lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective · 2016-06-07 · lattice paths from an...

Post on 27-Jul-2020

2 Views

Category:

Documents

0 Downloads

Preview:

Click to see full reader

TRANSCRIPT

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

L. Ferrari

Dipartimento di Matematica e Informatica, Universita degli Studi di Firenze,Viale Morgagni 65, 50134 Firenze, Italy

luca.ferrari@unifi.it

GASCom 2016,Bastia, 2-4 June 2016

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Outline

Table of contents IIntroduction

PathsPosetsOutline of the talk

Lattices of paths

Distributive lattice structureRepresentationsThe Euler Characteristic

Unimodality

Heyting algebra structureDyck algebrasThe logic of subintervalsPosets of intervalsOpen problems

Counting chains in lattices of pathsChains in Dyck latticesSaturated chains of length 1

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Outline

Table of contents IISaturated chains in Dyck latticesOpen problems

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableauxThe case of Schroder pathsThe poset of Schroder partitionsAn RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableauxAn alternative presentation of Schroder tableauxFurther work

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posetsDyck latticesMotzkin (and Schroder) latticesGrand-Dyck lattices

The notion of path patternThe Dyck pattern poset(Principal) pattern avoiding classesThe Mobius functionOpen problems

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Paths

Paths

A class of paths is the set of all paths starting at the origin of a fixedCartesian coordinate system, ending on the x-axis, never going below thex-axis, and using only a prescribed set of steps.

E.g.: Dyck paths tU,Du.

Motzkin paths tU,H,Du.

Schroder paths tU,H2,Du.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Paths

Paths

A class of paths is the set of all paths starting at the origin of a fixedCartesian coordinate system, ending on the x-axis, never going below thex-axis, and using only a prescribed set of steps.

E.g.: Dyck paths tU,Du.

Motzkin paths tU,H,Du.

Schroder paths tU,H2,Du.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Paths

Grand paths

Given a class of paths, the associated class of Grand paths is defined inthe same way, except for the fact that we are allowed to go below thex-axis.

E.g.: Grand Dyck paths

Grand Motzkin paths

Grand Schroder paths

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Paths

Grand paths

Given a class of paths, the associated class of Grand paths is defined inthe same way, except for the fact that we are allowed to go below thex-axis.

E.g.: Grand Dyck paths

Grand Motzkin paths

Grand Schroder paths

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of paths

Any class of (Grand) paths of the same length can be endowed with anatural partial order structure, by declaring P ¤ Q when P lies weaklybelow Q in the usual two-dimensional drawing of paths.

Below are depicted the Hasse diagrams of the lattices of Dyck paths ofsemilength 3, Motzkin paths of length 4 and Schroder paths ofsemilength 2, respectively.

D3 M4 S2

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of paths

Any class of (Grand) paths of the same length can be endowed with anatural partial order structure, by declaring P ¤ Q when P lies weaklybelow Q in the usual two-dimensional drawing of paths.

Below are depicted the Hasse diagrams of the lattices of Dyck paths ofsemilength 3, Motzkin paths of length 4 and Schroder paths ofsemilength 2, respectively.

D3 M4 S2

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of paths

Any class of (Grand) paths of the same length can be endowed with anatural partial order structure, by declaring P ¤ Q when P lies weaklybelow Q in the usual two-dimensional drawing of paths.

Below are depicted the Hasse diagrams of the lattices of Dyck paths ofsemilength 3, Motzkin paths of length 4 and Schroder paths ofsemilength 2, respectively.

D3 M4 S2

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of pathsIn some cases, this partial order has already appeared in some differentform. For instance, in the Dyck case there is an alternative description interms of Young lattices (precisely, Dyck posets are order-isomorphic tothe Young lattices of staircase partitions).

Another instance of these posets (which are actually lattices) appears ina paper by Stanley (1975), and for this reason they are called Stanleylattices by Bernardi (2009). Moreover, Cautis and Jackson (2003) find anappearance of Dyck posets in the study of the matrix of chromatic joins.

In the last decade, Dyck posets have been investigated (directly orindirectly) by several authors (Sapounakis, Tasoulas, Tsikouras (2006),Santocanale (2007), Owczarek, Prellberg (2012), Barnabei, Bonetti,Silimbani (2013), Braun, Browder, Klee (2013), Muhle (2013,2014,2015),Blanco, Petersen (2014), Gobet, Williams (2016),...).

However, it does not seem that this approach has ever been tried forlattice paths in general. At any rate, I believe that the language of latticepaths gives a geometric flavor to the subject which allows to expressseveral properties in a more fascinating way.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of pathsIn some cases, this partial order has already appeared in some differentform. For instance, in the Dyck case there is an alternative description interms of Young lattices (precisely, Dyck posets are order-isomorphic tothe Young lattices of staircase partitions).

Another instance of these posets (which are actually lattices) appears ina paper by Stanley (1975), and for this reason they are called Stanleylattices by Bernardi (2009). Moreover, Cautis and Jackson (2003) find anappearance of Dyck posets in the study of the matrix of chromatic joins.

In the last decade, Dyck posets have been investigated (directly orindirectly) by several authors (Sapounakis, Tasoulas, Tsikouras (2006),Santocanale (2007), Owczarek, Prellberg (2012), Barnabei, Bonetti,Silimbani (2013), Braun, Browder, Klee (2013), Muhle (2013,2014,2015),Blanco, Petersen (2014), Gobet, Williams (2016),...).

However, it does not seem that this approach has ever been tried forlattice paths in general. At any rate, I believe that the language of latticepaths gives a geometric flavor to the subject which allows to expressseveral properties in a more fascinating way.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of pathsIn some cases, this partial order has already appeared in some differentform. For instance, in the Dyck case there is an alternative description interms of Young lattices (precisely, Dyck posets are order-isomorphic tothe Young lattices of staircase partitions).

Another instance of these posets (which are actually lattices) appears ina paper by Stanley (1975), and for this reason they are called Stanleylattices by Bernardi (2009). Moreover, Cautis and Jackson (2003) find anappearance of Dyck posets in the study of the matrix of chromatic joins.

In the last decade, Dyck posets have been investigated (directly orindirectly) by several authors (Sapounakis, Tasoulas, Tsikouras (2006),Santocanale (2007), Owczarek, Prellberg (2012), Barnabei, Bonetti,Silimbani (2013), Braun, Browder, Klee (2013), Muhle (2013,2014,2015),Blanco, Petersen (2014), Gobet, Williams (2016),...).

However, it does not seem that this approach has ever been tried forlattice paths in general. At any rate, I believe that the language of latticepaths gives a geometric flavor to the subject which allows to expressseveral properties in a more fascinating way.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Posets

Posets of pathsIn some cases, this partial order has already appeared in some differentform. For instance, in the Dyck case there is an alternative description interms of Young lattices (precisely, Dyck posets are order-isomorphic tothe Young lattices of staircase partitions).

Another instance of these posets (which are actually lattices) appears ina paper by Stanley (1975), and for this reason they are called Stanleylattices by Bernardi (2009). Moreover, Cautis and Jackson (2003) find anappearance of Dyck posets in the study of the matrix of chromatic joins.

In the last decade, Dyck posets have been investigated (directly orindirectly) by several authors (Sapounakis, Tasoulas, Tsikouras (2006),Santocanale (2007), Owczarek, Prellberg (2012), Barnabei, Bonetti,Silimbani (2013), Braun, Browder, Klee (2013), Muhle (2013,2014,2015),Blanco, Petersen (2014), Gobet, Williams (2016),...).

However, it does not seem that this approach has ever been tried forlattice paths in general. At any rate, I believe that the language of latticepaths gives a geometric flavor to the subject which allows to expressseveral properties in a more fascinating way.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...Some natural and interesting problems concerned with this partial orderstructure are the following.

� In which cases do we get lattices?� In case we obtain (finite) distributive lattices:

� what can we say on the poset of their join-irreducibles?(ù (Birkhoff’s) representation theorems);

� Euler characteristic;� rank-unimodality (even in case we just have ranked posets, of

course);� Heyting algebra structure and logic-theoretic applications;

� Enumeration of (saturated) chains.� enumeration of edges (= saturated chains of length 1) in several

lattices of paths;� enumeration of chains and saturated chains in Dyck lattices;� new structures for counting chains in Schroder lattices: Schroder

tableaux.

� Isomorphisms with other interesting posets having combinatorialrelevance.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...

Another interesting issue of an order-theoretic nature concerns a different(although equally natural) partial order relation defined on the set of allpaths of a certain class, which is the pattern containment relation.

This partial order is defined in analogy with the classical patterncontainment order on permutations.

Here we will have a look at some structural and enumerative propertiesof the pattern containment order in the special case of Dyck paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...

Another interesting issue of an order-theoretic nature concerns a different(although equally natural) partial order relation defined on the set of allpaths of a certain class, which is the pattern containment relation.

This partial order is defined in analogy with the classical patterncontainment order on permutations.

Here we will have a look at some structural and enumerative propertiesof the pattern containment order in the special case of Dyck paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

(Possibly) in this talk...

Another interesting issue of an order-theoretic nature concerns a different(although equally natural) partial order relation defined on the set of allpaths of a certain class, which is the pattern containment relation.

This partial order is defined in analogy with the classical patterncontainment order on permutations.

Here we will have a look at some structural and enumerative propertiesof the pattern containment order in the special case of Dyck paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

Not in this talk...

We point out that there are other instances of partial orders, more or lessnaturally defined on lattice paths, that we are not going to consider here.

Among them, the most well known are certainly the Tamari lattices,widely studied by many authors, but probably better espressed in terms ofdifferent combinatorial structures.

A little bit less known, but not less interesting, are also other types oflattices considered by Baril and Pallo (2006,2008,2014), such as thephagocyte lattices and the pruning-grafting lattices.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

Not in this talk...

We point out that there are other instances of partial orders, more or lessnaturally defined on lattice paths, that we are not going to consider here.

Among them, the most well known are certainly the Tamari lattices,widely studied by many authors, but probably better espressed in terms ofdifferent combinatorial structures.

A little bit less known, but not less interesting, are also other types oflattices considered by Baril and Pallo (2006,2008,2014), such as thephagocyte lattices and the pruning-grafting lattices.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Introduction

Outline of the talk

Not in this talk...

We point out that there are other instances of partial orders, more or lessnaturally defined on lattice paths, that we are not going to consider here.

Among them, the most well known are certainly the Tamari lattices,widely studied by many authors, but probably better espressed in terms ofdifferent combinatorial structures.

A little bit less known, but not less interesting, are also other types oflattices considered by Baril and Pallo (2006,2008,2014), such as thephagocyte lattices and the pruning-grafting lattices.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Distributivity

In which cases do we get lattices? We still don’t know in general...

Simpler question: in which cases do we get distributive lattices withcoordinatewise meet and join? We have a characterization, when theclass of paths only has unitary steps.

Unitary step means: each step is of type p1, kq, for some k P Z. A class ofpaths of length n having only unitary steps can be identified with the set

CΓn � tf : r0, ns Ñ N | f p0q � f pnq � 0, f pk � 1q � f pkq P Γ,@k   nu,

where Γ � Z is a finite set of steps.

CΓn : Γ-paths of length n.

CΓ � �nPN CΓn : Γ-paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Distributivity

In which cases do we get lattices? We still don’t know in general...

Simpler question: in which cases do we get distributive lattices withcoordinatewise meet and join? We have a characterization, when theclass of paths only has unitary steps.

Unitary step means: each step is of type p1, kq, for some k P Z. A class ofpaths of length n having only unitary steps can be identified with the set

CΓn � tf : r0, ns Ñ N | f p0q � f pnq � 0, f pk � 1q � f pkq P Γ,@k   nu,

where Γ � Z is a finite set of steps.

CΓn : Γ-paths of length n.

CΓ � �nPN CΓn : Γ-paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Distributivity

In which cases do we get lattices? We still don’t know in general...

Simpler question: in which cases do we get distributive lattices withcoordinatewise meet and join? We have a characterization, when theclass of paths only has unitary steps.

Unitary step means: each step is of type p1, kq, for some k P Z. A class ofpaths of length n having only unitary steps can be identified with the set

CΓn � tf : r0, ns Ñ N | f p0q � f pnq � 0, f pk � 1q � f pkq P Γ,@k   nu,

where Γ � Z is a finite set of steps.

CΓn : Γ-paths of length n.

CΓ � �nPN CΓn : Γ-paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Distributivity

In which cases do we get lattices? We still don’t know in general...

Simpler question: in which cases do we get distributive lattices withcoordinatewise meet and join? We have a characterization, when theclass of paths only has unitary steps.

Unitary step means: each step is of type p1, kq, for some k P Z. A class ofpaths of length n having only unitary steps can be identified with the set

CΓn � tf : r0, ns Ñ N | f p0q � f pnq � 0, f pk � 1q � f pkq P Γ,@k   nu,

where Γ � Z is a finite set of steps.

CΓn : Γ-paths of length n.

CΓ � �nPN CΓn : Γ-paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Counterexamples

Notice that there are cases in which we don’t get lattices.

CΓ5 , Γ � t�1, 1, 2u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Counterexamples

Notice that there are cases in which we don’t get lattices.

CΓ5 , Γ � t�1, 1, 2u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Counterexamples

Moreover, even when we get lattices, it may happen that they are notdistributive.CΓ

4 , Γ � t�1, 0, 2u.

HHHH

UDDH

UDHD

UHDD

HUDD

Notice that UDDH ^ HUDD � HHHH, which is not the coordinatewisemeet of the two paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Counterexamples

Moreover, even when we get lattices, it may happen that they are notdistributive.CΓ

4 , Γ � t�1, 0, 2u.

HHHH

UDDH

UDHD

UHDD

HUDD

Notice that UDDH ^ HUDD � HHHH, which is not the coordinatewisemeet of the two paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Main result

Theorem (F., Pinzani (2005))CΓn is a (finite distributive) lattice with respect to coordinatewise meet

and join if and only if

p∆Γ � Γq X rγ�, γ�s � Γ,

where

� γ� � max Γ, γ� � min Γ;

� ∆Γn � t

°ni�1pxi � yi q | xi , yi P Γ, xi � yj ,@i , ju;

� ∆Γ � �nPN ∆Γn,

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Main result

Theorem (F., Pinzani (2005))CΓn is a (finite distributive) lattice with respect to coordinatewise meet

and join if and only if

p∆Γ � Γq X rγ�, γ�s � Γ,

where

� γ� � max Γ, γ� � min Γ;

� ∆Γn � t

°ni�1pxi � yi q | xi , yi P Γ, xi � yj ,@i , ju;

� ∆Γ � �nPN ∆Γn,

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Main result

Theorem (F., Pinzani (2005))CΓn is a (finite distributive) lattice with respect to coordinatewise meet

and join if and only if

p∆Γ � Γq X rγ�, γ�s � Γ,

where

� γ� � max Γ, γ� � min Γ;

� ∆Γn � t

°ni�1pxi � yi q | xi , yi P Γ, xi � yj ,@i , ju;

� ∆Γ � �nPN ∆Γn,

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Main result

Theorem (F., Pinzani (2005))CΓn is a (finite distributive) lattice with respect to coordinatewise meet

and join if and only if

p∆Γ � Γq X rγ�, γ�s � Γ,

where

� γ� � max Γ, γ� � min Γ;

� ∆Γn � t

°ni�1pxi � yi q | xi , yi P Γ, xi � yj ,@i , ju;

� ∆Γ � �nPN ∆Γn,

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Some consequences

Corollary (F.,Pinzani (2005))(Motzkin) If Γ is an interval (i.e. Γ � rγ�, γ�s), then CΓ

n is a lattice.

Corollary (F.,Pinzani (2005))(Dyck) If Γ � t�b, au (a, b P N), then CΓ

n is a lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Lattices of paths

Some consequences

Corollary (F.,Pinzani (2005))(Motzkin) If Γ is an interval (i.e. Γ � rγ�, γ�s), then CΓ

n is a lattice.

Corollary (F.,Pinzani (2005))(Dyck) If Γ � t�b, au (a, b P N), then CΓ

n is a lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Lattices of Dyck-like pathsA Dyck-like path of type pa, bq is a t�b, au-path. They are a naturalgeneralization of Dyck paths, already considered by Duchon (2000).More recently, see also Bergeron, Preville-Ratelle (2012) and Banderier,Wallner (2015).

Lattices of Dyck-like paths will be denoted Dpa,bqn . Not new: they are

Young lattices in disguise!

-

6

q qq q

q qq

q qq q

q q

q qq q

q

q qq q

q

q qq qq q

qq q

qq q q q�

���������

��������

�������

�������

�����

����

����

��

AAAAAA

AAAAA

AAAAAAA

AAAAAAAA

AAAAAAAAAA

ppppppp pppppp pppppppppp pppp ppp ppp pp p pÓ

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Lattices of Dyck-like paths

The distributive lattice Dpa,bqn is isomorphic to the dual of the Young

lattice Yλpa,bqn

.

Proposition (F., Munarini (2011))Let gcdpa, bq � 1. For any n P N,

λpa,bqn � pλn,b, . . . , λn,1, λn�1,b, . . . , λn�1,1, . . . , λ2,b, . . . , λ2,1, λ1,b, . . . , λ1,2q

is a partition with nb � 1 parts, where λh,k � ph � 1qa� tpk � 1q � a{bu.In particular,

|λpa,bqn | � abnpn � 1q

2� n|λpa,bq1 |.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Join-irreducibles

� Dyck r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r��@@��@@����@

@@@��@@��@@��@@

0 2i 2j 2n� Motzkin

q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q���@

@@

0 i j n

� Schroder

q q q q q q q q q q q q���@

@@

0 2i 2j 2n

orq q q q q q q q q q q�

� @@

0 2i 2j 2n

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Join-irreducibles

� Dyck r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r��@@��@@����@

@@@��@@��@@��@@

0 2i 2j 2n� Motzkin

q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q���@

@@

0 i j n

� Schroder

q q q q q q q q q q q q���@

@@

0 2i 2j 2n

orq q q q q q q q q q q�

� @@

0 2i 2j 2n

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Join-irreducibles

� Dyck r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r r��@@��@@����@

@@@��@@��@@��@@

0 2i 2j 2n� Motzkin

q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q q���@

@@

0 i j n

� Schroder

q q q q q q q q q q q q���@

@@

0 2i 2j 2n

orq q q q q q q q q q q�

� @@

0 2i 2j 2n

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Birkhoff representations

Poset of join-irreducibles:

� The spectrum of Dn is isomorphic to the poset of the intervals of achain Cn�2 with n � 1 elements, i.e.SpecpDnq � tpi , jq P C2

n | i ¤ j � 2u � IntpCn�2q.� The spectrum of Mn is isomorphic to the poset of the intervals of

even length of a chain Cn having n � 1 elements, i.e.SpecpMnq � tpi , jq P C2

n | Dk P N such that j � i � 2k � 2qu.� SpecpSnq � tpi , j , kq P C2

n � C1 | j � i ¥ k � 1u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Birkhoff representations

Poset of join-irreducibles:

� The spectrum of Dn is isomorphic to the poset of the intervals of achain Cn�2 with n � 1 elements, i.e.SpecpDnq � tpi , jq P C2

n | i ¤ j � 2u � IntpCn�2q.� The spectrum of Mn is isomorphic to the poset of the intervals of

even length of a chain Cn having n � 1 elements, i.e.SpecpMnq � tpi , jq P C2

n | Dk P N such that j � i � 2k � 2qu.� SpecpSnq � tpi , j , kq P C2

n � C1 | j � i ¥ k � 1u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Birkhoff representations

Poset of join-irreducibles:

� The spectrum of Dn is isomorphic to the poset of the intervals of achain Cn�2 with n � 1 elements, i.e.SpecpDnq � tpi , jq P C2

n | i ¤ j � 2u � IntpCn�2q.� The spectrum of Mn is isomorphic to the poset of the intervals of

even length of a chain Cn having n � 1 elements, i.e.SpecpMnq � tpi , jq P C2

n | Dk P N such that j � i � 2k � 2qu.� SpecpSnq � tpi , j , kq P C2

n � C1 | j � i ¥ k � 1u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

Representations

Birkhoff representations

qqd qd qdq q qqd q qdq qqqd

@@��@

@@

����

��

@@@���

@@@

��@@D4

q q qq qq���

@@@

@@��SpecpD4q

qqb qb qb qbq q q q q qq q q qqb q qbq qq

HHH

H@@������

AA�����Q

QQ���!!

!!!

aaaa

a

AA���aa

aaa

AA��

�����AA!!

!!!

