aristotle on moral responsibilitysmeyer/documents/amrnewintroproofs.pdf · oup uncorrected proof...

26
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi Aristotle on Moral Responsibility Meyer_FM.indd i Meyer_FM.indd i 10/20/2011 7:05:21 PM 10/20/2011 7:05:21 PM

Upload: others

Post on 02-Jan-2020

5 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Aristotle on Moral Responsibility

Meyer_FM.indd iMeyer_FM.indd i 10/20/2011 7:05:21 PM10/20/2011 7:05:21 PM

Page 2: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Meyer_FM.indd iiMeyer_FM.indd ii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 3: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Aristotle on Moral Responsibility

Character and Cause

Susan Sauvé Meyer

1

Meyer_FM.indd iiiMeyer_FM.indd iii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 4: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

3Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,

and education by publishing worldwide inOxford New York

Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi

New Delhi Shanghai Taipei TorontoWith offi ces in

Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam

Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries

Published in the United Statesby Oxford University Press Inc., New York

© Susan Sauvé Meyer 1993 and 2011

The moral rights of the author have been assertedDatabase right Oxford University Press (maker)

First edition published by Blackwell Publishers 1993This edition fi rst published 2011

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,

without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate

reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,

Oxford University Press, at the address above

You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer

British Library Cataloguing in Publication DataData available

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication DataData available

Typeset by Pure Tech Corporation, Pondicherry, IndiaPrinted in Great Britain

on acid-free paper byMPG Books

ISBN 978–0–19–969742–7 (Hbk.) 978–0–19–969743–4 (Pbk.)

1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2

Meyer_FM.indd ivMeyer_FM.indd iv 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 5: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

To Milton

Meyer_FM.indd vMeyer_FM.indd v 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 6: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Meyer_FM.indd viMeyer_FM.indd vi 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 7: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Contents

Acknowledgments x

Abbreviations of Aristotle’s Works xi

Tables xii

Introduction to the 2011 Edition: Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xiii

Introduction Moral Responsibility and Aristotle’s Concerns 1

1 Moral Responsibility and Aristotle’s Concerns 1 2 Aristotle’s Conception of Moral Responsibility 3 3 Outline by Chapters 5 4 Assumptions about Aristotle’s Texts 8 5 Ordinary Notions of Hekousion and Akousion 9

1 Moral Responsibility and Moral Character 17

1 Moral Responsibility and Moral Agency 17 2 Virtue and Vice of Character 19 3 Rationality and Morality 24 4 The Scope of Moral Agency 28 5 Conclusions about Moral Agency and Moral Character 30

2 Voluntariness, Praiseworthiness, and Character 36

1 Voluntariness and Causal Responsibility 36 2 The Signifi cance of Voluntariness 39

Meyer_FM.indd viiMeyer_FM.indd vii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 8: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

viii Contents

3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of Praiseworthiness 44 4 The Causal Presuppositions of Praise and Blame 46 5 The Focal Nature of Praiseworthiness 48 6 Voluntariness and Moral Responsibility 50

3 The Dialectical Inquiry into Voluntariness 59

1 Dialectic and the Inquiry into Voluntariness 60 2 The Aporetic Discussion of Desire (EE 1223a29–b38) 63 3 The Dialectical Premises 66 4 Solving the Puzzles: The Discussion of Decision

(EE 1223b38–1224a4) 71 5 Force and Involuntariness in EE ii 8 76 6 The Dialectical and Deductive Defi nitions 78 7 The Nicomachean Discussion of Voluntariness Reconsidered 82 8 Goals and Achievements of the Dialectical Inquiry 84

4 Force, Compulsion, and the Internal Origin of Action 93

1 Force and Compulsion in the MM, EE, and EN 94 2 Criteria for Compulsion: Psychological and Rational 98 3 Voluntariness and the Non-accidental Origin of Action 100 4 Accidental and Non-accidental Production 103 5 Compelled Actions as Accidentally Caused 106 6 Problems with the Eudemian Conditions 110 7 Non-accidental Production and the Nicomachean View 112 8 Mixed Actions and Accidental Production 116

5 Responsibility for Character: Its Scope and Signifi cance 122

1 On the Importance of Being Raised in Good Habits 123 2 Full vs. Qualifi ed Responsibility for Character 126 3 The Asymmetry Thesis Introduced (EN 1113b3–21) 129 4 Considerations Against the Asymmetry Thesis

(EN 1113b21–1114a31) 133 5 An Argument for the Asymmetry Thesis Considered

(EN 1114a31–b25) 141 6 Moral Responsibility without Responsibility for Character? 145

6 Moral Agency and the Origination of Action 149

1 Origins, External Causes, and Self-Motion 149 2 The Unmoved Mover in the Moral Agent 153

Meyer_FM.indd viiiMeyer_FM.indd viii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 9: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Contents ix

3 Worries about Determinism 156 4 Accidental vs. Non-accidental Antecedent Causes 158 5 Distinctive Features of Moral Responsibility 161

Appendix I: Varieties of Knowledge and Ignorance 170

1 Universal and Particular Knowledge 171 2 ‘In Ignorance’ vs. ‘Because of Ignorance’ 176 3 Culpable Ignorance 180

Appendix II: “Up to Us” and the Internal Origin 185

Bibliography 190

General Index 197

Index Locorum 202

Meyer_FM.indd ixMeyer_FM.indd ix 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 10: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Acknowledgments

While preparing this manuscript, I have benefi tted from the comments and criticism of many colleagues and students. Special thanks are due to John Carriero, Paula Gottlieb, Terry Irwin, Milton Wachsberg Meyer, Elijah Mill-gram, Tim Scanlon, and Gisela Striker. Seth Fagen and Mitzi Lee provided valuable bibliographical assistance, Mitzi Lee and Mary Sullivan saved me from many errors, and Mary Sullivan helped to prepare the indices. Drafts of various chapters have benefi tted from discussion at colloquia at Queen’s Uni-versity, the University of California at Berkeley, the University of California at Los Angeles, and the University of Wisconsin at Madison. For the leisure to prepare the fi rst draft of the manuscript I am grateful to the President and Fellows of Harvard College who granted me a Presidential leave during the academic year 1989–90, and to the National Endowment for the Humanities who awarded me a Fellowship for University Teachers in 1990.

