applicability of narrative ethics

Upload: jy7878

Post on 14-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    1/9

    This article was downloaded by: [Yonsei University]On: 14 October 2013, At: 03:54Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Journal of Applied Communication

    ResearchPublication details, including instructions for authors and

    subscription information:

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjac20

    The Applicability of Narrative EthicsTeresa L. Thompson

    Published online: 08 May 2009.

    To cite this article: Teresa L. Thompson (2009) The Applicability of Narrative Ethics, Journal of

    Applied Communication Research, 37:2, 188-195, DOI: 10.1080/00909880902792305

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00909880902792305

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the

    Content) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as tothe accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views ofor endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Contentshould not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoeveror howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms &Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00909880902792305http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/00909880902792305http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjac20http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjac20http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00909880902792305http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/00909880902792305http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjac20
  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    2/9

    The Applicability of Narrative EthicsTeresa L. Thompson

    Keywords: Narrative Medicine; Ethics; DoctorPatient Interaction; Health

    Communication

    I was not fortunate enough to be able to be at the program at the NationalCommunication Association (NCA) at which the papers included within this issue

    were presented. I had planned to be there*I was to chair the panel*but a medical

    narrative led to replotting. My sister-in-law was suddenly diagnosed with rather

    advanced cancer in several parts of the body, and I was needed to care for her at the

    time. The moral, ethical decision was a straightforward one, and I was happy to be

    able to be with her.

    As I read the e-mail correspondence that was shared amongst members of that

    panel following the conference, it became obvious that I had missed a very special

    panel. I attended my first professional conference 35 years ago, and never have

    I experienced the sharing of emotions and passion*the depth and sincerity of

    response*about a scholarly panel that I did when reading the responses to the panel

    discussing and honoring Dr. Charons work. The reactions were similar to those I had

    experienced as I read her books Stories Matter (Charon & Montello, 2002b) and

    Narrative Medicine(Charon, 2006). Dr. Charons perspective describes medicine as it

    should be practiced. It describes ethics as they should be enacted. It describes the

    power of narratives in the health communication process. The same can be said of

    Dr. Zaners compelling narrative in this issue (2009), and of the work of Dr. Anderson

    described in Harters essay in this issue (2009).

    Ive been studying and writing about health communication for at least 26 years*longer if one includes my early work on disability. Most scholars in this area of study

    showed no recognition of the role of narrative in the health communication process

    when I began to survey the literature, with Barbara Sharf and David Smith being

    notable exceptions. Over the years, however, the examination of narrative has become

    an important one within this area of study, as it has in the field of communication as

    Teresa L. Thompson is a Professor in the Department of Communication at the University of Dayton.

    Correspondence to: Teresa L. Thompson, Department of Communication, University of Dayton, Dayton, OH

    45469-1410, USA. E-mail: [email protected]

    Editors Note: This manuscript is one of many in a special issue of the Journal of Applied Communication

    Researchon Health as Narrative, volume 37, issue 2.

    ISSN 0090-9882 (print)/ISSN 1479-5752 (online) # 2009 National Communication Association

    DOI: 10.1080/00909880902792305

    Journal of Applied Communication Research

    Vol. 37, No. 2, May 2009, pp. 188195

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    3/9

    a whole (Arnett, 1987). Arnetts review of the writing on communication ethics prior

    to 1986 already showed narrative ethics as a salient paradigm. Medicine came to the

    narrative table somewhat later (Charon & Montello, 2002a). Much of the most

    interesting work that has been done in the health communication area in the 20'

    years that Ive been editing the journal Health Communication is narratively based.Nonetheless, very little of it has explicitly dealt with ethical concerns. Ethical and

    moral concerns are implicit in much of that work, including my own writing about

    narratives, but have not been developed in the ways that are apparent in Dr. Charons

    work. The strength of Dr. Charons work is this melding of an astute understanding of

    ethical considerations, the intelligence and compassion of a fine healthcare provider, a

    sophisticated understanding of narrative, and an overriding focus on human

    relationships as created through communication. Her work thrills and inspires.

    Indeed, it extends far beyond conceptualizations of narrative medicine and ethics and

    substantially furthers our understanding of bioethics and ethics in health commu-nication in general. The implications for all ethical considerations are also obvious.

    As I approached the composition of this essay, I originally envisioned writing a

    health narrative or writing about the emerging directions evident in the health

    communication research that focuses on narrative. Instead, I found myselfstuck on

    an issue, and before long saw that I was writing about it. In the process of this,

    however, I have found that I will tell a story.