AA���aa

aaa

���aa

aaa

��Q

QQAA

AA��

����@@

HHHH

��

���HH �� PP

P�� HH

M5

q q q qq q��@@��@@

SpecpM5q

qqd qd qdq q qqd q qdqd q q qdq q qq qqqdqd

@@��@

@@@

����

����

����

����

@@

@@

@@@@

@@

@@

��@@S3

q q qq qq qqq��@@��@@

��@@

SpecpS3q

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

The Euler characteristic

Given a (finite) distributive lattice, an interesting problem is that ofdetermining its Euler characteristic.

The Euler characteristic is a classical invariant measure which plays animportant role, for instance, in combinatorial geometry and in geometricprobability.

The combinatorial interest of the Euler characteristic lies in its deeprelation with the Mobius function, revealed by G.-C. Rota.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

The Euler characteristic

Given a (finite) distributive lattice, an interesting problem is that ofdetermining its Euler characteristic.

The Euler characteristic is a classical invariant measure which plays animportant role, for instance, in combinatorial geometry and in geometricprobability.

The combinatorial interest of the Euler characteristic lies in its deeprelation with the Mobius function, revealed by G.-C. Rota.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

The Euler characteristic

Given a (finite) distributive lattice, an interesting problem is that ofdetermining its Euler characteristic.

The Euler characteristic is a classical invariant measure which plays animportant role, for instance, in combinatorial geometry and in geometricprobability.

The combinatorial interest of the Euler characteristic lies in its deeprelation with the Mobius function, revealed by G.-C. Rota.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Valuations of distributive lattices

The Euler characteristic of a distributive lattice is a particular valuation.

A valuation on a distributive lattice D with values in R is a functionν : D Ñ R such that νpp0q � 0 and νpx _ yq � νpx ^ yq � νpxq � νpyqfor every x , y P D. A valuation on a finite distributive lattice D isuniquely determined by the values it takes on the set of join-irreduciblesof D, and these values can be arbitrarily assigned.

The (Euler) characteristic of D is defined as the unique valuation χ suchthat χpp0q � 0 and χpxq � 1 for every join-irreducible x of D. Inparticular, χpDq � χpp1q.Is there a nice way of interpreting the Euler characteristic inside ourlattices of paths?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Valuations of distributive lattices

The Euler characteristic of a distributive lattice is a particular valuation.

A valuation on a distributive lattice D with values in R is a functionν : D Ñ R such that νpp0q � 0 and νpx _ yq � νpx ^ yq � νpxq � νpyqfor every x , y P D. A valuation on a finite distributive lattice D isuniquely determined by the values it takes on the set of join-irreduciblesof D, and these values can be arbitrarily assigned.

The (Euler) characteristic of D is defined as the unique valuation χ suchthat χpp0q � 0 and χpxq � 1 for every join-irreducible x of D. Inparticular, χpDq � χpp1q.Is there a nice way of interpreting the Euler characteristic inside ourlattices of paths?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Valuations of distributive lattices

The Euler characteristic of a distributive lattice is a particular valuation.

A valuation on a distributive lattice D with values in R is a functionν : D Ñ R such that νpp0q � 0 and νpx _ yq � νpx ^ yq � νpxq � νpyqfor every x , y P D. A valuation on a finite distributive lattice D isuniquely determined by the values it takes on the set of join-irreduciblesof D, and these values can be arbitrarily assigned.

The (Euler) characteristic of D is defined as the unique valuation χ suchthat χpp0q � 0 and χpxq � 1 for every join-irreducible x of D. Inparticular, χpDq � χpp1q.Is there a nice way of interpreting the Euler characteristic inside ourlattices of paths?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Valuations of distributive lattices

The Euler characteristic of a distributive lattice is a particular valuation.

A valuation on a distributive lattice D with values in R is a functionν : D Ñ R such that νpp0q � 0 and νpx _ yq � νpx ^ yq � νpxq � νpyqfor every x , y P D. A valuation on a finite distributive lattice D isuniquely determined by the values it takes on the set of join-irreduciblesof D, and these values can be arbitrarily assigned.

The (Euler) characteristic of D is defined as the unique valuation χ suchthat χpp0q � 0 and χpxq � 1 for every join-irreducible x of D. Inparticular, χpDq � χpp1q.Is there a nice way of interpreting the Euler characteristic inside ourlattices of paths?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

In the Dyck and Schroder case, the combinatorial interpretation of theEuler characteristic follows from a more general algebraic approach.

A Dyck-like lattice is a distributive lattice whose spectrum is a rankedposet admitting a labelling of its elements with the following properties:all labels are positive integers and every antichain S � ts1, . . . , snu ofjoin-irreducibles can be linearly ordered so that the labels of the elementsof S are distinct and, if s1 and sn are the elements having minimum andmaximum labels, respectively, then s1 ^ sn � s1 ^ s2 ^ � � � ^ sn�1 ^ sn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

In the Dyck and Schroder case, the combinatorial interpretation of theEuler characteristic follows from a more general algebraic approach.

A Dyck-like lattice is a distributive lattice whose spectrum is a rankedposet admitting a labelling of its elements with the following properties:all labels are positive integers and every antichain S � ts1, . . . , snu ofjoin-irreducibles can be linearly ordered so that the labels of the elementsof S are distinct and, if s1 and sn are the elements having minimum andmaximum labels, respectively, then s1 ^ sn � s1 ^ s2 ^ � � � ^ sn�1 ^ sn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

Proposition (F., Munarini (2011))For any a, b P N and for every n P N, the lattice Dpa,bq

n is a Dyck-likelattice.

Conjecture (F., Munarini (2011))Every finite Dyck-like lattice can be represented as a sublattice of alattice of Dyck-like paths of suitable length.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

Proposition (F., Munarini (2011))For any a, b P N and for every n P N, the lattice Dpa,bq

n is a Dyck-likelattice.

Conjecture (F., Munarini (2011))Every finite Dyck-like lattice can be represented as a sublattice of alattice of Dyck-like paths of suitable length.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

We will say that an element x of a distributive lattice D isquasi-join-irreducible when there exists an ordered k-tuple ps1, . . . , skqforming an antichain of join-irreducibles such that x � s1 _ � � � _ sk andsi ^ si�1 � p0, for every i � 1, 2, . . . , k � 1.

A special Dyck-like lattice is a Dyck-like lattice where the meet of any

two join-irreducibles is p0 or a join-irreducible. Notice that Dpa,bqn is a

special Dyck-like lattice.

PropositionIn a special Dyck-like lattice D, every quasi-join-irreducible element hasEuler characteristic equal to 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

We will say that an element x of a distributive lattice D isquasi-join-irreducible when there exists an ordered k-tuple ps1, . . . , skqforming an antichain of join-irreducibles such that x � s1 _ � � � _ sk andsi ^ si�1 � p0, for every i � 1, 2, . . . , k � 1.

A special Dyck-like lattice is a Dyck-like lattice where the meet of any

two join-irreducibles is p0 or a join-irreducible. Notice that Dpa,bqn is a

special Dyck-like lattice.

PropositionIn a special Dyck-like lattice D, every quasi-join-irreducible element hasEuler characteristic equal to 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

We will say that an element x of a distributive lattice D isquasi-join-irreducible when there exists an ordered k-tuple ps1, . . . , skqforming an antichain of join-irreducibles such that x � s1 _ � � � _ sk andsi ^ si�1 � p0, for every i � 1, 2, . . . , k � 1.

A special Dyck-like lattice is a Dyck-like lattice where the meet of any

two join-irreducibles is p0 or a join-irreducible. Notice that Dpa,bqn is a

special Dyck-like lattice.

PropositionIn a special Dyck-like lattice D, every quasi-join-irreducible element hasEuler characteristic equal to 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

An element x of a finite distributive lattice is said to have aquasi-join-irreducible decomposition when it can be expressed as a join ofquasi-join-irreducible elements x1, . . . , xk such that xi ^ xj � p0, for everyi � j .

PropositionEvery element x � p0 of a finite Dyck-like lattice has an essentially uniquequasi-join-irreducible decomposition.

TheoremLet D be a finite special Dyck-like lattice. Then, for every x P Dztp0u,χpxq is the number of quasi-join-irreducibles in a decomposition of x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

An element x of a finite distributive lattice is said to have aquasi-join-irreducible decomposition when it can be expressed as a join ofquasi-join-irreducible elements x1, . . . , xk such that xi ^ xj � p0, for everyi � j .

PropositionEvery element x � p0 of a finite Dyck-like lattice has an essentially uniquequasi-join-irreducible decomposition.

TheoremLet D be a finite special Dyck-like lattice. Then, for every x P Dztp0u,χpxq is the number of quasi-join-irreducibles in a decomposition of x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck-like lattices

An element x of a finite distributive lattice is said to have aquasi-join-irreducible decomposition when it can be expressed as a join ofquasi-join-irreducible elements x1, . . . , xk such that xi ^ xj � p0, for everyi � j .

PropositionEvery element x � p0 of a finite Dyck-like lattice has an essentially uniquequasi-join-irreducible decomposition.

TheoremLet D be a finite special Dyck-like lattice. Then, for every x P Dztp0u,χpxq is the number of quasi-join-irreducibles in a decomposition of x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck and Schroder lattices

In the case of Dyck paths, the characteristic can be interpretedcombinatorially as follows.

TheoremA Dyck path x P Dn is quasi-join-irreducible if and only if it has preciselyone 1-tunnel. Therefore the characteristic of a Dyck path is the numberof its 1-tunnels.

The case of Schroder lattices is completely analogous, since they arespecial Dyck-like lattices. In particular, we have the following result.

TheoremA Schroder path is quasi-join-irreducible if and only if it has exactly one0-tunnel. Therefore the characteristic of a Schroder path equals thenumber of its 0-tunnels.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Dyck and Schroder lattices

In the case of Dyck paths, the characteristic can be interpretedcombinatorially as follows.

TheoremA Dyck path x P Dn is quasi-join-irreducible if and only if it has preciselyone 1-tunnel. Therefore the characteristic of a Dyck path is the numberof its 1-tunnels.

The case of Schroder lattices is completely analogous, since they arespecial Dyck-like lattices. In particular, we have the following result.

TheoremA Schroder path is quasi-join-irreducible if and only if it has exactly one0-tunnel. Therefore the characteristic of a Schroder path equals thenumber of its 0-tunnels.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

Motzkin lattices are more difficult, since they are not special. In fact, ifthe meet of two join-irreducibles is � p0, then it is not necessarily ajoin-irreducible.

q q q q q q q q q qq q q q q q q q q��� @

@@

@@@

���

Need for an alternative approach...

First of all, we need to understand the meet of two genericjoin-irreducibles.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

Motzkin lattices are more difficult, since they are not special. In fact, ifthe meet of two join-irreducibles is � p0, then it is not necessarily ajoin-irreducible.

q q q q q q q q q qq q q q q q q q q��� @

@@

@@@

���

Need for an alternative approach...

First of all, we need to understand the meet of two genericjoin-irreducibles.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

Truncated pyramid: sequence of k ¥ 1 up steps followed by a sequenceof m ¥ 1 horizontal steps followed by a sequence of k down steps, i.e.UkHmDk (k : dimension, m: length, h: height (if the horizontal steps lieon the line y � h)).

Tn,m,k : set of Motzkin paths of length n having only horizontal steps atheight 0, except for a unique truncated pyramid of dimension k andlength m.

p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p p�� @

@

PropositionIn Mn the meet of two join-irreducibles is either p0 or a join-irreducible oran element of Tn,1,k , k ¤ n � 2 (i.e., a Motzkin path with a uniquetruncated pyramid of length 1).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

LemmaIf x P Tn,m,h, then χpxq � p�1qh�1m � 1.

PropositionLet x PMn be a quasi-join-irreducible. Then χpxq � opxq � epxq � 1,where opxq is the number of horizontal steps at odd height and epxq isthe number of horizontal steps at even nonzero height (i.e. at evenheight and not lying on the x-axis).

TheoremThe characteristic of a Motzkin path x � p0 is χpxq � }x} � o1pxq � epxq,where }x} denotes the number of quasi-join-irreducibles in adecomposition of x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

LemmaIf x P Tn,m,h, then χpxq � p�1qh�1m � 1.

PropositionLet x PMn be a quasi-join-irreducible. Then χpxq � opxq � epxq � 1,where opxq is the number of horizontal steps at odd height and epxq isthe number of horizontal steps at even nonzero height (i.e. at evenheight and not lying on the x-axis).

TheoremThe characteristic of a Motzkin path x � p0 is χpxq � }x} � o1pxq � epxq,where }x} denotes the number of quasi-join-irreducibles in adecomposition of x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

LemmaIf x P Tn,m,h, then χpxq � p�1qh�1m � 1.

PropositionLet x PMn be a quasi-join-irreducible. Then χpxq � opxq � epxq � 1,where opxq is the number of horizontal steps at odd height and epxq isthe number of horizontal steps at even nonzero height (i.e. at evenheight and not lying on the x-axis).

TheoremThe characteristic of a Motzkin path x � p0 is χpxq � }x} � o1pxq � epxq,where }x} denotes the number of quasi-join-irreducibles in adecomposition of x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

PropositionA Motzkin path is quasi-join-irreducible if and only if either it has aunique elevated factor having no horizontal steps at height 1 or it has aunique peak at height 1.

TheoremThe characteristic of a Motzkin path x PMn is

χpxq � opxq � epxq � t1pxq � f1pxq � p1pxq � r1pxq,

where fhpxq, phpxq, thpxq and rhpxq are respectively the number oftruncated pyramids, peaks, maximal sequences of consecutive 1-tunnelsand reverse truncated pyramid of height h in x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Distributive lattice structure

The Euler Characteristic

Motzkin lattices

PropositionA Motzkin path is quasi-join-irreducible if and only if either it has aunique elevated factor having no horizontal steps at height 1 or it has aunique peak at height 1.

TheoremThe characteristic of a Motzkin path x PMn is

χpxq � opxq � epxq � t1pxq � f1pxq � p1pxq � r1pxq,

where fhpxq, phpxq, thpxq and rhpxq are respectively the number oftruncated pyramids, peaks, maximal sequences of consecutive 1-tunnelsand reverse truncated pyramid of height h in x .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Statement of the problem

Is the Dyck (resp. Motzkin, Schroder) lattice Dn (resp. Mn, Sn)rank-unimodal, for all n P N?

(A finite sequence a1, a2, . . . an is called unimodal whenever there existsi ¤ n such that a1 ¤ a2 ¤ � � � ¤ ai�1 ¤ ai ¥ ai�1 ¥ � � � an�1 ¥ an).

Equivalent formulations of the same problem:

� Given λ � pn, n � 1, . . . 2, 1q, is the Young lattice Yλ rank-unimodal,for all n P N? (Stanton, 1990).

� Are Dyck paths unimodal with respect to the area? (Bonin, Shapiro,Simion, 1993).

� Is the inv statistic unimodal on 312-avoiding permutations(???...source...???)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Statement of the problem

Is the Dyck (resp. Motzkin, Schroder) lattice Dn (resp. Mn, Sn)rank-unimodal, for all n P N?

(A finite sequence a1, a2, . . . an is called unimodal whenever there existsi ¤ n such that a1 ¤ a2 ¤ � � � ¤ ai�1 ¤ ai ¥ ai�1 ¥ � � � an�1 ¥ an).

Equivalent formulations of the same problem:

� Given λ � pn, n � 1, . . . 2, 1q, is the Young lattice Yλ rank-unimodal,for all n P N? (Stanton, 1990).

� Are Dyck paths unimodal with respect to the area? (Bonin, Shapiro,Simion, 1993).

� Is the inv statistic unimodal on 312-avoiding permutations(???...source...???)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Statement of the problem

Is the Dyck (resp. Motzkin, Schroder) lattice Dn (resp. Mn, Sn)rank-unimodal, for all n P N?

(A finite sequence a1, a2, . . . an is called unimodal whenever there existsi ¤ n such that a1 ¤ a2 ¤ � � � ¤ ai�1 ¤ ai ¥ ai�1 ¥ � � � an�1 ¥ an).

Equivalent formulations of the same problem:

� Given λ � pn, n � 1, . . . 2, 1q, is the Young lattice Yλ rank-unimodal,for all n P N? (Stanton, 1990).

� Are Dyck paths unimodal with respect to the area? (Bonin, Shapiro,Simion, 1993).

� Is the inv statistic unimodal on 312-avoiding permutations(???...source...???)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Statement of the problem

Is the Dyck (resp. Motzkin, Schroder) lattice Dn (resp. Mn, Sn)rank-unimodal, for all n P N?

(A finite sequence a1, a2, . . . an is called unimodal whenever there existsi ¤ n such that a1 ¤ a2 ¤ � � � ¤ ai�1 ¤ ai ¥ ai�1 ¥ � � � an�1 ¥ an).

Equivalent formulations of the same problem:

� Given λ � pn, n � 1, . . . 2, 1q, is the Young lattice Yλ rank-unimodal,for all n P N? (Stanton, 1990).

� Are Dyck paths unimodal with respect to the area? (Bonin, Shapiro,Simion, 1993).

� Is the inv statistic unimodal on 312-avoiding permutations(???...source...???)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Statement of the problem

Is the Dyck (resp. Motzkin, Schroder) lattice Dn (resp. Mn, Sn)rank-unimodal, for all n P N?

(A finite sequence a1, a2, . . . an is called unimodal whenever there existsi ¤ n such that a1 ¤ a2 ¤ � � � ¤ ai�1 ¤ ai ¥ ai�1 ¥ � � � an�1 ¥ an).

Equivalent formulations of the same problem:

� Given λ � pn, n � 1, . . . 2, 1q, is the Young lattice Yλ rank-unimodal,for all n P N? (Stanton, 1990).

� Are Dyck paths unimodal with respect to the area? (Bonin, Shapiro,Simion, 1993).

� Is the inv statistic unimodal on 312-avoiding permutations(???...source...???)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Unfortunately...

We have not been able to solve this long-standing open problem (even ifthere is some strong computational evidence supporting a positiveanswer, also in the Motzkin and Schroder cases).

However, we have proposed a presumably new approach based on theso-called ECO methodology (Barcucci, Del Lungo, Pergola, Pinzani(1999)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Unfortunately...

We have not been able to solve this long-standing open problem (even ifthere is some strong computational evidence supporting a positiveanswer, also in the Motzkin and Schroder cases).

However, we have proposed a presumably new approach based on theso-called ECO methodology (Barcucci, Del Lungo, Pergola, Pinzani(1999)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

An ECO construction for Dyck paths

Local rule for constructing Dyck paths of semilength n � 1 starting fromDyck paths of semilength n: add a peak in each of the points of the lastdescent.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Why this construction?

This is a nice construction in that it provides a partition of the set ofDyck paths having the same length.

Such a partition of Dn is also interesting from an order-theoretic point ofview. In fact, blocks are saturated chains of Dn. So we have a saturatedchain partition of each Dn.

rr rr rrr rr rr r r r

������

��������

����

ppppp pppppppppp pppppppppp ppppp ppppp

ppppppppppppppp ppppppppppppppp ppppppppppppppp ppppppppppppppp ppppppppppppppp

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Why this construction?

We claim that this saturated chain partition plays a relevant role inproving that Dyck lattices are rank-unimodal...

... even if we have not been able to show how yet...!

However, we have found some results concerning the polynomials Ppkqn pxq

which describe the distribution of area and length of the last descent inDyck paths. These polynomials already appeared in works of Carlitz(1972) and subsequently Krattenthaler (1989) (even if from a slightlydifferent perspective).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Why this construction?

We claim that this saturated chain partition plays a relevant role inproving that Dyck lattices are rank-unimodal...

... even if we have not been able to show how yet...!

However, we have found some results concerning the polynomials Ppkqn pxq

which describe the distribution of area and length of the last descent inDyck paths. These polynomials already appeared in works of Carlitz(1972) and subsequently Krattenthaler (1989) (even if from a slightlydifferent perspective).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Why this construction?

We claim that this saturated chain partition plays a relevant role inproving that Dyck lattices are rank-unimodal...

... even if we have not been able to show how yet...!

