baecker - 2008 - form and forms of communication(2)

Upload: felipe-padilla

Post on 10-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    1/102

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    3. In Society

    3.1 Expecting Expectations

    Sociologically speaking, perhaps the most remarkable circumstance in connection with

    the phenomenon of communication is that people can communicate not solely for the

    sake of communicating. The principle formulated by Watzlawick, Beavin and Jackson

    does indeed apply, to the effect that, as soon as we are dealing with two organisms in

    their environments and in a mutually related form, that is, with mutual perception, we

    cannot not communicate (Watzlawick/Beavin/Jackson 1967: 51). But it equally holds

    good, that we cannot just communicate; we have to communicate about something at the

    same time. Of course, there are elaborated techniques of communicating only

    communication, as developed, above all, in group therapy. Yet they are, just as in thecase of meditation, a form of consciousness where consciousness perceives only

    consciousness, virtuoso performances, which derive their meaning from, among other

    things, making the normal case visible by going to the exterior of form and trying out the

    contrary. The general rule is that, now formulated in the cybernetic tradition, we cannot

    communicate without simultaneously communicating that we are controlling as we

    communicate (with surprising consequences to match), or again, formulated in our

    models conceptual mode, that we cannot stipulate degrees of freedom, if we have not

    introduced them in the first place.

    The step from the general model of communication to applying and testing it

    sociologically is hence a step from the singular of communications form to the plural of

    its forms. As soon as we communicate, we find ourselves engaging with particular forms

    of communication, the special nature of which is incomparably more conspicuous than

    the forms general nature, so that it is accordingly difficult to observe communication as

    such, or respectively, to observe it alongside the circumstances we have to deal with in

    each case, noting also that we are engaged in communicating.

    Nonetheless, the forms with which the following intends to deal are forms within the

    form of communication, or respectively forms taken out of the form, as GeorgeSpencer Brown formulates it for the case of his general calculation. Regardless of which

    concrete form is of interest in what follows, we are dealing fundamentally with a form of

    introducing and stipulating of degrees of freedom in the context of a combination of

    indication and differentiation. We shall see that the form of communication plays with

    various possibilities of much rather focussing freedoms spaces for action or alternatively

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    2/102

    51

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    of much rather emphasising stipulations and to that extent offers a wide spectrum

    between emphasising spontaneity, on the one hand, and ritualisation, on the other. With

    each individual form, it is always a question, however, of both, of introducing and

    stipulating degrees of freedom, so that the result of engaging with one form always

    means tying one to the other in the sense of Ronald D. Laings pinpointedly accurate

    parables (Laing 1970). Whoever participates in communication is engaging socially,

    regardless of whether through fleeting mutual notice at the bus stop, a collegial exchange

    at work, watching the television with the family or reading poems alone.

    The first of the forms we want to present here serves as a bridge between the general

    form of communication and its concrete forms. At the same time, it is simply the

    structure, that aims at concrete structures, individual themes of communication, therefore,

    yet in its general nature makes sure that every concrete structure can be swapped for

    another concrete structure, depending on the history of communication. This, the first of

    the forms derived from form and general structure, is expectation. It is patently not

    possible, so runs the thesis in this context, to engage in communication, without attaching

    to it an expectation about what we are getting involved in. More acutely formulated, it is

    not even possible to engage in communication, without attaching certain expectations

    about what we are getting involved in. That does not have to mean that we attach certain

    intentions, goals and interests to communication, but it does mean, in any case, that we

    have, depending on the communication, an idea of what offers of behaviour we are going

    to be involved with and what behaviour of our own is opportune and what is not. We

    accept an expectation, as we engage with a communication and we look to see

    subsequently what has become of it and how far it determines what is possible in

    engaging with it. And from the beginning, the expectation is effective in a moderated

    state; it can be amplified and weakened, emphasised and denied, shifted conspicuously or

    inconspicuously and is, in this manner, already a stipulation of the degree of freedom, the

    introduction of which is here the point.

    An expectation becoming effective happens as a rule so peripherally that we scarcely

    notice it. We enter a church and lower our voices, we greet our guests for dinner and

    involuntarily become a notion jollier, we get to work and seem a touch more determined.

    And if we do not, we communicate that we are not collaborating in a way then to be

    defined more closely or found out, as may be.

    We describe an expectation as a structure, because this concept corresponds to Alfred

    Korzybskis reflections, as it posits that there are no isolated processes, events or objects

    in the world (we then would not know anything about them; they would inhabit another

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    3/102

    52

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    world) and hence directs each of these phenomena to its possible relations to another

    phenomenon (Korzybski 1958: 55ff.). Observing the structure of something accordingly

    allows examining a phenomenon for what it is not, yet for what it has in common with

    others. That is always only possible hypothetically, tentatively, experimentally and

    riskily, but it is possible. To avoid falling into the structuralist trap, we only have to take

    care not to confuse this structure with the actual reason for a process, an event or an

    object. The concept of structure only provides that traces of one thing lie in the other,

    where one relates to the other through the game, as Jacques Derrida says (1970), and not

    perhaps through a mutual or even directed determination. This concept of structure

    corresponds sufficiently with the concept of form, which allows more exact examining of

    the structure of one as indicating similarities and differences in comparison with the other

    while reaching back to differentiating one thing from another.

    An expectation always stands in the context of expecting to be disappointed, however

    strongly or weakly this moment may indeed be marked in the particular case, and with

    that, because we cannot not expect, in the context of exchange for another expectation.

    An expectation is a structure on the hop, but a structure nonetheless. It defines itself in

    differing from its possible disappointment, but does not perhaps use the disappointment

    not to expect anything any more, but to expect something else, including the possibility

    of expecting nothing. We can set down the corresponding form as follows:

    That says nothing other than that expectation determines itself in a communicative

    context by differentiating itself from its disappointment and uses the reflection on this

    possible disappointment for determining itself through the differentiation from itself, that

    is, from possible other expectations. Reckoning with disappointment is the

    differentiation, which allows defining an expectation.

    In a communicative context, this becomes acute in at least four respects.

    Firstly, we ought not to confuse observing expectations in communications form with

    observing them in the form of consciousness. What expectations perform in

    communications form is, in consciousness, probably performed by attention (Markowitz

    1986: 10f., 61f., 110f.), in as far as this is also a structure, which allows undertaking a

    definition and at the same time leaving open, whether a definition can be maintained on

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    4/102

    53

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    both sides, on the consciousness side, which can be distracted and nevertheless, if even in

    favour of attention to something else, thinks further, and on the object side, which really

    does not merit so much attention or some other sort of attention from what we had

    imagined. We are deliberately leaving open what role expectations play for

    consciousness, in order instead to underline all the more obviously that the structures of

    expectation dealt with by communication are expectations of communication, which

    make reference to observing consciousness engaged in communication but simply not

    identical with this consciousnesss possible expectations itself or with sorts of attention.

    In fact, emphasising this is important, because secondly it has, since Talcott Parsons,

    concerned so-called complimentary expectations (Parsons/Shils 1951; Parsons 1964).

