an attempt to understand svatah pramanyavada in advaita vedanta - tara chatterjee

20
TARA CHATTERJEE AN ATTEMPT TO UNDERSTAND SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA When we see a pot in front of us, or we have an 5xnalaka fruit in our palm, or when we know that there is fire in a distant house as smoke is coming out of its windows, or when we learn that Agoka was a great ruler from our teacher in a history class, we naturally, automatically and instantaneously know that these apprehensions are true, i.e., there is a pot, there is an fimalaka and there is fire, and that there was a great king called Agoka, and we do not wait for any verification or confirmation or justification for such knowledge. This is exactly what the svatah,prdmdn.yavdda, which I want to elucidate, seeks to assert. Its main opponents, the Naiyfiyikas, never question the empirical truth of these claims. But they contend that this is not what is meant by apprehension of truth. Truth in their view is a complicated property which can only be grasped by reflective, mediate, inferential knowl- edge. The svatah.-paratah, controversy about truth/pramdtva/prdmdnya is a traditional controversy in Indian philosophy, and all the major schools have participated in it. The arguments, the counter arguments, and their philosophical implications have been discussed again and again. But it is a curious fact that modern scholars have to some extent neglected the svata.h theory, and even when they have turned to it, they name the Bh~ttas and the Pr~bhhkaras as its main upholders, and sadly omit the Advaita Ved~ntins. One of the reasons for this neglect is the preoccupation of the Advaitins with absolute reality and the consequent neglect of the empirical concepts. They usually hold that the empirical concepts are logically inconsistent, hence meta- physically untenable. Their attitude is the same towards the concept of truth. After subtle dialectical criticism of the Ny~ya theory, Advaitins present their typical judgement that pramdtva is rationally inexplicable and only the verdicts of common sense regulate our practical life. But then Madhusfidana Sarasvati, the great Advaita thinker, does some- thing exceptional, in as much as he supplements his destructive Journal of lndian Philosophy 19: 229--248, 1991. © 1991 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Upload: vistascan

Post on 07-Dec-2015

281 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

DESCRIPTION

A paper on Advaita Vedanta

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

T A R A C H A T T E R J E E

A N A T T E M P T T O U N D E R S T A N D S V A T A H

P R A M A N Y A V A D A IN A D V A I T A V E D A N T A

When we see a pot in front of us, or we have an 5xnalaka fruit in our palm, or when we know that there is fire in a distant house as smoke is coming out of its windows, or when we learn that Agoka was a great ruler from our teacher in a history class, we naturally, automatically and instantaneously know that these apprehensions are true, i.e., there is a pot, there is an fimalaka and there is fire, and that there was a great king called Agoka, and we do not wait for any verification or confirmation or justification for such knowledge. This is exactly what the svatah, prdmdn.yavdda, which I want to elucidate, seeks to assert. Its main opponents, the Naiyfiyikas, never question the empirical truth of these claims. But they contend that this is not what is meant by apprehension of truth. Truth in their view is a complicated property which can only be grasped by reflective, mediate, inferential knowl- edge.

The svatah.-paratah, controversy about truth/pramdtva/prdmdnya is a traditional controversy in Indian philosophy, and all the major schools have participated in it. The arguments, the counter arguments, and their philosophical implications have been discussed again and again. But it is a curious fact that modern scholars have to some extent neglected the svata.h theory, and even when they have turned to it, they name the Bh~ttas and the Pr~bhhkaras as its main upholders, and sadly omit the Advaita Ved~ntins. One of the reasons for this neglect is the preoccupation of the Advaitins with absolute reality and the consequent neglect of the empirical concepts. They usually hold that the empirical concepts are logically inconsistent, hence meta- physically untenable. Their attitude is the same towards the concept of truth. After subtle dialectical criticism of the Ny~ya theory, Advaitins present their typical judgement that pramdtva is rationally inexplicable and only the verdicts of common sense regulate our practical life. But then Madhusfidana Sarasvati, the great Advaita thinker, does some- thing exceptional, in as much as he supplements his destructive

Journal o f lndian Philosophy 19: 229--248, 1991. © 1991 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

Page 2: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

230 TARA CHATTERJEE

criticism of the concept of pramdtva by a positive constructive discus- sion of the commonsense, naive, practical concept.

His theory, shorn of all technicalities and in the barest outline, is this: all apprehensions are known apprehensions, and they are 1Oaown as true. The question of revision arises only if later circumstances suggest that the previous apprehension was false. In this paper my main aim is to find out whether this naive approach can be retained or not. I have also tried to understand how the Advaitins have developed this theory, whether there is any scope for reconstruction of this theory on the lines suggested by them, or whether this naive approach has to be given up in favor of other subtle philosophical considera- tions.