    My story comes about in reaction to the wonder that I find in the work on

    narrative medicine and narrative ethics. That wonder, however, leaves me with one

    hesitation. What about all of the healthcare providers who do not have the empathic

    abilities and interpersonal sensitivity to perceive what is not stated, to put their workand words into the context of a familys life, and to live up to the moral duties

    enshrined in ethical principles with sensitivity and compassion (Robinson, 2002,

    p. 103)? All of the writing that we do on narrative and narrative ethics seems to

    ignore them. What about the care providers who lack those basic cognitive/emotional

    capacities? These are not skills that everyone has. This skill set is a precious and rare

    one. Certainly, all of us would wish for a care provider like Dr. Charon*a care

    provider with the cognitive capacity to perceive what is not stated. And certainly all

    care providers could become better care givers by learning to take a narrative stance.

    But how over-idealistic is the presentation by many of us who write about narrativesand narrative ethics, as we describe what a care provider should do? Im not raising

    questions of taking the time to do this*thats not an argument that Ill buy. Im

    raising the questions of capacities and competence.

    Let me now share a story with you. Our protagonists name is Bob. Ive known him

    since he was an undergraduate. Hes great at math and science. He had great grades

    and test scores. He sailed into and through medical school. He struggled with his

    internship and residency, but hes now a practicing physician. But, bright as he is in

    many ways, his cognitive and emotional capacities in other ways are limited. His

    ability to take the perspective of the other is particularly limited. I ve often accused

    him of being stubborn, and of just refusing to take the perspective of the other. ButI think that Ive been wrong about that. He tells me you give me more credit than

    Narrative Ethics 189

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    4/9

    I deserve. I just cant think about things like that. Ive known him long enough

    that I think such a capacity would indeed have shown its face now and then if it were

    there. I think, as Ive seen him mature as a person and grow intellectually, that the

    capacities to perceive what is not stated would have in some way become evident to

    me if they were there. And Ive yet to see them. Ive known him for years, and in a

    variety of different contexts. Ive tried to reach him through example, conversations,

    nagging, and giving him readings. Ive told stories to him. Ive created stories with

    him. Medical curricula also attempt to reach people such as Bob, sometimes more

    successfully and sometimes less successfully. Dr. Charon could probably reach him,

    but how many Dr. Charons are there?

    What can we as writers about narrative and narrative ethics offer for someone like

    Bob? How can he use this sophisticated, compassionate perspective to become a

    better doctor? Do we just give up on him? Im aware that the same kinds of questions

    could be raised about much of the writing on bioethics and the practice ofmedicine*some people are going to be better and more astute than others. But Ive

    never felt that lack of applicability of a perspective as deeply as I do when I read about

    the power and passion of narrative medicine and contrast that with this technically

    good but empathically limited physician. I struggle with the notion of how to use a

    narrative approach and narrative ethics to help Bob become a better doctor and a

    better person. I dont think that weve addressed that issue. Narrative competence is

    something at which not everyone excels. Spiro (1993), for instance, discusses

    physicians who are alexithymic*not in touch with their own emotions, let alone

    those of their patients.There is considerable evidence that empathy, which is required for the utilization

    of a narrative perspective and understanding narrative ethics (Chambers &

    Montgomery, 2002; Jones, 2002), is an individual difference, trait-like variable

    (Mehrabian, Young, & Sato, 1988; Wiesenfeld, Whitman, & Malatesta, 1984),

    although it is also state-related and developmental (Haviland-Jones, Gebelt, &

    Stapley, 1997). There is a genetic component to empathy (Rushton, Fulker, Neale,

    Nias, & Eysenck, 1986) but it is also strongly influenced by both previous experiences

    (Jones, 2002) and temperament (Mehrabian et al., 1988). It is related to moral

    reasoning (Eisenberg, 1977; Eisenberg-Berg & Mussen, 1978; Kalliopuska, 1983);more empathic individuals make higher level moral decisions. Importantly, Salovey

    and Mayers (1990) review of relevant research noted that, there has been a century-

    long tradition among clinicians recognizing that people differ in the capacity to

    understand and express emotions (p. 191). They then go on to describe it as a

    dispositional variable (p. 195). Dr. Charon (2006, p. 133) cites the definition

    provided by Roy Schafer of empathy: Generative empathy may be defined as the

    inner experience of sharing in and comprehending the momentary psychological

    state of another person.

    One of the more thorough theories of empathy, Zillmans (2006) three-factor

    theory, is based on the data indicating that:

    190 T. L. Thompson

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    5/9

    emphatic ability tends to be treated as an enduring disposition or trait. People are

    presumed to have it to varying degrees; that is, to have this trait in moderation or

    abundance or to be deficient in it. No doubt empathic ability differs greatly among

    people and should be treated as an individual-difference variable of consequence.