Susan Sauvé MeyerCambridge, Massachusetts

Meyer_FM.indd xMeyer_FM.indd x 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 11: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

APst. Posterior AnalyticsCatg. CategoriesDA De AnimaDe Int. De InterpretationeEE Eudemian EthicsEN Nicomachean EthicsGA De Generatione AnimaliumMA De Motu AnimaliumMet. MetaphysicsMM Magna MoraliaPh. PhysicsPoet. PoeticsPol. PoliticsRhet. RhetoricTop. Topics

Abbreviations of Aristotle’s Works

Meyer_FM.indd xiMeyer_FM.indd xi 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 12: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Tables

4.1 Two scenarios for “A produces B accidentally” 1056.1 Aspects of effi cient causation 1546.2 Examples of accidental production 159

Meyer_FM.indd xiiMeyer_FM.indd xii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 13: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

This is a book about Aristotle’s views on voluntariness (to hekousion) and involuntariness (to akousion), a topic to which he devotes lengthy and interest-ingly different treatments in the Eudemian and the Nicomachean Ethics. The issues raised by these discussions have proved to be of enduring interest in the interval since the original publication of this volume, and my aim in the pres-ent introduction is to locate its main lines of argument in the context of this more recent scholarship.1

While it may not appear obvious to modern readers why a treatise on ethics should be concerned with the difference between voluntary and involuntary action, Aristotle is not the fi rst to invoke the notion in an ethical context. A familiar refrain in Plato’s dialogues is that no one does wrong voluntarily.2 In these contexts, Plato presents wrongdoing as deriving from ignorance of the good and he exploits the ordinary assumption that actions performed in ignorance are involuntary.3 His goal is not, of course, to absolve wrongdoers of responsibility or blame. Rather, his point is to exhort his audience to

Introduction to the 2011 EditionVoluntariness, Morality, and Causality

1 I will also refer to a few works published earlier: Broadie 1991, whose chapter on the volun-tary continues to be widely cited; Donini’s magisterial monograph, Ethos: Aristoteles e il determin-ismo (1989), now translated beautifully into English as Donini 2010; and Heinaman 1986, which was omitted from my original bibliography. Destrée 2011 has a particularly thorough account of recent literature.

2 Prot. 345e1–4, 358c7, e5–6; Gorg. 509e5–6; Tim. 86d7–e3; Laws 731c2–3, 734b2–3, 860d5–e4. In these contexts, ‘voluntarily’ (hekôn) is often translated “willingly”. I defend the appropriateness of translating Aristotle’s pair of terms by ‘voluntary’ and ‘involuntary’ on pp. 9–16 below. See also Heinaman 1986: 128–130, Bostock 2000: 102–3, and Taylor 2006: 125–6. The new French translation by Bodeus 2004 uses ‘consenti’ (roughly, “intentional”) for hekou-sion, on which see Labarrière 2009:11.

3 Hence the equivalent statement of the thesis as “no one does wrong knowingly” (e.g. Prot. 352c4–7, 355b1–3). On the relation between the two theses, see Segvic 2009.

Meyer_FM.indd xiiiMeyer_FM.indd xiii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 14: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

xiv Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality

cultivate ethical knowledge. Aristotle, by contrast, is interested in voluntari-ness as a causal notion. He considers a human agent to be an origin (arche ) or cause (aitios) of actions and he investigates voluntariness with a view to capturing that causal relation. He introduces the topic of voluntariness by noting that it is a condition for praise and blame, and he is evidently con-cerned to establish that our good actions and our bad ones are equally volun-tary—an emphatic rejection of the Platonic account, on which only our good actions are voluntary.

Just how Aristotle construes the causality involved in voluntary action, as well as the implications he thinks it has concerning praise and blame, are mat-ters of dispute. Interpretations have run the gamut from supposing that Aris-totle is articulating a libertarian analysis of human agency as the ground for holding people responsible for their actions,4 to the proposal that Aristotle is concerned simply with the conditions in which praise and blame are effective instruments for shaping character and infl uencing future actions.5 The read-ing I offer in the chapters below strikes a middle course. Aristotle is not con-cerned to carve out for human agency an exceptional status within the causal nexus of the natural world, but neither is he concerned simply with how edu-cators and other social forces might infl uence behavior and shape character. He is genuinely interested in describing the conditions in which human agents are responsible for their actions, a form of responsibility that is, in his view, integral to the workings of character.