The svatah.-paratah, controversy centers round two questions: how is truth known and how is truth produced. The problem is sometimes extended to other related spheres, but these two are fundamental. I have tried to restrict myself mainly to the former question, and have discussed the question of origination, only in order to bring out some aspects of the former question. The questions are raised about both truth and falsehood. These problems are closely linked with another associated problem: how is an apprehension known? Here by permu- tation and combination of all the available answers, we get numerous alternative theories, and we have considered the Advaita solution only as one such attempt. I have chosen the Naiy~tyikas, the stalwart Indian logicians and epistemologists, as our main opponents. I have mainly taken the Nyfiya arguments from Gahge~a's Pr~mdnyav~da (leaving aside the technical formulations), as introduced, translated and interpreted by J. N. Mohanty. It should be borne in mind that Gahge~a directed his criticisms against the Bhfittas, the Mi~ras and the Prfibhfikaras, and never against the Advaltins. However, the Advaitins share with the N~lmS.msakas the main tenet that truth is intrinsic and falsehood is extrinsic to apprehensions. That is why I find the stage set by Gahge~a most convenient for a discussion of the Advaita view. I have Lried to confine myself strictly to the Advaita version of svatah prarnanyav~tda, and have made stray references to the M-un~unsakas

Page 3: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PR,~M.~NYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 231

only in so far as that helps to bring out fully some aspects of the Advaita theory.

When the Naiyfiyikas assert that truth and falsehood are extrinsic, they mean that these are certain specific properties of apprehensions, produced and determined by some factors other than those which are responsible for the production of apprehensions. They hold that the apprehensions are not self-manifesting, they are known by reflective cognitions called anuvyavasdya. This means that an ordinary appre- hension of the form 'this is a pot' reveals the pot only, and the cognition itself is known by a further knowledge of the form 'I have a knowledge that this is a pot'. But even this reflective cognition does not grasp the truth of the first cognition. Truth is a complicated property of the cognition 'this is a pot', determined by the objective situation, and it is known by mediate inferential processes based on the reflective cognition and further experience. The same is the case with falsehood.

The MimS_msakas and the Advaitins also agree that falsehood is extrinsic. But with truth they take an opposite stand. They hold that truth is produced by the factors which produce an apprehension, truth is known when the apprehension itself is known. Or to borrow a description from Gafige~a, according to svatah, prdmdnyavdda cogni- tions are always known as possessing truth)

Gaflge~a in his five alternate formulations has tried to express with great persuasiveness and accuracy the exact difference between the opponents. 2 He suggests that according to svatah, pramanyavdda truth is known by all those apprehensions which know the apprehension under consideration (except of course the one which knows it as untrue), whereas their opponents hold that truth is known only by some of these apprehensions (the apprehension which is the result of the truth-establishing inference). His formulations also suggest that according to paratah, pramanyavdda truth is only known by a mediate knowledge, knowledge or inference based on reflective apprehension of the cognition under consideration, whereas according to svatah pramanyavdda truth is known immediately by the apprehension which knows the initial cognition. In this context, we can quote one of J. N. Mohanty's illuminating and suggestive comments. He speaks of the svatah, prdmdnya theory as asserting "that there is no criterion of

Page 4: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

232 T A R A C H A T T E R J E E

truth, though there are criteria of error". 3 This at once shows the difference of the svatah theory from the corresponding paratah. theory, and the difference of the Indian controversy from the Western controversy about the criteria of truth. The Naiyfiyikas assert that we need some criteria to measure truth, so knowledge of truth is always mediate; they have spoken of different criteria of truth such as coher- ence, correspondence, conative satisfaction, etc. But according to the svatah theory truth is natural to a cognition, it requires no external criterion, it is known immediately when the apprehension is known. In the Western tradition philosophers hold that truth necessarily needs some justification and they discuss the relative merits of coherence, etc. as measures of truth, and as Mohanty points out some of them accept even self-evidence as such a criterion.

The Advaitins use the term 'vrtti-jfidna' to designate the temporal psychic occurrents which are called 'jhdna' in other philosophical systems. But in every individual there is said to be one continuous identical principle of awareness, always self-aware, distinct from the changing mental states called the sdksin. The sdksin continuously takes note of all the experiences of an individual. But this awareness is different in kind from the empirical cognitions as it does not take place through separate mental states; the sdksin is directly and automatically aware of them. When an individual knows that 'this is a pot' he is aware that he has this knowledge, although there is no cor- responding mental state which explicitly formulates this knowledge. He also believes that as a matter of fact this is a pot, and it is absurd to claim that the apprehension is neutral as regards its own truth, which is to be ascertained later. Apprehensions most naturally involve the claim that objects are as they are taken to be. This is truth. So the apprehension 'this is a pot' is not complete in itself. It implies that the sdksin is aware of it, and also that it is aware of its truth.

But apprehension or rather its Indian synonym 'jhdna' has a wide scope. It covers not only all perceptual, inferential and linguistic cognitions, but also such phenomena as error and doubt. And the Advaitin, as a svatah, prdmdnyavddin, has to explain how truth, which is a property that distinguishes true cognitions from erroneous ones, is cognised in both true and untrue cognitions alike. Is truth in the same sense present in both? How do we explain the errors which are

Page 5: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 233

initially accepted as true, later on rejected as lacking truth? Is truth that is initially apprehended a real objective property or just a psychological claim to truth? These are some of the questions which the Advaitin must answer.

The Bh~.ttas have identified truth with the psychological claim to truth. They assert that all apprehensions are initially apprehended as true but the corrective cognition destroys that truth. 4 The corrective cognition either shows that the object is not what it has been taken to be, or the apprehensi0n has been tarnished by some defective cause. Let the apprehension be 'this is a snake'. Now if subsequent experi- ence points out that it was only a rope and not a snake, or that light had been scanty so there had been improper cognition, then the initial truth is destroyed. But the truth which is destructible is nothing but the initial sense of certainty, not truth proper but only a truth-claim.

