of causality)

    (6) lago causes Horner's death (from (1), (5), and principle D)

    We are taking (1), (2), and (4) as given. If we suppose that there can

    be cases in which we would want to say that it is the husband, and not

    lago, who causes the death, where should we stop the chain of

    reasoning in such cases?

    Well, the first cause principle would block (3); but Feinberg has

    given us good reason to reject that as a general principle. Granted, we

    might try to say that, even though the first cause principle is not in

    general true, this causal claim [namely, a version of (3)] fails whenever

    we think that the agent of the earlier act does not herself cause the

    later upshot [that is, whenever we reject a version of (6)]. But this

    seems to me unlikely to work as a general explanation of our

    unwillingness to say, in such cases of voluntary intervention, that the

    agent of the earlier act causes the later upshot. It seems clear to me, for example, (though it would probably not be clear to Hart and

    Honor?, given their tendency to insist on a fairly sharp divide

    between reasons and causes) that Iago's remarks cause the husband's

    shooting of Horner. What remains unclear is whether lago causes

    Horner's death or whether we should say, instead, that the husband, and not lago, causes the death.

    Again, the transitivity of causation is a fairly basic idea, one not to

    be given up lightly; so there would be a high price to pay if we were to

    try to stop the inference from (3) and (4) to (5). There is, then, pressure, if we do not want to end up at (6), to seek to qualify

    principle D and not to accept it in its present form.

    Davidson saw this clearly. In a footnote he writes:

    Suppose Jones intentionally causes Smith intentionally to shoot Clifford to death. We certainly won't conclude that Jones shot Clifford ... Still [principle D] is correct

    provided we can go from 'Jones's action caused Clifford's death' to 'Jones caused

    Clifford's death'. There will, of course, be a conflict if we deny that both Jones and

    Smith ... could be said to have caused Clifford's death, and at the same time affirm

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 16 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    the transitivity of causality. We could however, preserve [principle D] in the face of a

    denial that under the circumstances Jones could be said to have caused Clifford's

    death by saying that under the circumstances the transitivity of causality also breaks

    down.26

    So Davidson suggests that if we are unwilling to say that Jones causes

    the death, we nevertheless defend principle D by giving up on the

    transitivity of causation and in that way blocking the move to a

    version of (5). But, as I have said, abandoning the transitivity of

    causation is a high price to pay. So perhaps we should seek a more

    qualified version of principle D. And the point to emphasize is that

    we could do this while holding onto both Feinberg's example-based

    rejection of the voluntary intervention principle, and Feinberg's version of the accordion effect, principle F. The claims that are most

    central to these two papers of Feinberg do not, in the end, require

    Feinberg to defend principle D in its full generality, and there may well be reason not to.

    It may be that Feinberg does not consider this possibility because

    he sees the move from "Agent's act causes upshot" to "Agent causes

    upshot" as remaining within the domain of causal ascription to

    human agency, rather than as a transition to an ascription of causal

    agency. This is the - to my mind, idiosyncratic

    - feature of Feinberg's discussion that I highlighted earlier. But if we take seriously the

    natural idea that to say that lago caused the death is to ascribe causal

    agency to lago, then principle D will not seem, as it apparently does

    to Feinberg, trivial (though different from the accordion effect); and

    considerations from Hart and Honor? may lead us to seek to qualify

    principle D even while agreeing with Feinberg that the voluntary intervention principle is overly general in its claims.

    John Atwell has also challenged what I am calling principle D?1

    Atwell sees that this principle is not the same as Feinberg's accordion

    effect (though I have offered a different treatment of that accordion

    effect than does Atwell).28 What I call principle D Atwell calls

    Feinberg's "sub-thesis," and he argues against it by way of an example:

    26 Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, pp. 53-54n. 27 John E. Atwell, "The Accordion Effect Thesis," The Philosophical Quarterly 19

    (1969), pp. 337-342. 28

    As I see it, Atwell's criticisms of Feinberg's accordion effect do not take suf

    ficient account of Feinberg's explicit remarks about the exceptions to the accordion

    effect. This is a separate matter, though, from Atwell's discussion of what I have

    called principle D.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 17

    "Brown was partially paralyzed, and had been for years. During that

    long trying period Mrs. Brown faithfully cared for him. One day, with

    all the strength he could muster, Brown managed a faint smile of

    gratitude; but, as the fates would have it, Mrs. Brown was so

    overwhelmed with joy that she suffered a heart attack and died."29

    Since the smiling caused the death it follows, according to principle Z), that Mr. Brown caused Mrs. Brown's death. But to say this, says

    Atwell, is to make "a minimal suggestion that Brown is somehow at

    fault."30 Since Brown is in no way at fault, we should balk at saying that Brown caused the death. So we should not accept the "sub-thesis"