    Communication does not merely mean that participants engage in it with expectations,

    however much that may be the case. On the contrary, communication means, above all,

    that each of these expectations is besides expecting what the other expects. When people

    enter a church, they expect that the priest expects them to behave piously in some way or

    other, however multifarious, modifiable and susceptible to civilising this expectation

    expected by the priest may indeed then turn out to be. That is, not least, the reason why

    so many styles of belief do indeed differentiate themselves, allowing the priest in

    question to offer, respectively, different frames for projecting a definite notion of what he

    may indeed expect. In a school, teachers expect that the pupils expect from them that they

    will teach them something. That is all that enables them to appear as authoritarian or,

    respectively, antiauthoritarian and to make offers to the pupils, which make clear to them

    what is expected of them. There are not a few teachers, who, not long after retiring,

    cannot imagine any more how they were able to control and to fascinate twenty to forty

    pupils, as they do not know anything of the structure of complementary expectations,

    which came to their aid communicatively, and have all their life attributed being able to

    do it to their personal capabilities, not least in order to keep going. A fine example from

    Parsons (1964: 330) describes the communication between a doctor and, in this case, a

    female patient, both of whom have to know exactly what they expect of each other,

    namely neutral, practical treatment and examination even in the case of intimate

    touching, in order to be able then, through minimally varying their behaviour, by a

    somewhat stronger hand pressure, a somewhat longer look, to test if there is eventually

    anything to be gained by believing the other has other expectations as well, which can be

    perhaps exploited to shift the context of the medical treatment to that of a sexual affair.

    Communicatively, we do not simply expect that something else is possible perhaps,

    but we rely on expectations of expectation and on these being modifiable by the

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    5/102

    54

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    suggestion of other expectations. If the other does not engage with the expectations we

    offer as available to them, we withdraw again and did not in our doubt expect at all that

    the other could expect anything. Then the somewhat stronger hand pressure, the

    somewhat longer look were chance, a personal idiosyncrasy of the particular doctor or

    whatever, in any case something innocuous. Whoever thinks anything else in this

    connection, has already engaged with the possibility of other expectations.

    Our third aspect is that this subtlety of expectations of expectation relates to the fact

    that it has to manage without a solid reference point outside of the particular modifiable

    situation. It is indeed not only expectations but also expectations of expectation that are

    structures in the sense, that they make it possible to indicate something they are not and,

    to that extent, to try out for itself an ordering, which has still got to maintain itself. But

    they have to do all this themselves in the framework of a reference of their own to be

    justified in the situation, not in the framework of an exogenous guarantee assuring what

    is to be expected in what situation for what reasons. That is why sociologists speak of

    institutions (Schelsky 1970; Meyer/Rowan 1977), of arrangements, which make mutually

    attributing a consensus on certain ways of behaving, on intentions and considerations

    possible, and which can then be so treated as if they were given. But communication can

    only decide in the situation and only for itself, if we can put it that way, with which

    institutions it will engage.

    A radical formulation for this outward insecurity of communication is the theorem,

    likewise developed by Talcott Parson, of double contingency (Parsons/Shils 1951: 15ff.;

    Parsons 1964: 89ff.), which, in his case, explicitly takes the place of the theorem of the

    struggle of all against all formulated three hundred years earlier by Thomas Hobbes in

    Leviathan (1651). Sociality, according to Hobbes, means having to reckon with the worst.

    Sociality, according to Parsons, means not knowing what we have to reckon with and

    hence relying on culture. Niklas Luhmann would then suggest replacing the reference to

    culture with the reference to chance and time (Luhmann 1995: 105f.; see Baecker 2001b:

    133ff.).

    In any case, this means the following: when two observers, individuals, persons of

    whatever (we have to keep that open here, but will come back to it) meet, they are in the

    situation of not knowing what (including: which expectations) is to be expected from the

    other. One of them could hence do this, but also something else (simple contingency); the

    other could do that, but likewise something else (double contingency). In this situation,

    the one waits for the other to do something, start something, whilst the other does the

    same. Both wait for the other to declare themselves and hence open up a differentiation.

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    6/102

    55

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    Nothing happens. The behaviour of both, from attitude to direction of gaze, is fixed by

    not allowing themselves to be fixed on anything. The situation becomes increasingly

    onerous, because people do not, in fact, renounce communication whilst waiting, as this

    is already communication, mutual perception. They are communicating about not

    communicating with each other, because neither of the pair knows how they could begin.

    When this theorem became known in the 1950s, people liked to discuss it using the

    example of the communication of two strangers in a train compartment.

    Here once again, the decisive point is also that the communication is not blocked by

    anything, but blocks itself. Nothing happens, because what is being communicated is that

    each of the pair is waiting for the other, in order to receive an indication of what can

    actually be expected in and from a communication between the two of them. That is, as

    it were, the primal situation of the social, primal situation, because nothing else is

    happening here but the social itself. Group therapies, particularly the so-called training

    group (Kasenbacher 2003: 142ff.), like to exploit this, in order to make experiencing the

    social itself possible. Obviously, people anticipate beneficial effects from it. The primal

    situation is experienced as a problem demanding a solution. For this reason, Parsons

    speaks of the problem of double contingency. This problem is identical with the

    indefiniteness of communications, which reflects on itself. It is the indefiniteness in the

    face of every differentiation, which people cannot tolerate, but which they have to learn

    to tolerate, if they want to be in a position to observe, so to speak, communication in pure

    form.

    At the same time it is not, in fact, the case that this problem of double contingency

    only appears at the start of a communication and then never again. On the contrary, it

    seems to be the rule that people begin to communicate with each other in a fully defined

    situation and only then do moments materialise, in which the previous expectations of

    expectation are exhausted and no new ones appear, without people maybe being, for that

    reason, already prepared to end the communication and go away. That is something about

    which those situations concerned with initially crossing a threshold to a certain trust can

    sing a refrain, for instance, when leading up to business of the more demanding kind, to

    intimacy or also to belief. The problem of the double contingency accompanies

    communication, never leaves it and is solved repeatedly and, depending on

    circumstances, in various ways, however much organisations, marriages, confession, or

    interviews with politicians, of example, also develop rituals of solving the problem,

    which can be invoked almost as needed.

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    7/102

    56

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    Now Parsons thinks, it would be culture, understood as, for the social, the external

    horizon of values and corresponding norms of what is right and what wrong, which

    enables the solving of the problem of the double contingency. And in actual fact, it does

    seem that there was indeed a time when people knew how to behave as a stranger in a

    railway compartment, as a husband to a wife also in instances of, as it were, dropping out

    of the marriage, or as a teacher to a pupil, before the latter began to learn. It is equally

    certain that this knowledge, about how to behave adequately for a situation, about the

    correct offers of behaviour and the incorrect intrusions within the various cultural

    frictions between the generations, the sexes and the backgrounds, tends to dissolve itself,

    however much fundamentalist of all kinds try to mitigate against it. It is certain in

    addition, that, in any society, people cannot assume any more that they can rely on a

    culture given to society out of some horizon or other. In cultural comparison, every

    society learns that it has itself, its own customs, norms and prejudices to thank for its

    culture and not, for instance, some nature of things, however inscrutable. With the

    descriptions of correct behaviour that is the actual drama the differentiations, which

    kept these descriptions stable, also dissolve themselves, without people believing that

    they even actually knew them (Geertz 1973: 142ff.).

    According to Luhmann, solving the problem of the double contingency cannot,

    therefore, already exist exclusively in culture, which only has to be invoked in every

    problematical situation. Cultivated behaviour can actually exacerbate the problem, just as

    much as deliberately treating cultural expectations casually. So the mechanism allowing

    respective problems to be solved has to be more generally, at the same time self-

    referentially and more strongly related to the resources of the given situation. Luhmann

    deduces that chance and time will solve the problem. Something happens; a bird flies past

    the railway compartment window and one person tries a friendly smile, the other a piece

    of chocolate. A particular narrative of interaction develops, however minimal it may be,

    and we become increasingly sure about the sort of expectations of expectation we are

    handling. We keep the disappointment of possible other expectations to ourselves or we

    otherwise wait to see, if the further narrative of interaction will sometime or other offer

    reference points for trying out feeding in again these other expectations about attributing

    the particular complementary expectation.