The Advaitins look at the problem from a different angle. They say that under normal conditions all our cognitions are true to their objects. Only under abnormal circumstances, if there is something irregular in the generating factors and the presence of such irregularity is known, then doubt arises and the question of revision creeps in. The corrective apprehension does not destroy truth; it only reveals that the initial apprehension being erroneous is not an apprehension at all. In other words, all apprehensions qua apprehensions are true, errors are similar to normal apprehensions only in appearance; actually they are distortions. The Advaitin accepts error as a phenomenon, but does not grant it any cognitive status. Errors are produced by defects which hamper the production of cognitions proper. We see a rope as a snake only if the light is scanty; we see a yellow conchshell only when we suffer from jaundice. So some defect or other disturbs the normal situation. The analysis is significant in as much as it implies that errors are not cognitions; they only falsely simulate j~dna proper, and they must not influence our analysis of j~dna itself.

Madhusfidana is particularly clear on this point, and he leaves no scope for misinterpretation. He speaks of error and doubt as 'jfidnd- bhdsa' which literally means that they have the semblance of j~dna, but as a matter of fact they are not j~dna. He makes his point abso- lutely clear by comparing error with inferential fallacies. In Indian philosophy 'hetvdbhdsas' stand for the inferential fallacies, which

Page 6: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

234 T A R A C H A T T E R J E E

hinder the inference from taking place. These literally mean those which have the appearance of a hetu (or a valid middle term), but as a matter of fact they are not hetu as they do not properly fulfil all the conditions necessary for being a hetu proper. Madhusfidana asserts that just as hetvdbhdsas are not hetu proper, similarly jfidnabhdsas are not jhdna proper. 5

This is a very important proposal, as it reveals the fundamental difference of approach of the two schools. According to Nyftya, 'jfidna' includes under it both pramd and apramd, truth and falsehood. The two classes share certain common characteretics. A jfidna is called true, if it possesses a property called truth. It is called untrue if "untruth" characterises it. Truth is said to be produced by a guna or a special excellence, which is something more than the conditions which produce jfidna. Similarly, "untruth" is said to be produced by defects in the causal conditions.

Some svatahprdmd.nyavddins have accepted this basic Ny~ya analysis, for example, the Bh~tttas. They share the Nyftya platform in the sense that they accept truth and falsehood as subordinate classes under the wider class jfidna. But the Advaitins hold that jfidna and pramd are coextensive, the conditions which produce jhdna are those that produce truth. They consider apramd as an exception, a distor- tion, so that an analysis of this distortion must not influence our analysis of cognition proper.

To sum up, the Advaitins hold that the apprehensions occur, they are known, and they are also known to be true, not by explicit reflective secondary judgements, but automatically and implicitly. They hold that jhdna has a direct natural access to reality. For them, apprehensions (at the empirical level) are nothing but ascertainment of objects, and the Vivaranaprameya Sam. graha asserts that truth is as much essential to knowledge, as heat is to fire. 6 Madhusfidana says that just as when we know a particular we know the universal present in it, so also when we know an apprehension we know the truth present in it . v

But then the Advaita theory gives rise to a series of questions. Truth, as the Naiy~yikas have carefully defined it, is a very com- plicated property, and how can it be grasped so easily and automati- cally? If the Advaitin decides to give up the Ny~ya definition he has to

Page 7: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 235

come forward with an alternative definition. We have already mentioned that traditionally they have been asked, if truth is grasped initially, then how is error possible and how is doubt possible. A m o d e m critic may be worried that the theory blurs over the distinc- tion between knowledge and belief. He may want to ask the svatah prdmdnyavddin to explain that distinction on his own theory. Pramd is usually rendered into English as knowledge, and 'knowledge' is explained as 'justified true belief'. Svatah. prdmdnyavdda treats all apprehensions as pramd, and describes pramd as true belief, holding that the question of justification does not arise, for justification is neither possible nor necessary. So svatah, prdmdnyavdda has to explain why it rejects the commonly accepted difference between knowledge and belief. As a matter of fact we seek justification and confirmation for truth, so svatah, pramanyavdda has to show in what sense these processes of validation are significant. These are some of the questions which must be discussed before finally evaluating the Advaita theory of svatah, pr(~mdnyavdda.

I!

First let us turn to Madhusfidana's treatment of the concept of truth. The Naiygyikas defined truth as 'tadvati tatprakdrakatva'. It is a

special property of certain apprehensions. An apprehension is said to be true if it posseses the 'tat' as a qualifier, when the 'tat' as a matter of fact is present in the ontological object. J. N. Mohanty has analysed in detail the precise meaning and significance of this definition, follow- ing the Ny~ya tradition and Gafigega in his introduction to the Gafigega's Theory of Truth. 8 For our convenience we would like to refer to a few points.

