barbara herman (2006) reasoning to obligation

21
 This article was downloaded by: [Universidad Autonoma Metropolitana] On: 05 March 2015, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/sinq20 Reasoning to Obligation Barbara Herman a a  University of California , Los Angeles, USA Published online: 20 Aug 2006. To cite this article: Barbara Herman (2006) Reasoning to Obligation, Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy , 49:1, 44-61, DOI: 10.1080/00201740500497415 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00201740500497415 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content.

Upload: natalia-wolfgang

Post on 06-Oct-2015

5 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

If, as Kant says, ‘‘the will is practical reason’’, we should think of willingas a mode of reasoning, and its activity represented in movement from evaluativepremises to intention by way of a validity-securing principle of inference. Such a view ofwilling takes motive and rational choice out of empirical psychology, therebyeliminating grounds for many familiar objections to Kant’s account of morally goodaction. The categorical imperative provides the fundamental principle of valid practicalinference; however, for good willing, we also require correct premises. These come fromspecifications of the two obligatory ends – our own perfection and the happiness ofothers. Interpreting good willing as good reasoning not only fits well with Kant’smetaphysics of free action, it also offers a sound method for reasoning to and aboutindividual as well as role-dependent moral obligations.

TRANSCRIPT

  • This article was downloaded by: [Universidad Autonoma Metropolitana]On: 05 March 2015, At: 08:10Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T3JH, UK

    Inquiry: An InterdisciplinaryJournal of PhilosophyPublication details, including instructions forauthors and subscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/sinq20

    Reasoning to ObligationBarbara Herman aa University of California , Los Angeles, USAPublished online: 20 Aug 2006.

    To cite this article: Barbara Herman (2006) Reasoning to Obligation,Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 49:1, 44-61, DOI:10.1080/00201740500497415

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00201740500497415

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of allthe information (the Content) contained in the publications on ourplatform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensorsmake no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy,completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views ofthe authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis.The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should beindependently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor andFrancis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings,demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoeveror howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, inrelation to or arising out of the use of the Content.

  • This article may be used for research, teaching, and private studypurposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution,reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any formto anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use canbe found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • Reasoning to Obligation

    BARBARA HERMAN

    University of California, Los Angeles, USA

    (Received 31 October 2005)

    ABSTRACT If, as Kant says, the will is practical reason, we should think of willingas a mode of reasoning, and its activity represented in movement from evaluativepremises to intention by way of a validity-securing principle of inference. Such a view ofwilling takes motive and rational choice out of empirical psychology, therebyeliminating grounds for many familiar objections to Kants account of morally goodaction. The categorical imperative provides the fundamental principle of valid practicalinference; however, for good willing, we also require correct premises. These come fromspecifications of the two obligatory ends our own perfection and the happiness ofothers. Interpreting good willing as good reasoning not only fits well with Kantsmetaphysics of free action, it also offers a sound method for reasoning to and aboutindividual as well as role-dependent moral obligations.

    In this paper, I propose to set out an attractive simplification of some basic

    elements of Kants moral philosophy. My focus will be on the familiar idea

    of the will as practical reason, but I will emphasize its active mode, as a

    faculty of practical reasoning. It is a small shift, but one that resounds. The

    plan is to walk through the simplified account, to point out some obvious

    advantages it offers for defusing familiar objections, and to indicate some of

    what would have to be the case for the account to work. I will not often

    touch down on stretches of text; most of what I will be talking about is very

    well known. What I say will often be close to what others have said about

    Kants theory, just put in an unusually literal way; the upshot is significantly

    different because the simplification resists psychologizing Kants account of

    moral action and motivation. That allows us to lay some worn worries to

    rest, and redirect our attention to more interesting questions.