However, we have found some results concerning the polynomials Ppkqn pxq

which describe the distribution of area and length of the last descent inDyck paths. These polynomials already appeared in works of Carlitz(1972) and subsequently Krattenthaler (1989) (even if from a slightlydifferent perspective).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Main results

� Two recursions (F., 2013):

Ppkqn pxq � xk � pPpk�1q

n�1 pxq � � � � � Ppn�2qn�1 pxqq

Ppkqn pxq � x � pPpk�1q

n pxq � xk�1Ppk�2qn�1 pxqq

� A succession rule which generates the Ppkqn pxq’s (F., 2013):

" p00qpαβqù pα0qppα� 1q1q � � � ppα� βqβqppα� β � 1qβ�1q .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Main results

� Two recursions (F., 2013):

Ppkqn pxq � xk � pPpk�1q

n�1 pxq � � � � � Ppn�2qn�1 pxqq

Ppkqn pxq � x � pPpk�1q

n pxq � xk�1Ppk�2qn�1 pxqq

� A succession rule which generates the Ppkqn pxq’s (F., 2013):

" p00qpαβqù pα0qppα� 1q1q � � � ppα� βqβqppα� β � 1qβ�1q .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Main results

00

00 11

00 11 10 21 32

00 11 10 21 32 10 21 20 31 42 30 41 52 63

For instance, Pp1q5 pxq gives the distribution at level 5-2=3 of the labels

piq1.

Pp1q5 pxq � x � 2x2 � x3 � x4.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Unimodality

Main results

00

00 11

00 11 10 21 32

00 11 10 21 32 10 21 20 31 42 30 41 52 63

For instance, Pp1q5 pxq gives the distribution at level 5-2=3 of the labels

piq1.

Pp1q5 pxq � x � 2x2 � x3 � x4.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Dyck algebras

A Heyting algebra is a lattice H with minimum 0 and maximum 1 suchthat the relative pseudocomplement of x with respect to y exists for allx , y P H. By definition, the relative pseudocomplement of x with respectto y is the element x ù y defined as follows:

x ù y � maxtz P H | x ^ z ¤ yu.

Fact: Every finite distributive lattice is a Heyting algebra (in a canonicalway).

Since Dyck lattices are finite distributive, it could be interesting to exploretheir Heyting algebra structure, as well as its logic-theoretic aspects.

In particular, Heyting algebra properties of Dyck lattices has beeninvestigated also by Muhle (2015).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Dyck algebras

A Heyting algebra is a lattice H with minimum 0 and maximum 1 suchthat the relative pseudocomplement of x with respect to y exists for allx , y P H. By definition, the relative pseudocomplement of x with respectto y is the element x ù y defined as follows:

x ù y � maxtz P H | x ^ z ¤ yu.

Fact: Every finite distributive lattice is a Heyting algebra (in a canonicalway).

Since Dyck lattices are finite distributive, it could be interesting to exploretheir Heyting algebra structure, as well as its logic-theoretic aspects.

In particular, Heyting algebra properties of Dyck lattices has beeninvestigated also by Muhle (2015).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Dyck algebras

A Heyting algebra is a lattice H with minimum 0 and maximum 1 suchthat the relative pseudocomplement of x with respect to y exists for allx , y P H. By definition, the relative pseudocomplement of x with respectto y is the element x ù y defined as follows:

x ù y � maxtz P H | x ^ z ¤ yu.

Fact: Every finite distributive lattice is a Heyting algebra (in a canonicalway).

Since Dyck lattices are finite distributive, it could be interesting to exploretheir Heyting algebra structure, as well as its logic-theoretic aspects.

In particular, Heyting algebra properties of Dyck lattices has beeninvestigated also by Muhle (2015).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Dyck algebras

A Heyting algebra is a lattice H with minimum 0 and maximum 1 suchthat the relative pseudocomplement of x with respect to y exists for allx , y P H. By definition, the relative pseudocomplement of x with respectto y is the element x ù y defined as follows:

x ù y � maxtz P H | x ^ z ¤ yu.

Fact: Every finite distributive lattice is a Heyting algebra (in a canonicalway).

Since Dyck lattices are finite distributive, it could be interesting to exploretheir Heyting algebra structure, as well as its logic-theoretic aspects.

In particular, Heyting algebra properties of Dyck lattices has beeninvestigated also by Muhle (2015).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Relative pseudocomplements

Proposition (F. (2015+))Given P,Q P Dn, P ù Q is obtained from Q by replacing thoseportions of path in which P lies weakly below Q with the highest possibleDyck factors.

x0 x1 x2 x3 x4 x5

Figure: P is red, Q is blue and Pù Q is green.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Pseudocomplement and regular elements

In a Heyting algebra, the pseudocomplement of x is defined as�x � x ù 0. It can be shown that x ¤��x . The converse, however,does not hold in general. An element x is said to be regular wheneverx ���x . The subposet of regular elements of a Heyting algebra forms aBoolean algebra.

Proposition (F. (2015+))Let P P Dn. Then �P � P ù 0 is obtained from P by

1. replacing each sequence of consecutive hills with a pyramid ofsuitable length and height, and

2. completing the path by suitably adding a (finite) set of hills.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Pseudocomplement and regular elements

In a Heyting algebra, the pseudocomplement of x is defined as�x � x ù 0. It can be shown that x ¤��x . The converse, however,does not hold in general. An element x is said to be regular wheneverx ���x . The subposet of regular elements of a Heyting algebra forms aBoolean algebra.

Proposition (F. (2015+))Let P P Dn. Then �P � P ù 0 is obtained from P by

1. replacing each sequence of consecutive hills with a pyramid ofsuitable length and height, and

2. completing the path by suitably adding a (finite) set of hills.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Pseudocomplement and regular elements

In a Heyting algebra, the pseudocomplement of x is defined as�x � x ù 0. It can be shown that x ¤��x . The converse, however,does not hold in general. An element x is said to be regular wheneverx ���x . The subposet of regular elements of a Heyting algebra forms aBoolean algebra.

Proposition (F. (2015+))Let P P Dn. Then �P � P ù 0 is obtained from P by

1. replacing each sequence of consecutive hills with a pyramid ofsuitable length and height, and

2. completing the path by suitably adding a (finite) set of hills.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Pseudocomplement and regular elements

In a Heyting algebra, the pseudocomplement of x is defined as�x � x ù 0. It can be shown that x ¤��x . The converse, however,does not hold in general. An element x is said to be regular wheneverx ���x . The subposet of regular elements of a Heyting algebra forms aBoolean algebra.

Proposition (F. (2015+))Let P P Dn. Then �P � P ù 0 is obtained from P by

1. replacing each sequence of consecutive hills with a pyramid ofsuitable length and height, and

2. completing the path by suitably adding a (finite) set of hills.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Pseudocomplement and regular elements

Figure: A Dyck path (black) and its pseudocomplement (green).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Dyck algebras

Pseudocomplement and regular elements

Proposition (F. (2015+))A Dyck path is regular if and only if its factors are all pyramids.

1111

211 121 112

31 22 13

4

Figure: The Boolean algebra of regular elements of D4 and its isomorphicrepresentation in terms of compositions of 4.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logicIs it possible to give a logic-theoretic interpretation of Dyck algebras?

Yes, using interval temporal logic!

A temporal logic is essentially a kind of logic which allows to deal withstatements whose truth values can vary in time.

An interval temporal logic is characterized by the fact that the truth of astatement depends on the time interval it is evaluated on (rather thanthe time instant).

Typically useful in computer science (when it is important to work withproperties which remain true or false for a certain amount of time):

� processes, in particular concurrent real-time processes,

� temporal databases,

� specification, design and verification of hardware components.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logic

There is a large literature on interval temporal logics. In particular,fragments of specific logics are investigated from the point of view ofcomputability and computational complexity (Goranko, Montanari,Sciavicco (2004), Montanari, Pratt-Hartmann, Sala (2010), Bresolin,Della Monica, Montanari, Sala, Sciavicco (2014) ...)

We will focus on a specific fragment of the whole Halpern-Shoham logic,which is sometimes called the logic of subintervals. In a sense, this is anintermediate step between genuine interval logics and classical logics (oftime instants rather than intervals). So, it is probably not among themost expressive fragments from a purely logic-theoretic point of view (itsdecidability has been studied by Marcinkowski and Michaliszyn (2014)).However, it has a very nice and effective combinatorial description, whichwe are going to develop in the next slides.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

Interval temporal logic

There is a large literature on interval temporal logics. In particular,fragments of specific logics are investigated from the point of view ofcomputability and computational complexity (Goranko, Montanari,Sciavicco (2004), Montanari, Pratt-Hartmann, Sala (2010), Bresolin,Della Monica, Montanari, Sala, Sciavicco (2014) ...)

We will focus on a specific fragment of the whole Halpern-Shoham logic,which is sometimes called the logic of subintervals. In a sense, this is anintermediate step between genuine interval logics and classical logics (oftime instants rather than intervals). So, it is probably not among themost expressive fragments from a purely logic-theoretic point of view (itsdecidability has been studied by Marcinkowski and Michaliszyn (2014)).However, it has a very nice and effective combinatorial description, whichwe are going to develop in the next slides.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

� Tn � tt1, t2, . . . , tnu: finite linearly ordered set of time states.

� IntpTnq: set of intervals of Tn.

� IntpTnq is partially ordered by inclusion.

Set of propositions ITLn recursively defined as follows:

� K,J P ITLn; for all 1 ¤ i ¤ n, εi P ITLn (propositional variables);

� if ϕ,ψ P ITLn, then ϕ_ ψ,ϕ^ ψ,ϕÑ ψ, ϕ P ITLn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

� Tn � tt1, t2, . . . , tnu: finite linearly ordered set of time states.

� IntpTnq: set of intervals of Tn.

� IntpTnq is partially ordered by inclusion.

Set of propositions ITLn recursively defined as follows:

� K,J P ITLn; for all 1 ¤ i ¤ n, εi P ITLn (propositional variables);

� if ϕ,ψ P ITLn, then ϕ_ ψ,ϕ^ ψ,ϕÑ ψ, ϕ P ITLn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

� Tn � tt1, t2, . . . , tnu: finite linearly ordered set of time states.

� IntpTnq: set of intervals of Tn.

� IntpTnq is partially ordered by inclusion.

Set of propositions ITLn recursively defined as follows:

� K,J P ITLn; for all 1 ¤ i ¤ n, εi P ITLn (propositional variables);

� if ϕ,ψ P ITLn, then ϕ_ ψ,ϕ^ ψ,ϕÑ ψ, ϕ P ITLn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

� Tn � tt1, t2, . . . , tnu: finite linearly ordered set of time states.

� IntpTnq: set of intervals of Tn.

� IntpTnq is partially ordered by inclusion.

Set of propositions ITLn recursively defined as follows:

� K,J P ITLn; for all 1 ¤ i ¤ n, εi P ITLn (propositional variables);

� if ϕ,ψ P ITLn, then ϕ_ ψ,ϕ^ ψ,ϕÑ ψ, ϕ P ITLn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

� Tn � tt1, t2, . . . , tnu: finite linearly ordered set of time states.

� IntpTnq: set of intervals of Tn.

� IntpTnq is partially ordered by inclusion.

Set of propositions ITLn recursively defined as follows:

� K,J P ITLn; for all 1 ¤ i ¤ n, εi P ITLn (propositional variables);

� if ϕ,ψ P ITLn, then ϕ_ ψ,ϕ^ ψ,ϕÑ ψ, ϕ P ITLn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

Interval-based semantics:

v : ITLn ÝÑ 2IntpTnq

: ϕ ÞÝÑ vϕ : IntpTnq ÝÑ t0, 1u

where vϕpI q � ϕpI q � 0 (resp., 1) if ϕ is false (resp., true) whenevaluated on the interval I .

We consider a specific evaluation v :

� εi pI q � 1 whenever I � ttiu;� pϕ_ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 or ψpI q � 1;

� pϕ^ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 and ψpI q � 1;

� p ϕqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 0;

� pϕÑ ψqpI q � 1 whenever if ϕpI q � 1 then ψpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

Interval-based semantics:

v : ITLn ÝÑ 2IntpTnq

: ϕ ÞÝÑ vϕ : IntpTnq ÝÑ t0, 1u

where vϕpI q � ϕpI q � 0 (resp., 1) if ϕ is false (resp., true) whenevaluated on the interval I .

We consider a specific evaluation v :

� εi pI q � 1 whenever I � ttiu;� pϕ_ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 or ψpI q � 1;

� pϕ^ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 and ψpI q � 1;

� p ϕqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 0;

� pϕÑ ψqpI q � 1 whenever if ϕpI q � 1 then ψpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

Interval-based semantics:

v : ITLn ÝÑ 2IntpTnq

: ϕ ÞÝÑ vϕ : IntpTnq ÝÑ t0, 1u

where vϕpI q � ϕpI q � 0 (resp., 1) if ϕ is false (resp., true) whenevaluated on the interval I .

We consider a specific evaluation v :

� εi pI q � 1 whenever I � ttiu;� pϕ_ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 or ψpI q � 1;

� pϕ^ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 and ψpI q � 1;

� p ϕqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 0;

� pϕÑ ψqpI q � 1 whenever if ϕpI q � 1 then ψpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

Interval-based semantics:

v : ITLn ÝÑ 2IntpTnq

: ϕ ÞÝÑ vϕ : IntpTnq ÝÑ t0, 1u

where vϕpI q � ϕpI q � 0 (resp., 1) if ϕ is false (resp., true) whenevaluated on the interval I .

We consider a specific evaluation v :

� εi pI q � 1 whenever I � ttiu;� pϕ_ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 or ψpI q � 1;

� pϕ^ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 and ψpI q � 1;

� p ϕqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 0;

� pϕÑ ψqpI q � 1 whenever if ϕpI q � 1 then ψpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

Interval-based semantics:

v : ITLn ÝÑ 2IntpTnq

: ϕ ÞÝÑ vϕ : IntpTnq ÝÑ t0, 1u

where vϕpI q � ϕpI q � 0 (resp., 1) if ϕ is false (resp., true) whenevaluated on the interval I .

We consider a specific evaluation v :

� εi pI q � 1 whenever I � ttiu;� pϕ_ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 or ψpI q � 1;

� pϕ^ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 and ψpI q � 1;

� p ϕqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 0;

� pϕÑ ψqpI q � 1 whenever if ϕpI q � 1 then ψpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The general framework

Interval-based semantics:

v : ITLn ÝÑ 2IntpTnq

: ϕ ÞÝÑ vϕ : IntpTnq ÝÑ t0, 1u

where vϕpI q � ϕpI q � 0 (resp., 1) if ϕ is false (resp., true) whenevaluated on the interval I .

We consider a specific evaluation v :

� εi pI q � 1 whenever I � ttiu;� pϕ_ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 or ψpI q � 1;

� pϕ^ ψqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 1 and ψpI q � 1;

� p ϕqpI q � 1 whenever ϕpI q � 0;

� pϕÑ ψqpI q � 1 whenever if ϕpI q � 1 then ψpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Two new connectives:

� plϕqpI q � 1 when, for all intervals J � I , ϕpJq � 1;

� p♦ϕqpI q � 1 when there exists an interval J � I such that ϕpJq � 1.

ϕ is valid when ϕpI q � 1 for all I P IntpTnq.

Θn � tϕ P ITLn | ϕÑ lϕ is validu.

Translation: if ϕ is true in I , then ϕ is true in all subintervals of I .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Two new connectives:

� plϕqpI q � 1 when, for all intervals J � I , ϕpJq � 1;

� p♦ϕqpI q � 1 when there exists an interval J � I such that ϕpJq � 1.

ϕ is valid when ϕpI q � 1 for all I P IntpTnq.

Θn � tϕ P ITLn | ϕÑ lϕ is validu.

Translation: if ϕ is true in I , then ϕ is true in all subintervals of I .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Two new connectives:

� plϕqpI q � 1 when, for all intervals J � I , ϕpJq � 1;

� p♦ϕqpI q � 1 when there exists an interval J � I such that ϕpJq � 1.

ϕ is valid when ϕpI q � 1 for all I P IntpTnq.

Θn � tϕ P ITLn | ϕÑ lϕ is validu.

Translation: if ϕ is true in I , then ϕ is true in all subintervals of I .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Two new connectives:

� plϕqpI q � 1 when, for all intervals J � I , ϕpJq � 1;

� p♦ϕqpI q � 1 when there exists an interval J � I such that ϕpJq � 1.

ϕ is valid when ϕpI q � 1 for all I P IntpTnq.

Θn � tϕ P ITLn | ϕÑ lϕ is validu.

Translation: if ϕ is true in I , then ϕ is true in all subintervals of I .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Two new connectives:

� plϕqpI q � 1 when, for all intervals J � I , ϕpJq � 1;

� p♦ϕqpI q � 1 when there exists an interval J � I such that ϕpJq � 1.

ϕ is valid when ϕpI q � 1 for all I P IntpTnq.

Θn � tϕ P ITLn | ϕÑ lϕ is validu.

Translation: if ϕ is true in I , then ϕ is true in all subintervals of I .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Behavior of Θn with respect to classical connectives:

Proposition (F. (2015+))

� ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ ϕ^ ψ,ϕ_ ψ P Θn.

� Dϕ P Θn : ϕ R Θn.

� Dϕ,ψ P Θn : ϕÑ ψ R Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Behavior of Θn with respect to classical connectives:

Proposition (F. (2015+))

� ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ ϕ^ ψ,ϕ_ ψ P Θn.

� Dϕ P Θn : ϕ R Θn.

� Dϕ,ψ P Θn : ϕÑ ψ R Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Behavior of Θn with respect to classical connectives:

Proposition (F. (2015+))

� ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ ϕ^ ψ,ϕ_ ψ P Θn.

� Dϕ P Θn : ϕ R Θn.

� Dϕ,ψ P Θn : ϕÑ ψ R Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Behavior of Θn with respect to classical connectives:

Proposition (F. (2015+))

� ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ ϕ^ ψ,ϕ_ ψ P Θn.

� Dϕ P Θn : ϕ R Θn.

� Dϕ,ψ P Θn : ϕÑ ψ R Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

We need better negation and implication!

Define two new connectives � (pseudonegation) and ù(pseudoimplication) with the following semantics:

� p�ϕqpI q � 1 whenever @J � I , ϕpJq � 0;

� pϕù ψqpI q � 1 whenever @J � I , if ϕpJq � 1, then ψpJq � 1.

ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ�ϕ, ϕ ù ψ P Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

We need better negation and implication!

Define two new connectives � (pseudonegation) and ù(pseudoimplication) with the following semantics:

� p�ϕqpI q � 1 whenever @J � I , ϕpJq � 0;

� pϕù ψqpI q � 1 whenever @J � I , if ϕpJq � 1, then ψpJq � 1.

ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ�ϕ, ϕ ù ψ P Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

We need better negation and implication!

Define two new connectives � (pseudonegation) and ù(pseudoimplication) with the following semantics:

� p�ϕqpI q � 1 whenever @J � I , ϕpJq � 0;

� pϕù ψqpI q � 1 whenever @J � I , if ϕpJq � 1, then ψpJq � 1.

ϕ,ψ P Θn ñ�ϕ, ϕ ù ψ P Θn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Pseudonegation has the typical behavior of an intuitionistic negation.

� ϕpI q � 1 ñ p��ϕqpI q � 1, but the converse does not hold ingeneral;

� p�ϕqpI q � 1 ô p���ϕqpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The logic of subintervals

Pseudonegation has the typical behavior of an intuitionistic negation.

� ϕpI q � 1 ñ p��ϕqpI q � 1, but the converse does not hold ingeneral;

� p�ϕqpI q � 1 ô p���ϕqpI q � 1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

� ϕ () ψ when vpϕq � vpψq.� () is an equivalence relation on Θn which preserves _,^,ù,�.

� Canonical distributive lattice structure on the quotient Θn{().

Proposition (F. (2015+))For every ϕ,ψ P Θn, we have:

rϕsù rψs �ªtrαs P Θn{() | rϕs ^ rαs ¤ rψsu.

In other words, ù is the relative pseudocomplement operation in thecanonical Heyting algebra structure of rΘns.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

� ϕ () ψ when vpϕq � vpψq.� () is an equivalence relation on Θn which preserves _,^,ù,�.

� Canonical distributive lattice structure on the quotient Θn{().

Proposition (F. (2015+))For every ϕ,ψ P Θn, we have:

rϕsù rψs �ªtrαs P Θn{() | rϕs ^ rαs ¤ rψsu.

In other words, ù is the relative pseudocomplement operation in thecanonical Heyting algebra structure of rΘns.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

� ϕ () ψ when vpϕq � vpψq.� () is an equivalence relation on Θn which preserves _,^,ù,�.

� Canonical distributive lattice structure on the quotient Θn{().

Proposition (F. (2015+))For every ϕ,ψ P Θn, we have:

rϕsù rψs �ªtrαs P Θn{() | rϕs ^ rαs ¤ rψsu.

In other words, ù is the relative pseudocomplement operation in thecanonical Heyting algebra structure of rΘns.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

� ϕ () ψ when vpϕq � vpψq.� () is an equivalence relation on Θn which preserves _,^,ù,�.