J. N. Mohanty says that according to Nyfiya "True knowledge is an experience whose qualifier is such that it belongs to the object". Qualifiers are epistemic components of knowledge. In the apprehen- sion 'S is P', S-ness, P-ness and P are the qualifiers. In the apprehen- sion 'this is silver', 'this-ness', 'silver-ness' and silver are the qualifiers. So to claim that 'this is silver' is true, is to mean that 'this-ness', 'silver- ness', etc. are present in the corresponding object. Here J. N. Mohanty points out that this analysis amply shows that truth is a relational

Page 8: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

236 TARA CHATTERJEE

property, a hybrid entity composed of both ontological and epistemic constituents. The first part 'tadvati' refers to the ontological situation, where the qualifier is present in the object. The second part 'tat- prakdrakatva' refers to the apprehension which is said to involve the qualifiers. J. N. Mohanty warns us that Gaflgega did not subscribe to any copy theory. Gaflge~a rejected the concept of truth as 'ydthdrthya' on the ground that there cannot be any similarity between cognition and object. The Nyftya concept of truth is not to be interpreted as correspondence.

When Madhusfidana says that 'tadvati tatprakarakatva' is a property that is common to truth and error, he is blamed for distorting Gaflge~a, for misinterpreting the ontological object as the epistemolog- ical object. He is accused of twisting 'tadvati' into 'tadvadvigesyakatve sati' and the 'viges.ya' is not the ontological object, but it is the qualificandum which is relative to the apprehension. So he destroys the ontological component of truth, and turns truth into a fully epistemological concept. But in all fairness to Madhusfidana, it must be acknowledged that he argues that once you accept the distinction between the epistemological object and the ontological object, the former acts as a screen, the latter eludes our grasp, and it is impos- sible to find the latter. His dialectical criticism of the Nyftya definition, as well as the construction of the empirical concept of truth are based on this criticism.

The Ny~tya of course does not speak of the epistemic and the ontological object. Nor does Madhusfidana mention them or state explicitly what we have suggested here. Ny~tya speaks of the object and the epistemological components of an apprehension. But Ny~ya is not very clear about the ontological status of these components. On the primary level they are transparent, they are not the media through which the object is presented or represented. This is absolutely consistent with the Nyftya tenet that the apprehensions do not have any form of their own. On this level cognitions have a direct access to reality; they grasp the object and its properties and their relatedness, as is expected of Nyftya realism. Nyftya further holds that the objects determine the character of apprehensions. Had this been all, Ny~ya would have said that by knowing an apprehension it is possible to know the objective situation, and it would have at once automatically

Page 9: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PR,~MANYAV,~DA IN A D V A I T A VED,~NTA 237

become a supporter of svatah, pramanyavdda. But the Naiyfiyika takes a different stand. He says that the reflective apprehensions have no direct access to reality. 9 If the primary apprehension is of the form 'this is silver', then the corresponding reflective cognition is of the form 'I know this through this-ness and silver-ness'J ° This being so we require further investigation to determine whether all these qualifiers are present in the object or not. Although the primary apprehension has direct access to reality, the reflective awareness is limited only to the epistemic qualifiers. Ny~ya holds that one cannot judge by looking at an apprehension whether the relatedness which appears in knowl- edge is objective or not. So truth cannot be grasped ab initio. If this be conceded, apprehensions assume a screen-like character. All the descriptive elements involved in a cognition are said to be qualifiers; only the bare 'this' refers to the object. Nyfiya claims that the qualifiers are determined by the objects, yet the relatedness of the qualifiers and the 'this' are not so determined. So the apprehension as a whole assumes a form of its own, and further investigations are needed to ascertain its truth. Thus although Nyfiya rejects that concept of cor- respondence, it enters into it through the backdoor. Further when Ny~ya holds that 'apprehension' comprehends two sub-classes pramd and apramd, they somehow loosen the direct link of apprehension qufi apprehension with reality. With this in mind, it is easy to understand Madhusfidana's point: to say that the ontological object and the cor- responding apprehension are separate from each other and there may be disparity between the two is to lose the object which can never be successfully recovered.

It is very difficult to bring out clearly the essence of Madhusfidana's argument from his complicated dialectical arguments and the maze of numerous alternatives. He criticises all the prevalent definitions of truth, including the traditionally accepted Advaita concept of truth as abddhitatva. His ultimate conclusion is that truth is anirvacaniya and logically non-justifiable. 11 However, on the empirical level, for all practical dealings some concept of truth is unavoidable, and for that purpose he offers his own concept of truth as a sort of working hypothesis.

As we have already mentioned, he criticised the Ny~ya definition of truth as tadvati tatprakdrakatva by saying that it extends to error. He

Page 10: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

238 TARA C H A T T E R J E E

says this because according to him, that which appears in an appre- hension is its object. In 'tadvati tatprakdrakatva' the tadvati refers to the ontological situation. It means that the tat is present in the object. But what does this presence mean? When can we say that x is present in y or y is the substratum of x? Here the mere appearence of x in y does not solve the problem, for in all apprehensions the qualifiers appear in the substratum. Let us take the case of a red crystal, where the crystal appears as red, because of the proximity of a red flower. The redness as well the whiteness appear in the substratum, so why do we accept whiteness as a true qualifier and reject the claim of redness? So appearance is not the sole deciding factor. If we try to account for the situation by saying that redness has no connection with the substratum as it is later on rejected, then Madhusfidana would say that we are shifting grounds, for appearance is no more the guiding factor.

In fact existence can never be explained in terms of appearance, for appearance in its own turn has to be explained in terms of existence and the whole discussion becomes circular. For, if it be asked, 'where do the qualifiers exist?' it cannot be said 'that they exist in the object in which they appear' for the counter question 'where do the qualifiers appear?' can only be answered by the circular statement that they appear in the substratum in which they exist.