    In the spirit of Kant to Hegel, I will at the end briefly discuss a problem

    that joins with one of Hegels criticisms of Kants ethics, and which is of

    Correspondence Address: Barbara Herman, Department of Philosophy, UCLA, Los Angeles

    CA 90095-1451, USA. Email: [email protected]

    Inquiry,

    Vol. 49, No. 1, 4461, February 2006

    0020-174X Print/15023923 Online/06/01004418 # 2006 Taylor & Francis

    DOI: 10.1080/00201740500497415

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • concern in its own right. The problem arises from a fact that Hegels own

    ethics starts from, and that he believes Kant did not fully appreciate: that

    most of our obligations are set by social roles of various sorts doctor,

    parent, soldier, clerk. Ordinary moral life would not make sense otherwise.

    The problem is that the institutions that set the social terms of our actions

    may not be morally benign, even if they fill a morally necessary social

    function (that is, they fill it badly). So the question naturally arises about the

    limits of these socially-determined obligations. It may not be clear that we

    can think about any of this from within Kants ethics. Kant doesnt

    talk much about such issues; the discussion in the essay What is

    Enlightenment? should make us hesitant to judge Kant unaware of them,

    but its uneasy solution, balancing freedom of thought and obedience, is

    not broadly illuminating. My conjecture is that features of the simplified

    view amplify the resources Kantian theory has to make room for the

    embeddedness of ordinary moral life in social roles and practices, while at

    the same time preserving the kind of autonomous authority and individual

    responsibility that is, if anything is, a touchstone of Kants moral theory.

    I. The Basic Picture

    Suppose the identification of the will with practical reason amounts to (at

    least in part) the claim that in the realm of action and choice (including the

    setting of ends) we are to come to action by reasoning appropriately. When

    our action follows from correct reasoning we act well. A good wills good

    willing is then in its correct reasoning about action; this is what it means to

    say that its goodness is in its principle. The terminus of practical reasoning

    or willing is an intention to act or refrain from acting; the intention is

    normally completed in action (unless it is impeded, or there is conflict or

    weakness of will).

    If good willing is a mode of good reasoning, then to understand good

    willing we need to attend to what makes for good reasoning a matter of

    getting it right about premises and about appropriate principles of inference:

    warranted transitions from thought to thought, thought to belief, thought to

    intention or choice (or between the propositions or sentences that represent

    them). Anything that counts as reasoning will involve that. In the moral

    case, it need not be easy to grasp what the appropriate premises and

    principles are, only that it is premises and principles of inference that we

    seek. Later on I will make a case that the two obligatory ends identified in

    the Metaphysics of Morals determine correct premises. It is not much of a

    reach to see the principles of the practical imperatives (however many there

    are) as the candidate principles of inference. I think it is obvious that Kant

    views the principle that underlies the categorical imperative (the principle of

    the formula of universal law) as the ultimate standard or most basic

    Reasoning to Obligation 45

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • principle of practical inference: the principle that sets final terms of validity

    for the movement of thought from practical premises to intention to act.

    Heres what reasoning to obligation looks like.1 Someone has given me

    something of value to hold for her (a deposit), but she dies before its date of

    return. No one else knows I have it. Correct practical reasoning takes me

    from some complex evaluative premise about possession to some conclusion

    about what is to be done by way of a principle or rule of inference that in itsmost abstract form says: act only on that maxim that can at the same time

    be willed a universal law. When, by contrast, my proposed principle is to

    increase my property by every safe means when that is my maxim then

    my reasoning by way of my maxim from the premise of possession to

    keeping the deposit involves a contradiction in just the sense that it would if

    I reasoned in some way to not q, when I knew that both p, and if p then q,

    were the case.

    A couple of cautionary points. I am assuming that for Kant there is nobarrier to talking about principles of inference in this broader way: that is,

    that we are not restricted to the patterns of reasoning warranted by logical

    connectives, modes ponens and the like, to what can count as a legitimate

    principle of inference. Part of Kants purpose in insisting on the possibility

    of synthetic a priori judgment is to extend the domain of necessary

    connection between cognitions. So, for example, the category of causality

    warrants our regarding some temporal sequences as involving cause and

    effect; we can of course be wrong about which sequences are properlyrepresented as warranting the causal inference this so then that, but we

    could not even be wrong unless we were warranted in forming causal

    hypotheses. Downstream, we will encounter specific laws laws of gasses,

    the laws of thermodynamics, etc. which are, ideally, empirically articulated

    instances of the general a priori principle. It all gets very complicated as we

    move into science, but the basic point the point that Hume denies and

    Kant asserts is that causal reasoning, reasoning that maps the idea of

    necessary connection between events, is possible. Moral reasoning involves aparallel story.