� Canonical distributive lattice structure on the quotient Θn{().

Proposition (F. (2015+))For every ϕ,ψ P Θn, we have:

rϕsù rψs �ªtrαs P Θn{() | rϕs ^ rαs ¤ rψsu.

In other words, ù is the relative pseudocomplement operation in thecanonical Heyting algebra structure of rΘns.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

Lemma (F. (2015+))For any ϕ P ITLn, set ϕ ���ϕ. Given an interval I of rns, set εI �

�iPI εi . Then,

for any ϕ P Θn, there exists an antichain of intervals I1, I2, . . . , Ir of rns such that

ϕ () εI1 _ εI2 _ � � � _ εIr .

Moreover, when the intervals are listed in increasing order of their minima, the aboveone is the unique proposition of that form equivalent to ϕ.

This will be called the closed disjunctive form (CDF) of ϕ.

Theorem (F. (2015+))The Heyting algebra Dn of Dyck paths of semilength n is isomorphic tothe Heyting algebra rΘn�1s.Therefore, a Dyck path of semilength n can be identified with a suitableantichain of intervals of rn � 1s.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

Lemma (F. (2015+))For any ϕ P ITLn, set ϕ ���ϕ. Given an interval I of rns, set εI �

�iPI εi . Then,

for any ϕ P Θn, there exists an antichain of intervals I1, I2, . . . , Ir of rns such that

ϕ () εI1 _ εI2 _ � � � _ εIr .

Moreover, when the intervals are listed in increasing order of their minima, the aboveone is the unique proposition of that form equivalent to ϕ.

This will be called the closed disjunctive form (CDF) of ϕ.

Theorem (F. (2015+))The Heyting algebra Dn of Dyck paths of semilength n is isomorphic tothe Heyting algebra rΘn�1s.Therefore, a Dyck path of semilength n can be identified with a suitableantichain of intervals of rn � 1s.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

Lemma (F. (2015+))For any ϕ P ITLn, set ϕ ���ϕ. Given an interval I of rns, set εI �

�iPI εi . Then,

for any ϕ P Θn, there exists an antichain of intervals I1, I2, . . . , Ir of rns such that

ϕ () εI1 _ εI2 _ � � � _ εIr .

Moreover, when the intervals are listed in increasing order of their minima, the aboveone is the unique proposition of that form equivalent to ϕ.

This will be called the closed disjunctive form (CDF) of ϕ.

Theorem (F. (2015+))The Heyting algebra Dn of Dyck paths of semilength n is isomorphic tothe Heyting algebra rΘn�1s.Therefore, a Dyck path of semilength n can be identified with a suitableantichain of intervals of rn � 1s.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

The logic of subintervals

The isomorphism theorem

Lemma (F. (2015+))For any ϕ P ITLn, set ϕ ���ϕ. Given an interval I of rns, set εI �

�iPI εi . Then,

for any ϕ P Θn, there exists an antichain of intervals I1, I2, . . . , Ir of rns such that

ϕ () εI1 _ εI2 _ � � � _ εIr .

Moreover, when the intervals are listed in increasing order of their minima, the aboveone is the unique proposition of that form equivalent to ϕ.

This will be called the closed disjunctive form (CDF) of ϕ.

Theorem (F. (2015+))The Heyting algebra Dn of Dyck paths of semilength n is isomorphic tothe Heyting algebra rΘn�1s.Therefore, a Dyck path of semilength n can be identified with a suitableantichain of intervals of rn � 1s.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Posets of intervals

A more general point of view:

� Given a finite poset P, consider IntpPq (intervals of P) ordered bycontainment.

� Study the Heyting algebra OpIntpPqq obtained via Birkhoff theorem(P is the set of atoms of OpIntpPqq).

� Interesting cases (|P| � n):

1. P discrete ñ OpIntpPqq � Bn (Boolean algebra having n atoms);2. P linearly ordered ñ OpIntpPqq � Dn�1;3. P Boolean algebra ñ IntpPq � cubical lattices of faces of an n-cubeñ OpIntpPqq �??? (Rota, Metropolis (1978), Bailey, Oliveira(1998), Mundici (2016)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Posets of intervals

A more general point of view:

� Given a finite poset P, consider IntpPq (intervals of P) ordered bycontainment.

� Study the Heyting algebra OpIntpPqq obtained via Birkhoff theorem(P is the set of atoms of OpIntpPqq).

� Interesting cases (|P| � n):

1. P discrete ñ OpIntpPqq � Bn (Boolean algebra having n atoms);2. P linearly ordered ñ OpIntpPqq � Dn�1;3. P Boolean algebra ñ IntpPq � cubical lattices of faces of an n-cubeñ OpIntpPqq �??? (Rota, Metropolis (1978), Bailey, Oliveira(1998), Mundici (2016)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Posets of intervals

A more general point of view:

� Given a finite poset P, consider IntpPq (intervals of P) ordered bycontainment.

� Study the Heyting algebra OpIntpPqq obtained via Birkhoff theorem(P is the set of atoms of OpIntpPqq).

� Interesting cases (|P| � n):

1. P discrete ñ OpIntpPqq � Bn (Boolean algebra having n atoms);2. P linearly ordered ñ OpIntpPqq � Dn�1;3. P Boolean algebra ñ IntpPq � cubical lattices of faces of an n-cubeñ OpIntpPqq �??? (Rota, Metropolis (1978), Bailey, Oliveira(1998), Mundici (2016)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Posets of intervals

A more general point of view:

� Given a finite poset P, consider IntpPq (intervals of P) ordered bycontainment.

� Study the Heyting algebra OpIntpPqq obtained via Birkhoff theorem(P is the set of atoms of OpIntpPqq).

� Interesting cases (|P| � n):

1. P discrete ñ OpIntpPqq � Bn (Boolean algebra having n atoms);2. P linearly ordered ñ OpIntpPqq � Dn�1;3. P Boolean algebra ñ IntpPq � cubical lattices of faces of an n-cubeñ OpIntpPqq �??? (Rota, Metropolis (1978), Bailey, Oliveira(1998), Mundici (2016)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Posets of intervals

A more general point of view:

� Given a finite poset P, consider IntpPq (intervals of P) ordered bycontainment.

� Study the Heyting algebra OpIntpPqq obtained via Birkhoff theorem(P is the set of atoms of OpIntpPqq).

� Interesting cases (|P| � n):

1. P discrete ñ OpIntpPqq � Bn (Boolean algebra having n atoms);2. P linearly ordered ñ OpIntpPqq � Dn�1;3. P Boolean algebra ñ IntpPq � cubical lattices of faces of an n-cubeñ OpIntpPqq �??? (Rota, Metropolis (1978), Bailey, Oliveira(1998), Mundici (2016)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Posets of intervals

A more general point of view:

� Given a finite poset P, consider IntpPq (intervals of P) ordered bycontainment.

� Study the Heyting algebra OpIntpPqq obtained via Birkhoff theorem(P is the set of atoms of OpIntpPqq).

� Interesting cases (|P| � n):

1. P discrete ñ OpIntpPqq � Bn (Boolean algebra having n atoms);2. P linearly ordered ñ OpIntpPqq � Dn�1;3. P Boolean algebra ñ IntpPq � cubical lattices of faces of an n-cubeñ OpIntpPqq �??? (Rota, Metropolis (1978), Bailey, Oliveira(1998), Mundici (2016)).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

Is it possible to recover combinatorial properties of Dyck paths from theHeyting algebra structure of Dn and from the linear order structure of itsatoms?

P a Dyck path of semilength n.

� FP � tI1, . . . , Imu: antichain of intervals of rn � 1s associated withP;

� |FP | � m: number of intervals of FP ;

� }FP} � |I1 Y � � � Y Im|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

Is it possible to recover combinatorial properties of Dyck paths from theHeyting algebra structure of Dn and from the linear order structure of itsatoms?

P a Dyck path of semilength n.

� FP � tI1, . . . , Imu: antichain of intervals of rn � 1s associated withP;

� |FP | � m: number of intervals of FP ;

� }FP} � |I1 Y � � � Y Im|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

Is it possible to recover combinatorial properties of Dyck paths from theHeyting algebra structure of Dn and from the linear order structure of itsatoms?

P a Dyck path of semilength n.

� FP � tI1, . . . , Imu: antichain of intervals of rn � 1s associated withP;

� |FP | � m: number of intervals of FP ;

� }FP} � |I1 Y � � � Y Im|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

Is it possible to recover combinatorial properties of Dyck paths from theHeyting algebra structure of Dn and from the linear order structure of itsatoms?

P a Dyck path of semilength n.

� FP � tI1, . . . , Imu: antichain of intervals of rn � 1s associated withP;

� |FP | � m: number of intervals of FP ;

� }FP} � |I1 Y � � � Y Im|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Posets of intervals

Combinatorial statistics on Dyck paths

A bunch of interesting statistics (F. (2015+)):

� Number of peaks of P: |FP | � }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Number of hills of P: }F�P} � |F��P |.

� Sum of the heights of the peaks of P:}FP} � |FP | � }F�P} � |F�

�P | � n � 1 � |FP | � |F��P |.

� Number of returns of P: }F�P} � 1.

� Height of the first peak of P:"|I1| � 1 , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of peaks before the first return of P:"maxtk | Ii�1 and Ii are not distanced, for all i ¤ ku , if 1 P I11 , otherwise

.

� Number of occurrences of the (consecutive) factor duu:|ti ¤ n � 1 | either Ii�1 and Ii are distanced or |Ii�1|   |Ii |u|.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Open problems

Further work

� Heyting algebra structure of the finite distributive lattice of thedownsets of the poset of intervals of a finite (poset).

� Algebraic characterization of Dyck lattices and of Dyck algebras.

� Analogous approach in the Motzkin and Schroder cases.

� Other kinds of interval temporal logics.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Open problems

Further work

� Heyting algebra structure of the finite distributive lattice of thedownsets of the poset of intervals of a finite (poset).

� Algebraic characterization of Dyck lattices and of Dyck algebras.

� Analogous approach in the Motzkin and Schroder cases.

� Other kinds of interval temporal logics.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Open problems

Further work

� Heyting algebra structure of the finite distributive lattice of thedownsets of the poset of intervals of a finite (poset).

� Algebraic characterization of Dyck lattices and of Dyck algebras.

� Analogous approach in the Motzkin and Schroder cases.

� Other kinds of interval temporal logics.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Heyting algebra structure

Open problems

Further work

� Heyting algebra structure of the finite distributive lattice of thedownsets of the poset of intervals of a finite (poset).

� Algebraic characterization of Dyck lattices and of Dyck algebras.

� Analogous approach in the Motzkin and Schroder cases.

� Other kinds of interval temporal logics.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Statement of the problem

Given a poset, a very natural problem is to count how many chains ithas...

... and another one is to count saturated chains...(which one is easier?)

A saturated chain in a poset is a chain such that, if x   y areconsecutive elements in the chain, then y covers x .

We aim at finding formulas for the enumeration of chains and saturatedchains of length h, for any h P N, in the sequence of posets Pdetermined by a given class of paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Statement of the problem

Given a poset, a very natural problem is to count how many chains ithas...

... and another one is to count saturated chains...(which one is easier?)

A saturated chain in a poset is a chain such that, if x   y areconsecutive elements in the chain, then y covers x .

We aim at finding formulas for the enumeration of chains and saturatedchains of length h, for any h P N, in the sequence of posets Pdetermined by a given class of paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Statement of the problem

Given a poset, a very natural problem is to count how many chains ithas...

... and another one is to count saturated chains...(which one is easier?)

A saturated chain in a poset is a chain such that, if x   y areconsecutive elements in the chain, then y covers x .

We aim at finding formulas for the enumeration of chains and saturatedchains of length h, for any h P N, in the sequence of posets Pdetermined by a given class of paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Statement of the problem

Given a poset, a very natural problem is to count how many chains ithas...

... and another one is to count saturated chains...(which one is easier?)

A saturated chain in a poset is a chain such that, if x   y areconsecutive elements in the chain, then y covers x .

We aim at finding formulas for the enumeration of chains and saturatedchains of length h, for any h P N, in the sequence of posets Pdetermined by a given class of paths.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Chains in Dyck lattices

Chains in Dyck latticesCounting multichains in Dyck lattices: Lindstrom,Gessel,Viennot.

A0A1A2 B0 B1 B2

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Chains in Dyck lattices

Chains in Dyck lattices

Proposition (F., Munarini (2015))The number of k-multichains in Dn is given by

mkpDnq � detrCn�i�j ski,j�0 �

∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣Cn Cn�1 � � � Cn�k

Cn�1 Cn�2 � � � Cn�k�1

......

...Cn�k Cn�k�1 � � � Cn�2k

∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣ .

Theorem (F., Munarini (2015))The number of k-chains in Dn is given by

ckpDnq �k

i�0

�k

i

p�1qk�i �

±i�1j�1 Cn�j�1 �

±ij�1p2j � 1q!±i

j�1pn � j � 1qj � pn � 2i � 2� jqj

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Chains in Dyck lattices

Chains in Dyck lattices

Proposition (F., Munarini (2015))The number of k-multichains in Dn is given by

mkpDnq � detrCn�i�j ski,j�0 �

∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣Cn Cn�1 � � � Cn�k

Cn�1 Cn�2 � � � Cn�k�1

......

...Cn�k Cn�k�1 � � � Cn�2k

∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣∣ .

Theorem (F., Munarini (2015))The number of k-chains in Dn is given by

ckpDnq �k

i�0

�k

i

p�1qk�i �

±i�1j�1 Cn�j�1 �

±ij�1p2j � 1q!±i

j�1pn � j � 1qj � pn � 2i � 2� jqj

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

Saturated chains: the case h � 1

The easiest case occurs when h � 1. These are saturated chains of length1 or, equivalently, edges in the Hasse diagram of the considered posets.

General strategy for counting edges in the Hasse diagram of a sequenceof posets P � pPnqnPN:

� `pPnq �°

xPPn|∆x |, where ∆x is the set of all elements covering x

in Pn;

� `pPnq ��B∆pPn,qq

Bq

�q�1

, where ∆pPn, qq �°

xPPnq|∆x|;

� `Ppxq ��B∆Ppq,xq

Bq

�q�1

, where `Ppxq �°

n `pPnqxn and

∆Ppq, xq �°

n ∆pPn, qqxn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

Saturated chains: the case h � 1

The easiest case occurs when h � 1. These are saturated chains of length1 or, equivalently, edges in the Hasse diagram of the considered posets.

General strategy for counting edges in the Hasse diagram of a sequenceof posets P � pPnqnPN:

� `pPnq �°

xPPn|∆x |, where ∆x is the set of all elements covering x

in Pn;

� `pPnq ��B∆pPn,qq

Bq

�q�1

, where ∆pPn, qq �°

xPPnq|∆x|;

� `Ppxq ��B∆Ppq,xq

Bq

�q�1

, where `Ppxq �°

n `pPnqxn and

∆Ppq, xq �°

n ∆pPn, qqxn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

Saturated chains: the case h � 1

The easiest case occurs when h � 1. These are saturated chains of length1 or, equivalently, edges in the Hasse diagram of the considered posets.

General strategy for counting edges in the Hasse diagram of a sequenceof posets P � pPnqnPN:

� `pPnq �°

xPPn|∆x |, where ∆x is the set of all elements covering x

in Pn;

� `pPnq ��B∆pPn,qq

Bq

�q�1

, where ∆pPn, qq �°

xPPnq|∆x|;

� `Ppxq ��B∆Ppq,xq

Bq

�q�1

, where `Ppxq �°

n `pPnqxn and

∆Ppq, xq �°

n ∆pPn, qqxn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

Saturated chains: the case h � 1

The easiest case occurs when h � 1. These are saturated chains of length1 or, equivalently, edges in the Hasse diagram of the considered posets.

General strategy for counting edges in the Hasse diagram of a sequenceof posets P � pPnqnPN:

� `pPnq �°

xPPn|∆x |, where ∆x is the set of all elements covering x

in Pn;

� `pPnq ��B∆pPn,qq

Bq

�q�1

, where ∆pPn, qq �°

xPPnq|∆x|;

� `Ppxq ��B∆Ppq,xq

Bq

�q�1

, where `Ppxq �°

n `pPnqxn and

∆Ppq, xq �°

n ∆pPn, qqxn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

The covering relation

Combinatorial interpretation of the covering relation in the Dyck,Motzkin and Schroder cases, respectively (γ denotes an arbitrary path ofthe class):

� Dyck: |∆γ| � #pduqγ ;

� Motzkin: |∆γ| � #phuqγ �#pdhqγ �#pduqγ �#phhqγ ;

� Schroder: |∆γ| � #ph2qγ �#pduqγ .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

The covering relation

Combinatorial interpretation of the covering relation in the Dyck,Motzkin and Schroder cases, respectively (γ denotes an arbitrary path ofthe class):

� Dyck: |∆γ| � #pduqγ ;

� Motzkin: |∆γ| � #phuqγ �#pdhqγ �#pduqγ �#phhqγ ;

� Schroder: |∆γ| � #ph2qγ �#pduqγ .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

The covering relation

Combinatorial interpretation of the covering relation in the Dyck,Motzkin and Schroder cases, respectively (γ denotes an arbitrary path ofthe class):

� Dyck: |∆γ| � #pduqγ ;

� Motzkin: |∆γ| � #phuqγ �#pdhqγ �#pduqγ �#phhqγ ;

� Schroder: |∆γ| � #ph2qγ �#pduqγ .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

Main results

A summary of the results we have obtained is reported in the next table(F., Munarini (2014)).

Poset Edge generating function Coefficients

Dyck1�3x�p1�xq?1�4x

2x?

1�4x12

�2nn

n�1n�1

��

2n�1n�2

Grand Dyck x

p1�4xq3{2�

2nn

n2

Motzkinp1�xqp1�2x�x2�p1�xq

b1�2x�3x2q

2x2b

1�2x�3x2

�n; 3n

� Mn �

�n�1; 3n�1

� Mn�1 pn ¥ 1q

Grand Motzkin 2x2

p1�3xqb

1�2x�3x22°nk�0

�k; 3k

3n�k

Schroderp1�xqp1�4x�x2�p1�xq

b1�6x�x2q

2x

b1�6x�x2

°nk�0

��2k

n�k

�2kk

k

k�1

Grand Schroder2px�x2q

p1�6x�x2q3{2 2°nk�0

�n�k

2k

�2kk

pn � kq

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains of length 1

Main results

A summary of the results we have obtained is reported in the next table(F., Munarini (2014)).

Poset Edge generating function Coefficients

Dyck1�3x�p1�xq?1�4x

2x?

1�4x12

�2nn

n�1n�1

��

2n�1n�2

Grand Dyck x

p1�4xq3{2�

2nn

n2

Motzkinp1�xqp1�2x�x2�p1�xq

b1�2x�3x2q

2x2b

1�2x�3x2

�n; 3n

� Mn �

�n�1; 3n�1

� Mn�1 pn ¥ 1q

Grand Motzkin 2x2

p1�3xqb

1�2x�3x22°nk�0

�k; 3k

3n�k

Schroderp1�xqp1�4x�x2�p1�xq

b1�6x�x2q

2x

b1�6x�x2

°nk�0

��2k

n�k

�2kk

k

k�1

Grand Schroder2px�x2q

p1�6x�x2q3{2 2°nk�0

�n�k

2k

�2kk

pn � kq

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

... but what happens for longer saturated chains? We address thisproblem in the case of Dyck lattices.

Let γ   γ1 be two Dyck paths having the same length. A saturated chainstarting from γ and ending at γ1 is essentially equivalent to a certain setof skew Young tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

... but what happens for longer saturated chains? We address thisproblem in the case of Dyck lattices.

Let γ   γ1 be two Dyck paths having the same length. A saturated chainstarting from γ and ending at γ1 is essentially equivalent to a certain setof skew Young tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

... but what happens for longer saturated chains? We address thisproblem in the case of Dyck lattices.

Let γ   γ1 be two Dyck paths having the same length. A saturated chainstarting from γ and ending at γ1 is essentially equivalent to a certain setof skew Young tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

How many saturated chains of length h are there in Dn starting from agiven path γ?

� Start with a partition λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq of h.

� Next choose a set γ1, . . . , γk of pairwise disjoint factors of γ suchthat, for any i ¤ k, we can build a skew Ferrers shape ϕi on γihaving area λi .

� Finally, linearly order the cells of the Ferrers shapes thus obtained,or, equivalently, endow each of the shapes with a skew Youngtableaux structure.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

How many saturated chains of length h are there in Dn starting from agiven path γ?

� Start with a partition λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq of h.