Nor can the impasse be solved by introducing the concept of videsya, by replacing the 'tadvati' by the 'tadvadviges.yakatve sati', or by substituting the ontological object by the qualificandum or the correlate of the qualifiers. Truth cannot be defined as a property of being an apprehension which involves as a qualifier that which is pres- ent in the qualificandum, for none of the alternative explanations of the above definition is acceptable. Does the term 'viges.ya' indicate that which as a matter of fact is the object, or that which appears as the object? The former explanation is not acceptable, for that is the very issue under discussion; we want to find out what as a matter of fact is the object. Then he urges that the silver in the silver-shell illusion should be called the object, for it appears as object in the apprehen- sion, and the mark of being a qualificandum, viz., the property of being the correlate of the qualifiers is present in it. Unless we accept the silver as the qualificandum how can we explain all the activities which arise after the apprehension of silver?

Page 11: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 239

In fact Madhusfidana suggests that it is impossible to locate the object as the substratum of the epistemic qualifiers. Every property that appears in an apprehension is called a qualifier. The only access to reality can be through the bare 'that' bereft of all the qualifiers. But Madhusfidana argues that why should that which is presented be called the vi~es.ya, when it is not necessarily the substratum of the vigesanas appearing in an apprehension?

Or in other words Madhusfidana suggests that truth in the sense of such a complicated property is not tenable. Later on he would argue that truth in that sense cannot be ascertained either. But we shall come to that.

Madhusfidana likes to speak in terms of the whole object and the whole apprehension, instead of splitting and analysing the apprehen- sion into various parts. Truth is the property of being ascertainment of a hitherto unknown object; untrue apprehensions are directed towards apparent objects only. True apprehensions are directed towards real objects -- objects capable of possessing unknown existence. The objects of error are not pre-existent; they come into existence only with the apprehensions. To give an example, a snake seen in a rope is a false snake, for it was not there before the illusion took place; so the snake as well as the corresponding experience are untrue. Whereas the experience of a rope as a rope is correct, for the rope is there, whether anybody experiences it or not. So truth is not identical with the initial psychological sense of certainty and it does not extend to apramd.

Apprehensions as well as their truth are called £aks..i-vedya. This means that a principle of consciousness is always there, which knows the apprehensions as well as their truth, without the mediation of any other mental state. Or in other words when a person sees a rope, he is aware that he is seeing it, he is also aware that he is seeing a rope that independently existed even before he saw it, whether he is explicitly aware of these implications through full-fledged mental states or not. When Madhusfidana claims that truth is svatah.-pramd he means exactly this.

When Madhusfidana states that falsehood is apprehended through extrinsic sources, he means two things. A corrective knowledge called bddha-jfidna, or a cognition of some defect or abnormality in the

Page 12: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

240 T A R A C H A T T E R J E E

generating situation called dosa-j~dna, may lead to rectification of error. Perception of a snake in a rope may be corrected by a proper perception of rope, or the perception of a stick bent in water may be

corrected by our knowledge that the apparent bentness is caused by deflection of light. However error is always caused by some defect. The most significant word in this context is that these errors are jfidndbhdsas or only apparent cognitions. When an apprehension previously known as true is now rejected as error, the error loses not only its claim to be true, but also its claim to be jfidna. It is a simulat- ing process, a distortion, which should not influence our analysis of jhdna proper. Or in order to accommodate error we should not think of jfidna as a screenlike duplicate of reality which might give a correct picture of reality or it might not. Cognitions have direct access to reality, and errors are defects to be rejected as defects. Doubt as an apramd has been explained by Madhusfidana in the same way.

Il l

So the conclusion which emerges out of all these discussions is that the Indian philosophers have spoken of knowledge of truth in two different senses. It is true that both the contending parties mean by truth a property of awareness determined by the object. But still there is a difference. In one sense truth is nothing but the naive compelling sense of certainty of the object, which is an essential component of an apprehension; in the more sophisticated sense it stands for a com- plicated relational property of apprehension determined by the object. Naturally knowledge of truth also has different meanings. According to the first sense, to know an apprehension is to know that it is true, for truth is its essential component. According to the other party knowledge of truth is by definition a reflective judgement, which compares the statement and the object, confirms that the statement asserts something about the object which as a matter of fact is present in the object.

In all fairness to Gafige~a it must be admitted that it is he who sensed the difference between these two senses of truth for the first time. He spoke of them as arthani~caya and prdmdn.yani~caya as ascertainment of the object and ascertainment of truth. He holds that

Page 13: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 241

ascertainment of the object is an essential feature of an apprehension, but the ascertainment of truth takes place only if the occasion demands. Gafige~a presents this differentiation in his answer to the traditional charge of infinite regress brought against Nyfiya.

The Nyfiya position in a nutshell is this: the truths of all apprehen- sions are known through inferences. In most cases these inferences are based on familiarity, that is similarity to clearly validated and familiar apprehensions. But in the cases of novel apprehensions (anabhydsada- ~otpannajhdna) truth is inferred through samvddajTtdna, apprehension of coherence, and/or phalajhdna or apprehension of successful activity issuing out of the primary cognition. Here the critics urge that the Ny~ya position involves a vicious infinite regress. The truth of a primary apprehension is known through an inference, but how do we know the truth of this inference, and the truth of the apprehensions involved in this inference, such as sam. vddajfidna, phalajhdna, etc.? If it be known through some other inference then that inference in its own turn needs do be justified, and so on ad infinitum.