    Second, for purposes of laying things out, I will just accept Kants basic

    claim about the generation of action: that a human rational agent has the

    dual capacity to be moved by either inclinations or rational considerations.

    That is, we have the ability to take our inclinations as giving us reasons to

    act, and then, with a bit of means-end deliberation, form an appropriate

    intention. Or, we can start the chain of reasoning elsewhere in rational

    premises and decide on the appropriateness of an intended action byattending, as Kant would say, to our maxims form, not merely its matter.

    (We can also start in inclination and constrain our action by a rational

    standard. This is the space where permissible action resides.)

    With just this much, for now ignoring what the correct moral premises are

    (but assuming there are some), and not worrying about the specific form of

    46 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • moral inference, we can say some significant things about reasoning to

    obligation. If a good will is a will that acts on or out of correct reasoning

    about action, then someones finding an action difficult or easy is irrelevant

    to the question whether there has been good willing. Similarly, a morally

    worthy action is commendable independently of effort or cost, whether it is

    welcomed or disliked, simply as it is a dutiful action intended as such as the

    result of correct reasoning to it. We may have reasons to admire personswho are able to be rational in the face of apathy or adversity, but that is a

    very different kind of commendation than the judgment of correctness in

    reasoning to action (we might equally commend someone who can think

    clearly about physics in the midst of distracting noise or lack of sleep). We

    can then restate the second proposition about moral worth2 as, simply: an

    action has moral worth if and only if the intention to do what is morally

    required is the result of good i.e. correct reasoning. That is what it is to

    act from duty. An action that merely accords with duty, while the rightthing to do, is arrived at some other way, from a principle about ones own

    interest, or for the sake of some further end, etc. One gets the right result,

    but not for the right reasons.

    One might wonder whether or in what way it matters that the reasoning is

    easy or difficult. Kant thought the reasoning required of a moral agent was

    accessible to the ordinary person (perhaps through the use of deliberative

    heuristics, a subject we will return to). Many if not most impediments to

    correct deliberation occur prior to reasoning to action in settling whichmoral considerations bear and in what way (the killing is not murder but

    pre-emptive self-defense; the promise is a lie but the circumstances are

    exceptional). But there surely will be difficult cases, where it is hard to figure

    out what to do. A first thing to say is that while norms of correct reasoning

    frame problem-solving, they are not a problem-solving device. Their good

    use depends on practical knowledge. Just as when I want the roof to stop

    leaking, while its a simple step to the conclusion that it has to be repaired,

    whether it needs a patch or to be replaced is not a question this reasoningcan answer, though the right answer will have the rational form of leak-

    stopping roof-repair. If I dont already know a lot about roofs, I call for

    expert advice. There has to be a place for technical or casuistical expertise in

    morals as well as roof-repair. It can make sense to seek advice to clarify the

    issues we may be facing, and, sometimes, directly about what to do. But

    none of this bears on whether we reason well, given what we know or accept:

    that is entirely up to us. I think we cannot be taken to be engaged in moral

    reasoning at all if we cannot grasp what we do in terms that are connected tomoral norms of reasoning; so the reasoning cannot be too demanding.

    Insofar as one reasons to action in accordance with a moral norm or

    principle, there is no extra step of commitment or volition required to get

    from maxim to action, nor any further conception of the action as morally

    required that is not already present in the reasoning. Correctly reasoning to

    Reasoning to Obligation 47

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • a promise-keeping intention, I will keep my promise, other things equal, and

    I will conceive of what I do as required by the promise. There is also nothing

    moralistic or oddly impersonal involved in coming to act in this way.