    It is obvious that the way interactively developing communications depend on chance

    and their own narrative tends to reinforce the cultural uncertainty of correct and incorrect

    behaviour rather than weaken it, because we can experience so many different things and

    are directed towards finding the differences interesting, rather than the similarities. We

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    8/102

    57

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    can, therefore, reckon with situations involving double contingency being, in times of

    cultural uncertainty, both more often noticeable and routinely covered up as well. to the

    point where we can begin wondering, if these routines do not constitute a new form of

    culture. Reflections of this kind lead to combining Parsons solution with Luhmanns

    and, on one side, continuing to regard it as a solution to the problem of double

    contingency, albeit, on the other, only as a solution among others and as a solution, which

    does not refer to a resource endogenously given but in each case endogenously open to

    contesting all over again.

    Finally, the fourth and, in our context, last aspect, where the structure of expectations

    of expectation is critical in communication and for it, is the possibility of describing

    feelings as constructions arising from the amplification of expectations into demands, and

    this both in the case of expectations being confirmed and in that of them being

    disappointed. Whilst expectations are normally either disappointed or confirmed, and we

    can then decide if we retain them and reinforce them normatively, expectations can, in

    particular situations concerning the mobilisation of individual or collective effects of

    solidarity, be boosted into demands, which are anchored in the participating individuals

    as feelings. At least in this way we can collate those reference points towards a sociology

    of emotion, which are to be found variously with Talcott Parsons and Niklas Luhmann

    (Parsons 1977: 218f., 247ff.; Luhmann 1995: 269f., 274f.; Stenner 2004; Baecker 2004).

    Feelings of fulfilment intensify confirmed expectations into demands striving after

    further confirmation; feelings of disappointment retain demands, and that also when the

    basic expectations were disappointed and were possibly even dropped.

    It is interesting that feelings only achieve this intensification of expectations into

    demands under two conditions, namely, on the one hand, on condition of trying also to tie

    in emotionally the complementary expectation of the respective interlocutor and, on the

    other, on condition of what we feel hitting on a statement, indubitable because subjective,

    on the objective situation we are in. From that, ambivalences as regards attribution can be

    gained, which allow leaving it open whether subsequent communications connect with

    the person of the other or with their situation. It seems that this is the only way to win

    over the respective interlocutor for the feeling, without anything being too definite about

    has been gained by such a win. That is because the situation invoking hatred, love,

    sadness or joy is just as interesting as the person who reacts accordingly.

    In this way, feelings make a differentiation, which opens a space other to that of other

    differentiations. Still without knowing exactly what they denote, that is, what

    expectations they make possible, they signal an indefinitely definite dealing with

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    9/102

    58

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    disappointments, which allows relating the situations resources and the participating

    persons resources in such a way that both can be newly coordinated with each other. If

    feelings promote solidarity, as Parsons says, then this does not only apply to the

    relationship between persons, but also to the relationship between persons and situations.

    People can only come to accept things emotionally and can only decide emotionally to

    risk something new. That is the case, because, when differentiating feelings, one thing, as

    does another, brings new resources into play, which re-actualise the entire narrative of

    persons and their situations, without having, therefore, to thematise them as well. To the

    intellectual function of conscious thought, that is something uncanny. But it has to rely on

    it for this feeling as well.

    3.2 Number, Order, Calculus

    Expectations of expectation are the structures forming the background to communications

    becoming events that count themselves, that is, can be identified and connected. That

    communication has happened can be established through the confirming or disappointing

    of an expectation of expectation, and that consequently certain connections are more

    likely, other less so.

    We talk about counting communicative events, because one of the results of research

    in cybernetics and systems theory is that the self-organisation of a complex phenomenon

    pre-supposes that the phenomenon is in a position to decide among its own units, to count

    them and to decide accordingly which further operations are possible and necessary

    (Baecker 2003). In this sense, the cyberneticist Warren McCulloch has spoken about how

    he engaged with cybernetics theoretical potential by trying to find out how a crustacean

    succeeds in directing the growth of its shell, including its spiral and pattern, by adding up

    the stage of growth it is in at any given time (McCulloch 2004). Communication is a

    process of calculation, which posits that events can be differentiated, in order to separate

    and to connect them. Confirming or disappointing expectations provides the scanning and

    outlining capable, in this sense, of profiling communicative events

    (Watzlawick/Beavin/Jackson 1967: 54ff.; Wilden 1972: 111ff.).

    The respective unit of communication capable of being counted as an event depends

    on the structure of expectation, as background to observing communication. Here we can

    reckon not only in great historical periods but also to the beat of seconds, depending on

    whether it concerns the imperial communication of the Roman Empire or the

    micromoment management of a particular socially interactive situation (Leifer 2002).

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    10/102

    59

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    Beyond that, we can, with George Spencer Brown, talk about countable

    communicative events, which establish certain distinctions (for instance: in the empire,

    only the power of the centre counts) can be, on the one hand, confirmed by repetition,

    on the other, however, can be condensed into the difference they make:

    These two expressions denote in Spencer Browns calculations (1972: 10f.), which hedescribes as calculations of quantity. What is meant by that is that distinctions once made

    may be repeated without the repetition itself having to make a difference to the distinctio.

    We can repeatedly put questions, give instructions, confess our love, or offer money

    without the repetition changing anything about the questioning, instructing, loving or

    paying. Naturally, subtle observations establishing a difference in the repetition, for

    instance, increasing enthusiasm and deepening trust or also growing boredom or

    gradually awakening mistrust, are not excluded with these counting processes (Deleuze

    1968). But these assume an observing of form which indicates already relations of order

    and not only of number. Here at least mathematics and sociology agree that not only what

    is extraordinary and subtle deserves recording, but also what is ordinary and self-evident.

    The two forms of confirmation and of condensation go back to the first of the two

    laws, which Spencer Brown formulates in hisLaws of Form, namely to the law of

    calling: the value of a call made again is the value of the call (1972: 1), respectively:

    For our reflections, this means that, taking into account the expectations, which they set

    and confirm, or disappoint, communications can be repeated in their value as well as

    summarised with regard to it. We can repeatedly call up what maintains them. We can,

    however, also try to find out what it is actually all about. Time and again, we meet

    particular friends to attend a concert together. At some point, we discover that concert

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    11/102

    60

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    visits concerts are nothing else than celebrating and confirming the friendship on both

    sides. The differentiation is not unimportant, as it makes it possible, among other things,

    to choose between regretting that, on one particular evening, a friend is not going along

    to the concert again, on one side, and suspecting that this other persons friendship has

    diminished, on the other. And accordingly, we will react in various ways, and

    accordingly, the friend will be well advised to look a various ways of formulating their

    regrets.

    He calls these two other possibilities cancellation,

    and compensation,

    Cancellation means that a difference already established can be abandoned through the

    instruction to delete the indication and the mark in favour of the unmarked state. On the

    contrary, compensation means that the unmarked state can be marked by a self-deleting

    distinction. Both possibilities rest on the second of the two laws of form on which

    Spencer Brown grounds his calculation, namely, the law of crossing: The value of a

    crossing made again is not the value of the crossing (1972: 2, and see ibid.: 10),

    respectively:

    One of the calculations crucial ideas consists in the formulation of this second law. Itmakes explicit what has been gained with the concept of form. The concept of form

    actually implies nothing less than introducing the distinctions initially uncertain exterior,

    which an observer of the second order can define, and which hence means introducing an

    empty space, and the calculation reckons with it as it does with the indicated and marked

    interior of the distinction. The law of calling formulates how this unmarked space can be

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    12/102

    61

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    reached: by putting a cross against a distinction or better un-crossing it. If I have just

    said to my friend, Id like to go to the cinema, and subsequently say, Id rather not go

    to the cinema, I thereby gain the possibility of not wanting anything. Communicatively,

    this possibility can be shaped just as interestingly as the possibility of wanting something.