The Naiyftyikas have answered this charge in two ways. Some of them, like V~caspati, have said that apprehensions involved in confirmatory inference, such as inferential process, samvddajfidna, etc. are self-valid, hence they need not be examined again, and thus there is no infinite regress) 2 They have of course added the explanatory note that these are svatah-pramd in a very special sense. Truth in the sense of tadvati tatprakdrakatva is not grasped immediately, but they are self-valid in the sense that under no situation may their truth be doubted, and as they are beyond doubt, we do not require any inference to test their validity and as such the question of regress does not arise.

Gaflge~a, however, has a slightly different answer. He says that all apprehensions involve ascertainment of the object, and that is suf- ficient for all our practical dealings. But, under special circumstances, if we doubt the claim of the initial knowledge to reveal reality, i.e., if there is doubt about the certainty of the object of the primary appre- hension, the normalcy of the situation is disturbed and there cannot be any unwavering activity. Now the certainty can be restored only by ascertaining the truth of the apprehension and we take recourse to inference which seeks out the truth.J3 This inference can always

Page 14: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

242 TARA CHATTERJEE

perform its duty without itself being justified; it has to be examined only if fresh occasions cause doubt about its validity; hence under ordinary circumstances the question of regress does not arise.

Gaflge~a's answer to the charge is interesting. The svatah prdmdn.ya- vadin has not denied all this, only he has given a very different inter- pretation of the whole situation.

We have previously said that the concept of truth as tadvati tatpra- kdrakatva is untenable according to the Advaitins. They also urge that had it been tenable, because of the very nature of the concept it would have been impossible to ascertain it. The confirmatory inferences can only confirm the initial sense of certainty, but in what way is it indicator of the tadvati tatprakdrakatva? Gaflge~a himself was aware of these difficulties. Thus he poses the problem: how is tadvati tatpra- kdrakatva known for the first time?

The svatah, prdmdn.yavddins have critcised the superior claim of the confirmatory cognitions to reveal reality in many places. Time and again they have pointed out that confirmation, coherence etc. are found in wish fulfilment dreams. These are found to be dreams when we wake up, hence why should we attach a superior sense of certainty to them? When we look at water we may doubt our perception, but when we go and touch it or taste it, and find that it is water, we confirm our previous perception. Here we are only advocating the superiority of touch over vision, but why should we propose such a preferential treatment?

But then, the critic would surely ask, if confirmation is not valuable how is it that we use confirmation so much in our everyday life? When new grounds are trodden the scientists repeat their experiments again and again, to confirm their hypothesis. In philosophical literature philosophers have spoken highly about confirmation. These have been called the ends of cognitive situations. What is the significance of all this? How do we come out of the impasse, when there is doubt about the truth of a certain apprehension, unless we rely upon the confirma- tory cognitions?

In classical Advaita we get the answer in the Vivaran. aprameya- sam. graha. There it is said that later apprehensions are necessary, not to find out or confirm truth, but to dispel doubt or to reject error. 14 So it can be proposed that the scientists repeat their experiments to

Page 15: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 243

find out the mistakes in the calculations and procedures, if there be any, and not to confirm truth.

Both the Advaitins and Gafige~a agree that in every apprehension there is ascertainment of the object. But whereas the Advaitin further holds that here we are implicitly also aware that the apprehensions correctly ascertain the hitherto unknown object, the Ny~ya speaks of no such awareness. Again both of them agree that we take up further enquiry only in cases of doubt. But, whereas Gafige~a holds that the further enquiry leads to ascertainment of truth, the Advaitin holds that ascertainment of truth in the Ny~ya sense is impossible, it only leads to discovery of the defects which led to the emergence of doubt.

Madhusfidana asserts that apprehensions are of two types, one in which defects and disturbing factors are present, another in which they are absent. In the former the natural apprehension of truth is absent and the question of revision arises. 15 In this sense even novelty and

unfamiliarity, which have been called 'anabhydsa' are defects, and we take up enquiry to get rid of these defects. To give a very simple example, if in the darkness we see something like a snake, we bring a torch and try to remove the darkness; if in the proper light we see that the apparent snake is just a rope, we give up our previous apprehen- sion, be it doubt or error, and there it ends, we do not get involved in the analysis of proper cognition.

Ascertainments, whether true or false, are complete in themselves; it is doubt which issues in further enquiry. The doubt may be of two types. One is doubt proper, which is a very unstable state of mind. Because of some hindrances and disturbances the proper apprehen- sion does not take place. Here we have some idea about the object, but not any definite knowledge; alternative predicates suggest them- selves and we do not know which one to choose. Such an uneasiness can be solved by a removal of defects. To go back to the naive example given above, by bringing in light we solve the doubt, 'is it a snake or a rope?'

The other type of doubt is the philosophical doubt, doubt asso- ciated with academic scepticism, doubt for doubt's sake, a doubt which never can be resolved. In Indian philosophy there is no place for such doubt. Truth is natural, all our experiences involve a compel- ling sense of certainty, which does not demand any justification. All

Page 16: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

244 TARA CHATTERJEE

those questions arise in case of doubt. But doubt arises only in abnormal circumstances and doubt must not be universalised.