    Recognizing As situation of need as one that makes a moral claim on me, I

    act for As sake, not for the sake of duty, though I arrive at the intention to

    help A by reasoning from a recognition of As moral claim. My intention

    carries its value source, which inflects what I aim to bring about. This willshow in the urgency with which I act, the costs I am prepared to bear, and

    the way I negotiate other moral demands I may have.

    We are now in position to dispose of the vexing pair of issues about the

    moral worth of dutiful actions: can actions have moral worth when they are

    the product of good but nonmoral motives, and must they lack moral

    worth if overdetermined by concurrent moral and nonmoral motives? On the

    good or correct reasoning account, neither issue can properly arise. Consider,

    first, the claim that motivation by one of the positive emotions, such assympathy, can compete with acting from duty for assignment of moral worth

    to an agents action. If moral worth signals correct reasoning to a morally

    required action, on no account of an emotion as a motive is it a course of

    reasoning or even an element of one. Emotions can be important for correct

    reasoning, but as sources of information for the premises, or as something

    that can facilitate reasoning. The claim on behalf of the emotions is not

    stronger if an action arises from a maxim grounded in an emotion (I make it

    my principle to act as sympathy prompts...). If, as Kant clearly holds, bothpremises and principle of the maxim must be a priori justified if the reasoning

    is to be moral and the willing good, then any emotion-based maxim is

    disqualified because it is a maxim with empirical grounds or premises.

    The problem about emotions as motives and moral worth will seem acute

    if one thinks there is another modular motive the motive of duty that

    plays an analogous causal role: moving us to act towards an object that the

    motive picks out. If the motive of duty were some kind of attachment to

    doing the right thing or doing the right thing because it is the rightthing, then doing that right thing out of some emotion-based care or

    concern could seem equally good or admirable or, as many have thought,

    better. But acting from duty is not acting from any such motive of

    attachment to duty; it is acting or intending from correct reasoning. There

    may be, as Kant allows, all sorts of reasons to value acting from certain

    emotions; but assigning moral worth to actions from feeling is to make a

    category mistake.

    It is then easy to understand the further claim that a maxim of duty a maxim that expresses a course of moral reasoning about action has a

    different content than a maxim that arises from emotion, or a course of (e.g.

    instrumental) reasoning prompted by emotion. This is the point Kant makes

    about sympathy and the inclination to honor: no maxim of acting from

    either has moral content because the reasoning to action they support is not

    48 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • moral reasoning neither premises nor principle of inference are moral.3

    (One might act from sympathy or honor on condition that ones actions

    were permissible. That the condition on action is a moral one does not make

    the intention a moral intention.) When we think of the philanthropic man

    whose mind is overclouded by grief, who is able nonetheless to be beneficent

    from duty, or the person of cold temperament who acts from duty, we are to

    think of someone reasoning well, of getting something right for the rightreasons, in less than optimal conditions. This is not an especially moral

    virtue, though moral virtue depends on it. In any of the domains where

    getting something right for the right reasons matters, we are often impressed

    when someone reasons well in a direction not supported by, or opposed by,

    her interests or feelings.

    Now, about overdetermination of action by concurrent motives. Is it

    inappropriate or less good, less morally worthy, to act from duty and

    sympathy? Again, this is a problem that should not have seemed difficult toresolve. If we are focused on the overdetermination of an action qua event,

    we will tend to see the action as coming about in more than one way, as the

    possible effect of more than one cause; it then seems natural to ask, Which

    motive, which cause, is the cause? In response to the question put this way,

    I once argued that the cause is the motive in whose terms the agent conceives

    of what she does, or the one that she is committed to acting on.4 So long as it

    is morality that guides his will, the agents action has moral worth.