Voluntariness, responsibility, and morality

In the chapters below, I describe this as an account of what we might today call “moral responsibility” —“moral” to indicate its connection to the virtues of character (courage, temperance, generosity, justice) — and “responsibility” to indicate the causal relation Aristotle posits between agents and their voluntary actions. This terminology has proved to be a distraction, especially to readers who take “morality” to be a distinctively modern notion.6 While Chapter 1

4 Most recently Destrée 2011 and Natali 2004 chapters VIII and IX. Broadie 1991: 158–9 takes Aristotle’s discussion of voluntariness, at least in the EE, to articulate a “proto-indetermin-ism” about human agency, but this is, in her view, a practical perspective adopted by those engaged in action or in the evaluation of agents, rather than a metaphysical account of action. Bobzien (forthcoming) rejects this new wave of indeterminist interpretations.

5 Most recently Frede 2011: 98–99.6 Thus Tuozzo 1997 and the review by Roberts in Philosophical Review 104 (4), October

1995: 577–9; but compare Dahl’s review in Ethics 106 (2) January 1996: 455–7 and the more nuanced reservations expressed by Chappell (Mind 105 (417) 181–6. Bobzien (forthcoming) §2

Meyer_FM.indd xivMeyer_FM.indd xiv 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 15: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xv

below explains my grounds for applying the label ‘moral’ to Aristotle’s virtues and vices of character, and hence the fairly minimal implications of construing the relevant kind of responsibility as moral, the bulk of the argument in the rest of the book does not depend on this construal. Readers who are allergic to associating the term ‘moral’ with the ancient ethical tradition may safely bracket the term and replace it with ‘ethical’.

Indeed, one of my central interpretive claims about Aristotle is that a thesis often associated with distinctively “moral” responsibility is conspicuously absent from his account. This is the view that moral responsibility for one’s actions, in contrast with merely casual responsibility (which inanimate objects and non-human animals can have), requires that we be responsible for the behavioral dispositions from which we act: in other words, that moral respon-sibility for action requires responsibility for character. Aristotle is often taken to subscribe to such a thesis, on the basis of his argument the Nicomachean Ethics III 5 that we are responsible for our states of character.7 However, Aris-totle does not present this thesis as a necessary condition for responsible action. In fact, most of the texts where he is generally taken to be arguing for the thesis do not concern responsibility for character at all.8 Rather, Aristotle is there contesting the Platonic thesis that only our virtuous actions, not also our vicious ones, are voluntary. Such, at any rate, is the burden of Chapter 5.9

While the implications of these issues for general philosophical questions about responsibility, causality, and agency are large, my primary focus below is on elucidating key texts in Aristotle’s ethical writings. My aim is to lay bare their structure and argumentation, with a view especially to identifying the problems that Aristotle takes himself to be addressing when he discusses vol-untariness. I begin (Chapter 2) by investigating the connection that Aristotle

defends the thesis that moral responsibility is at stake in Aristotle’s discussion of voluntariness, while Donini argues emphatically against the view that a distinctively modern kind of responsi-bility is at stake there (Donini 2010: 138–9, esp. n 6). By contrast, interpreters as diverse as Heinaman and Natali are quite happy to use expressions such as ‘moral responsibility’ or ‘moral evaluation’ à propos Arisottle’s account of the voluntary (Heinaman 1986: 128, 130; Natali 2004: 206 and 2002: 290, although the relevant passages of the latter are omitted from the 2004 ver-sion]. Annas 1993 is an extended argument for reading ancient ethical philosophy as moral philosophy, although she does not discuss voluntariness or responsibility except obliquely (p. 49), when discussing EN 1106a2–4. Meyer 2008 is my own account of the distinctive fea-tures of ancient ethical philosophy.

7 Thus, for example Broadie 1991: 160, Pakaluk 2005: 144–6 and Destrée 2010: 287. See also Zingano 2007, chapter 10.

8 The careful assessment of Aristotle’s argument in Donini 2010: 140–148 concurs with my contention that only responsibility for action is at stake in EN 1113b6–21. Ott 2000 resists this interpretation, adducing considerations from Plato’s later dialogues.

9 I offer an abbreviated version of these arguments in Meyer 2006.

Meyer_FM.indd xvMeyer_FM.indd xv 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 16: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

xvi Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality

posits between praiseworthiness and voluntariness, which I elucidate in light of his distinction between praise and encomium in EN I 12 and his frequent remarks about the praiseworthiness of virtue and the blameworthiness of vice. This background, together with careful attention to Aristotle’s precise state-ments of the causal conditions of praise and blame,10 shows that Aristotle takes character and actions to be praiseworthy in different, although system-atically related, ways. Actions are praiseworthy and blameworthy because we are responsible for bringing them about, whereas states of character are praise-worthy and blameworthy because of the actions that they bring about. The focal causal notion in each case is that of character issuing in action – hence my original subtitle: “Character and Cause”.11

The Eudemian and Nicomachean accounts

Chapters 3 and 4 focus on the texts in which Aristotle explores the nature of the hekousion and the akousion and develops his own positive account of the matter. These are EE II 6-9 and EN III 1.12 The former, in particular, is an exceedingly tortuous stretch of argument that has proved baffl ing many read-ers. While the latter account may appear more straightforward, it too has its puzzling elements, such as the requirement that involuntary actions be painful or regretted.13 I resist both these impressions, arguing that the Eudemian dis-cussion is a perfectly respectable piece of dialectical reasoning, that the Nico-machean account presupposes and extends it, and that seen from this vantage point, the apparent oddities of the latter are well motivated applications of central tenets of Aristotle’s analysis.

10 E.g. the conclusion of the argument at EE 1223a9–15, is usually construed as the thesis that we are responsible for our states of character. However, Aristotle is careful to conclude there that the virtue and vice “concern (peri, a14) things for which we are responsible”—not that they are themselves things for which we are responsible. Broadie, for example, omits this point in her analysis of the argument (1991: 162–3).