    (p. 151)

    Zillman directly relates empathy to narrative. He argues that storytelling of any kind

    is a principal forum of empathic reactivity (p. 152). However, his review of the

    empathy research makes clear that, in addition to being an individual-difference

    variable, how a responder looks at the person with whom he or she is attempting to

    empathize will color empathic responses or their lack. He notes that all impetus for

    attending revelations of the characters fate would be lost if we were not lovingly

    disposed to care for them, or, for that matter, if we were not disposed by disdain to

    wish harm upon them. The empathy concept can thus be considered pivotal to any

    interest in and, likely, any gratification from, storytelling via the media ofcommunication (p. 152).

    Participants demonstrated empathy . . . only under conditions of positive affective

    dispositions . . .. Under conditions of negative affective dispositions, empathy was not

    only absent, but discordant affect was observed (Zillman, 2006, p. 169). Further,

    Zillman argues that three factors must interact to lead to the development of

    empathy: dispositional, excitatory, and experiential factors. He adds that excitatory

    preparation is largely independent of cognitive mediation and, in fact, eludes

    volitional cognitive intervention to a high degree (p. 163) and that unqualified

    liking constitutes the optimal condition for the development of empathic reactivity;

    unqualified disliking for the development of callousness necessary for counter-

    empathic responses (p. 176). Similarly, Charon (2006) discusses one of her students,

    who explicitly describes his intense anger at and inability to empathize with a patient:

    For me to imagine myself in his shoes, I basically have to imagine myself to be

    someone I hate (p. 165), although he then goes on to describe the subsequent pity he

    learned to feel for the patient.

    With (a) empathy necessary for the practice of narrative medicine and narrative

    ethics, (b) empathic ability varying amongst individuals, and (c) empathic responses

    varying based on degree of liking for the other interactant, it seems that narrative

    ethics and narrative medicine might be limited in their usefulness for some medical

    care providers. What does the narrative perspective offer to us for someone who is

    incredibly low in empathic ability? Do we tell him to give up his hope of being a good

    doctor? The inspiration I feel when I read and think about narrative medicine is

    shadowed by the despair I experience when I think about care providers such as Bob

    and their lack of empathy, which will impact their abilities to understand narratives

    and narrative ethics. And if Bob cant reach the empathic level necessary for an

    understanding of others narratives, what hope has he (or we for him) of going

    beyond that to the disidentification advocated by Langellier in this issue (2009)? Its

    one thing to talk about all the problems in medicine and providerpatientinteractions on a global level. Its something else to look at a particular doctor and

    Narrative Ethics 191

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    6/9

    the struggle he experiences to try to achieve the kind of IThou relationship (Buber,

    1958) made possible by a narrative approach to medicine.

    Some of the writing on narrative does indeed address the difficulty of the concept

    and the sophistication involved in using it (Childress, 2002; Jones, 2002), including

    Langelliers essay (this issue 2009). It is also obvious that Dr. Charon is well aware ofthis difficulty and requisite sophistication. She writes, sophisticated knowledge of

    how stories work is not attained without considerable effort and commitment

    (2006, p. ix) and, in describing a particular cardiologist, that This doctor is not

    equipped with the imagination, the ability to see from anothers point of view, the

    knowledge of human fears and hopes, and the ear for language and silence necessary

    to grasp fully the predicament of his patient and his patients wife (p. 20). Langellier,

    for instance, identifies the multitudinous factors involved in narrative competence;

    she discusses unresolvable tensions (p. 153). Childress, writing in Stories Matter

    (Charon & Montello, 2002b), uses such terms as highly skilled (2002, p. 119) andnotes that seldom, if at all, are students and residents taught the sorts of interpretive

    precepts and skills of close reading that will help them to make the most of the

    narratives that they hear and, in turn, construct (p. 120). She closes with the caution,

    if thinking with stories is to contribute substantively to ethical ways of doctoring,

    physicians need considerable self-awareness as tellers and hearers of stories. They also

    need good interpretive skills with which to understand the myriad stories that fill

    their practice life (p. 125).

    Similarly, Jones (2002) provides a long list of the skills that are sequentially

    necessary for the development of narrative competence; she describes a narrativelycomplex skill (p. 161). In addition to the areas of expertise that she itemizes, she

    points out that narrative medicine requires an existential witnessing of patients

    suffering that goes beyond the often-task oriented medical encounter (p. 161).