� Next choose a set γ1, . . . , γk of pairwise disjoint factors of γ suchthat, for any i ¤ k, we can build a skew Ferrers shape ϕi on γihaving area λi .

� Finally, linearly order the cells of the Ferrers shapes thus obtained,or, equivalently, endow each of the shapes with a skew Youngtableaux structure.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

How many saturated chains of length h are there in Dn starting from agiven path γ?

� Start with a partition λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq of h.

� Next choose a set γ1, . . . , γk of pairwise disjoint factors of γ suchthat, for any i ¤ k, we can build a skew Ferrers shape ϕi on γihaving area λi .

� Finally, linearly order the cells of the Ferrers shapes thus obtained,or, equivalently, endow each of the shapes with a skew Youngtableaux structure.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h ¡ 1 for Dyck lattices

How many saturated chains of length h are there in Dn starting from agiven path γ?

� Start with a partition λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq of h.

� Next choose a set γ1, . . . , γk of pairwise disjoint factors of γ suchthat, for any i ¤ k, we can build a skew Ferrers shape ϕi on γihaving area λi .

� Finally, linearly order the cells of the Ferrers shapes thus obtained,or, equivalently, endow each of the shapes with a skew Youngtableaux structure.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The general formula

Since the set of integers actually used to fill in the cells of each ϕi can beany possible set of λi integers less than or equal to h, we have proved thefollowing:

Theorem (F., Munarini (2015))The number schpDnq of saturated chains of length h of the lattice Dn isgiven by the following formula:¸

γPDn

¸λ$h

¸γ1,...,γk p.d.o.

p@iqpDϕiPSkFSpλi qqbpϕi q�γi

¸pϕ1,...,ϕk qPSkFSk

p@iqpbpϕi q�γi ,Apϕi q�λi q

� h

Apϕ1q, . . . ,Apϕk q

tpϕ1q � � � tpϕk q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 2 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 2:

� 2 partitions of 2: p1, 1q and p2q;� one pair of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the pair.

� two skew Ferrers shapes of area 2: and ; one Young tableauxstructure on such shape.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 2 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 2:

� 2 partitions of 2: p1, 1q and p2q;� one pair of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the pair.

� two skew Ferrers shapes of area 2: and ; one Young tableauxstructure on such shape.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 2 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 2:

� 2 partitions of 2: p1, 1q and p2q;� one pair of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the pair.

� two skew Ferrers shapes of area 2: and ; one Young tableauxstructure on such shape.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 2 for Dyck lattices

Proposition (F., Munarini (2015))The generating series for the number of saturated chains of length 2 ofDyck lattices is given by

SC2pxq �¸n¥0

� ¸γPDn

p2 �#pdu, duqγ �#pdduqγ �#pduuqγq�xn,

where with #pγ1, . . . , γkqγ we denote the number of pairwise disjointoccurrences of the γi ’s in γ.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 2 for Dyck lattices

Denote with F pq, xq and V pq, xq the generating series of all Dyck pathswhere x keeps track of the semilength and q keeps track of the factorduu and of the factor du (i.e. valleys), respectively. Then

SC2pxq � 2 ��BFBq�q�1

��B2V

Bq2

�q�1

� 1� 6x � 6x2 � p1� 4xq?1� 4x

�p1� 4xq?1� 4x.

Consequently

sc2pDnq ��

2n

n

pn � 1qpn � 2q2p2n � 1q pn ¥ 1q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 2 for Dyck lattices

The integer sequence associated with SC2pxq starts0, 0, 0, 4, 30, 168, 840, 3960, 18018, 80080, . . .. Observe that the terms ofthe above sequence divided by 2 yield sequence A002740 of the SloaneEncyclopedia. In terms of Dyck paths, this sequence gives the sum of theabscissae of the valleys in all Dyck paths of semilength n� 1. It would benice to have a combinatorial explanation of this fact.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 3 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 3:

� 3 partitions of 3: p1, 1, 1q, p2, 1q and p3q;� one triple of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the triple.

� two pairs of skew Ferrers shapes of area 2 and 1 respectively: p , qand p , q; one Young tableaux structure on each shape of eachpair.

� four skew Ferrers shapes of area 3: , , and ; one Youngtableaux structure on each of the first two shapes, two Young

tableaux structures on each of the last two shapes:3

2 1 ,2

3 1 and3 12 ,

3 21 .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 3 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 3:

� 3 partitions of 3: p1, 1, 1q, p2, 1q and p3q;� one triple of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the triple.

� two pairs of skew Ferrers shapes of area 2 and 1 respectively: p , qand p , q; one Young tableaux structure on each shape of eachpair.

� four skew Ferrers shapes of area 3: , , and ; one Youngtableaux structure on each of the first two shapes, two Young

tableaux structures on each of the last two shapes:3

2 1 ,2

3 1 and3 12 ,

3 21 .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 3 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 3:

� 3 partitions of 3: p1, 1, 1q, p2, 1q and p3q;� one triple of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the triple.

� two pairs of skew Ferrers shapes of area 2 and 1 respectively: p , qand p , q; one Young tableaux structure on each shape of eachpair.

� four skew Ferrers shapes of area 3: , , and ; one Youngtableaux structure on each of the first two shapes, two Young

tableaux structures on each of the last two shapes:3

2 1 ,2

3 1 and3 12 ,

3 21 .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 3 for Dyck lattices

Case h � 3:

� 3 partitions of 3: p1, 1, 1q, p2, 1q and p3q;� one triple of skew Ferrers shapes of area 1: p , , q; one Young

tableaux structure on each shape of the triple.

� two pairs of skew Ferrers shapes of area 2 and 1 respectively: p , qand p , q; one Young tableaux structure on each shape of eachpair.

� four skew Ferrers shapes of area 3: , , and ; one Youngtableaux structure on each of the first two shapes, two Young

tableaux structures on each of the last two shapes:3

2 1 ,2

3 1 and3 12 ,

3 21 .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 3 for Dyck lattices

Proposition (F., Munarini (2015))The generating series for the number of saturated chains of length 3 ofDyck lattices is given by

SC3pxq �¸n¥0

¸γPDn

p6 �#pdu, du, duqγ � 3 �#pdu, dduqγ

� 3 �#pdu, duuqγ �#pddduqγ �#pduuuqγ� 2 �#pdduuqγ � 2 �#pduduqγq xn.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 3 for Dyck lattices

Denote with Apq, xq, Bpq, xq and C pq, xq the generating series of Dyckpaths where x keeps track of the semilength and q keeps track of thefactors dduu, dudu and duuu, respectively. Moreover, let V pq, xq andF py , q, xq be defined as before, except that we have now added anindeterminate y in F to keep track of valleys (i.e. of the factor du). Then

SC3pxq � 2 ��BABq�q�1

� 2 ��BBBq�q�1

� 2 ��BCBq�q�1

��B3V

Bq3

�q�1

� 6 �� B2F

ByBq �BFBq�y�q�1

� Ppxq � Qpxq?1� 4x

xp1� 4xq3 ,

for Ppxq � 1�13x �59x2�100x3�16x4�64x5 � p1�4xq3p1� x � x2qand Qpxq � 1� 11x � 39x2 � 40x3 � 22x4.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 4 for Dyck lattices

We have results for h=4 as well...

SC4pxq �¸n¥0

sc4pDnq xn � ppxq � qpxq?1� 4x

xp1� 4xq4 ,

where

ppxq � 1� 12x � 31x2 � 144x3 � 864x4 � 1280x5 � 256x6,

qpxq � 1� 10x � 13x2 � 154x3 � 560x4 � 488x5 � 88x6.

Moreover, the coefficients sc4pDnq can be expressed as

sc4pDnq ��

2n

n

pn4 � 2n3 � 13n2 � 4n � 8qpn � 3qpn � 2q4p2n � 1qp2n � 3qpn � 1q pn ¥ 2q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Saturated chains in Dyck lattices

The case h � 4 for Dyck lattices

We have results for h=4 as well...

SC4pxq �¸n¥0

sc4pDnq xn � ppxq � qpxq?1� 4x

xp1� 4xq4 ,

where

ppxq � 1� 12x � 31x2 � 144x3 � 864x4 � 1280x5 � 256x6,

qpxq � 1� 10x � 13x2 � 154x3 � 560x4 � 488x5 � 88x6.

Moreover, the coefficients sc4pDnq can be expressed as

sc4pDnq ��

2n

n

pn4 � 2n3 � 13n2 � 4n � 8qpn � 3qpn � 2q4p2n � 1qp2n � 3qpn � 1q pn ¥ 2q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Open problems

Further work

� A conjecture for general h:

schpDnq ��

2n�hn

��2nn

� 1

n � h � 1phpnq�Cn �

�2n � h

n

phpnq

pn � 1qpn � h � 1q ,

where phpnq is a monic polynomial of degree h� 1 (this formula onlymakes sense for n ¥ h).

� This approach is computationally difficult when h becomes big.Alternative approaches?

� What about other lattices of paths (Motzkin, Schroder)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Open problems

Further work

� A conjecture for general h:

schpDnq ��

2n�hn

��2nn

� 1

n � h � 1phpnq�Cn �

�2n � h

n

phpnq

pn � 1qpn � h � 1q ,

where phpnq is a monic polynomial of degree h� 1 (this formula onlymakes sense for n ¥ h).

� This approach is computationally difficult when h becomes big.Alternative approaches?

� What about other lattices of paths (Motzkin, Schroder)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Counting chains in lattices of paths

Open problems

Further work

� A conjecture for general h:

schpDnq ��

2n�hn

��2nn

� 1

n � h � 1phpnq�Cn �

�2n � h

n

phpnq

pn � 1qpn � h � 1q ,

where phpnq is a monic polynomial of degree h� 1 (this formula onlymakes sense for n ¥ h).

� This approach is computationally difficult when h becomes big.Alternative approaches?

� What about other lattices of paths (Motzkin, Schroder)?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

The case of Schroder paths

What if we replace Dyck paths with Schroder paths? Can we use thesame approach to count saturated chains?

The main difference lies in the shapes we obtain by taking the regionbetween two comparable Schroder paths.

Let’s compare the two situations.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

The case of Schroder paths

What if we replace Dyck paths with Schroder paths? Can we use thesame approach to count saturated chains?

The main difference lies in the shapes we obtain by taking the regionbetween two comparable Schroder paths.

Let’s compare the two situations.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

The case of Schroder paths

What if we replace Dyck paths with Schroder paths? Can we use thesame approach to count saturated chains?

The main difference lies in the shapes we obtain by taking the regionbetween two comparable Schroder paths.

Let’s compare the two situations.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

Young tableaux and Dyck lattices

The Dyck lattice of order n is isomorphic to (the dual of) the Younglattice of the staircase partition pn � 1, n � 2, . . . , 2, 1q.

A Dyck path (red) and the associated Young shape:

-

6

p p pp p p

pp p p

pp pp pp p p p p��

���

����

@@ @@@

@@@@@

@@������@@

@@@@@@@

p :

This isomorphism determines a bijection between standard Youngtableaux and upper saturated chains of Dyck lattices.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

Young tableaux and Dyck lattices

The Dyck lattice of order n is isomorphic to (the dual of) the Younglattice of the staircase partition pn � 1, n � 2, . . . , 2, 1q.

A Dyck path (red) and the associated Young shape:

-

6

p p pp p p

pp p p

pp pp pp p p p p��

���

����

@@ @@@

@@@@@

@@������@@

@@@@@@@

p :

This isomorphism determines a bijection between standard Youngtableaux and upper saturated chains of Dyck lattices.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

Young tableaux and Dyck lattices

The Dyck lattice of order n is isomorphic to (the dual of) the Younglattice of the staircase partition pn � 1, n � 2, . . . , 2, 1q.

A Dyck path (red) and the associated Young shape:

-

6

p p pp p p

pp p p

pp pp pp p p p p��

���

����

@@ @@@

@@@@@

@@������@@

@@@@@@@

p :

This isomorphism determines a bijection between standard Youngtableaux and upper saturated chains of Dyck lattices.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

Schroder tableaux and Schroder lattices

Similarly to the case of Dyck lattices, we can define a family ofisomorphisms between Schroder lattices and a special class of shapes,which we call Schroder shapes:

-

6

�����

���

���

������

����p

@@@@ p@@@@

p@@@@@@@@@@ @@

@@@ :

���

��

����

�����

12

36

711

16

45

812

910

1315

14

An upper saturated chain in a Schroder lattice corresponds to a Schrodertableau, which is a filling of the triangular cells of a Schroder shape withdistinct positive integers such that both rows and columns are increasing.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

Schroder tableaux and Schroder lattices

Similarly to the case of Dyck lattices, we can define a family ofisomorphisms between Schroder lattices and a special class of shapes,which we call Schroder shapes:

-

6

�����

���

���

������

����p

@@@@ p@@@@

p@@@@@@@@@@ @@

@@@ :

���

��

����

�����

12

36

711

16

45

812

910

1315

14

An upper saturated chain in a Schroder lattice corresponds to a Schrodertableau, which is a filling of the triangular cells of a Schroder shape withdistinct positive integers such that both rows and columns are increasing.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The case of Schroder paths

Schroder tableaux and Schroder lattices

Similarly to the case of Dyck lattices, we can define a family ofisomorphisms between Schroder lattices and a special class of shapes,which we call Schroder shapes:

-

6

�����

���

���

������

����p

@@@@ p@@@@

p@@@@@@@@@@ @@

@@@ :

���

��

����

�����

12

36

711

16

45

812

910

1315

14

An upper saturated chain in a Schroder lattice corresponds to a Schrodertableau, which is a filling of the triangular cells of a Schroder shape withdistinct positive integers such that both rows and columns are increasing.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Schroder partitions and their enumeration

Schroder shapes correspond to partitions whose odd parts are simple(i.e., have multiplicity 1). We call them Schroder partitions.

The enumeration of Schroder partitions is known (sequence A006950 inOEIS). Their generating function is

¹k¡0

1� x2k�1

1� x2k.

There are also far more general results, concerning for instance partitionswhose odd parts have prescribed multiplicities (Drake, 2009).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Schroder partitions and their enumeration

Schroder shapes correspond to partitions whose odd parts are simple(i.e., have multiplicity 1). We call them Schroder partitions.

The enumeration of Schroder partitions is known (sequence A006950 inOEIS). Their generating function is

¹k¡0

1� x2k�1

1� x2k.

There are also far more general results, concerning for instance partitionswhose odd parts have prescribed multiplicities (Drake, 2009).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

A refined enumerative result

sn,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts.s 1n,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts having smallest partdifferent from 1.

PropositionFor all n ¥ k ¥ 1:

(i) sn,k � s 1n,k � s 1n�1,k�1;

(ii) s 1n,k � s 1n�2,k�1 � s 1n�2k�1,k�1 � s 1n�2k,k .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

A refined enumerative result

sn,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts.s 1n,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts having smallest partdifferent from 1.

PropositionFor all n ¥ k ¥ 1:

(i) sn,k � s 1n,k � s 1n�1,k�1;

(ii) s 1n,k � s 1n�2,k�1 � s 1n�2k�1,k�1 � s 1n�2k,k .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

A refined enumerative result

sn,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts.s 1n,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts having smallest partdifferent from 1.

PropositionFor all n ¥ k ¥ 1:

(i) sn,k � s 1n,k � s 1n�1,k�1;

(ii) s 1n,k � s 1n�2,k�1 � s 1n�2k�1,k�1 � s 1n�2k,k .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

A refined enumerative result

sn,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts.s 1n,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts having smallest partdifferent from 1.

PropositionFor all n ¥ k ¥ 1:

(i) sn,k � s 1n,k � s 1n�1,k�1;

(ii) s 1n,k � s 1n�2,k�1 � s 1n�2k�1,k�1 � s 1n�2k,k .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

A refined enumerative result

sn,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts.s 1n,k : number of Schroder partitions of n into k parts having smallest partdifferent from 1.

PropositionFor all n ¥ k ¥ 1:

(i) sn,k � s 1n,k � s 1n�1,k�1;

(ii) s 1n,k � s 1n�2,k�1 � s 1n�2k�1,k�1 � s 1n�2k,k .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Generalized conjugation maps

cn : partitions ÝÑ partitions

: λ ÞÝÑ µ � pµ1, . . . , µkq

such that µi �°in

j�pi�1qn�1 (j-th column of λ).

c3 :

a a a b b b c c ca a a b b b ca a a b b ba a a b b ba a a b b ba a a ba a aa a aa a ÞÝÑ

a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a ab b b b b b b b b b b b b b b bc c c c

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Generalized conjugation maps

cn : partitions ÝÑ partitions

: λ ÞÝÑ µ � pµ1, . . . , µkq

such that µi �°in

j�pi�1qn�1 (j-th column of λ).

c3 :

a a a b b b c c ca a a b b b ca a a b b ba a a b b ba a a b b ba a a ba a aa a aa a ÞÝÑ

a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a a ab b b b b b b b b b b b b b b bc c c c

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Properties of cn

� cn doesn’t modify the size of the input partition, so it is anendofunction on the set of integer partitions of fixed size.

� c1 is the classical conjugation maps (exchanging rows and columns);in particular, it is an involution.

� for all n ¡ 1, cn is not an involution.

Which are the fixed points of c2n?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Properties of cn

� cn doesn’t modify the size of the input partition, so it is anendofunction on the set of integer partitions of fixed size.

� c1 is the classical conjugation maps (exchanging rows and columns);in particular, it is an involution.

� for all n ¡ 1, cn is not an involution.

Which are the fixed points of c2n?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Properties of cn

� cn doesn’t modify the size of the input partition, so it is anendofunction on the set of integer partitions of fixed size.

� c1 is the classical conjugation maps (exchanging rows and columns);in particular, it is an involution.

� for all n ¡ 1, cn is not an involution.

Which are the fixed points of c2n?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Properties of cn

� cn doesn’t modify the size of the input partition, so it is anendofunction on the set of integer partitions of fixed size.

� c1 is the classical conjugation maps (exchanging rows and columns);in particular, it is an involution.

� for all n ¡ 1, cn is not an involution.

Which are the fixed points of c2n?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Properties of cn

� cn doesn’t modify the size of the input partition, so it is anendofunction on the set of integer partitions of fixed size.

� c1 is the classical conjugation maps (exchanging rows and columns);in particular, it is an involution.

� for all n ¡ 1, cn is not an involution.

Which are the fixed points of c2n?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Characterization of the fixed points of cn

PropositionFor λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq, c2

n pλq � λ iff

� for all i , λi � 0 pmod nq ñ λi is simple;

� there is at most one part λi of λ such that λi   n.

Corollary

� c1 is an involution;

� c22 pλq � λ iff λ is a Schroder partition.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Characterization of the fixed points of cn

PropositionFor λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq, c2

n pλq � λ iff

� for all i , λi � 0 pmod nq ñ λi is simple;

� there is at most one part λi of λ such that λi   n.

Corollary

� c1 is an involution;

� c22 pλq � λ iff λ is a Schroder partition.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Characterization of the fixed points of cn

PropositionFor λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq, c2

n pλq � λ iff

� for all i , λi � 0 pmod nq ñ λi is simple;

� there is at most one part λi of λ such that λi   n.

Corollary

� c1 is an involution;

� c22 pλq � λ iff λ is a Schroder partition.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Characterization of the fixed points of cn

PropositionFor λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq, c2

n pλq � λ iff

� for all i , λi � 0 pmod nq ñ λi is simple;

� there is at most one part λi of λ such that λi   n.

Corollary

� c1 is an involution;

� c22 pλq � λ iff λ is a Schroder partition.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Characterization of the fixed points of cn

PropositionFor λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq, c2

n pλq � λ iff

� for all i , λi � 0 pmod nq ñ λi is simple;

� there is at most one part λi of λ such that λi   n.

Corollary

� c1 is an involution;

� c22 pλq � λ iff λ is a Schroder partition.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Characterization of the fixed points of cn

PropositionFor λ � pλ1, . . . , λkq, c2

n pλq � λ iff

� for all i , λi � 0 pmod nq ñ λi is simple;

� there is at most one part λi of λ such that λi   n.

Corollary

� c1 is an involution;

� c22 pλq � λ iff λ is a Schroder partition.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

The Young-Schroder poset

λ ¤ µ when, for all i , λi ¤ µi .

Set of Schroder partitions as a subposet of the Young lattice (of allpartitions): Young-Schroder poset.

But not at all a trivial one! For instance, intervals in the Young latticewhose endpoints are Schroder partitions don’t contain only Schroderpartitions.

In terms of Schroder shapes: the Schroder shape of λ is contained in theSchroder shape of µ when the top left cells coincide.