11 That Aristotle takes voluntary actions to be the route by which a person’s character makes its mark on the world is endorsed by Broadie 1991:124 and Pakaluk 2004: 118–119. On the relation of this to Aristotle’s remark that prohairesis (decision) displays character better than action (EN 1111b5–6) see Meyer 2006:140 and 2008: 71–2.

12 I refer to chapters as marked by the marginal Roman numerals in the editions of the EN by Burnet (1894) and of the EE by Walzer and Mingay (1991).

13 Broadie 1991: 132–142 is a forceful statement of the diffi culties provoked by this require-ment, although she fails to note (p. 133) that Aristotle articulates the requirement for involun-tary actions quite generally, not just for those due to ignorance (EN 1111a32). Bostock 2000: 111–112 fi nds similar diffi culties.

Meyer_FM.indd xviMeyer_FM.indd xvi 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 17: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xvii

Chapter 3 explains how the argument in EE II 6-9 makes sense if we read it as a dialectical exploration of potential criteria for voluntariness whose aim is to secure the (anti-Platonic) result that cases of wrongdoing are voluntary. Aristotle starts out with the hypothesis that the difference between voluntary and involuntary action may be modeled by the distinction between natural and “forced” (biaion) movements, where forced movements are conceived of as contrary to internal impulse. He considers how to apply this paradigm to the case of human action, compares its implications to those of the Platonic conception of voluntariness, and rejects any version on which obvious cases of wrongdoing (e.g. akratic action) turn out to be forced. The conception of force that emerges from this dialectic has been revised and expanded to apply to the case of distinctively human action (where confl icting internal impulses are possible):14 in addition to being contrary to impulse, forced action must not originate in the agent.

This is the requirement for force that Aristotle stresses at the beginning of the Nicomachean account, where he introduces forced action as one of the two kinds of involuntary action. The other type, comprising acts due to ignorance, is also mentioned in the Eudemian account, but only briefl y and at the end, where it is hastily and (I argue) ineptly integrated into the results of the more elaborate discussion of force. Rectifying this fault in the Eudemian account is one of Aristotle’s achievements in the Nicomachean version.15 There he also devotes considerable attention to identifying precisely the sort of knowledge that is required for voluntariness—once again with a view to resisting the Pla-tonic contention that actions performed in ignorance of the good are involun-tary. His additional goal, I argue, is to complete the project, begun in the EE, of integrating the two paradigms for involuntariness (forced actions and those due to ignorance) into a single coherent account.16 His error in the EE is to construe “action due to ignorance” as exemplifying the contrariety essential to forced actions. In the EN, by contrast, he recognizes that the requisite contra-riety is independent of the epistemic requirement, but still views contrariety to impulse as central to involuntariness—hence his insistence that actions due to ignorance must be painful or regretted if they are to count as involuntary.17

14 Natali construes the potential for internal confl ict as the source of the contingency of human action (Natali 2004: 211–12).

15 Heinaman 1986 provides additional reasons for supposing the EN account is an improve-ment over that of the EE.

16 By contrast, other readers, such as Broadie 1991 and Bostock 2000, fi nd Aristotle vacillat-ing between the confl icting paradigms.

17 In Broadie and Rowe 2002 the translation of akousion as “counter- voluntary” rather than “involuntary” nicely captures this essential contrariety; but it gives the misleading impression

Meyer_FM.indd xviiMeyer_FM.indd xvii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 18: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

xviii Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality

The Nicomachean account of voluntariness, so understood, builds on and com-pletes the dialectical argument of the Eudemian discussion.

A particularly diffi cult class of actions to which Aristotle devotes attention in his discussions of voluntariness are cases of what we might call coercion or duress—for example, throwing the ship’s cargo overboard in a storm to save the ship and the lives of its crew. Are such actions voluntary or involuntary? In the EE, he inclines to the verdict that they are involuntary (1225a11-14), but in the EN he resolutely insists that they are voluntary (1110b1-6). Chapter 4 explores Aristotle’s apparent vacillation on this question, which arises from alternative options for making precise the notion of an action having its “ori-gin” (archē) in an agent. Aristotle resolves the issue, I argue, in the light of his over-arching goal of rejecting any account that classifi es blameworthy actions as involuntary. 18

Aristotle’s causal notions

Exploring Aristotle’s treatment of these diffi cult cases reveals the continuity between the causal notions invoked in his treatments of voluntariness and those that he deploys more broadly in his natural philosophy. Most important among these, in Chapter 4, is the distinction between accidental (kata sumbe-bekos) and non-accidental causation, which Aristotle invokes explicitly when discussing the voluntariness of actions under duress.19 To be the origin of an action, in Aristotle’s terms, is to be its non-accidental cause. Chapter 6 explores the relation of voluntariness to “self-movement”— another item in Aristotle’s causal repertoire, which is articulated at length in the Physics.20 The voluntary agent, as the “origin” of an action, is thereby in Aristotle’s view a “self-mover”. This means, among other things, that some aspect of the agent is an “unmoved mover”. This is to say that it moves the agent to act, but exercises this causality

that involuntariness on its own fails to involve such contrariety. I note below (pp. 9–16) that this is a feature both of the ordinary Greek notion of the akousion and of the English ‘involuntary’ on one of its ordinary senses.