The last question which remains to be answered is that if truth be apprehended in true and erroneous cognitions alike, how does it serve to differentiate between the two? Here the conclusion which seems to be most consistent with the arguments advanced by svatah, prdmdn.ya- vdda is that truth is not a property at all. When the Advaitin states that j~dna and prarnd are identical, he obviously denies the traditional explication that pramd is jhdna plus truth. He is trying to take the stand that truth is the essential character of all apprehensions. Just as heat is to fire so also truth is to cognitions. It is something so natural that we are not explicitly aware of its presence, unless and until some very special occasion makes us consciously reflective of its presence. To give a very material analogy it is something like health; we are not fully aware of its presence as long as it is there, but its absence makes us fully conscious of its previous presence.

Actually the emphasis is totally on error. Svatah pramanyavdda has defined error, and has given different criteria of error. We can take svatah, prdmdn.yavdda as saying that to focus on and explain error, we posit a certain property called truth, but that is probably unnecessary.

In Indian philosophy error has been treated as a very important phenomenon. Even Gafige~a has not been able to deny its importance. When Gaflge~a tries to find out the philosophical derivation of the concept of truth, he first lands on the concept of truth as absence of error. To quote J. N. Mohanty, 'Gaflge~a has said that the first appre- hension of truth is not of truth qu~ truth, but of truth taken of as absence of falsity'. 16 We find the same emphasis in svatah, pramanya- vdda. Its approach is that in order to accommodate error, we must not distort the nature of ordinary apprehension. A criterion of truth is necessary to dispel doubt, explain error and confirm certainty. But the very concept of "criterion of truth" is riddled with confusion. To say that the confirmatory cognition is self-justifying is to be inconsistent, for the very demand for the confirmatory cognition shows that the claim of cognition to truth is dubitable. Now, if by calling all cogni- tions true by their own right, and if by introducing a criterion of error, we can explain error and dispel doubt, why not do it?

It is to be noted that although the importance of error has been

Page 17: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

SVATAH PRAMANYAVADA IN ADVAITA VEDANTA 245

equally acknowledged by both Ny~ya and Advaita, their concept of truth vis-h-vis error is diametrically opposite. In Ny~ya both truth and error are equally fundamental, so that each of them can be described as the negation of the other. Here positive and negative descriptions are interchangeable; pramd has been as much described as samvddi or coherent as avisamvddi or non-incoherent. If Gafige~a has spoken of inference as grasping pramd as absence of error, there are many Naiyftyikas, starting from Gotama and Vfitsfiyana, who hold that successful activity certifies that the cognition is true of the correspond- ing object.

But such negative descriptions of pramdtva should not be welcome to the classical Vedgmtists. Much has been made of 'abddhitatva', which was admitted by the Veddntaparibhdsd as the mark of truth. But to accept absence of falsification as the negative mark of truth, or absence of dosa or defect as a factor operative in generation of truth, is to sacrifice the robust svatah prdmdn.yavdda of Advaita. All the Advaitins agree that 'bddha' or correction is the sign of error. They all agree that the absence of possibility of falsification in the past, present or future is the essence of the highest metaphysical truth. 17 But they are divided amongst themselves about the tenability of abddhitatva as a mark of truth, with reference to empirical apprehensions. ~riharsa, the Vaitandika, has criticised it; Madhusfidana in his Advaitasiddhi has tried to retain it with many modifications. Citsukha in his Tattva- pradipikd has in unambiguous language dismissed any attempt to incorporate negative factors.

Citsukha asserts that the intrinsic nature of prdmdnya means that it is produced by the factors which produce the cognition and by nothing ab extra; these extras cover as much 'gun. a's as absence of defects; to accept either/both of them is to accept too much. He goes on that it cannot be argued that as defects are conditions of errors, so by implication absence of defect is a necessary condition of truth. For the mark of causality is unconditional invariability, whereas absence of defect is directly related to error, being responsible for its frustration, and hence it is not a necessary condition of truth. So the acceptance of absence of defect as a factor is baseless, and pramd originates from the conditions of cognition. 18

In a similar way he says that corrective cognition is necessary for

Page 18: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

246 T A R A C H A T T E R J E E

the detection of error, but this must not be construed to imply that the absence of awareness of falsification leads to the apprehension of prdmdnya. The conditions responsible for the apprehension of the cognition are responsible for the apprehension of prdmdnya too. He repeats that error is known by corrective cognition or awareness of defect, yet their absence is not the cause of apprehension of truth. In fact he holds that if awareness of the absence of these two cognitions are admitted to be operative, then the svatah, theory too would be subject to the fallacy of infinite regress. 19 I think that this is the most consistent explanation of the position. In Advaita truth is fundamental, error is an accidental exception, 2° and to look at absence of falsifica- tion as a criterion of truth is to miss the real point of svatah pramanyavdda. 21

I have discussed to some extent all the questions I have raised. There remains only one charge, namely, svatah, prFtmdnyavdda glosses over the commonly accepted difference between knowledge and belief. I would like to take up the discussion in detail in some other place, but here I would like to suggest the following explanation. According to this theory all cognitions are true unless proved otherwise, and justification does not increase the truth value of the initial apprehen- sion. The above accusation would be correct, if it be an accusation at all. However, in this theory apprehensions are not 'beliefs', if belief means apprehensions which we entertain, knowing full well that they may be untrue; nor are they 'knowledge', if knowledge stands for apprehensions which absolutely disallow any future chance of revision. The former they would perhaps categorize as an instance of doubt where due to some defect, say, lack of proper awareness of all the associated facts, the proper apprehension has not taken place, but would be resolved with further progress of knowledge.