    I am not committed to anything, but have to, if I want something, set up a new difference,

    and with this I have, in turn, the possibility of subsequently cancelling it. I do not want to

    go to the cinema, not to the concert and do not want to stay at home too: with this, the

    other person is called upon to occupy themselves with the one who could want

    something, but does not want anything, and first of all to find out what is causing the

    unwillingness to set up one of the differences we have been so consistently establishing

    up to now.

    But that is not all. We can not only put a cross against what has held good up to now,

    but we can also imply observations of form, which allow observing how what we

    establish so successfully as differentiations compensates for the emptiness they replace.

    And this possibility is always on hand, is orientated according to every expectation we

    might use to profile a communication, regardless of whether it is a matter of a friendship,

    a task, enjoying art, admiring a woman or socialising. We will need reasons and reference

    points, complementary expectations too, in order to initiate observing form this way. But

    whoever seeks, they shall find. We might only think of Gustave Flauberts novels, above

    all,Lducation Sentimentale (1869), in which a society is presented, where nothing

    moves it other than compensating for its own emptiness.

    Against the background of the law of calling, Spencer Brown links these two

    possibilities of cancellation and compensation to the concept of order in as different from

    that of number. When counting, it is a question of finding out what lasts and in what

    regards it can be consolidated, with ordering, it is a question of scrutinising every

    difference we establish against the background of possibly also cancelling it again. Both

    concepts reckon with both sides of form, as counting also functions only if the indefinite

    is incorporated every time as the exterior of the definite. We cannot count without

    attending to intersections. But with ordering, the outside of the form becomes an

    interesting argument in its own right, if we can put it like that. Ordering only functions,

    when the two possibilities of defining and of the undefined are treated symmetrically. For

    only in that way can we decide for and against an order. And that is the only reason why

    an order is an order.

    With that, we have unobtrusively introduced the premises or the axioms of Spencer

    Browns calculation. Anything more than the two named laws does not exist. And

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    13/102

    62

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    anything more than the three possibilities they nominate for dealing with distinctions:

    putting a cross against them, cancelling them and re-entering them into the space of

    distinction again something we will come back to also does not exist.

    3.3 Forms of the Social

    Society is number, order and re-entry of communication. It repeats, confirms and

    consolidates itself (number); it deletes itself and sets itself up as an alternative possibility

    to itself (order); it explores what it creates as the space of its own possibilities (re-entry).

    Society is a title for these three forms of dealing with communication. And each of

    these three forms is embedded in observing the three degrees of freedom and how they

    are stipulated. It is repeatedly a matter of opening a space of differentiation and the

    descriptions possible within it. It is correspondingly demanding to construct a theory of

    society. Society cannot be posited as the cosmos or chaos of its communicative

    possibilities any more, but has to be developed from the form of differentiating

    communication through describing communication as operation.

    We have fixed the possibility of counting communication through the structures of

    complementary expectation, which can be fixed through every single communicative

    event and allow differentiating these events, for their part, from each other. We will deal

    with the re-entry of communication into the space of the society it creates in the next

    chapter under the heading meaning. In this and the two following sections, it is a

    question of the order of society, which we will describe as an ordering of differentiation

    and of self-description. In this case, we are not concerned with working out a general

    theory of society, but only with making comprehensible how far society can be

    understood as an ordering of communication.

    Society is only then the ordering of communication, when it fulfils itself as a self-

    establishing and self-cancelling differentiation of communication, with which we can

    engage alternately, which includes in each individual version the possibility of all others,

    and these, therefore, relate with more or less severe exclusivity to each other. The

    singular of this order is hence to be understood as a plural of its orders. Society always

    appears as differing from itself, not least as differing from that community, which it

    always has incorporated as the dream of being defined though its own definitions

    (Plessner 1999). Communication is always engaged in the leap, delayed more or less, into

    another possibility of being itself.

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    14/102

    63

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    Hence, society needs robust differentiations, which firstly denote various possibilities

    for using communication, can secondly attract a sufficient number of communicative

    events, in order both to hone its profile and also become structurally rich enough to

    include the perspective onto alternative possibilities, and thirdly are sufficiently capable

    of reflexion not to lose sight of the precarious terrain they operate on. The differentiations

    have to be robust, because they accompany communication as, in the sense advanced by

    Jrgen Ruesch and Gregory Bateson, metacommunications which are, on one side,

    communicatively included on the same level as the themes of communication and, on

    another, set the conditions, which describe how communication can be continued

    (Ruesch/Bateson 1987: 209ff.). These conditions extend beyond the respective thematic

    and material attractivity of communication and denote the respective form of the social,

    which can be called on by communication and is reproduced by communication. They

    establish a differentiation foreshadowing which indications can be expected.

    We have recourse to Niklas Luhmanns theory of society as developed in the book Die

    Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft(1997), in order to nominate candidates for such forms of

    the social. These candidates are here presented exemplarily and without any claim to

    completeness, even if I would find it difficult at present to imagine any more of them.

    These candidates are interaction, organisation, protest movements and society itself, the

    latter being further ordered into tribes, levels and systems of functioning. The following

    form denotes the context of the corresponding differentiations:

    It is important that society itself appears once again in its order, because it would

    otherwise have no possibility of differentiating and observing itself as what it is.

    However, what is more interesting than merely nominating the candidates is describingthem from the point of view of ordering communication. How do interaction,

    organisation, protest movements and society cope all together with the task of

    establishing and repeatedly cancelling themselves? How do they succeed in profiling

    themselves as possibilities of communication, without running the risk of establishing

    themselves as the only possibility and not only excluding all others (that would indeed

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    15/102

    64

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    contain, even if in the form of negation, a nevertheless concurrent memory of them), but

    of losing sight of them? How do they enable differentiations of events, objects and states,

    without neglecting to embed these in the concurrent observation of other possibilities?

    Interaction performs this task through differentiating presence, the organisation

    through differentiating membership, the social movement by differentiating protest and

    society as a whole by differentiating communication from the viewpoint of its

    extendability. These distinctions are everything we have already named: they are delay

    and supplement (diffrance); they are opposition and contrast (diffrend); they are a game

    with a division (partition) and they are the space, in which correcting mistakes is

    possible. Amid all that, they are the attractors or the inherent values of societys

    communicative events, which can be counted using confirmed or disappointed

    expectations. Distinguishing presence, membership, protest and communication itself

    introduces the degrees of freedom exploited and stipulated in any particular order.

    Interaction is that order of communication, which already occurs through individuals

    (and in general: organisms) perceiving that they perceive themselves. Their condition is

    the presence of the individuals communicating with each other, on condition that this

    presence is established, that is, differentiated, that is, marked out against the possibility of

    absence. We can engage with interactions when and because we can know how we can

    also stop them again. Only in this way can presence in an interaction be shaped from the

    viewpoint of conceivably being also absent from it, of the other person present

    conceivably being absent too and of there existing absent people, whose presence is

    excluded but can certainly be incorporated in this form of exclusion.

    This last viewpoint has fascinated social theory from Georg Simmel to Michael Serres

    under the heading of the so-called third party: how can we understand and describe

    actions, when we take into account that each individual present has, as it were, a third

    party at their back, who is, of course, not present but, as an absence, every time controls

    what happens in the interaction (Serres 1982). This third party can be authority figures

    like parents or teachers, imagined observers like spirits or gods, or also legitimisations

    like ideologies, fashions and interests, whose criteria govern assessing and selecting what

    happens in any given case, or whose power and plausibility respectively govern how we

    test to see if things can also work differently. They are the proverbial fulfilment of our

    condition of establishing and stipulating degrees of freedom, as referring to them renders

    a situation autonomous vis--vis other demands, yet, with that, simultaneously subjects it

    to this third party all the same (Miermont 1989).