18 Taylor 2006: 129–140 discusses the EN treatment of these cases in detail. Nielsen 2007 is the best recent discussion of Aristotle’s account, especially regarding its implications for our general understanding of his ethical theory. Klimchuk 2002 focuses on the jurisprudential impli-cations of Aristotle’s position.

19 EN V 8, 1135a15–19. Thus Natali 2002: 275 and 2004: 181 is mistaken to object that there is no textual support for applying Aristotle’s notion of accidental causation to the case of voluntary action.

20 A fl urry of relatively recent work on self-motion includes the papers in Gill and Lennox 1994, as well as Berryman 2002 and Morison 2004. Natali 2002: 271–4, 282–3 is critical of most such accounts.

Meyer_FM.indd xviiiMeyer_FM.indd xviii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 19: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xix

without itself being “moved”. It is, however, a mistake to suppose, as some readers do, that an Aristotelian self-mover is thereby exempt from the infl u-ence of external causes, or that the activity whereby it causes its own move-ment is undetermined by antecedent conditions.21 The unmoved aspect of the agent, I propose, is the state of character that issues in the action, and the sense in which it is “unmoved” in exercising its causality is quite simply that it is not “in motion”. This is a mode of causality that Aristotle fi nds quite broadly in the natural world, and is closely connected with the way in which formal causes interact with effi cient causes.22 I explain how it accords with Aristotle’s understanding of a state of character as a disposition (hexis) of our capacities for action and passion, and I explore his resources for resisting the objection that humans are not genuine self movers, on the ground that the causal history of our actions can always be traced back to external and antecedent causes. I argue that Aristotle’s distinction between accidental and non-accidental causes provides a powerful response to such worries.23

What is “up to us”

Another feature of Aristotle’s account often interpreted in libertarian terms is his frequent refrain that our voluntary actions are “up to us to do and not to do”. An action’s being up to an agent in this way, it is supposed, amounts to its

21 In a new version of such indeterminist construals of self-motion, Natali 2002: 284 rightly points out, in agreement with Meyer 1994: 68–9, that the object of desire, which Aristotle iden-tifi es as the “mover” of the self-mover’s desire, is not an effi cient cause that precipitates the self-mover’s desire. But he makes the stronger, and less plausible, further claim that the external object (e.g. the lamb perceived by the hungry lion) does not have an effi cient-causal effect on the self-mover’s desire (Natali 2002: 285–6).

22 A point I develop in greater detail in Sauvé 1987 (see original bibliography). Natali offers a similar explanation, roughly that formal causes “channel” the motive force of effi cient causes (Natali 2004: 210; cf. 189–90, 2002: 284)—an account whose plausibility is in some tension with his blanket insistence (2002: 281–4, 2004: 189–194) that causes from different Aristote-lian modalities cannot be combined in a continuous causal sequence.

23 Berryman 2002 objects that my invocation of accidental causation in this context fails to capture what is distinctive of self-movement. I am inclined to agree now that my proposal does not explain the “two- sidedness” of animal locomotion, but I still think that it shows Aristotle to be justifi ed in halting the regress of causes with the voluntary agent. The interpretation of animal self-motion in Morison 2004, which has concerns about cosmology rather than action theory as its focus, deploys Aristotle’s notion of the “accidental” in a manner different from, but compatible with the view I defend. Natali, who objects to my invocation of the accidental in this context (see note 20 above), responds to the threatened regress by arguing that it com-mits the anachronism of reducing formal and fi nal causes to effi cient causes (Natali 2002: 282–3).

Meyer_FM.indd xixMeyer_FM.indd xix 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 20: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

xx Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality

alternative being “open” or “possible” in a sense that determinism precludes.24 While I do not address this position directly in the chapters below, I would supplement my remarks on what is “up to us” in Appendix II with the follow-ing observations. While Aristotle does say at that such actions “admit of being otherwise” (EE 1222b41-1223a9), the sort of contingency invoked by the lat-ter locution has, fi rst of all, no implications regarding the truth or falsity of determinism.25 Second, Aristotle does not explain the notion of being “up to us” in terms of that contingency. Indeed, where Aristotle does elucidate the notion of something’s being “up to us”, he proceeds simply by distinguishing it from things whose occurrence or non-occurrence depends on factors other than ourselves: for example, whether the sun will rise this morning or whether my ticket will be drawn in the lottery.26 Thus he explains what is “up to us” as “what might happen through us” (EN 1112b27) and the “us”, as I argue in Appendix II, is identifi ed in terms of the psychological faculties involved in voluntary agency: roughly, thought and desire. So construed, it follows quite easily that those actions which originate in us are up to us to do and not to do. Thus Aristotle’s insistence that our voluntary actions are “up to us” in this way is not an invocation of their contingency, but of their dependence on our pow-ers of voluntary agency.

Indeterminist interpreters of “up to us” in Aristotle sometimes appeal for support to his contention that only what is up to us is a proper object of deliberation (EN 1112a31).27 Such, for example, is the position of the Aris-totelian commentator Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl . 200 CE) who proposes that the “two–sidedness” of what is “up to us” is to be understood in terms of Aristotle’s notion of a rational capacity, which is explicated in Metaphysics IX as a “capacity for opposites” (1046b1-7). Aristotle here says that a non-ratio-nal capacity, such as fi re’s capacity to burn, is one that, given the appropriate

24 Thus Broadie 1991: 150–54, 171–2, who labels Aristotle a “proto-indeterminist” (158–9); also Chappell 1995: 42–7, Destrée 2011: 289–96 and Natali 2002: 288–9. Even Donini 2010, who takes Aristotle’s fully developed view in the EN to be a form of psychological determinism, fi nds the Eudemian account to be “more decisively indeterministic” (p. 108). By contrast, Bobzien 1998: 282, 412 and 1998a argues that Aristotle’s conception of what is “up to us to do and not to do,” in contrast to that of later philosophers, is not libertarian. On the history of the notion in ancient philosophy see Frede 2011 and Destrée et al. (forthcoming).