    Although she discusses the value of learning to read literature, she reminds us that

    narrative competence can be achieved only if students develop the interpretive skills

    that are also required in narrative ethics (p. 162).

    But, indeed, isnt that what ethics is all about*the ought in the world, rather

    than the is? Bob is a doctor. Bob ought to be better at reading and participating

    in narratives. But hes not. Bob can, however, relate to principalist ethics. Theyre

    deductive. Bob can learn the principles and learn to apply them to particular cases.

    He wont be as good a doctor as he could be if he could look at ethics and medicine

    from a narrative perspective, but hell be better than he would be if he ignored ethics

    completely. Thus, we see the need for the argument offered by Morris (2002) that we

    must incorporate both principalist and narrative ethics into our medical curriculum.

    Let me also make clear at this juncture that the conceptualization of empathy offered

    by and implicit in Dr. Charons work is highly dialogic and dyadically constructed. It

    is not a simplistic trait, which is the conceptualization that is inherent in some of the

    psychological writing on empathy.

    All of that said, however, there is no doubt about the value of narrative ethics andthe practice of narrative medicine for those who have the requisite abilities to practice

    192 T. L. Thompson

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    7/9

    it, or for those who are able to develop those skill sets. Donald Spence (1982) put it

    appropriately when he noted:

    Freud made us aware of the persuasive power of a coherent narrative*inparticular, of the ways in which an aptly chosen reconstruction can fill the gap

    between two apparently unrelated events, and in the process, make sense out ofnon-sense. There seems no doubt but that a well-constructed story possesses a kindof narrative truth that is real and immediate and carries an important significancefor the process of therapeutic change. (p. 21)

    Closing Thoughts

    One of the many things that delights and inspires me as I read and think about

    narrative medicine and ethics is how this view of medicine gives the lie to an

    argument that I never bought anyway*that care providers have to maintain

    emotional distance in order to be good providers and to maintain their sanity.

    I raised the question of the validity of that argument at a health communication

    panel at the annual conference of the International Communication Association way

    back in 1985 and was completely disregarded by the remainder of the panelists and

    audience. Ive never been presented with data in support of that assertion. One of the

    many strengths of the narrative ethics view is that it shows us that emotional

    distancing is not necessary for either effective healthcare provision or for the

    emotional stability of the care provider. This perspective enables us to see that

    creating shared narratives and the closeness that this brings lead to better care

    provision than the oft-prescribed distancing. This argument is echoed by scholarssuch as Howard Spiro (1993), who has discussed at length the responses he has

    received to his writing on empathy from doctors who are tired of detachment and

    equanimity (p. 2).

    This notion of distancing relates to issues of power. One of the many values of

    narrative ethics and narrative medicine is some minimization of the power

    differences that have seemed so inherent to the practice of medicine (Charon,

    2006). Rubin (2002) writes, One of the outgrowths of the narrative approach is that

    it entails the sharing of power: the power of telling the story, commenting on it,

    revising it, and concluding with it. Closure comes out of the collective hearing andtelling and responding to one another (p. 112).

    As we think about narrative ethics and their relation to power, then, it also seems

    appropriate to incorporate considerations from feminist ethics and virtue ethics. In

    particular, for instance, Im thinking about the revised feminist ethic of care as

    grounded in standpoint theories (OBrien Hallstein, 1999) and virtue ethics as they

    go well beyond Aristotles original conceptualizations and build on the writing of

    such scholars as MacIntyre (1984), who is cited briefly by Charon (2006). Both

    narrative ethics and the ethic of care are founded on similar assumptions. They focus

    on the role of relationships and caring. Their complementarity is apparent. Virtue

    ethics provides a corresponding perspective that is especially relevant in the medicalcontext, in which decisions must sometimes be made incredibly quickly with little

    Narrative Ethics 193

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    8/9

    time for ethical consideration. A care provider who has developed the habits of virtue

    advocated by much of this writing does not have to ponder decisions in such

    emergencies. These three perspectives*narrative ethics, a feminist ethics of care, and

    virtue ethics*meld together nicely within the medical setting (Thompson &

    Guttman, in press).I close with a quote from Polkinghorne (1988, p. 14), borrowed from an

    unpublished manuscript by Roland Barthes in 1966. Barthes argues that the history

    of narrative begins with the history of mankind [sic]; there does not exist, and never

    has existed, a people without narratives. Powerful, indeed. I thank Dr. Charon for

    her work; she teaches us much about narratives beyond their application in medicine.

    References

    Arnett, R. (1987). The status of communication ethics scholarship in speech communicationjournals from 1915 to 1985. Central States Speech Journal, 38, 4461.