TheoremThe Young-Schroder poset is a distributive lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

The Young-Schroder poset

λ ¤ µ when, for all i , λi ¤ µi .

Set of Schroder partitions as a subposet of the Young lattice (of allpartitions): Young-Schroder poset.

But not at all a trivial one! For instance, intervals in the Young latticewhose endpoints are Schroder partitions don’t contain only Schroderpartitions.

In terms of Schroder shapes: the Schroder shape of λ is contained in theSchroder shape of µ when the top left cells coincide.

TheoremThe Young-Schroder poset is a distributive lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

The Young-Schroder poset

λ ¤ µ when, for all i , λi ¤ µi .

Set of Schroder partitions as a subposet of the Young lattice (of allpartitions): Young-Schroder poset.

But not at all a trivial one! For instance, intervals in the Young latticewhose endpoints are Schroder partitions don’t contain only Schroderpartitions.

In terms of Schroder shapes: the Schroder shape of λ is contained in theSchroder shape of µ when the top left cells coincide.

TheoremThe Young-Schroder poset is a distributive lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

The Young-Schroder poset

λ ¤ µ when, for all i , λi ¤ µi .

Set of Schroder partitions as a subposet of the Young lattice (of allpartitions): Young-Schroder poset.

But not at all a trivial one! For instance, intervals in the Young latticewhose endpoints are Schroder partitions don’t contain only Schroderpartitions.

In terms of Schroder shapes: the Schroder shape of λ is contained in theSchroder shape of µ when the top left cells coincide.

TheoremThe Young-Schroder poset is a distributive lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

The Young-Schroder poset

λ ¤ µ when, for all i , λi ¤ µi .

Set of Schroder partitions as a subposet of the Young lattice (of allpartitions): Young-Schroder poset.

But not at all a trivial one! For instance, intervals in the Young latticewhose endpoints are Schroder partitions don’t contain only Schroderpartitions.

In terms of Schroder shapes: the Schroder shape of λ is contained in theSchroder shape of µ when the top left cells coincide.

TheoremThe Young-Schroder poset is a distributive lattice.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Differential posets

An r-differential poset (for some positive integer r) is a locally finite,ranked poset P having a minimum and such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by exactly k � relements.

Remark. The Young lattice is a 1-differential poset (in fact, it is theunique 1-differential distributive lattice) (Stanley, 1988).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Differential posets

An r-differential poset (for some positive integer r) is a locally finite,ranked poset P having a minimum and such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by exactly k � relements.

Remark. The Young lattice is a 1-differential poset (in fact, it is theunique 1-differential distributive lattice) (Stanley, 1988).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Differential posets

An r-differential poset (for some positive integer r) is a locally finite,ranked poset P having a minimum and such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by exactly k � relements.

Remark. The Young lattice is a 1-differential poset (in fact, it is theunique 1-differential distributive lattice) (Stanley, 1988).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

Differential posets

An r-differential poset (for some positive integer r) is a locally finite,ranked poset P having a minimum and such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by exactly k � relements.

Remark. The Young lattice is a 1-differential poset (in fact, it is theunique 1-differential distributive lattice) (Stanley, 1988).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

ϕ-differential posetsLet ϕ be a map sending a positive integer k to an interval ϕpkq ofpositive integers. We say that a poset P is a ϕ-differential poset when itis an infinite, locally finite, ranked poset with a minimum such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by l elements, forsome l P ϕpkq.

Remark. If ϕpkq � tk � ru, for all k , then a ϕ-differential poset is justan r -differential poset.

PropositionThere exists ϕ such that the Young-Schroder poset is a ϕ-differentialdistributive lattice. More precisely, let λ be a Schroder partition coveringk Schroder partitions. Then λ is covered by l Schroder partitions, withr k�1

2 s ¤ l ¤ 2k.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

ϕ-differential posetsLet ϕ be a map sending a positive integer k to an interval ϕpkq ofpositive integers. We say that a poset P is a ϕ-differential poset when itis an infinite, locally finite, ranked poset with a minimum such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by l elements, forsome l P ϕpkq.

Remark. If ϕpkq � tk � ru, for all k , then a ϕ-differential poset is justan r -differential poset.

PropositionThere exists ϕ such that the Young-Schroder poset is a ϕ-differentialdistributive lattice. More precisely, let λ be a Schroder partition coveringk Schroder partitions. Then λ is covered by l Schroder partitions, withr k�1

2 s ¤ l ¤ 2k.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

ϕ-differential posetsLet ϕ be a map sending a positive integer k to an interval ϕpkq ofpositive integers. We say that a poset P is a ϕ-differential poset when itis an infinite, locally finite, ranked poset with a minimum such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by l elements, forsome l P ϕpkq.

Remark. If ϕpkq � tk � ru, for all k , then a ϕ-differential poset is justan r -differential poset.

PropositionThere exists ϕ such that the Young-Schroder poset is a ϕ-differentialdistributive lattice. More precisely, let λ be a Schroder partition coveringk Schroder partitions. Then λ is covered by l Schroder partitions, withr k�1

2 s ¤ l ¤ 2k.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

ϕ-differential posetsLet ϕ be a map sending a positive integer k to an interval ϕpkq ofpositive integers. We say that a poset P is a ϕ-differential poset when itis an infinite, locally finite, ranked poset with a minimum such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by l elements, forsome l P ϕpkq.

Remark. If ϕpkq � tk � ru, for all k , then a ϕ-differential poset is justan r -differential poset.

PropositionThere exists ϕ such that the Young-Schroder poset is a ϕ-differentialdistributive lattice. More precisely, let λ be a Schroder partition coveringk Schroder partitions. Then λ is covered by l Schroder partitions, withr k�1

2 s ¤ l ¤ 2k.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

The poset of Schroder partitions

ϕ-differential posetsLet ϕ be a map sending a positive integer k to an interval ϕpkq ofpositive integers. We say that a poset P is a ϕ-differential poset when itis an infinite, locally finite, ranked poset with a minimum such that:

1. for any two distinct elements x , y of P, if there are exactly kelements covered by both x and y , then there are exactly k elementswhich cover both x and y ;

2. if x covers exactly k elements, then x is covered by l elements, forsome l P ϕpkq.

Remark. If ϕpkq � tk � ru, for all k , then a ϕ-differential poset is justan r -differential poset.

PropositionThere exists ϕ such that the Young-Schroder poset is a ϕ-differentialdistributive lattice. More precisely, let λ be a Schroder partition coveringk Schroder partitions. Then λ is covered by l Schroder partitions, withr k�1

2 s ¤ l ¤ 2k.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:= 3 Q:= 1

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:= 3 9 Q:= 1 2

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 93 Q:=

1 23

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 53 9 Q:=

1 23 4

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 5 73 9 Q:=

1 2 53 4

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 2 73 59 Q:=

1 2 53 46

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 2 63 5 79 Q:=

1 2 53 4 76

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 2 43 5 679 Q:=

1 2 53 4 768

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 2 4 83 5 679 Q:=

1 2 5 93 4 768

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � 3 9 1 5 7 2 6 4 8

P:=

1 2 4 83 5 679 Q:=

1 2 5 93 4 768

P: insertion tableauQ: recording tableau

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

The Robinson-Schensted correspondence for Youngtableaux

π � π1π2 � � �πn permutation of length n.Algorithm 1: RS(π)

P :� π1 ;

Q :� 1 ;for k from 2 to n do

α :� πk ;for i ¥ 1 do

if α is bigger than all elements in the i-th row of P thenappend a cell with πk inside at the end of the i-th row of P;append the cell k at the end of the i-th row of Q;break;

elsewrite α in the cell of the i-th row containing the smallestelement β bigger than α;α :� β;

end

end

end

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Some properties of the RS correspondence

� The RS correspondence is a bijection; hence n! � °λ$npf λq2(f λ: number of STY of shape λ);

� RSpπq � pP,Qq ñ RSpπ�1q � pQ,Pq;� π involution ñ P � Q (and so involutions are in bijection with

STY);

� π involution ñ number of odd columns of the associated tableauxequals number of fixed points of π;

� the lengths of the longest increasing and decreasing subsequences ofπ corresponds to the lengths of the first row and column,respectively, of the corresponding tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Some properties of the RS correspondence

� The RS correspondence is a bijection; hence n! � °λ$npf λq2(f λ: number of STY of shape λ);

� RSpπq � pP,Qq ñ RSpπ�1q � pQ,Pq;� π involution ñ P � Q (and so involutions are in bijection with

STY);

� π involution ñ number of odd columns of the associated tableauxequals number of fixed points of π;

� the lengths of the longest increasing and decreasing subsequences ofπ corresponds to the lengths of the first row and column,respectively, of the corresponding tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Some properties of the RS correspondence

� The RS correspondence is a bijection; hence n! � °λ$npf λq2(f λ: number of STY of shape λ);

� RSpπq � pP,Qq ñ RSpπ�1q � pQ,Pq;� π involution ñ P � Q (and so involutions are in bijection with

STY);

� π involution ñ number of odd columns of the associated tableauxequals number of fixed points of π;

� the lengths of the longest increasing and decreasing subsequences ofπ corresponds to the lengths of the first row and column,respectively, of the corresponding tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Some properties of the RS correspondence

� The RS correspondence is a bijection; hence n! � °λ$npf λq2(f λ: number of STY of shape λ);

� RSpπq � pP,Qq ñ RSpπ�1q � pQ,Pq;� π involution ñ P � Q (and so involutions are in bijection with

STY);

� π involution ñ number of odd columns of the associated tableauxequals number of fixed points of π;

� the lengths of the longest increasing and decreasing subsequences ofπ corresponds to the lengths of the first row and column,respectively, of the corresponding tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Some properties of the RS correspondence

� The RS correspondence is a bijection; hence n! � °λ$npf λq2(f λ: number of STY of shape λ);

� RSpπq � pP,Qq ñ RSpπ�1q � pQ,Pq;� π involution ñ P � Q (and so involutions are in bijection with

STY);

� π involution ñ number of odd columns of the associated tableauxequals number of fixed points of π;

� the lengths of the longest increasing and decreasing subsequences ofπ corresponds to the lengths of the first row and column,respectively, of the corresponding tableaux.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=4

Q:=1

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=4

6 Q:=1

2

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

45

6Q:=

12

3

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

14

56 Q:=

12

34

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

14

56

9

Q:=

12

34

5

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

13

45

9

6Q:=

12

34

5

6

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

12

34

9

56 Q:=

12

34

5

67

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

12

34

8

56

9

Q:=

12

34

5

67

8

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

12

34

7

56

89

Q:=

12

34

5

67

89

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

π � 4 6 5 1 9 3 2 8 7

P:=

12

34

7

56

89

Q:=

12

34

5

67

89

P: insertion tableauQ: recording tableau

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

RS for Schroder tableaux

Algorithm 2: Sch(π)

P :� the 1-cell Schroder tableau with π1 written in the cell;Q :� the 1-cell Schroder tableau with 1 written in the cell;for k from 2 to n do

α :� πk ;for i ¥ 1 do

if α is bigger than all elements in the i-th row of P thenappend a cell (either an upper or a lower triangle) with πkinside at the end of the i-th row of P;append a cell (either an upper or a lower triangle) with kinside at the end of the i-th row of Q;break;

elselet A be the cell of the i-th row containing the smallestelement bigger than α;if A is an upper triangle then

β :� content of the lower triangle immediately below A;move the content of A to the lower triangle immediatelybelow A;write α in A;α :� β;

elseβ :� content of A;write α in A;α :� β;

end

end

end

end

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

π � π1 � � �πn

πi is left-to-right maximum (briefly, LR maximum) whenπi � maxpπ1, . . . , πi q.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single row if and only if, for alli ¤ n:

1. if i is odd, then πi is a LR maximum of π;

2. if i is even, then πi is a LR maximum of the permutation obtainedfrom π by removing πi�1 (and suitably renaming the remainingelements).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

π � π1 � � �πn

πi is left-to-right maximum (briefly, LR maximum) whenπi � maxpπ1, . . . , πi q.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single row if and only if, for alli ¤ n:

1. if i is odd, then πi is a LR maximum of π;

2. if i is even, then πi is a LR maximum of the permutation obtainedfrom π by removing πi�1 (and suitably renaming the remainingelements).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

π � π1 � � �πn

πi is left-to-right maximum (briefly, LR maximum) whenπi � maxpπ1, . . . , πi q.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single row if and only if, for alli ¤ n:

1. if i is odd, then πi is a LR maximum of π;

2. if i is even, then πi is a LR maximum of the permutation obtainedfrom π by removing πi�1 (and suitably renaming the remainingelements).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

π � π1 � � �πn

πi is left-to-right maximum (briefly, LR maximum) whenπi � maxpπ1, . . . , πi q.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single row if and only if, for alli ¤ n:

1. if i is odd, then πi is a LR maximum of π;

2. if i is even, then πi is a LR maximum of the permutation obtainedfrom π by removing πi�1 (and suitably renaming the remainingelements).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

π � π1 � � �πn

πi is left-to-right maximum (briefly, LR maximum) whenπi � maxpπ1, . . . , πi q.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single row if and only if, for alli ¤ n:

1. if i is odd, then πi is a LR maximum of π;

2. if i is even, then πi is a LR maximum of the permutation obtainedfrom π by removing πi�1 (and suitably renaming the remainingelements).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

��

��

�� , where

�is either

� 12 or

� 21.

CorollaryThe set of permutations of length n whose Schroder insertion tableauconsists of a single row has cardinality 2t n

2 u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle row

��

��

�� , where

�is either

� 12 or

� 21.

CorollaryThe set of permutations of length n whose Schroder insertion tableauconsists of a single row has cardinality 2t n

2 u.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

π � 3 6 1 5 8 2 4 9 7

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

π � 3 6 1 5 8 2 4 9 7

6 5 9 � 2 1 36 5 9 is an occurrence of the pattern 2 1 3 in π.

π doesn’t contain, or avoids, the pattern 3 4 2 1.

Avnpσq � permutations of length n avoiding σ.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single column if and only ifπ P Avnp123, 213q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

π � 3 6 1 5 8 2 4 9 7

6 5 9 � 2 1 36 5 9 is an occurrence of the pattern 2 1 3 in π.

π doesn’t contain, or avoids, the pattern 3 4 2 1.

Avnpσq � permutations of length n avoiding σ.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single column if and only ifπ P Avnp123, 213q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

π � 3 6 1 5 8 2 4 9 7

6 5 9 � 2 1 36 5 9 is an occurrence of the pattern 2 1 3 in π.

π doesn’t contain, or avoids, the pattern 3 4 2 1.

Avnpσq � permutations of length n avoiding σ.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single column if and only ifπ P Avnp123, 213q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

π � 3 6 1 5 8 2 4 9 7

6 5 9 � 2 1 36 5 9 is an occurrence of the pattern 2 1 3 in π.

π doesn’t contain, or avoids, the pattern 3 4 2 1.

Avnpσq � permutations of length n avoiding σ.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single column if and only ifπ P Avnp123, 213q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

π � 3 6 1 5 8 2 4 9 7

6 5 9 � 2 1 36 5 9 is an occurrence of the pattern 2 1 3 in π.

π doesn’t contain, or avoids, the pattern 3 4 2 1.

Avnpσq � permutations of length n avoiding σ.

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π has a single column if and only ifπ P Avnp123, 213q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

������ , where

�is

����� � 1 t pt � 1q � � � 3 2.

CorollaryThe set of permutations of length n whose Schroder insertion tableauconsists of a single column has cardinality 2n�1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Permutations with given insertion shapes: the case of asingle column

������ , where

�is

����� � 1 t pt � 1q � � � 3 2.

CorollaryThe set of permutations of length n whose Schroder insertion tableauconsists of a single column has cardinality 2n�1.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooks

A natural generalization arises considering Schroder shapes having asingle row and a single column: Schroder hooks.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooks

A natural generalization arises considering Schroder shapes having asingle row and a single column: Schroder hooks.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An RS-like correspondence for Schroder tableaux

Schroder hooksShuffle of two permutations:

2 5 1 4 3, 4 1 3 2

4 7 9 2 1 8 5 3 6.

k-rooted shuffle of two permutations:

2 5 3 4 6 1, 2 5 4 1 3

3 7 5 6 1 8 2 4(here k � 3).

PropositionThe Schroder insertion tableau of π is a Schroder hook if and only if π isa 2-rooted shuffle of two permutations having a single row Schroderinsertion tableau and a single column Schroder insertion tableau,respectively.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

Instead of considering two types of triangular cells (upper and lower)filled in with integers, one can consider square cells filled in with pairs ofintegers.

Schroder tableau S ÞÑ set of intervals IS with its interval order structure.

12

45

910

14

36

812

1315

711

16

p1, 2q

p4, 5q

p9, 10q

p14, 17q

p3, 6q

p8, 12q

p13, 15q

p7, 11q p16, 17q

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

Instead of considering two types of triangular cells (upper and lower)filled in with integers, one can consider square cells filled in with pairs ofintegers.

Schroder tableau S ÞÑ set of intervals IS with its interval order structure.

12

45

910

14

36

812

1315

711

16

p1, 2q

p4, 5q

p9, 10q

p14, 17q

p3, 6q

p8, 12q

p13, 15q

p7, 11q p16, 17q

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

Instead of considering two types of triangular cells (upper and lower)filled in with integers, one can consider square cells filled in with pairs ofintegers.

Schroder tableau S ÞÑ set of intervals IS with its interval order structure.

12

45

910

14

36

812

1315

711

16

p1, 2q

p4, 5q

p9, 10q

p14, 17q

p3, 6q

p8, 12q

p13, 15q

p7, 11q p16, 17q

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

| | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | |1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17

a b c d

e fg h

i

a

b e

c f g

h i

d

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

| | | | | | | | | | | | | | | | |1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17

a b c d

e fg h

i

a

b e

c f g

h i

d

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

� Given an interval order I, does there exist a Schroder tableau Ssuch that I � IS?

� In case of a positive answer to the previous question, how manySchroder tableaux associated with a given interval order are there?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Schroder tableaux and interval orders

� Given an interval order I, does there exist a Schroder tableau Ssuch that I � IS?

� In case of a positive answer to the previous question, how manySchroder tableaux associated with a given interval order are there?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Weak patterns in posets (and strong pattern avoidance)P,Q posets.P is weakly contained in Q (P is a weak pattern of Q) when thereexists an injective order-preserving function f : P Ñ Q. In this case wealso write P ¤ Q.

Note that f is not required to be order-reflecting (i.e. the “inverse” of fis not required to be order-preserving). In case it is, we obtain the usualnotion of (strong) pattern for posets.

When P is not weakly contained in Q, we say that Q strongly avoidsP, and we write Q P SAvpPq.

pX,¤q: poset of all finite posets with the weak pattern containmentrelation.pXn,¤q: poset of all posets of size n with the weak pattern containmentrelation. Notice that, when equipped with the strong patterncontainment relation, Xn is the discrete poset.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Weak patterns in posets (and strong pattern avoidance)P,Q posets.P is weakly contained in Q (P is a weak pattern of Q) when thereexists an injective order-preserving function f : P Ñ Q. In this case wealso write P ¤ Q.

Note that f is not required to be order-reflecting (i.e. the “inverse” of fis not required to be order-preserving). In case it is, we obtain the usualnotion of (strong) pattern for posets.

When P is not weakly contained in Q, we say that Q strongly avoidsP, and we write Q P SAvpPq.

pX,¤q: poset of all finite posets with the weak pattern containmentrelation.pXn,¤q: poset of all posets of size n with the weak pattern containmentrelation. Notice that, when equipped with the strong patterncontainment relation, Xn is the discrete poset.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Weak patterns in posets (and strong pattern avoidance)P,Q posets.P is weakly contained in Q (P is a weak pattern of Q) when thereexists an injective order-preserving function f : P Ñ Q. In this case wealso write P ¤ Q.

Note that f is not required to be order-reflecting (i.e. the “inverse” of fis not required to be order-preserving). In case it is, we obtain the usualnotion of (strong) pattern for posets.

When P is not weakly contained in Q, we say that Q strongly avoidsP, and we write Q P SAvpPq.

pX,¤q: poset of all finite posets with the weak pattern containmentrelation.pXn,¤q: poset of all posets of size n with the weak pattern containmentrelation. Notice that, when equipped with the strong patterncontainment relation, Xn is the discrete poset.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Weak patterns in posets (and strong pattern avoidance)P,Q posets.P is weakly contained in Q (P is a weak pattern of Q) when thereexists an injective order-preserving function f : P Ñ Q. In this case wealso write P ¤ Q.