25 A point I argue in greater detail in Meyer 1998.26 Thus Frede 2007 and 2011. See also Bobzien (forthcoming) §§ 5–6, who uses the helpful

locution “things within the agent’s reach” to capture the relevant category.27 Broadie 2001 and Zingano 2007 chapter 9 are sympathetic to such interpretations, which

are roundly criticized by Nielsen 2011.

Meyer_FM.indd xxMeyer_FM.indd xx 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 21: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xxi

conditions for its exercise, necessarily brings about its effect. By contrast, when a rational capacity (such as the medical art) is similarly situated, its exercise is not necessary (1048a5-8). For example, the physician may either treat the patient or leave him to die. Such a conception of “two-sidedness”, however, does not make Aristotle an indeterminist. Whether the physician treats the patient, he explains, depends on his desire or choice; but once this factor is taken into account his action (or inaction) is no less necessary than fi re’s burning (1048a10-15). Furthermore, this account implies nothing about whether the crucial desire or choice is determined by antecedent con-ditions; thus Alexander is wrong to invoke it as evidence that Aristotelian action is libertarian.28

Questions about determinism

In resisting these libertarian interpretations of Aristotle, my aim is not to establish that he is a determinist about action.29 Even if libertarianism and determinism are exhaustive options for the classifi cation of human action, it is misleading to classify particular philosophers as libertarian or determinist unless they explicitly face or articulate a recognizable thesis of determinism.30 To be sure, a version of determinism was hotly contested in post-Aristotelian philosophy, in the context of debates over the Stoic doctrine of fate,31 and

28 Donini 2010: 89–91 makes a careful textual case that the account of “two-sided capacities” in Metaphysics IX fails to imply that states of character are similarly “two-sided”. Bobzien 1998: 403 concurs. On the difference between virtues and “two sided capacities” see Garver 2006, chapter 2. Coope 2010: 441 raises additional objections to Alexander’s proposal that the notion of such a two-sided capacity illuminates Aristotle’s notion of what it up to us. Natali 2002: 290–93 and 2004: 194–7, 215–17 deofends a version of Alexander’s indeterminist interpreta-tion (on the basis of De Anima III 10, 433b5–10). On the relation between Aristotle’s and Alexander’s notions of what is up to us, see Labarrière 2009.

29 Thus I would dissent from the classifi cation of my interpretation as “determinist” in Des-trée 2011: 286 n4. By contrast, Donini 2010 expressly argues that Aristotle is a determinist about action.

30 I discuss the difference between affi rming a thesis of (in)determinism and being committed to it in Meyer 2003. In effect, Donini 2010 is an argument that Aristotle is committed to deter-minism about action.

31 On that debate see Bobzien 1998 and Salles 2005. While Natali proposes that the Stoic conception of a causal chain coincides largely with modern conceptions of determin-ism (Natali 2002: 283, 295; 2004: 178), I argue in Meyer 2009 that this appearance is deceiving.

Meyer_FM.indd xxiMeyer_FM.indd xxi 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 22: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

xxii Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality

Alexander’s libertarian interpretation of Aristotle is informed by those debates. But what would count as an affi rmation (or denial) of determinism in the context of Aristotle’s causal vocabulary and background assumptions is a very tricky question,32 which I won’t address here, beyond the simple observation that given the wide semantic range of ‘necessity’ in Aristotle,33 it is unsafe to read his affi rmation of the contingency our actions as eo ipso a denial of any-thing recognizable by philosophers today as a thesis of determinism.34 While it is safe to say that Aristotle insists on features of human action whose com-patibility with determinism has been hotly debated by philosophers for centu-ries, contemporary libertarian interpreters of Aristotle tend to construe these features as straightforwardly indeterminist—which is to beg the question on the issue of compatibility.35

I take the position in the chapters below that Aristotle himself shows no inclination to worry that determination by antecedent conditions is incompat-ible with voluntariness, praiseworthiness, or our actions being “up to us”. While he does assume that an action whose “origin” is “in us” cannot be attributed to origins “beyond those in us” (e.g. EN 1113b19-20), this is a concern about external causation, not causal determination,36 and the proper Aristotelian

32 On the complexities, see Broadie 1991: 130–1, who maintains that he nowhere engages with the thesis of determinism (157–9, 171), as well as Frede 2011: 15–16, 28. While Natali also stresses the differences between Aristotle’s causal notions and those invoked in familiar formulations of determinism, he does take Aristotle to have “identifi ed the main theoretic diffi culties of determinism” in De Interpretatione 9 and Metaphysics E 2 (Natali 2002: 278 n19).

33 See the range of uses of ‘necessary’ (anankaion) enumerated in Metaphysics V 5.34 A point I develop in Meyer 1998. By contrast, Destrée 2011 takes it to be suffi cient proof

of Aristotle’s commitment to indeterminism that he affi rms the contingency of particular actions. Donini 2010, although arguing that Aristotle is a determinist about action in the EN, takes the EE’s ascription of contingency to actions to be indeterminist, but also an immature view later superseded by the determinism in the Nicomachean account of the “unidirectional-ity” of developed character. Against construing Aristotelian character as fully determining how one acts in particular circumstances, see Dimuzio 2000 and 2008, as well as Destrée 2011.