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    16/102

    65

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    It is only from this viewpoint of differentiating presence from absence that interaction

    is able, for good or ill, to order its communicative possibilities, is able to cultivate what it

    can achieve and is able to describe the conditions under which repeatedly coming back to

    it remains attractive despite other possibilities. That other interlocutors are present opens

    up an action space for freedom, which we can only use, if we make clear what conditions

    we are maintaining and how we are willing to negotiate over these conditions. That is

    what interaction in school classes, in court, in families, out shopping, on sports grounds,

    or in offices and workshops lives by. From the viewpoint of presence, what we mutually

    demand of each other can be intensified or also loosened; and from the viewpoint of

    absence, we can give to understand that every interaction can also be ended, and it can

    also become clear that reasons can also be found outside of interaction for re-engaging in

    it.

    Let us only imagine a moment: we had to engage in an interaction - buying a ticket for

    a trip, going to the opera, taking part in a game of football - without also being able to

    imagine our own absence in this interaction, and we will understand what is meant here.

    But that goes for all participants; and every single interaction derives the extent of its

    attraction from them actually dealing with the ensuing awareness of contingency and also

    from their way of doing it. In this form, every interaction is interwoven and enmeshed

    with what it is not and in this form orders the expectations directed at its

    communications. The corresponding notation elucidates this point about differentiating

    presence and absence and about reflecting absence into presence:

    Sociology has occasionally described systems of interaction as simple or even

    undifferentiated systems (Kieserling 1999). In actual fact, nothing about them is easy or

    undifferentiated, because, in each case, they have include coping with what is also

    alternatively possible to them in society, and because they have to be at least so

    differentiated that they can succeed in profiling the grounds for communication in the

    interaction within the range of choice for other possibilities of interaction itself and for

    societys other possibilities (Luhmann 1997: 812ff.). This profiling, as we can presume,

    following the sociology of interaction developed by Erving Goffman, at least requires

    that participants in an interaction have not only the possibility to present something

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    17/102

    66

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    (performance) but also the possibility to watch (audience) (Goffman 1959). In every

    interaction, every participant oscillates to and fro within these two options, is sometimes

    presenter, sometimes spectator and, beyond that, has also to present their spectating and

    watch themselves as a presenter in the light of how long the others will indeed still accept

    what they are offering.

    This oscillation between presenting and spectating, both of which are forms of

    observation and forms of second order observation, lends interaction, via a second

    differentiation after the first one between presence and absence, a structural richness

    capable of being used to cultivate the conditions of presence and differentiate the

    conditions of absence. We can accelerate the oscillation between presenting and

    spectating and derive from that forms of highly cultivated social life, which are not

    comprehensible to anyone, who has not learned to take part in them (Gracin 1991). We

    can, however, build asymmetries into the oscillation and derive authority structures form

    them, which act as if only one of the participants were the presenter (authority, teacher,

    artist) and all others were spectators, who keep still as long as the performance,

    recognisable by certain formal signs, is running, but have at least to perform keeping still

    and may at least reckon with the main presenter being at the same time a spectator of the

    performance of spectating and deciding accordingly, how long to go on and how to make

    certain that what they are offering remains attractive enough.

    We can see that, at the latest, determining the oscillation ensures that the exterior of

    the interaction has, in fact, to be incorporated in the form of staging power, the

    organisation of a school or social interest in art, because cultivating the interaction would

    otherwise not have any bases for what it tries out. But then the opposite also applies, to

    the effect that social order profits communicatively from whatever proves itself

    interactively, and then arranges its own expectations quite differently with a view to

    power, education and art, as if there were nowhere to try out how long citizens, pupils

    and arts public are prepared to hold still.

    All this makes interaction structurally so rich, that the view could long persist - in

    Europe arguably up to the French Revolution - that society was on the whole to be

    organised via that communication, which proves itself interactively. In the final analysis,

    so people thought, it was a case of coming to terms within the family on the conditions

    for acknowledging persons and in public, and in the political cabinets referring to the

    public, of the conditions for organising society. People did not need anything more, in

    order to shape society justly (Plato) and in harmony with its own possibilities (telos).

    The French Revolution destroyed this fine hope irrevocably and, to use Hegels

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    18/102

    67

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    formulation, replaced it with the phenomenon of separation (Ritter 1965). That is because

    this revolution did not allow itself to be conducted as a negotiation between enlightened

    aristocrats and newly-rich citizens appearing as creditors, and with workers and peasants

    interested in ascending into the bourgeoisie, but it got all the more out of control, the

    more it tried doing just this, as an interaction under the guillotine.

    People discovered that there are orders in society, which establish and cancel

    themselves differently from those of interaction. People discovered society and initially

    developed, in theories of progress (Auguste Comte), then in theories of revolution (Karl

    Marx) and finally in theories of decadence (Matthew Arnold), various versions of this

    entity, which were, to a greater or lesser extent, in danger of substantiating it and of

    replacing the spirits and gods of the past with it. And people discovered organisation,

    which counted in the 19th century as the only insurance vis--vis an increasingly liberated

    and liberalised society (Russell 1934). For this reason, it was not only a question of more

    or less technocratically organising society itself as a State, but also the protest against

    this society in a more a less revolutionary form as a movement.

    Meanwhile, having in turn become quite unhappily wiser through the experiences of

    the 20th century, the ideological hopes of interaction, organisation, movements and

    society have cooled off correspondingly. Sociology, as providing enlightenment in the

    medium of differentiating systems, certainly has its share in this. In the meantime,

    interaction is no longer the model for measuring the other possibilities of ordering

    communication, but only one possibility among others, albeit one at least as prominent as

    them.

    What does organisation mean, then, if we do not understand by it the counterpart to

    freedom (be it in the shape of chaos, be it in the shape of the, as it were, unorganised,

    ordered cosmos), but an order of communication, which has combine freedom with

    unfreedom, perhaps in the form of definiteness and indefiniteness, just like all other

    orders? What sort of differentiation opens up the possibility of organisation?

    Organisation, as we assume it in the tradition of organisation theory (Simon 1997;

    March/Simon 1993; Luhmann 1995; Weick 1979), means quite plainly and in turn

    robustly differentiating the members of an organisation from its non-members and

    addressing behavioural expectations to the members of an organisation and being able, as

    a premise to this end, to treat possible differentiations, which would have no chance

    outside of the organisation:

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    19/102

    68

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    With that we take a significant step beyond interaction and one which also touches on

    what we can imagine as the form of communication. That is because differentiating

    members from non-members means being able to imagine a communication, which goes

    on between participants, who are not present in any particular situation, yet can

    nevertheless reach and also, in this sense, perceive each other. The space of this

    differentiation exceeds the condition of being there. Nothing is more unlikely than this,

    but, to the extent that organisation succeeds, it succeeds. A space of action for freedom

    opens up, unanticipated by society and fascinating and fearful for it, yet it gains its form

    only to the extent that conditions are discovered, which make it attractive to members to

    feel themselves committed to the organisation also outside of control by those present. It

    takes centuries, before this form of order becomes at all visible and differentiable. Until

    that point, organisation had to rely on commitments to the evidence of organised

    interaction and the social ideologies accompanying this evidence. It is only today that

    everyone can see that organisations decisive degree of freedom is not its order, but

    deciding the membership of this order, that is, a communication and not a practical

    necessity.

    This step should also be signalled here for the reason that it has been above allsociologists who have so far been able to imagine this possibility of communication

    among those absent. Many other have problems with it, which can, however, be reduced,

    if we imagine absence to be, in the first instance, something capable of being indeed

    present as a horizon for imaginings and, in the second, only playing a role anyway in

    those respects where grounds exist for imagining those absent who are to be reached.

    Hence, in organisations keeping written and electronic records plays such a central role.