    However, if the concurrent motives in question are competing modes ofconcern, or even just competing causes, it can seem difficult to assign just

    one of them authority in ones action. There then seems to be required

    something like a higher-order motive to make the motive of duty the motive

    that matters. But then why assign moral worth to the primary motive of

    duty in circumstances of overdetermination when it is the second-order

    motive that is, so to speak, getting it right for the agent if it is the motive in

    control? Apart from this not being Kants view, it is also not a very good

    strategy of argument, given familiar problems about the iteration ofoverdetermination at the higher level. One could, and I did, insist that

    without appeal to second-order anything, it is intelligible that we have

    multiple motives active in us and yet not act on some of them in the

    instance. Though an action may be in our interest, even one we would take

    for our interest were the circumstances different, as things are, we sometimes

    want to insist that we are moved to action by a different motive. Some might

    speak of commitment, integrity, endorsement. Or we might talk about how

    we would be guided in certain counterfactual situations. Neither is acomfortable answer.

    But if moral worth marks good willing as good reasoning, and the upshot

    of good reasoning is an intention (not the action separate from the intention

    or maxim), then in circumstances where there is a motive of a different sort

    sufficient to bring about the required action, that motive yields a different

    Reasoning to Obligation 49

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • intention (intentions getting their content from the motivational source or

    reasoning that leads to them). And if it is a different intention, there is no

    overdetermination problem. That one action can realize multiple intentions

    does not make it murky whether I act with the moral intention derived from

    good reasoning. The authority of the moral intention comes with the

    reasoning that supports it: that is, it is part of the content of the reasoning to

    intention in the moral case that if an action is by this reasoning required,then one sees it as required, and acts independent of this or that contending

    or cooperating motive. That in some sense one could have acted contrary to

    the dictates of good reasoning does not impugn its authority or its effect on

    ones intention when one reasons well.

    This point is not peculiar to the moral case. Evidence for or against some

    empirical proposition p is not in competition with the utility of believing

    that p. Perhaps my sympathy for you, or my desire for your friendship,

    makes me want to believe that though you caused harm, you meant well; itwas just an accident. When I investigate, I find that the evidence clearly

    points away from a deliberate doing. I am pleased by that outcome. But if I

    have fairly evaluated the evidence if I have reasoned well then the fact

    that I come to believe in the right way what I want to believe anyway does

    not impugn my warrant for the belief. Counterfactual possibilities about

    what would have happened had desire and reasoning come apart may say

    something about me, about my epistemic virtue, perhaps, but nothing about

    how I reasoned when, as it happened, I reasoned well.Likewise, my willingness to cheat in some competitive activity does not

    imply that when I do not maybe Im just better than everyone else that I

    didnt fairly gain my victory. Norms of practices and games prohibit

    behaviors, not long-range conditional intentions. In general, openness to

    civil- or norm-disobedience does not undermine the quality of ones lawful

    actions.5 What distinguishes morality on the good reasoning model from

    other norm-governed activities is that the willingness not to follow the rules

    for the sake of some actual or possible purpose is proscribed by the rulesthemselves. Not because there is a meta-rule in morality, but because the

    (moral) rule of good reasoning is authoritative in the domain it governs, and

    the domain in question is all of intentional action.

    II. Refinements

    In focusing on the interpretive issues surrounding the companion ideas of

    good willing and acting from duty, we have in effect been closing in onKants notion of motive especially the possible determination of our will

    independent of sensory impulses (of desire in the narrow sense) and by

    reason. The natural next step is to take a closer look at the elements

    involved in correct reasoning, and the powers of agency necessary to

    support them.

    50 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • If we consider the agents maxim, which represents her reasoning to

    action, the elements represented are an intention to act related to a desired

    end, and a motivating ground that gives the agents conception of the ends

    value. The relation between intended action and end is either instrumental

    or constitutive; the relation between end and motive is explanatory, and,

    ideally, also rationally justifying. Since the motivating ground provides

    the evaluative content of the maxim the respect in which the agent sees theaction-end pair as good (and so to be realized) it must be an element of the

    agents practical reasoning, either as a premise or in the principle(s) of

    inference (or both). In good willing both premises and the rule of inference

    are a priori rational; it then must be possible for the motivating ground to be

    a priori rational too. But if, as Kant maintains, the principle of pure

    practical reason fully determines good willing, it must then in some sense

    provide both the principle of inference and the necessary practical premises.