35 Such is explicitly the case with Natali, for example, who writes that whether to clas-sify a philosopher as determinist depends inter alia “on the criteria we deem necessary in order to demonstrate the freedom of human choice” (Natali 2002: 267; 2004: 175). This leaves no conceptual space to raise the question of whether freedom is compatible with determinism. Destrée 2011: 289–96 allows some room for a compatibilist interpretation of Aristotle’s claim that our actions are up to us, it invokes a “general” capacity to do oth-erwise rather than the possibility of performing either a particular pair of alternatives; yet, he still begs the question against a wide range of compatibilist positions (see note 34 above). This may be why he classifies my compatibilist interpretation of Aristotle as “deter-minist” (p. 286 n4).

36 On the difference between these two worries, see Meyer 2009: 87–89.

Meyer_FM.indd xxiiMeyer_FM.indd xxii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 23: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xxiii

context for interpreting his concerns is the doctrine of self movement. While I do argue in the course of Chapter 6 that Aristotle’s repertoire of causal notions provides him with the resources to mount a powerful response to incompati-bilist challenges, I take this to be a strength of his position, but not a goal of his discussion.

BIBLIOGRAPHY OF RECENT SCHOLARSHIP

Annas, J. 1993. The Morality of Happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Berryman, S. 2002. “Aristotle on Pneuma and Self Motion” in D. Sedley, ed., Oxford Stud-

ies in Ancient Philosophy XXIII, pp. 85–97.Bobzien, S. 1998. Determinism and Freedom in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: The Clarendon

Press.—— . 1998a. “The Inadvertent Conception and Late Birth of the Free-Will Problem,”

Phronesis 43 (2): 133–75.—— . forthcoming. “Choice and Moral Responsibility in Nicomachean Ethics iii 1–5,” in

R. Polansky, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Cam-bridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bodeüs, R. 2004. Aristote: Éthique à Nicomache, traduction et présentation. Paris: Flam-marion.

Bostock, D. 2000. “Responsibility ([EN] III.1, 5).” Chapter 5 of Aristotle’s Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 103–22.

Bravo Vivar, F. 2006. “Teoría aritotélica de la responsabilidad” Estudios de Filosofi a, 34, pp. 109–132.

Broadie, S. 1991. “The Voluntary.” Chapter 3 of Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

—— 2001. “From Necessity to Fate: A Fallacy?” Journal of Ethics 5 (1): 21–37.—— and Rowe, C. 2002. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, translated with notes. Oxford:

Oxford University Press.Chappell, T. D. J. 1995. Aristotle and Augustine on Freedom: Two Theories of Freedom,

Voluntary Action, and Akrasia. St. Martin’s Press.Coope, U. 2010. “Aristotle” in Timothy O’Connor and Constantine Sandis, eds., A Com-

panion to the Philosophy of Action. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 439–446.Dahl, N. 1996. Review of Meyer 1993. Ethics, Vol. 106 Issue 2, pp. 455–457.Destrée, P. 2011. “Aristotle on Responsibility for One’s Character,” in Michael Pakaluk and

Giles Pearson, eds., Moral Psychology and Human Action in Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 285–319.

—— , Salles, R., and Zingano, M., eds. (in preparation). What is up to us? Studies on Cau-sality and Responsibility in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

Dimuzio, G. 2000. “Aristotle on Improving one’s Character” Phronesis 45: 204–19.—— 2008. “Aristotle’s Alleged Moral Determinism in the Nicomachean Ethics.” Journal of

Philosophical Research 33: 19–32.

Meyer_FM.indd xxiiiMeyer_FM.indd xxiii 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 24: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

xxiv Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality

Donini, P. L. 1989. “Voluntarietà di vizio e virtù (Aristotl Eth. Nic. III 1–7).” in E. Berti and L. Napolitano Valditara, eds., Etica politica retorica: studi su Aristotele e la sua pre-senza nell’età moderna. L’Aquila: Japadre, 1989, pp. 3–21. Translated into English as chapter VI of Donini 2010.

—— 2010. Aristotle and Determinism. Louvain: Peeters. Translation into English by Laura Kopp of Ethos: Aristotele e il determinismo. Alessandria: Edizioni dell’orso, 1989, plus three additional chapters, including Donini 1989 as Ch. VI.

Eliasson, E. 2009. “Magna Moralia 1187a29–b20: The Early Reception of Aristotle’s notion of Voluntary Action,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37: 213–244.

Frede, M. 2007. “The Eph’ Hemin in Ancient Philosophy.” Philosophia 37: 110–23.—— 2011. A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought, edited by A. A. Long.

Sather Classical Lectures, Volume 68. Berkeley: University of California Press.Garcia Ninet, A. 1998. “El determinismo de la acción en Aristóteles” Agora: Papeles de

Filosofi a, vol. 17, no. 1, pp. 33–53.Garver, E. 2006. “Decision, Rational Powers, and Irrational Powers,” chapter 2 of Con-

fronting Aristotle’s Ethics: Ancient and Modern Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Gill, M. L and Lennox, J., eds. 1994. Self-Motion from Aristotle to Newton. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Gordillo, L. 1996. “El acto voluntario en Aristóteles” Pensamiento: Revista de Investigación e Información Filosofíca 52 (202): 127–139.

Heinaman, R. 1986. “The Eudemian Ethics on Knowledge and Voluntary Action” Phrone-sis 31 (2): 128–47.