    Buber, M. (1958). I and thou (2nd ed). New York: Charles Scribners Sons.

    Chambers, T., & Montgomery, K. (2002). Plot: Framing contingency and choice in bioethics. In

    R. Charon & M. Montello (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics (pp.

    7784). New York: Routledge.

    Charon, R. (2006). Narrative medicine: Honoring the stories of illness. New York and Oxford: Oxford

    University Press.

    Charon, R., & Montello, M. (2002a). Memory and anticipation: The practice of narrative ethics. In

    R. Charon & M. Montello (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics (pp.

    ixxii). New York: Routledge.

    Charon, R., & Montello, M. (2002b). Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics. NewYork: Routledge.

    Childress, M. D. (2002). Of symbols and silence: Using narrative and its interpretation to foster

    physician understanding. In R. Charon & M. Montello (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of

    narratives in medical ethics (pp. 119125). New York: Routledge.

    Eisenberg, N. (1977). The development of prosocial moral judgement and its correlates. Dissertation

    Abstracts International, 37, 4735B.

    Eisenberg-Berg, N., & Mussen, P. (1978). Empathy and moral development in adolescence.

    Developmental Psychology, 14, 185186.

    Harter, L. M. (2009). Narratives as dialogic, contested, and aesthetic performances. Journal of

    Applied Communication Research, 37, 140150.

    Haviland-Jones, J., Gebelt, J. L., & Stapley, J. C. (1997). The questions of development in emotion.In P. Salovey & D. J. Sluyter (Eds.), Emotional development and emotional intelligence (pp.

    233253). New York: Basic Books.

    Jones, A. H. (2002). The color of the wallpaper: Training for narrative ethics. In R. Charon &

    M. Montello (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics (pp. 160170).

    New York: Routledge.

    Kalliopuska, M. (1983). Relationship between moral judgement and empathy. Psychological Reports,

    53, 575578.

    Langellier, K. M. (2009). Performing narrative medicine. Journal of Applied Communication

    Research, 37, 151158.

    MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame

    University Press.

    Mehrabian, A., Young, A. L., & Sato, S. (1988). Emotional empathy and associated individual

    differences. Current Psychology, 7, 221240.

    194 T. L. Thompson

  • 7/27/2019 Applicability of Narrative Ethics

    9/9

    Morris, D. B. (2002). Narrative, ethics, and pain: Thinking with stories. In: R. Charon &

    M. Montello (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics (pp. 196218).

    New York: Routledge.

    OBrien Hallstein, D. L. (1999). A postmodern caring: Feminist standpoint theories, revisioned

    caring, and communication ethics. Western Journal of Communication, 63, 3256.

    Polkinghorne, D. E. (1988). Narrative knowing and the human sciences. Albany, NY: State Universityof New York Press.

    Robinson, W. M. (2002). The narrative of rescue in pediatric practice. In R. Charon & M. Montello

    (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics (pp. 97108). New York:

    Routledge.

    Rubin, S. B. (2002). Beyond the authoritative voice: Casting a wide net in ethics consultation. In

    R. Charon & M. Montello (Eds.), Stories matter: The role of narratives in medical ethics

    (pp. 109118). New York: Routledge.

    Rushton, J. P., Fulker, D. W., Neale, M. C., Nias, D. K. B., & Eysenck, H. J. (1986). Altruism and

    aggression: The heritability of individual differences. Journal of Personality and Social

    Psychology, 50, 11921198.

    Salovey, P., & Mayer, J. D. (1990). Emotional intelligence. Imagination. Cognition and Personality,9, 186211.

    Spence, D. (1982). Narrative truth and historical truth: Meaning and interpretation in psychoanalysis.

    New York: W. W. Norton.

    Spiro, H. M. (1993). Empathy and the practice of medicine. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Thompson, T. L., & Guttman, N. (in press). Ethics in health communication. In S. May, G. Cheney,

    & D. Munshi (Eds.), Handbook of communication ethics. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum

    Associates, Inc.

    Wiesenfeld, A. R., Whitman, P. B., & Malatesta, C. Z. (1984). Individual differences among adult

    women in sensitivity to infants: Evidence in support of an empathy concept. Journal of

    Personality and Social Psychology, 46, 118124.

    Zaner, R. M. (2009). Narrative and decision. Journal of Applied Communication Research, 37,174187.

    Zillman, D. (2006). Empathy: Affective reactivity to others emotional experiences. In J. Bryant &

    P. Vorderer (Eds.), Psychology of entertainment (pp. 151182). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence

    Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

    Narrative Ethics 195