    This is possible if (and only if) the principle of pure practical reason is theconstitutive principle or law of our power of free that is, not empirically

    determined choice. And it is.

    It is a further and essential fact that the role of the principle is not limited to

    moral action; the same principle is also constitutive of our most basic

    evaluative ability: to make and respond to comparative judgments.6 A

    comparative judgment is not just a matter of liking one thing more than

    another animals do that but of judging one thing better than another on

    some rational ground and being determined to action by way of that judgment(determined, not caused). The development of our general ability to make

    evaluative judgments, and so also of our ability to reason from what we judge

    good or better to action, is a process as natural in us as our coming to see the

    world in causal terms.7 What can be misleading is that we dont start our

    evaluative lives with a complete concept of the rational grounds of choice;

    rational abilities not only can but must be able to inform cognition without

    our having a full or reflective grasp of their constitutive principles. Part of the

    normal work of human cognitive development is gaining more explicit andfuller understanding of concepts already at work in our experience.

    Drawing on an analogy to the categories of experience, we should say that

    the principle or law of practical reason the a priori concept of the rational

    will is the possibility condition of all evaluative practical judgment (and so

    all choice for a reason). Its role is not to fully determine what we judge good

    or bad, but to make it the case that our judgments are evaluative judgments

    that they have a certain form, and so are answerable to formal standards.

    Although the initial mode of evaluative judgment is comparative, it wouldbe a mistake to regard better than as any kind of primitive, or as pointing

    to an independent evaluative norm. It is to be understood as a partial

    representation of, as well as a developmentally early step in acquiring access

    to, the full concept of the good (that is, the concept of the object of the

    law-constituted will). Better than points beyond itself, though in an

    Reasoning to Obligation 51

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • indeterminate way. In its formal function, the partial representation makes

    possible the ordered structure of preferences necessary for an idea of

    happiness, as well as the proto-moral intuitions and responses that

    characterize our early relationships with others (judging something better,

    we become sensitive to infringements on choice; a bit later, when

    comparison involves others, we are concerned about unfairness and

    inequality). When conjoined with other developmental pressures to putorder in desire-satisfaction e.g., to accommodate our awareness of the

    extended temporal horizon of a life we are drawn towards more complex

    evaluations and to the acquisition of various skills of reflection and self-

    management. And as we become aware of the extension of our evaluative

    and practical abilities, our effective power of choice is transformed. The

    process is only completed when the agent takes on the standard of judgment

    provided by the moral law. Ideally, from the point of view of practical

    reason, a healthy agent will have an integrated conception of the good,one that subordinates her concern for happiness to the authority of the

    fundamental law of practical reasoning.8

    Our next step is to integrate these elements of the account of rational

    agency into the basic moral story. We start with the evaluative capacities

    that structure our apprehension of actions and objects of action under

    rational concept(s) that determine choice. In so apprehending actions and

    objects, we value them. As with other basic conceptual tasks, the tools that

    make them possible are not neutral about their own proper use: that is, wedo not have ultimate discretion about how we evaluate objects and ways of

    acting there are standards. Of course, given the nature of our evaluative

    capacities, their dependence on other capacities, and our less than complete

    grasp of their principle, we go wrong in matters of value in various ways. We

    can err because we fail to judge particulars correctly, but we can also

    mislead ourselves about their evaluative valence: we can be biased in our

    appreciation of options or costs; we can miss or discount information we

    dont want to consider. In all such cases we exercise rational choice (that iswhy we are rightly held responsible for what we do), but exercise alone does

    not imply success in reasoning or willing well.