Labarrière, J.-L. 2009. “De ‘ce qui depend de nous.’ ” Études Philosophiques 1: 7–26.Klimchuk, D. 2002. “Aristotle on Necessity and Voluntariness” History of Philosophy Quar-

terly 19 (1), January 2002: 1–19.Meyer, S. S. 1994. “Self Movement and External Causation,” in Gill and Lennox, eds.,

1994: 65–80.—— 1998. “Moral Responsibility: Aristotle and After,” in Stephen Everson, ed., Compan-

ions to Ancient Thought, Volume 4: Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 221–40.

—— 2003. Review of Bobzien 1998. The Philosophical Review 112 (3): 405–409.—— 2006. “Aristotle on the Voluntary,” in Richard Kraut ed. The Blackwell Guide to Aris-

totle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 137–157.—— 2008. Ancient Ethics. London: Routledge.—— 2009. “Chain of Causes: What is Stoic Fate?” in Ricardo Salles, ed., God and Cosmos

in Stoicism, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 71–90.Morison, B. 2004. “Self Motion in Physics VIII” in A. Laks and M. Rashed, eds., Aristote

et le mouvement des animaux. Dix études sur le De motu animalium. Villeneuve d’Ascq: Presses Universitaires du Septentrion, pp. 67–79.

Natali, C. 1995. “Actions humains, événements naturels et la notion de responsabilité” in J-L. Petit (ed), Cahiers de philosophie politique et juridique 27: La querelle des norms, pp. 193–213. Reprinted as Chapter IX of Natali 2004, pp. 199–217.

Meyer_FM.indd xxivMeyer_FM.indd xxiv 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 25: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Voluntariness, Morality, and Causality xxv

—— . 2002. “Responsibility and Determinism in Aristotle’s Ethics” (translated by S. Wise) in M. Canto-sperber et P. Pellegrin (eds), Le style de la pensée: receuil de texts en hommage à Jacques Brunschwig. Paris: Belles Lettres, pp. 267–295. Reprinted, with some changes, in French as Chapter VIII of Natali 2004, pp. 175–198.

—— 2004. L’Action effi cace: études sur la philosophie de l’action d’Aristote. Louvain: Peeters.—— 2008. “Por que Aristóteles escreveu o livro III da EN?” Analytica, vol. 8, no. 2,

pp. 47–75.Ney, H.-O. 2009. “Délimitation juridique et morale de l’involontaire de Platon à Aristote”

in R. Lefebvre and A. Tordesillas, eds., Faiblesse de la volonté et maîtrise de soi: Doctrines antiques, perspectives contemporaines. Rennes: PUR: 91–103.

Nielsen, K. M. 2007. “Dirtying Aristotle’s Hands: Aristotle’s Analysis of Mixed Actions in Nicomachean Ethics III 1.” Phronesis 52 (3): 270–300.

—— 2011. “Deliberation as Inquiry: Aristotle’s Alternative to the Presumption of Open Alternatives,” The Philosophical Review 120 (3): 383–421.

O’Keefe, T. 2005. “Aristotle and Epicurus on the origins of character and action.” Chapter 3 of Epicurus on Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 48–64.

Ott, W. 2000. “On a troublesome passage in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics [EN 1113b3–14],” Ancient Philosophy 20: 99–107.

—— 2006. “Aristotle and Plato on Character.” Ancient Philosophy 26: 65–79.Pakaluk, M. 2005. “Actions as a sign of Character (Nicomachean Ethics 3.1–5).” Chapter 4

of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: An Introduction. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 118–150.

Raffoul, F. 2010. “Aristotle: Responsibility as Voluntariness.” Chapter 1 of Origins of Responsibility. Studies in Continental Thought. Bloomington, Indiana: University of Indiana Press, 39–57.

Rapp, C. 1995. “Freiwilligkeit, Entscheidung und Verantwortlichkeit” in O. Höffe, ed., Aristoteles, Die Nikomachische Ethik. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

Sakezles, P. K. 2007. “Aristotle and Chrysippus on the Psychology of Human Action: Cri-teria for Responsibility.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (2) May 2007: 225–252.

Salles, R. 2005. The Stoics on Determinism and Compatibilism. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.Segvic, H. 2009. “Deliberation and Choice in Aristotle,” From Protagoras to Aristotle: Essays

in Ancient Moral Philosophy, edited by M. F. Burnyeat. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 144–171. Original copyright in Michael Pakaluk and Giles Pearson, eds., Moral Psy-chology and Human Action in Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, 159–186.

Speight, A. 2005. “Listening to Reason: The Role of Persuasion in Aristotle’s Account of Praise, Blame, and the Voluntary,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 38, (3): pp. 213–225.

Taylor, C. C. W. 2006. Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics Books II–IV, translated with intro-duction and notes. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

Trueba, C. 2003. “Los principios de la acción en Aristóteles” Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofi a, 29 (1): 75–96.

Tuozzo, T. 1997. “Aristotle as Modern Moral Philosopher,” Phronesis 42 (3): 335–344.Zingano, M. 2007. Estudios de Ética Antigua. Sao Paulo: Discurso Editorial.

Meyer_FM.indd xxvMeyer_FM.indd xxv 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM

Page 26: Aristotle on Moral Responsibilitysmeyer/documents/AMRnewintroproofs.pdf · OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi viii Contents 3 Aristotle’s Canonical Account of

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRST-PROOF, 10/20/2011, SPi

Meyer_FM.indd xxviMeyer_FM.indd xxvi 10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM10/20/2011 7:05:22 PM