    (that is, principle D). While Atwell deserves credit for explicitly raising the question of

    whether the "sub-thesis" is true, I do not find his purported counter

    example convincing. I think we are used to saying "You caused this

    very bad thing, but through no fault of your own, and this does not

    mean you are a bad person or at fault." This can be the stuff of

    tragedies; but tragedies happen. As I see it, it is when another agent voluntarily intervenes between

    the action and the upshot that we sometimes have the potential for a

    violation of principle D - which is not, of course, to say that the

    voluntary intervention always blocks the causal attribution to the

    agent of the earlier action.31 We can learn this lesson from Hart and

    Honor? while agreeing with Feinberg that the voluntary intervention

    principle errs in its generality. These considerations interact with the use to which Davidson aims

    to put the accordion effect (as he understands it). Recall that

    Davidson wants to "take the accordion effect as a mark of agency." For Davidson this means that the applicability of principle D is a

    mark of agency: those "events in the life of a person"32 whose causal

    upshots are causally attributed to the agent, and so conform to

    principle D, are actions of that person. As Davidson says, the idea is

    29 Atwell, "The Accordion Effect Thesis," p. 341.

    30 Atwell, "The Accordion Effect Thesis," p. 341.

    31 Atwell's discussion is limited to a consideration of Feinberg's "Action and

    Responsibility." He does not address the discussion of voluntary interventions in

    "Causing Voluntary Actions." As I see it, it is in these issues about the impact of

    voluntary interventions that we find a more persuasive challenge to principle D. This

    is part of my general strategy of seeking a deeper understanding of the accordion

    effect and related matters by exploring interactions with the voluntary intervention

    principle and with Feinberg's criticisms of that principle. 32

    Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, p. 43.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 18 MICHAEL E. BRATMAN

    that "[I]t is a way of inquiring whether an event is a case of agency to

    ask whether we can attribute its effects to a person."33 Without asking whether this is going to work in the end, we can say that to pursue this

    idea without circularity we had better not use the very idea of action or

    agency in the relevant mark of agency.34 So if we tried to substitute for

    principle D something roughly along the lines of principle

    D'. If there is no relevant voluntary intervention of a certain sort, an agent causes

    what his actions cause,

    we would not be in a position to appeal to this substitute principle to get a non-circular mark of agency. This is because the very idea of agency is

    built into the appeal, in the substitute principle, to voluntary intervention. And it may be that a concern to avoid such circularity

    helped support Davidson's apparent inclination to defend principle D

    even if it meant allowing for intransitivities in causation.35 But if we give

    up this use of a substitute for principle D as, a mark of agency, we are

    33 Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, p. 54

    34 Davidson does say that the accordion effect is "a mark of actions but yields no

    analysis of agency" (Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, p. 60). So perhaps he

    would say that concerns of circularity arise only for an "analysis," not for a "mark"

    of agency. But this seems to me strained, and it does seem to me that Davidson's

    apparent use of the accordion effect argues against invoking the very idea of agency

    in the content of the principle in terms of which we understand that effect. 35

    I only say "may," because I find Davidson's considered view here difficult to

    interpret. One issue has already been raised in the previous note. Another issue is just

    how committed Davidson was to this use of the accordion effect. He concludes the

    section of this paper in which he has focused on the accordion effect as follows: "The

    accordion effect is interesting because it shows that we treat the consequences of actions

    differently from the way we treat the consequences of other events.... But as a criterion

    [the accordion effect] can hardly be counted as satisfactory: it works for some cases

    only, and of course it gives no clue as to what makes a primitive action an action"

    (Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, p. 55). I am unsure which cases Davidson has

    in mind when he says this "works for some cases only," but it does seem that he is here

    thinking of the "primitive" actions he goes on to mention. The idea of a "primitive"

    action is that of an action one performs not by performing some other action. Apparent

    examples are moving one's hand (and thereby...). Davidson, of course, has a distinctive

    view about the individuation of actions and primitive actions, but we do not need to

    consider these matters here. What is puzzling here, I think, is why Davidson thinks that

    the apparent fact that an agent causes what her primitive actions cause cannot explain

    why a primitive action is an action (though of course it cannot explain why it is

    primitive). But I will not try to sort this out here.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • WHAT IS THE ACCORDION EFFECT? 19

    not obliged in this way to defend an unqualified version of principle D.

    And, as we have seen, there may be good reason not to.36

    Department of Philosophy

    Stanford University

    Stanford, CA 94305 USA E-mail: [email protected]

    36 Thanks to Scott Shapiro for helpful conversation and to John Martin Fischer for helpful comments on an earlier draft. This essay was written while I was a Fellow

    at the Center for Advanced Study in Behavioral Sciences. I am grateful for financial

    support provided by the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation. I dedicate this essay to the

    memory of Joel Feinberg, teacher and friend.

    This content downloaded from 130.251.200.3 on Sun, 22 Dec 2013 08:40:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    Article Contentsp. [5]p. 6p. 7p. 8p. 9p. 10p. 11p. 12p. 13p. 14p. 15p. 16p. 17p. 18p. 19

    Issue Table of ContentsThe Journal of Ethics, Vol. 10, No. 1/2 (Jan., 2006), pp. 1-210Volume InformationEditor's Introduction [pp. 3-4]What Is the Accordion Effect? [pp. 5-19]Taking Law Seriously: Starting Points of the Hart/Devlin Debate [pp. 21-51]"Volenti" Goes to Market [pp. 53-74]Is That All There Is? [pp. 75-106]The Cards That Are Dealt You [pp. 107-129]The Philosophy of Joel Feinberg [pp. 131-191, 2]Review: Review Essay on the Roots of Evil [pp. 193-199]Bibliography of Joel Feinberg [pp. 201-204]Back Matter