    These records, whatever shape at all they adopt, lay down a trace we can follow, in order

    to reach those absent. Our own nameplate, our own desk, our own signing rights together

    with working discussions as needed and under the conditions of being present, these quite

    suffice to equip the individuals involved to be sufficiently conscious of the likelihood that

    their communicating is possible.

    In organisations too, structural richness is not gained by subjecting the members of an

    organisation to the purpose and the goals of the organisation, disciplining and motivating

    them accordingly and dismissing them again, if they do not conform (although that is

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    20/102

    69

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    exactly what happens), but by profiling and cultivating the possibilities of membership as

    against the possibilities of non-membership (Weber 1958; Trk 1995, 2000). In an

    organisation, every communication carries the condition of having to find and commit

    members, who, on one side, can leave the organisation again and who, on the other, know

    they are being observed by non-members of the organisation as to what they tolerate in

    their organisation and what they do not. For this reason, organised communication

    oscillates, albeit, in fact, in the range of micromoments too, between belonging and not

    belonging to the organisation. And for that reason alone, communication in the

    organisation takes on the form of a differentiation, that is, of doubly validating a sender

    and an addressee of communication. It does so because only in this way can it be

    focussed on the condition of membership in such a manner, as to allow the organisation

    to be, in each of it moments, profiled and examined as an order, that is as it own

    possibility and impossibility.

    Decisions have the decisive advantage that they are meant to commit the other person

    and hence have to test in advance the conditions, under which this commitment is

    accepted. Under the cloak of the one-way street (my decision commits you), the

    organisation cultivates a form, which is capable of being intensified almost at will and

    recursively reinsures communication through its own possibility (Luhmann 2000b, 1997:

    826ff.). This is the only reason why it could seem as if organisation were order

    epitomised: in the process of the recursive communication of decisions, it has found ways

    and means of committing and binding itself to those few conditions, which have proved

    themselves under these conditions. Put another way, it has found convincing grounds for

    excluding a world of possibilities, has developed a succession of suitable mechanisms

    (hierarchy, division of labour, routine, goal-setting) for, in actual fact, inhibiting these

    possibilities too, and legitimised all this under the viewpoint that the few realised

    possibilities (purposes, goals, products, processes) are, should they be retained, attractive

    enough for the members of the organisation and for the relevant non-members

    (commissioning clientle, customers, financiers, partners) and can be presented to the

    rest of the world as rational.

    But caution: all this is, as ever, only possible within the form of communication, that

    is, only within structures not only stipulating but also introducing degrees of freedom, not

    only describing efficiently and effectively pursuable goals, but also opening up a space of

    differentiation, which makes other goals imaginable. Hence it pays not to let ourselves be

    dazzled by organisations faades of order and to look in every single case, were it

    concerning a public authority, a university, a business, an association, an opera house, or

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    21/102

    70

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    a political party office, at how the participants get on with each other in their respective

    orders, deemed, as they are, organisations. Karl E. Weick has presented as concept,

    double interact, which permits describing how the perspectives of an organisations

    members, as they participate in it, have to be related to each other even under the most

    unlikely conditions of specific working practices, artificial hierarchies and as yet untested

    goal-settings, in order to be able to make sense, if only communally and only by

    acknowledging difference between them (Weick 1979: 110ff.). From that Niklas

    Luhmann has concluded that communication in the order of the organisation would, in

    principle, have to be at all times in a position to consider itself impossible, even outright

    insane and yet that is exactly what it has to be able to fortify itself against (Luhmann

    2000b: 141ff.). In other words, we really cannot deal with organisations ethnographically

    enough, accepting what is foreign, in order to do justice to the improbability they are

    capable of realising.

    In the order of society, the order of organisation makes a difference nowhere else

    apparent. Here, two points are remarkable. Firstly, organisation has to be in a position to

    justify its difference with a view to its members, the individuals participating in it. And

    secondly, the order of society, within which this order of organisation realises itself, has

    equally good grounds for espousing and allowing it, like interaction, which naturally also

    occurs massively in organisation.

    Interestingly, these two points are fulfilled in the form of one single condition.

    Organisation, and only organisation, allows orientating communication according to

    goals, that is, determining a future and, with a view to this future, treating things past

    always as present, like the space of possibilities for various options (Luhmann 2000,

    chap. 5). All other orders of society have to instead treat the future as open. Interactions

    can as little determine, were it not through organisation, who carries on, as someone

    present, having enough motives to participate in them, as societies can devise and shape

    what indeed becomes of them. And protest movements too cannot determine that their

    protest will be heard and abuses remedied. Only organisations determine their future by

    orientating themselves according to goals. Naturally, they can only do this for the reason

    that the future is unknown to them too and because they can, thanks to the channelling of

    their communication towards decisions, cancel these determinations and correct them in

    favour of other goals at almost any time and independently of deliberately invented

    strategic considerations.

    Fixing the organisation on a future, which is, in whatever form at all, always its

    future, makes the organisation attractive both for its members and for society watching it.

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    22/102

    71

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    We seek employment in and through organisations, because we can in that way reduce

    the uncertainty of the future or, respectively, replace it through the uncertainty of the

    organisations future, which is possibly better, because manageable in the self-integrating

    collective of the watchers. And in their social environment, all non-members of the

    organisation accept it, because only in this way can it be assured that tomorrow too there

    will still be possibilities for spiritual counselling from churches, provision of goods and

    services from businesses, treatment of the sick from hospitals, education from schools

    and warfare from the military. In this form, society accepts the importunities of organised

    behaviour and in this form the organisation orders, not least, society itself as well. It is

    hence not surprising, that society also takes organisations offer of order seriously in

    forms which overtax organisation, for instance, for securing what is taxable, for securing

    jobs or for securing chances of increasing income and wealth, even, in fact, for the dream

    of a being able to plan society.

    However, society and individual interactions intervening in the organisations offer of

    order does not mean that we would lose sight of the difference the organisation makes in

    society and vis--vis interaction. Admiring its order and capacity for collective action can

    at any time tip into criticism of the hierarchy. Being ready to rely on its capacity for

    reaching collectively binding differentiations always parallels dissatisfactions with its

    bureaucratic and undemocratic structures as if we could also have differentiations, if we

    secured them recursively through assuring uncommitted participation from everyone.

    Each society not least ensures that there are social buffers between the demands of the

    working world over typifying communication and the rest of societys ideas about

    acceptable forms of communication, which are often not compatible with such typifying

    (Udy 1959, 1970, 1990). In tribal societies, men returning from the bloody business of

    hunting are, first of all, cooled off in a quarantine station outside of the camp, before they

    come into contact with women, children and old people again. In the working societies of

    modern times, there is the institution of going to the pub, meanwhile rendered civilised as

    the blue hour, during which men, and increasingly women, can tell the heroic stories

    about what they would like to have experienced at work, which no-one believes at home.

    And if anyone finds the heroic stories too taxing, they can combine their evening errands

    with a stroll around the shops, which is equally well suited to rediscover themselves as

    sovereign over their own decisions, something they lost sight of in dealing with their

    superior. Extending and deregulating businesses opening hours falls in with this need

    and with the transformation of the chill out into an act of consuming.

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    23/102

    72

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    Organisation is order in the sense specified, namely in the sense of observing it

    establish itself and, for that very reason, in the possibility of its being cancelled.

    However, organisations order does show, perhaps in contrast to interactions order, that

    the operations of form amounting to cancellation or compensation cannot be achieved at

    one blow, in the framework of a stroke of the pen. Underlying each of these orders is a

    more or less comprehensible number of communications, which justify structures of

    expectation and are confirmed by structures of expectation reaching far beyond the

    respective order, namely into the order of society. That is why observing contingency, the

    possibility-of-being-otherwise of a form is one thing, cancelling it another. And that is

    why observing the possibility of a form, for instance, the founding idea of an

    organisation, is one thing and establishing it another. The history of revolutions, just as

    that of the capital markets, is also a history of more or less successful attempts to get rid

    of organisations of the state or of private enterprise respectively, that is, more elegantly

    expressed, to factor in exit options for them, as soon as they have installed themselves

    (Selznick 1952; Jensen 1993). We shall come back to organisations order in section 4.7.