Note that f is not required to be order-reflecting (i.e. the “inverse” of fis not required to be order-preserving). In case it is, we obtain the usualnotion of (strong) pattern for posets.

When P is not weakly contained in Q, we say that Q strongly avoidsP, and we write Q P SAvpPq.

pX,¤q: poset of all finite posets with the weak pattern containmentrelation.pXn,¤q: poset of all posets of size n with the weak pattern containmentrelation. Notice that, when equipped with the strong patterncontainment relation, Xn is the discrete poset.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Weak patterns in posets (and strong pattern avoidance)

Not entirely new. It has been considered in the context of families ofsets, in particular extremal properties of strong avoidance (Katona,Tarjan (1983), Griggs, Lu (2009)).

Seems to have never been considered from a purely order-theoretic pointof view, as well as for what concerns the enumeration andcharacterization of the classes.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Weak patterns in posets (and strong pattern avoidance)

Not entirely new. It has been considered in the context of families ofsets, in particular extremal properties of strong avoidance (Katona,Tarjan (1983), Griggs, Lu (2009)).

Seems to have never been considered from a purely order-theoretic pointof view, as well as for what concerns the enumeration andcharacterization of the classes.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Basic facts of the weak pattern containment order

� pX,¤q has minimum (the empty poset) and does not havemaximum.

� If P ¤ Q, then P has at most as many elements as Q.

� pX,¤q is a ranked poset; rank of P � |P|� total number of orderrelations between elements of P.

� Xn has minimum (the discrete poset on n elements) and maximum(the chain having n elements).

� Xn has exactly one atom, which is the poset of size n having a singlecovering relation.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Basic facts of the weak pattern containment order

� pX,¤q has minimum (the empty poset) and does not havemaximum.

� If P ¤ Q, then P has at most as many elements as Q.

� pX,¤q is a ranked poset; rank of P � |P|� total number of orderrelations between elements of P.

� Xn has minimum (the discrete poset on n elements) and maximum(the chain having n elements).

� Xn has exactly one atom, which is the poset of size n having a singlecovering relation.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Basic facts of the weak pattern containment order

� pX,¤q has minimum (the empty poset) and does not havemaximum.

� If P ¤ Q, then P has at most as many elements as Q.

� pX,¤q is a ranked poset; rank of P � |P|� total number of orderrelations between elements of P.

� Xn has minimum (the discrete poset on n elements) and maximum(the chain having n elements).

� Xn has exactly one atom, which is the poset of size n having a singlecovering relation.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Basic facts of the weak pattern containment order

� pX,¤q has minimum (the empty poset) and does not havemaximum.

� If P ¤ Q, then P has at most as many elements as Q.

� pX,¤q is a ranked poset; rank of P � |P|� total number of orderrelations between elements of P.

� Xn has minimum (the discrete poset on n elements) and maximum(the chain having n elements).

� Xn has exactly one atom, which is the poset of size n having a singlecovering relation.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Basic facts of the weak pattern containment order

� pX,¤q has minimum (the empty poset) and does not havemaximum.

� If P ¤ Q, then P has at most as many elements as Q.

� pX,¤q is a ranked poset; rank of P � |P|� total number of orderrelations between elements of P.

� Xn has minimum (the discrete poset on n elements) and maximum(the chain having n elements).

� Xn has exactly one atom, which is the poset of size n having a singlecovering relation.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Examples

Hasse diagrams of X3 (with explicit representation of each element) andX4.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

1. For every poset P P Xn, SAvpPq � AvpxPynq, where xPyn is theup-set generated by P in Xn.

2. If P is the discrete poset of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of allposets of size ¤ n � 1.

3. If P is the poset of size n containing a single covering relation, thenSAvpPq contains all posets of size ¤ n � 1 and all (finite) discreteposets.

4. If P is the chain of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of all finiteposets of height ¤ n � 1.

5. If P � , then SAvpPq is the class of all disjoint unions of flats.As a consequence, |SAvnpPq| � Bn, the n-th Bell number.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

1. For every poset P P Xn, SAvpPq � AvpxPynq, where xPyn is theup-set generated by P in Xn.

2. If P is the discrete poset of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of allposets of size ¤ n � 1.

3. If P is the poset of size n containing a single covering relation, thenSAvpPq contains all posets of size ¤ n � 1 and all (finite) discreteposets.

4. If P is the chain of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of all finiteposets of height ¤ n � 1.

5. If P � , then SAvpPq is the class of all disjoint unions of flats.As a consequence, |SAvnpPq| � Bn, the n-th Bell number.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

1. For every poset P P Xn, SAvpPq � AvpxPynq, where xPyn is theup-set generated by P in Xn.

2. If P is the discrete poset of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of allposets of size ¤ n � 1.

3. If P is the poset of size n containing a single covering relation, thenSAvpPq contains all posets of size ¤ n � 1 and all (finite) discreteposets.

4. If P is the chain of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of all finiteposets of height ¤ n � 1.

5. If P � , then SAvpPq is the class of all disjoint unions of flats.As a consequence, |SAvnpPq| � Bn, the n-th Bell number.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

1. For every poset P P Xn, SAvpPq � AvpxPynq, where xPyn is theup-set generated by P in Xn.

2. If P is the discrete poset of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of allposets of size ¤ n � 1.

3. If P is the poset of size n containing a single covering relation, thenSAvpPq contains all posets of size ¤ n � 1 and all (finite) discreteposets.

4. If P is the chain of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of all finiteposets of height ¤ n � 1.

5. If P � , then SAvpPq is the class of all disjoint unions of flats.As a consequence, |SAvnpPq| � Bn, the n-th Bell number.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

1. For every poset P P Xn, SAvpPq � AvpxPynq, where xPyn is theup-set generated by P in Xn.

2. If P is the discrete poset of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of allposets of size ¤ n � 1.

3. If P is the poset of size n containing a single covering relation, thenSAvpPq contains all posets of size ¤ n � 1 and all (finite) discreteposets.

4. If P is the chain of size n, then SAvpPq is the class of all finiteposets of height ¤ n � 1.

5. If P � , then SAvpPq is the class of all disjoint unions of flats.As a consequence, |SAvnpPq| � Bn, the n-th Bell number.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

PropositionLet P,Q be two posets.

1. R P SAvpP 9YQq if and only if, for every partition pR1,R2q into twoblocks of the ground set of R, denoting with R1,R2 the associatedinduced subposets, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq.

2. If R P SAvpP `Qq, then, for every ordered partition pR1,R2q intotwo blocks of R, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq. IfR R SAvpP `Qq, then there exists a weakly ordered partitionpR1,R2q into two blocks of R such that R1 R SAvpPq andR2 R SAvpQq.

PropositionIf Q P SAvpPq and P is connected, then Q is the disjoint union of afamily of posets strongly avoiding P.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

PropositionLet P,Q be two posets.

1. R P SAvpP 9YQq if and only if, for every partition pR1,R2q into twoblocks of the ground set of R, denoting with R1,R2 the associatedinduced subposets, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq.

2. If R P SAvpP `Qq, then, for every ordered partition pR1,R2q intotwo blocks of R, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq. IfR R SAvpP `Qq, then there exists a weakly ordered partitionpR1,R2q into two blocks of R such that R1 R SAvpPq andR2 R SAvpQq.

PropositionIf Q P SAvpPq and P is connected, then Q is the disjoint union of afamily of posets strongly avoiding P.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

PropositionLet P,Q be two posets.

1. R P SAvpP 9YQq if and only if, for every partition pR1,R2q into twoblocks of the ground set of R, denoting with R1,R2 the associatedinduced subposets, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq.

2. If R P SAvpP `Qq, then, for every ordered partition pR1,R2q intotwo blocks of R, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq. IfR R SAvpP `Qq, then there exists a weakly ordered partitionpR1,R2q into two blocks of R such that R1 R SAvpPq andR2 R SAvpQq.

PropositionIf Q P SAvpPq and P is connected, then Q is the disjoint union of afamily of posets strongly avoiding P.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

Results on strong avoidance

PropositionLet P,Q be two posets.

1. R P SAvpP 9YQq if and only if, for every partition pR1,R2q into twoblocks of the ground set of R, denoting with R1,R2 the associatedinduced subposets, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq.

2. If R P SAvpP `Qq, then, for every ordered partition pR1,R2q intotwo blocks of R, either R1 P SAvpPq or R2 P SAvpQq. IfR R SAvpP `Qq, then there exists a weakly ordered partitionpR1,R2q into two blocks of R such that R1 R SAvpPq andR2 R SAvpQq.

PropositionIf Q P SAvpPq and P is connected, then Q is the disjoint union of afamily of posets strongly avoiding P.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

An alternative presentation of Schroder tableaux

How Schroder tableaux come into play

TheoremLet I be an interval order of size n. There exists a Schroder tableau Ssuch that I � IS if and only if I weakly contains a down-set of size n ofN� N.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Schroder partitions and Schroder tableaux

Further work

Hints for further research� Properties of the Young-Schroder distributive lattice.

� Differential-like properties?

� Properties of our RS-like correspondence.� Inserting tableau: many more shapes to be investigated.� Role of the recording tableau.

� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux of given shape (hook-likeformulas?).

� Relationship with interval orders.� Enumeration of Schroder tableaux associated with a given interval

order.� Strong pattern avoidance for posets: seems interesting in its own.

� General combinatorics of Schroder tableaux, in analogy with thecombinatorics of Young tableaux.

� Schur functions,� plactic monoid,� Schutzenberger’s jeu de taquin,� Littlewood-Richardson rule,� Schubert calculus on Grassmannians and flag varieties.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

Statement of the problem

We have already seen that Dyck lattices are isomorphic to Young latticesof staircase partitions.

Are there other interesting combinatorial posets which are isomorphic toDyck lattices? And what about other lattices of paths?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

Statement of the problem

We have already seen that Dyck lattices are isomorphic to Young latticesof staircase partitions.

Are there other interesting combinatorial posets which are isomorphic toDyck lattices? And what about other lattices of paths?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

Classical bijections for Dyck pathsNice bijections between Dyck paths, noncrossing partitions and312-avoiding permutations (Krattenthaler?):

Ó

2 | 4 3 1 | 6 | 7 5 | 8

Ó

2 4 3 1 6 7 5 8

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

Classical bijections for Dyck pathsNice bijections between Dyck paths, noncrossing partitions and312-avoiding permutations (Krattenthaler?):

Ó

2 | 4 3 1 | 6 | 7 5 | 8

Ó

2 4 3 1 6 7 5 8

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A new noncrossing partition lattice

If we endow Dn with the usual partial order, what happens if wetransport the order structure along the two bijection described above?

π � B1| � � � |Bk P NC pnq is in standard form when:

� the elements inside each block are listed in decreasing order;

� the blocks are listed in increasing order of their maxima.

max-vector of π: maxpπq � pµ1, . . . , µnq, where µi � maximum of thefirst i elements in the standard form of π.

Example. π � 2|31|54, maxpπq � p2, 3, 3, 5, 5q.

Proposition (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))π ¤ ρ if and only if maxpπq ¤ maxpρq (coordinatewise).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A new noncrossing partition lattice

If we endow Dn with the usual partial order, what happens if wetransport the order structure along the two bijection described above?

π � B1| � � � |Bk P NC pnq is in standard form when:

� the elements inside each block are listed in decreasing order;

� the blocks are listed in increasing order of their maxima.

max-vector of π: maxpπq � pµ1, . . . , µnq, where µi � maximum of thefirst i elements in the standard form of π.

Example. π � 2|31|54, maxpπq � p2, 3, 3, 5, 5q.

Proposition (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))π ¤ ρ if and only if maxpπq ¤ maxpρq (coordinatewise).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A new noncrossing partition lattice

If we endow Dn with the usual partial order, what happens if wetransport the order structure along the two bijection described above?

π � B1| � � � |Bk P NC pnq is in standard form when:

� the elements inside each block are listed in decreasing order;

� the blocks are listed in increasing order of their maxima.

max-vector of π: maxpπq � pµ1, . . . , µnq, where µi � maximum of thefirst i elements in the standard form of π.

Example. π � 2|31|54, maxpπq � p2, 3, 3, 5, 5q.

Proposition (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))π ¤ ρ if and only if maxpπq ¤ maxpρq (coordinatewise).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A new noncrossing partition lattice

If we endow Dn with the usual partial order, what happens if wetransport the order structure along the two bijection described above?

π � B1| � � � |Bk P NC pnq is in standard form when:

� the elements inside each block are listed in decreasing order;

� the blocks are listed in increasing order of their maxima.

max-vector of π: maxpπq � pµ1, . . . , µnq, where µi � maximum of thefirst i elements in the standard form of π.

Example. π � 2|31|54, maxpπq � p2, 3, 3, 5, 5q.

Proposition (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))π ¤ ρ if and only if maxpπq ¤ maxpρq (coordinatewise).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A new noncrossing partition lattice

If we endow Dn with the usual partial order, what happens if wetransport the order structure along the two bijection described above?

π � B1| � � � |Bk P NC pnq is in standard form when:

� the elements inside each block are listed in decreasing order;

� the blocks are listed in increasing order of their maxima.

max-vector of π: maxpπq � pµ1, . . . , µnq, where µi � maximum of thefirst i elements in the standard form of π.

Example. π � 2|31|54, maxpπq � p2, 3, 3, 5, 5q.

Proposition (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))π ¤ ρ if and only if maxpπq ¤ maxpρq (coordinatewise).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A new noncrossing partition lattice

If we endow Dn with the usual partial order, what happens if wetransport the order structure along the two bijection described above?

π � B1| � � � |Bk P NC pnq is in standard form when:

� the elements inside each block are listed in decreasing order;

� the blocks are listed in increasing order of their maxima.

max-vector of π: maxpπq � pµ1, . . . , µnq, where µi � maximum of thefirst i elements in the standard form of π.

Example. π � 2|31|54, maxpπq � p2, 3, 3, 5, 5q.

Proposition (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))π ¤ ρ if and only if maxpπq ¤ maxpρq (coordinatewise).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A lattice structure on 312-avoiding permutations

... and what about 312-avoiding permutations?

Theorem (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))The bijection between Dyck paths of semilength n and 312-avoidingpermutations of size n illustrated in the previous slide is anorder-isomorphism between the Dyck poset of order n and Snp312qendowed with the (strong) Bruhat order.

As a byproduct, Snp312q is a distributive lattice when considered as asubposet of Sn with the Bruhat order.

Open problem. For which τ P Sk is Skpτq a (distributive) lattice underthe strong Bruhat order?

Solved by Drake (2005) for the weak Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A lattice structure on 312-avoiding permutations

... and what about 312-avoiding permutations?

Theorem (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))The bijection between Dyck paths of semilength n and 312-avoidingpermutations of size n illustrated in the previous slide is anorder-isomorphism between the Dyck poset of order n and Snp312qendowed with the (strong) Bruhat order.

As a byproduct, Snp312q is a distributive lattice when considered as asubposet of Sn with the Bruhat order.

Open problem. For which τ P Sk is Skpτq a (distributive) lattice underthe strong Bruhat order?

Solved by Drake (2005) for the weak Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A lattice structure on 312-avoiding permutations

... and what about 312-avoiding permutations?

Theorem (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))The bijection between Dyck paths of semilength n and 312-avoidingpermutations of size n illustrated in the previous slide is anorder-isomorphism between the Dyck poset of order n and Snp312qendowed with the (strong) Bruhat order.

As a byproduct, Snp312q is a distributive lattice when considered as asubposet of Sn with the Bruhat order.

Open problem. For which τ P Sk is Skpτq a (distributive) lattice underthe strong Bruhat order?

Solved by Drake (2005) for the weak Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A lattice structure on 312-avoiding permutations

... and what about 312-avoiding permutations?

Theorem (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))The bijection between Dyck paths of semilength n and 312-avoidingpermutations of size n illustrated in the previous slide is anorder-isomorphism between the Dyck poset of order n and Snp312qendowed with the (strong) Bruhat order.

As a byproduct, Snp312q is a distributive lattice when considered as asubposet of Sn with the Bruhat order.

Open problem. For which τ P Sk is Skpτq a (distributive) lattice underthe strong Bruhat order?

Solved by Drake (2005) for the weak Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A lattice structure on 312-avoiding permutations

... and what about 312-avoiding permutations?

Theorem (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))The bijection between Dyck paths of semilength n and 312-avoidingpermutations of size n illustrated in the previous slide is anorder-isomorphism between the Dyck poset of order n and Snp312qendowed with the (strong) Bruhat order.

As a byproduct, Snp312q is a distributive lattice when considered as asubposet of Sn with the Bruhat order.

Open problem. For which τ P Sk is Skpτq a (distributive) lattice underthe strong Bruhat order?

Solved by Drake (2005) for the weak Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Dyck lattices

A lattice structure on 312-avoiding permutations

... and what about 312-avoiding permutations?

Theorem (Barcucci, Bernini, F., Poneti (2005))The bijection between Dyck paths of semilength n and 312-avoidingpermutations of size n illustrated in the previous slide is anorder-isomorphism between the Dyck poset of order n and Snp312qendowed with the (strong) Bruhat order.

As a byproduct, Snp312q is a distributive lattice when considered as asubposet of Sn with the Bruhat order.

Open problem. For which τ P Sk is Skpτq a (distributive) lattice underthe strong Bruhat order?

Solved by Drake (2005) for the weak Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

Motzkin lattices and pattern avoiding permutations

Can we do something similar for other classes of paths?Elizalde and Mansour (2005) introduced a bijection between Motzkinpaths of length n and Dyck paths of semilength n without threeconsecutive down steps.

f :Mn Ñ Dp3qn

U 99K U

UD 99K H

UDD 99K D

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))f is an order-isomorphism, whence Mn is isomorphic toSnp3� 21, 31� 2q endowed with the strong Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

Motzkin lattices and pattern avoiding permutations

Can we do something similar for other classes of paths?Elizalde and Mansour (2005) introduced a bijection between Motzkinpaths of length n and Dyck paths of semilength n without threeconsecutive down steps.

f :Mn Ñ Dp3qn

U 99K U

UD 99K H

UDD 99K D

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))f is an order-isomorphism, whence Mn is isomorphic toSnp3� 21, 31� 2q endowed with the strong Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

Motzkin lattices and pattern avoiding permutations

Can we do something similar for other classes of paths?Elizalde and Mansour (2005) introduced a bijection between Motzkinpaths of length n and Dyck paths of semilength n without threeconsecutive down steps.

f :Mn Ñ Dp3qn

U 99K U

UD 99K H

UDD 99K D

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))f is an order-isomorphism, whence Mn is isomorphic toSnp3� 21, 31� 2q endowed with the strong Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

Motzkin lattices and pattern avoiding permutations

Can we do something similar for other classes of paths?Elizalde and Mansour (2005) introduced a bijection between Motzkinpaths of length n and Dyck paths of semilength n without threeconsecutive down steps.

f :Mn Ñ Dp3qn

U 99K U

UD 99K H

UDD 99K D

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))f is an order-isomorphism, whence Mn is isomorphic toSnp3� 21, 31� 2q endowed with the strong Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

A generalization

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))The following posets are isomorphic:

� Cr�k�2,1sn : poset of r�k � 2, 1s-paths of length n;

� Dpkqn : poset of Dyck paths of semilength n having no k consecutive

down steps;

� Snp31� 2, k � pk � 1qpk � 2q � � � 21q endowed with the strongBruhat order.

Observe that, when k tends to infinity, we get in particular anorder-isomorphism between the poset of Dyck paths of semilength n andthe poset of Lukasiewicz paths (which are, by definition, Γ-path withΓ � t�1u Y N).

Unfortunately, we still don’t have anything similar for Schroder lattices...

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

A generalization

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))The following posets are isomorphic:

� Cr�k�2,1sn : poset of r�k � 2, 1s-paths of length n;

� Dpkqn : poset of Dyck paths of semilength n having no k consecutive

down steps;

� Snp31� 2, k � pk � 1qpk � 2q � � � 21q endowed with the strongBruhat order.

Observe that, when k tends to infinity, we get in particular anorder-isomorphism between the poset of Dyck paths of semilength n andthe poset of Lukasiewicz paths (which are, by definition, Γ-path withΓ � t�1u Y N).

Unfortunately, we still don’t have anything similar for Schroder lattices...

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

A generalization

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))The following posets are isomorphic:

� Cr�k�2,1sn : poset of r�k � 2, 1s-paths of length n;

� Dpkqn : poset of Dyck paths of semilength n having no k consecutive

down steps;

� Snp31� 2, k � pk � 1qpk � 2q � � � 21q endowed with the strongBruhat order.