Some critics may urge that to accept svatah prdmdn.yavdda is to say that there can be no finality in our epistemic claims, for what is called ffifma today may turn out to be jfidndbhdsa tomorrow. This, however I feel speaks for svatah prdrndnyavdda, for the history of science is a history of discarded certainties, where what has been called fh(ma by thinkers of one generation has been given up by those of the next age, when they have been found to involve defects. It should be agreed by all coricerned that finality is an ever eluding aim, which recedes more and more with the advancement of knowledge.

Page 19: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

S V A T A H P R A . M A N Y A V ~ . D A IN A D V A I T A V E D A N T A 247

N O T E S

i j. N. Mohanty, GahgeAa's Theory of Truth, Visva Bharati, 1966 'Svataste pr~n~.ya- vata eva jfi~nasya grahfit' p. 99. 2 Ibid. p. 93. 3 Ibid. p. 24. 4 ~lokavdrtika, Madras, 1940, 'Tasmfid bodhfitmakatvena prfipt~ buddheh pram~.atfi Arth~myathfitva hetutthal? dosa-jfiS_nfid apodyate, I1/53, p. 57. 5 Madhusfidana Sarasvati, Advaitaratnaraks.anam, Nirnaya Sagar Press, Bombay, 1917, 'Na hi hetvfibhfiso hetur bhavati tadvad na jfihnabh~sasya jfi~aatvam', p. 33. 6 Vidyfira0.ya, Vivaranaprameyasam. graha, Vasumati, Calcutta, Vol. II, p. 226. 7 Advaita Ratna Ral~.anam p. 34. s Gahgega's Theory of Truth, p. 37. 9 Ibid., 'Maivam, idam rajatarn, ca jLqfirniti, nfinuvyavasayall., bahirvi~esyake manaso' svatantryfit', p. 154. 111 Ibid., 'Kintvi dam idantvena rajatatvena j~n~niti', p. 154. 11 Advaitaratnaraks.anam, 'Pramfitvam anirvacaniyam, lokasiddham', p. 32. 12 NyFtyadargana, Calcutta, 1936, p. 9. 13 Gatige~a's Theory of Truth, p. 217. 14 Vivaranaprameyasarn. graha, 'Tatra dvitiy~dijfifin~mi prathamajfifinapr~'n~.ya- pratibandhakasar9. ~ay~dinirfisini, na tu tatpr~'aa~.yani~cayak~ni', p. 225. 15 Advaitaratnaraks.anam, p. 34. 16 Gahgega's Theory of Truth, p. 183. 17 Madhusfidana Sarasvati, Advaita Siddhi, Mysore, 1937, 'Trik~abfidhyatvarfipat~t- vikaprhm~..yam', Vol. II, p. 184; 'Kasminnapi de~e kasminnapi kfile ken~pi purusen- fib~dhyatvarn, hi param~Fthasattvam', Vol. I, p. 397. 18 Citsukhficfirya, Tattvapradipikd, Bombay, 1915, 'Vijfi~nas~magrijanyatvesati tadati- riktahetvfijanyatva.m pramfiyfih svatastvam, n~xna . . . . Vijfifinas~magrimfitrfideva pramotpattisambhave tadatiriktasya gunasya dos~bhavasya va kfiranatva kalpana- gauravaprasafiga. . . ' p. 122 -- 125. 19 Tattvapradipikd, 'Tathfi pramajfi~ptirapi vijfi~najfifipakasfimagrita eva' . . . p. 124-- 126. 20 Advaitaratnara~anam 'Apram~tvasya tu kat kficitkatv~t ' 21 Here I draw the attention of my reader to an article 'Jfi~na and Pramh: The Logic of Knowing -- A Critical Appraisal' by Purusottama Bilimoria which appeared in Vol. 13, No. 1, March, 1985 of Journal of Indian Philosophy.

My position is definitely opposed to the compromise suggested by the author towards the end of that paper. He tries to bring two approaches to truth (Ny~ya and Advaita) a little closer'. There he says that both the schools can be interpreted as saying that 'a true cognition is a cognition that is not falsified or shown to be false', My stand is that this is permissible in Nyaya but not in Advaita. In fact I have argued that the gap between the two is unbridgeable, for the views on prdmrnya are neces- sarily linked to the respective analysis of the structure of cognition.

I have already discussed that the very concept of criterion of truth is repugnant to the Advaitin. So I do not agree with the author when he suggests that absence of falsification, etc. are accepted as a corroborative test of what already appears to be true, or when he asserts that 'In principle however Advaita does not find any difficulty in agreeing with Ny~ya on the viability of any, may be all, of the criteria proposed' (p. 94). I would rather agree with the comment of the same author that 'Advaita does not

Page 20: An attempt to understand Svatah pramanyavada in Advaita Vedanta - Tara Chatterjee

248 T A R A C H A T T E R J E E

belive in the efficacy of the empirical modes of establishing truth in contradistinction to falsity' (p. 95) or when he suggests that the criterial marks are used to ascertain the absence of falsity and not to ascertain truth as in the case of Ny~ya.

Lady Brabourne College Calcutta