    The overburdening of interaction by societys order and the more or less radical

    difference organisations order can set, may already be enough to account for society

    having sufficient cause to protest against itself. We can hence foresee also in societys

    order, alongside interaction, organisation and society as a whole (we will be coming back

    to that directly), an order of protest and then we always talk about a social movement or

    about a protest movement too, when communications appear, to which a protest against

    society lends a profile, which, interestingly, at least presupposes the same society being

    simultaneously accepted as condition for the possibility of protest.

    Protest movements, in this sense, range from revolts and peasants uprisings to the

    classical examples from modern society, namely workers movements, womens

    movements, peace movements and ecological movements, yet are meant to include less

    welcome manifestations like racist movements, fundamentalist movements or movements

    hostile to foreigners. Recently there have even been protest movements that protest

    against themselves: we can describe the globalisation movement as a movement

    appearing in the two mutually inimical forms of criticism of globalisation and of the

    reform movement, yet wanting in both forms the same thing, the democratically secured

    order of world society, about which we do not exactly know, if it is not identical with

    todays world society constituted of nations (Tilly 2004).

    Just as organisation, protest movements too do not depend on those present.

    Differently from organisation they do not, however, arrange to reach those absent through

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    24/102

    73

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    the formal condition of membership, but rather do so through the attractivity of the

    protest itself, that is, through turning the reasons why into scandals, through the vision of

    a better society and through the feelings of community resulting from ritualising and

    already staging, right now in anticipation, the possibility of a better society (including

    invoking feelings, which, as shown above, result from the intensification of expectations

    into demands). They have their degree of freedom in the protest, their conditions in its

    justification. Just like organisations, protest movements depend on reaching those absent

    stigmergetically, that is, via an environment which animates sufficiently many

    individuals, typically a mostly indeterminate number, to subscribe to the protests

    motives and its form of expression (Grass 1959; Bonabeau/Dorigo/Theraulaz 1999).

    That purpose is served by texts we read when we turn against the same thing, just as do

    chains of light, which we can join, and supporting payments, which not only help but also

    put our own motives to the test.

    On the other hand, it is true that protest movements order communication through

    society as something we can climb into and out of again. As a rule, we take care of our

    children or our parents parallel to the protest; we go to work, feed ourselves, travel and

    read other books from those of the movement. The other possibilities remain attractive,

    although they take place in the society we are protesting against. We can indeed then

    decide, whether our own parents, some colleagues, particular destinations or forms of

    nourishment actually participate in exactly that misery we are protesting against, but, as a

    rule, we will not protest against everything, and we do not for the reason that we would

    have to protest against our own protest. That is why we suggest setting down the form of

    protest as follows:

    That means the society we are protesting against is simultaneously affirmed, welcomedand confirmed as the one to which we owe our own motives, our encounters with like-

    minded others and the prospect of improvement (Adorno 1981). Describing the protest

    takes place in a space opened up by the acknowledgement of our own circumstances, for

    example, by describing these circumstances for what they are when seen from our own

    perspective. We communicate our protest with a sidelong glance at the affirmation, which

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    25/102

    74

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    allows not only finding our own protest good, but also finding the society good, that

    furnishes forms for protesting against it.

    It may be attractive for a while to look for forms of protest, which are so radical that

    the exterior of affirmation can be blacked out (for example, engaging in a terrorist

    organisation), or also for forms of protest capable of being linked to affirmation so easily,

    that we can live with them without the constant suspicion, we are not serious (for

    example, riding a bicycle). In each case, the form of the protest movement makes sure,

    that the protest against society takes place in society and is hence an option for ordering

    society itself. The protest makes sure, that society is complete, as Luhmann probably

    would formulate it: it now controls the possibility of its own negation as well (Benjamin

    1986; Luhmann 1981b). For its part, negation has, however, to be communicated; it is an

    operation by observers of the first order, who reckon, in their communicating, with

    observers of the second order, the like-minded, opponents and journalists, and hence

    commit themselves to society just like everyone else. But that is exactly what protest

    does indeed aim at: it protests against society, in order to change it, not quit it.

    Finally, the order of society itself. It epitomises the form of the social and in society

    once again appears in this form among the other forms of the social itself, because the

    condition of society being continued, of the social, can itself only be formulated in this

    way. In each specific form, in an interaction, an organisation or a protest movement,

    reflecting on the possibility of continuing communication always comes along too, as the

    thesis has it, under unspecific conditions, that is, ones still to be specified. We observe

    communication being limited by constellations of presence and absence, by the condition

    of membership or by the blinkers of protest and wish we could go on communicating

    under other conditions. And the other way round, we discover that we cannot do what we

    want with those present, that not even membership allows intervening fully and that

    protest gets stuck half way and contributes to a society, which meanwhile goes on

    communicating and, as a concomitant horizon of other possibilities, does not let itself be

    simply negated.

    Societys form inside the order of society is hence the how communication itself is

    marked, differentiated form its indeterminate exterior, which plays a role in all specific

    forms of the social only, but all the same, as exterior of the respective binary form:

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    26/102

    75

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    Or perhaps it is:

    In this form, the indeterminate itself becomes, as concomitant exterior of communication,

    an argument, that is, itself becomes an observation delineating the range of choice among

    possible communications. According to the situation in which we find ourselves, and

    according to the interlocutor we are dealing with, this argument can fascinate or horrify.

    Society means operating in the space of a differentiation, which is indeterminate as long

    as no communication is happening. Moments arise in communication, which make it

    clear, that we are communicating but could also desist, and that we are for exactly this

    reason moving in a space of possibilities, which do not exhaust the space of possibilities,

    but let it go along too as an indeterminate world. It is only in this moment, that is, only

    when looking at a society, which for this very reason appears as invisible as it is

    overwhelming, does communication itself become visible as a degree of freedom, about

    which no one knows who introduced it (as in the case of the world and of life, it is, with

    communication too, a matter of a unique invention), but about which all argue as to howit is to be stipulated.

    This is the point of connection for all kinds of religions, which already know, but then

    have to designate, who opened up or, respectively, revealed the indeterminate space,

    without that enabling them to establish anything other than options of human

    communication, which have repeatedly to prove themselves all over again in the face of

    this indeterminate situation. This is why the theologians know better than anyone how to

    designate something that at the same time has to remain indeterminate. The individuality

    of an individual, the intentionality of action, the in-between of inter-subjectivity or the

    risk of acknowledgement can, however, also be applied as needed. Here we presume a

    sort of source of communication, without thinking it possible that indeterminacy itself is

    quite enough to provide communication with motives for describing how it can possibly

    prolong itself (Waldenfels 1994). This is because it is only then that communication

    observes itself and will find what it needs.

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    27/102

    76

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    In tribal societies, what is indeterminate attracts attempts to control it by magic, in

    advanced civilisations it triggers utopian schemes and in present day society it adopts the

    form of insight into the futures uncertainty. And according to situation and interlocutor,

    this argument can be related, from as far away as possible, to society as a whole and,

    from as close as possible, to the situation and the interlocutor themselves. People suspect

    that arguing like this is the intellectuals stock-in-trade, whether they appear as shaman

    and magician, as humanist and scholar or as revolutionary and trend researcher. Each

    case concerns reflecting communications indeterminacy into communication and

    confronting communication with the outright need for continuity by unbalancing it

    (Fuller 2005). If we ask, how then can this need be handled every time, certain specific

    possibilities can and must be named, which in turn call other intellectuals, not satisfied

    with all that, onto the scene. What is indeterminate can be determined in many ways, but

    throughout it never quite loses the character of indeterminacy.