Observe that, when k tends to infinity, we get in particular anorder-isomorphism between the poset of Dyck paths of semilength n andthe poset of Lukasiewicz paths (which are, by definition, Γ-path withΓ � t�1u Y N).

Unfortunately, we still don’t have anything similar for Schroder lattices...

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

A generalization

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))The following posets are isomorphic:

� Cr�k�2,1sn : poset of r�k � 2, 1s-paths of length n;

� Dpkqn : poset of Dyck paths of semilength n having no k consecutive

down steps;

� Snp31� 2, k � pk � 1qpk � 2q � � � 21q endowed with the strongBruhat order.

Observe that, when k tends to infinity, we get in particular anorder-isomorphism between the poset of Dyck paths of semilength n andthe poset of Lukasiewicz paths (which are, by definition, Γ-path withΓ � t�1u Y N).

Unfortunately, we still don’t have anything similar for Schroder lattices...

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

A generalization

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))The following posets are isomorphic:

� Cr�k�2,1sn : poset of r�k � 2, 1s-paths of length n;

� Dpkqn : poset of Dyck paths of semilength n having no k consecutive

down steps;

� Snp31� 2, k � pk � 1qpk � 2q � � � 21q endowed with the strongBruhat order.

Observe that, when k tends to infinity, we get in particular anorder-isomorphism between the poset of Dyck paths of semilength n andthe poset of Lukasiewicz paths (which are, by definition, Γ-path withΓ � t�1u Y N).

Unfortunately, we still don’t have anything similar for Schroder lattices...

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Motzkin (and Schroder) lattices

A generalization

Proposition (Bernini, F. (2007))The following posets are isomorphic:

� Cr�k�2,1sn : poset of r�k � 2, 1s-paths of length n;

� Dpkqn : poset of Dyck paths of semilength n having no k consecutive

down steps;

� Snp31� 2, k � pk � 1qpk � 2q � � � 21q endowed with the strongBruhat order.

Observe that, when k tends to infinity, we get in particular anorder-isomorphism between the poset of Dyck paths of semilength n andthe poset of Lukasiewicz paths (which are, by definition, Γ-path withΓ � t�1u Y N).

Unfortunately, we still don’t have anything similar for Schroder lattices...

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

Instead, there are analogous results for Grand-Dyck lattices.

They are of course isomorphic to Young lattices of integer partitions lyinginside a square (Proctor (1982), Stanley (1991)).

Bn: signed permutations of length n.Define the Bruhat order on Bn as follows (see for instance Bjorner, Brenti(2005)):

� for π1 P Bn, define π P Bn by reversing and changing all sign to π1;

� let π be the juxtaposition of π and π1, so that π is a permutation ofthe set rn, ns � tn, n � 1, . . . 1, 1, . . . n� 1, nu; denote by S�n the setof all permutations of rn, ns;

� say that π1 ¤ ρ1 in the Bruhat order of Bn whenever π ¤ ρ in theBruhat order of the symmetric group S�n.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

Instead, there are analogous results for Grand-Dyck lattices.

They are of course isomorphic to Young lattices of integer partitions lyinginside a square (Proctor (1982), Stanley (1991)).

Bn: signed permutations of length n.Define the Bruhat order on Bn as follows (see for instance Bjorner, Brenti(2005)):

� for π1 P Bn, define π P Bn by reversing and changing all sign to π1;

� let π be the juxtaposition of π and π1, so that π is a permutation ofthe set rn, ns � tn, n � 1, . . . 1, 1, . . . n� 1, nu; denote by S�n the setof all permutations of rn, ns;

� say that π1 ¤ ρ1 in the Bruhat order of Bn whenever π ¤ ρ in theBruhat order of the symmetric group S�n.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

Instead, there are analogous results for Grand-Dyck lattices.

They are of course isomorphic to Young lattices of integer partitions lyinginside a square (Proctor (1982), Stanley (1991)).

Bn: signed permutations of length n.Define the Bruhat order on Bn as follows (see for instance Bjorner, Brenti(2005)):

� for π1 P Bn, define π P Bn by reversing and changing all sign to π1;

� let π be the juxtaposition of π and π1, so that π is a permutation ofthe set rn, ns � tn, n � 1, . . . 1, 1, . . . n� 1, nu; denote by S�n the setof all permutations of rn, ns;

� say that π1 ¤ ρ1 in the Bruhat order of Bn whenever π ¤ ρ in theBruhat order of the symmetric group S�n.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

Instead, there are analogous results for Grand-Dyck lattices.

They are of course isomorphic to Young lattices of integer partitions lyinginside a square (Proctor (1982), Stanley (1991)).

Bn: signed permutations of length n.Define the Bruhat order on Bn as follows (see for instance Bjorner, Brenti(2005)):

� for π1 P Bn, define π P Bn by reversing and changing all sign to π1;

� let π be the juxtaposition of π and π1, so that π is a permutation ofthe set rn, ns � tn, n � 1, . . . 1, 1, . . . n� 1, nu; denote by S�n the setof all permutations of rn, ns;

� say that π1 ¤ ρ1 in the Bruhat order of Bn whenever π ¤ ρ in theBruhat order of the symmetric group S�n.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

Instead, there are analogous results for Grand-Dyck lattices.

They are of course isomorphic to Young lattices of integer partitions lyinginside a square (Proctor (1982), Stanley (1991)).

Bn: signed permutations of length n.Define the Bruhat order on Bn as follows (see for instance Bjorner, Brenti(2005)):

� for π1 P Bn, define π P Bn by reversing and changing all sign to π1;

� let π be the juxtaposition of π and π1, so that π is a permutation ofthe set rn, ns � tn, n � 1, . . . 1, 1, . . . n� 1, nu; denote by S�n the setof all permutations of rn, ns;

� say that π1 ¤ ρ1 in the Bruhat order of Bn whenever π ¤ ρ in theBruhat order of the symmetric group S�n.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

For instance, if π1 � 14523, then π � 32541 and π � 3254114523.Moreover, if ρ1 � 14253, then π1 ¤ ρ1.

Theorem (F. (2010))The poset GDn of Grand-Dyck paths of semilength n is isomorphic to theposet Bnp213, 213, 12, 12q with the Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

Isomorphisms with other combinatorial posets

Grand-Dyck lattices

Grand-Dyck lattices and signed pattern avoidingpermutations

For instance, if π1 � 14523, then π � 32541 and π � 3254114523.Moreover, if ρ1 � 14253, then π1 ¤ ρ1.

Theorem (F. (2010))The poset GDn of Grand-Dyck paths of semilength n is isomorphic to theposet Bnp213, 213, 12, 12q with the Bruhat order.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The Dyck pattern poset

Let D be the set of all Dyck paths. Given P,Q P D, define P ¤ Q whenP appears as a subword of Q.

This definition of pattern is clearly suggested by the analogous wellknown notion for permutations. It is a special case of the subword orderstudied by Bjorner (1990).

D � pD,¤q is an infinite poset with minimum (the empty path), withoutmaximum, with rank (given by the semilength of a path). Moreover, it isa partial well order, i.e. it contains neither an infinite properly decreasingsequence nor an infinite antichain (this is a consequence of a theorem ofHigman).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The Dyck pattern poset

Let D be the set of all Dyck paths. Given P,Q P D, define P ¤ Q whenP appears as a subword of Q.

This definition of pattern is clearly suggested by the analogous wellknown notion for permutations. It is a special case of the subword orderstudied by Bjorner (1990).

D � pD,¤q is an infinite poset with minimum (the empty path), withoutmaximum, with rank (given by the semilength of a path). Moreover, it isa partial well order, i.e. it contains neither an infinite properly decreasingsequence nor an infinite antichain (this is a consequence of a theorem ofHigman).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The Dyck pattern poset

Let D be the set of all Dyck paths. Given P,Q P D, define P ¤ Q whenP appears as a subword of Q.

This definition of pattern is clearly suggested by the analogous wellknown notion for permutations. It is a special case of the subword orderstudied by Bjorner (1990).

D � pD,¤q is an infinite poset with minimum (the empty path), withoutmaximum, with rank (given by the semilength of a path). Moreover, it isa partial well order, i.e. it contains neither an infinite properly decreasingsequence nor an infinite antichain (this is a consequence of a theorem ofHigman).

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The Dyck pattern poset

The first levels of the Dyck pattern poset:

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The Dyck pattern poset

An interval of rank 3:

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The covering relation

Structural properties of D: for instance, denoting with ∇P/∆P the setof elements covered by/covering P in D, what about |∇P| and |∆P|?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The covering relation

Some useful notations and parameters:

0p

F 1

p1

F 2

p2

F 3

p3

pi return points;Fi factor between pi�1 and pi ;fi semilength of Fi ;ni number of ascents in Fi ;|UDU| number of consecutive UDU’s;|DUD| number of consecutive DUD’s.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The covering relation

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))If P is a Dyck path with k factors F1, . . .Fk , with Fi having ni ascents,then the number of Dyck paths covered by P is given by

|∇P| �°k

i�1 ni2 � p°k

i�1 ni q22

� |UDU| � |DUD| .

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))If P is a Dyck path of semilength n with k factors F1, . . .Fk , with Fi

having semilength fi , then the number of Dyck paths covering P is givenby

|∆P| � 1�¸i

f 2i �

¸i j

fi fj .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Dyck pattern poset

The covering relation

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))If P is a Dyck path with k factors F1, . . .Fk , with Fi having ni ascents,then the number of Dyck paths covered by P is given by

|∇P| �°k

i�1 ni2 � p°k

i�1 ni q22

� |UDU| � |DUD| .

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))If P is a Dyck path of semilength n with k factors F1, . . .Fk , with Fi

having semilength fi , then the number of Dyck paths covering P is givenby

|∆P| � 1�¸i

f 2i �

¸i j

fi fj .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Enumerative issues

Enumerative properties of D: given P P D, how many paths ofsemilength n in D avoid P? Denote it with dnpPq, and let DnpPq be theset of all such paths.

Obvious cases:

� dnpUDq � 0, n ¡ 0;

� dnpUDUDq � 1, @n;

� dnpUUDDq � 0, n ¥ 3.

We have found results for all patterns of semilength 3. Each case isobtained as a special instance of a more general result.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Enumerative issues

Enumerative properties of D: given P P D, how many paths ofsemilength n in D avoid P? Denote it with dnpPq, and let DnpPq be theset of all such paths.

Obvious cases:

� dnpUDq � 0, n ¡ 0;

� dnpUDUDq � 1, @n;

� dnpUUDDq � 0, n ¥ 3.

We have found results for all patterns of semilength 3. Each case isobtained as a special instance of a more general result.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Enumerative issues

Enumerative properties of D: given P P D, how many paths ofsemilength n in D avoid P? Denote it with dnpPq, and let DnpPq be theset of all such paths.

Obvious cases:

� dnpUDq � 0, n ¡ 0;

� dnpUDUDq � 1, @n;

� dnpUUDDq � 0, n ¥ 3.

We have found results for all patterns of semilength 3. Each case isobtained as a special instance of a more general result.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Enumerative issues

Enumerative properties of D: given P P D, how many paths ofsemilength n in D avoid P? Denote it with dnpPq, and let DnpPq be theset of all such paths.

Obvious cases:

� dnpUDq � 0, n ¡ 0;

� dnpUDUDq � 1, @n;

� dnpUUDDq � 0, n ¥ 3.

We have found results for all patterns of semilength 3. Each case isobtained as a special instance of a more general result.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Enumerative issues

Enumerative properties of D: given P P D, how many paths ofsemilength n in D avoid P? Denote it with dnpPq, and let DnpPq be theset of all such paths.

Obvious cases:

� dnpUDq � 0, n ¡ 0;

� dnpUDUDq � 1, @n;

� dnpUUDDq � 0, n ¥ 3.

We have found results for all patterns of semilength 3. Each case isobtained as a special instance of a more general result.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Enumerative issues

Enumerative properties of D: given P P D, how many paths ofsemilength n in D avoid P? Denote it with dnpPq, and let DnpPq be theset of all such paths.

Obvious cases:

� dnpUDq � 0, n ¡ 0;

� dnpUDUDq � 1, @n;

� dnpUUDDq � 0, n ¥ 3.

We have found results for all patterns of semilength 3. Each case isobtained as a special instance of a more general result.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Avoiding pUDqk

P � UDUDUD

We have the following more general result.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))For any k P N, P P DnppUDqkq if and only if P has at most k � 1 peaks.

The distribution of peaks in Dyck paths is given by Narayana numbersNn,k � 1

n

�nk

��n

k�1

�, so that

dnppUDqkq �k�1

i�1

Nn,i .

In particular, dnppUDq3q � 1� �n2�.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Avoiding Uk�1DUDk�1

P � UUDUDD

We have the following more general result.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))Given P � Uk�1DUDk�1, for any n, k P N we have

dnpPq �"

C 2k�1 if n ¥ 2k � 3;°

j¥1 b2k�j,n�k�j if k � 1 ¤ n ¤ 2k � 3.

,

where bi,j � i�j�1i�1

�i�ji

�is a ballot number (number of Dyck prefixes

having i U steps and j D steps) and Cn � 1n�1

�2nn

�is a Catalan number.

In particular, dnpUUDUDDq � C 22 � 4 for n ¥ 3.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Avoiding UkDk

P � U3D3

We have the following more general result.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))Given P � UkDk , for any n, k P N we have

dnpPq �"

0 if n ¥ 2k � 1;°j¥1 b

2k�j,n�k�j if k � 1 ¤ n ¤ 2k � 1.

.

In particular, dnpU3D3q � 0 for n ¥ 5.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Avoiding Uk�1Dk�1U

P � UUDDUD p or UDUUDDqWe have the following more general result.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Pinzani, West (2013))Given P � Uk�1Dk�1UD, for any n, k P N we have

dnpPq ��n � 1

k � 2

Ck�1

�k�2

s�2

bk�2,s ��

s�2

i�0

bk�3�i,s�2�i

�n � k � s � 3� 2i

i

�. (1)

In particular, dnpUUDDUDq � 2n � 2 for n ¥ 3.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

A recursive approach

� ∆Ppxq: generating function of Dyck paths avoiding P, where xtracks the length.

� CPpx , yq: bivariate generating function of smallest Dyck prefixescontaining the pattern P (i.e., such that no proper prefixcontains P), where x tracks the length and y the final height.

� ε: empty path.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

A recursive approach

� ∆Ppxq: generating function of Dyck paths avoiding P, where xtracks the length.

� CPpx , yq: bivariate generating function of smallest Dyck prefixescontaining the pattern P (i.e., such that no proper prefixcontains P), where x tracks the length and y the final height.

� ε: empty path.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

A recursive approach

� ∆Ppxq: generating function of Dyck paths avoiding P, where xtracks the length.

� CPpx , yq: bivariate generating function of smallest Dyck prefixescontaining the pattern P (i.e., such that no proper prefixcontains P), where x tracks the length and y the final height.

� ε: empty path.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

A recursive approach

Theorem (Bacher, Bernini, F., Gunby, Pinzani, West (2014))For any pattern P, the generating function CPpx , yq satisfies thefollowing recurrence formulas:

Cεpx , yq � 1;

CPUpx , yq � yCPpx , yq � xCPpx , xqy � x

xy ;

CPDpx , yq � xy�1

1� xyCPpx , yq � xy�1CPpx , 0q.

Moreover, the generating function ∆Ppxq is given by:

∆εpxq � 0;

∆PUpxq � ∆Ppxq � CPpx , xq;∆PDpxq � ∆Ppxq � CPpx , 0q.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

A recursive approach

Corollary (Bacher, Bernini, F., Gunby, Pinzani, West (2014))For any pattern P, the generating function CPpx , yq is of the form:

CPpx , yq � Apx , yqp1� x2qi p1� xyqj ,

where Apx , yq is a polynomial and i and j are nonnegative integers.Moreover, the generating function ∆Ppxq has the form:

∆Ppxq � Bpxqp1� x2qk ,

where Bpxq is an even polynomial and k a nonnegative integer.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

A recursive approach

The last equation enables us to compute the number dPpnq for sufficientlylarge values of n. Writing Bpxq � B0 � B1x

2 � � � � � Bdx2d ,we have:

dPpnq �d

i�0

Bi

�n � i � k � 1

k � 1

,

which shows that dPpnq is always given by a polynomial function of n forlarge values of n.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Asymptotics

Given any two unrestricted paths P and Q on tU,Du having the same length, we say

that Q is strictly higher than P whenever P lies below Q and the only contact points

are the starting and ending points of the two paths.

Theorem (Bacher, Bernini, F., Gunby, Pinzani, West (2014))Let P be a word of tU,Du� of the form P � Ua P 1Db, such that eitherP 1 is empty or it starts with a D, ends with a U and has c up steps andd down steps (note that P does not have to be a Dyck path). Letk � c � d � 2 and let αP be the number of paths with c up steps and ddown steps strictly higher than P 1. The number dnpPq of Dyck paths oflength 2n avoiding P is asymptotic to:

dnpPq � Ca Cb αP

k!nk .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

(Principal) pattern avoiding classes

Asymptotics

Given any two unrestricted paths P and Q on tU,Du having the same length, we say

that Q is strictly higher than P whenever P lies below Q and the only contact points

are the starting and ending points of the two paths.

Theorem (Bacher, Bernini, F., Gunby, Pinzani, West (2014))Let P be a word of tU,Du� of the form P � Ua P 1Db, such that eitherP 1 is empty or it starts with a D, ends with a U and has c up steps andd down steps (note that P does not have to be a Dyck path). Letk � c � d � 2 and let αP be the number of paths with c up steps and ddown steps strictly higher than P 1. The number dnpPq of Dyck paths oflength 2n avoiding P is asymptotic to:

dnpPq � Ca Cb αP

k!nk .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

The Mobius function

Given a locally finite poset P, its Mobius function is defined as

µ :P � P ÝÑ C:px , xq ÞÝÑ 1,

:px , yq ÞÝÑ �¸

x¤z y

µpx , zq � �¸

x z¤y

µpz , yq px � yq

Note that µpx , yq � 0 if x ¦ y .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

The Mobius function

Given a locally finite poset P, its Mobius function is defined as

µ :P � P ÝÑ C:px , xq ÞÝÑ 1,

:px , yq ÞÝÑ �¸

x¤z y

µpx , zq � �¸

x z¤y

µpz , yq px � yq

Note that µpx , yq � 0 if x ¦ y .

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

The Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset

The computation of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isstill largely open, even if the structure of this poset appears to be simplerthan the structure of the permutation pattern poset.

In the next slides I’ll list a few simple facts we have been able to prove.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

The Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset

The computation of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isstill largely open, even if the structure of this poset appears to be simplerthan the structure of the permutation pattern poset.

In the next slides I’ll list a few simple facts we have been able to prove.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Basic facts

The absolute value of the Mobius function of the Dyck pattern poset isunbounded. This is a consequence of the following:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � pUDqn�1 and Q � pUDqn�1, we have µpP,Qq � �n2�.The maximum value on interval of rank 2 is n2. More precisely:

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Given P � UpUDqn�1D and Q � UpUDqn�1D, we have µpP,Qq � n2,and this is the maximum value attained by µ on intervals of rank 2.

Conjecture. The maximum value of the Mobius function on intervalsof rank 3 is p2n � 1q � n2, attained by the intervalrUpUDqn�1D,UpUDqn�2Ds.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

The Mobius function

Dyck paths having two peaksClearly the Mobius function of an initial interval where the maximum hasonly one peak is trivial to compute.We have complete results concerning the Mobius function of initialintervals in which the maximum has two peaks.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)Let P � UαDβUγDδ. If at least one among |α� β|, |β � γ| and |γ � δ|is ¡ 1, then µpUD,Pq � 0.

Proposition (Bernini, F., Steingrımsson)If |α� β|, |β � γ|, |γ � δ| ¤ 1, then one of the following holds (providedthat P is long enough):

� P has even semilength, thus:

� P � UαDα�1UαDα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � �1;� P � UαDαUαDα, and µpUD,Pq � �2;

� P has odd semilength, thus:

� P � UαDαUα�1Dα�1 (or the reverse one), and µpUD,Pq � 1;� P � Uα�1DαUαDα�1, and µpUD,Pq � 2.

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

Lattice paths from an order-theoretic perspective

The notion of path pattern

Open problems

Further work

� Two or more patterns?

� Wilf-equivalence?

� Transport along bijections onto other combinatorial structures?

� Number of (saturated) chains? Structure of the intervals?

� Other classes of paths (Motzkin, Schroder, ...)?

� Mobius function:

� µpUD,Pq when P has three peaks? Or more?� alternates in sign? (Lexicographic shellability...)� closure operators? Galois connections?

top related