    Now, it is interesting, that this overall determining of society as a form of the social, is

    exploited, as an indeterminate possibility for continuing communication, semantically by

    intellectuals of all colours and, however, at the same time structurally by society itself.

    The intellectuals unsettling argument has its pendant in societys various forms of

    difference, in which what is indeterminate is accepted as such, localised and mirrored so

    often, that it can be reached from every structurally determined form of society. In the

    last few decades, various directions of research in sociology have described four such

    forms of difference: tribal society, empires, advanced civilisations, and modern society

    (Schimank 2000; Luhmann 1997: chap. 4). In individual cases, these forms cut across

    each other, but, with regard to addressing and localising what is not determined to use it

    for communication, they can be differentiated exactly enough. That also goes historically.

    These four forms make a particular historical progression is unmistakable; conversely,

    however, our historical consciousness has got used to considering simultaneous what is

    not as conceivable and factual, so that we know how far the communicative possibilities

    of tribal society, of empires and of advanced civilisations persist among us.

    In tribal society, our own tribe is determinate and all other tribes are not. We know

    they exist and we consider the other tribes particular forms of living barbaric and every

    form of warlike confrontation, economic cheating and abducting of women justified.

    Nevertheless, our most exact knowledge about the danger of boundaries, the possibility

    of infection, the need for conjuration and how sensitive marking out transitional

    situations and stations is, all of which together amount to a dramatics of practical, social

    and temporal differentiations, where the communication of things differentiated from

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    28/102

    77

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    each other is less hindered than much rather orchestrated (Leach 1976). That our own

    tribe is determined not only secures this, but endangers it also, because what our tribe

    differs from is too indeterminate.

    In an empire, a Reich, the centre of power is determined religiously, economically,

    politically and not least bureaucratically, and the chance of building in gradations,

    including the possibility of shifting the borders due to further conquests, renders the

    periphery all the more indeterminate the further we progress outwards. We act in the full

    awareness of our own power and we know how this power is acknowledged throughout

    the empire, yet we assume, both rulers and subjects, that power ends at the border of the

    empire, hence becomes impotent. In this form it can be reflected back into the empire

    again, in order to find out how we can evade power, how we can subvert it or how we can

    mount a resistance likely to succeed, and naturally also, how we can build power up

    again. With the last of these, for example, creating addresses on the periphery can be

    decisive, ones reachable for our own communications in the dimensions we consider

    important and ones that, for their part, order the periphery with regard to the centre that

    speaks to it (Dobbins 2003).

    In advanced civilisations, our own respective social level, the level of the nobility, the

    clergy and the peasants, certainly later of the bourgeoisie too, is indeterminate from the

    perspective of all individuals and from that of each individual level. We know how to

    behave as nobility, as priest or as peasant. However, we deem the others behaviour as

    much remarkable as incomprehensible. The bourgeoisie is the level untypical in this

    regard and it explodes the schema and hence the societys form of differentiation, and

    does comes upon the idea first that we can also then imitate the behaviour of another

    level, when, beyond just laughing at the others as usual, we seriously mean it. To become

    typified individually, we have to stop resembling the others in our own level any more,

    yet all we have to do is copy selectively what we can use. The bourgeoisie begins by

    imitating the nobility and then, however, introduces, with increasing uncertainty over the

    question of what its identity is, the possibility of imitating the peasants and the workers as

    well, reaching a high point in theBiedermeier idyll, which amalgamates the behavioural

    forms of the nobility (social life), the peasants (bound to the soil), trade (local loyalties)

    and the workers (industriousness) into a scarcely very durable form.

    In the advanced civilisation of a stratified society, social inequality hence only means,

    that we know the behavioural pattern by which to orientate ourselves - or not to.

    Communication between the levels is limited to a few forms (the lord and his coachman,

    the lady and her gardener, the duke out hunting and the girl gathering mushrooms in the

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    29/102

    78

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    woods), which are soon not enough any more, as society becomes more complex, and we

    have to know how we can deal with teachers, judges and pharmacists, and, the other way

    round, with schoolchildren, accused people and customers, without treating them

    according to the behavioural patterns of incompatible levels.

    But in an advanced civilisation, we naturally also communicate about two things,

    about what is determinate for our level and what is not for the other, and we bring along

    cosmological notions describing how one fits in with the other, they being, however,

    unknown to each other and allowed to remain so. Karl Marxs theory of the capitalist

    class society is a remarkable outgrowth from this social form of advanced civilisation, as

    it differentiates two classes, both of which, in a Hegelian manner, derive their

    determining factors from their respective counterpart (the proletarian as non-capitalist,

    the capitalist as non-proletarian), and lose sight of all other classes, above all of the

    consuming, voting, managing and self-generating bourgeoisie.

    What should additionally be noted is how from the beginning (Babylon) the social

    form of the city cuts somewhat across societys large scale and dominating forms of

    differentiation, yet fulfils the schema of the binary form of determinacy and

    indeterminacy precisely. Plat already discovers in his dialogue Politeia, that empirical

    variety (equalling indeterminacy?) abides the necessity of ascertaining its just order (To

    each his own!) only with difficulty (Politeia 427ff.). But it is only Max Weber, who first

    brings up the point that challenge of but also the achievement of urban life consists in

    strangers being able and having to live here with each other, in complete contrast to

    relations in the tribe, the clan and the feudal hierarchies (Weber 1958). And only the

    concept of the ecology of the city, which Chicago city sociology develops in the 1920s

    (Burgess/McKenzie/Park 1967), formulated first of all how the social order of city

    defines itself via local and functional neighbourhoods, markets and news networks

    (rumours, stories, mass media), which combine perfectly with the fact that the citys

    order as a whole is indeterminable.

    Hence the city also is a social order, which establishes and cancels itself. We engage

    with it communicatively, that is, in our behaviour, in our observations and in our feelings,

    because we tolerate living together with strangers and the way we do it, but only as long

    as certain forms and rituals, described as civilised, are to hand and permit getting to know

    the strangers. However, by contrast too, it then counts as particularly cultivated to treat

    acquaintances as strangers again in specific respects, for example, with reference to their

    political preferences, their income, their taste in art, the intensity of their faith and their

    erotic inclinations. Monotheistic religions are invented, so that city-dwellers, certain

  • 8/8/2019 Baecker - 2008 - Form and Forms of Communication(2)

    30/102

    79

    Dirk Baecker, Form and Forms of Communication

    pariahs excluded, can come together for acts of worship, which do not recall the gods of

    tribal society and the ancestors of clans (Weber 1958). And queuing at the bread shop, at

    bus stops and at box offices is invented so that we can tolerate situations shared together

    without having to find out if the other is friend or foe. It is quite enough to be able to treat

    them as strangers, whose origins are cosmopolitan and hence indeterminate and the

    conditions for whose staying here are municipally determined (with liberal spaces for

    action and excluding marginal groups) (Stichweh 1992).

    In its social form, the city is something like the form of society re-entering into

    society. That is because the city renders indeterminate what tribes, clans, centres and

    social levels have just been getting into order, whilst other things are newly determined

    (trade and transport, education and culture, career and individuality), which hence start

    looking for their indeterminate exteriors in modern society, as it is called, perhaps for that

    reason (Tilly 1992: 54ff.). With the city, the binary form of being determined and

    undetermined becomes so much of a fractal, a self-identical and multiply scalable

    structure of society, that city and society can finally establish themselves as

    undetermined, although every individual expectation of expectation capable of

    structuring a possible communicative event, that is, connecting it with others, is always

    and fundamentally determined. In other words, city and society are treated as mod