    In the normal case, relatively general judgments of value provide evaluative

    premises of practical reasoning. We think: this is a kind of thing worth

    having, that good to avoid; we reason from the evaluative premise to an

    intention to act, according to a principle of practical inference.9 Because the

    same (material) end can be represented in different ways merely as an object

    of desire, as an object judged more important than others, as an object ofdesire whose pursuit is subject to moral constraint, or as an object of moral

    requirement agents who appear to have the same end will reason from

    different premises (though not necessarily to different actions). How an agent

    reasons is typically signaled by her apprehension of the evaluative content of

    her premise in what sense she regards the object of her action as good.

    52 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • It is natural to interpret Kant as holding that when agents reason in these

    different ways, they follow different practical principles instrumental,

    prudential, or moral. I believe this is misleading. Despite talk of hypo-

    thetical imperatives, there doesnt seem to be a distinct principle of this sort

    that is, one that applies to and is not implied by willing an end. There are

    actions and intentions to which we are committed in adopting an end, but

    not because of a separate principle of practical inference. In adopting anend, we already conceive of ourselves as its proximate or at least initiating

    instrumental cause; questions that remain are technical, about the details of

    effective action. This aspect of practical rationality is thus not exhibited in

    reasoning from ends, but in satisfying the conditions of end adoption.

    Having adopted an end, any end, our practical reasoning has instrumental

    form that is, it goes from an end-related premise to an intention to act (to

    promote or act with respect to the end).

    There may seem to be a better case for the principle of prudence as aseparate practical principle. The mark of an independent principle is that it is

    directive independently of the specific ends we adopt. Since each of us is

    motivated to shape our life such that it will be, as best we can manage it, an

    object of satisfaction, once we form an idea of our happiness and make it our

    end, we get reasons both to do things and to adopt ends. But this is not the

    kind of separateness that marks an independent principle. First, it is nothing

    about the end of happiness that gives us reason to adopt ends, it is simply that it

    is a complex end, requiring subordinate ends as means.10 And second, insofaras there are distinctive counsels of prudence, they are no more than empirical

    generalizations about how best to form and pursue an idea of happiness.

    The status of the principle of practical inference in the moral case is

    delicate it is in one sense separate, not implied by our willing any thing, but

    it also cannot be independent of our will. Under the law of morality, the

    connection of the deed with the will is a priori, independent of any

    inclination. There must therefore be, Kant argues, a practical proposition

    that does not derive the volition of an action analytically from anothervolition already presupposed (for we have no such perfect will), but connects

    it immediately with the concept of the will of a rational being as something

    that is not contained in it (G 420n). That is, a principle of practical

    reasoning can show an intention necessary (derive it), not from a

    presupposed willed end, but from something about the nature of our

    rational will. Although the metaphysics of this claim is difficult, what is

    claimed fits nicely with the basic view I am presenting. There is one, and

    only one, principle of valid reasoning that takes us from premises (ends) ofwhatever sort to intentions.

    If an a priori principle of willing is immediately connected to the

    concept of the will of a rational being, then conformity to the principle is

    essential to rational willing.11 Then to say of a maxim, or volition of action,

    that it cannot be derived from the concept of the will of a rational being is at

    Reasoning to Obligation 53

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • least to say that it is in some way inconsistent with the a priori principle of

    rational willing. So if one erroneously supposed that ones maxim was

    consistent with the a priori principle that it was (in conformity with) a

    valid principle of rational willing methods of good reasoning ought to be

    able to show a contradiction. Unhappily, we cannot follow this direction,

    not having an adequate cognition of the a priori principle or of how to apply

    it (this is in the argument Of the Typic of Pure Practical Reason, (KpV6770)). But we are not without resources.

    The task is assigned to the two tests of the formula of the law of nature.

    By showing that a given maxim lacks the form of a possible law of (human

    rational) nature, they show a fortiori that it is inconsistent with the a priori

    principle of rational willing. We can think of the tests as the moral analogue

    of truth trees, a heuristic for a priori rational inference. If the heuristic is

    valid, in using it one is reasoning as one should. So while we cannot tell

    which principles are the principles that all rational wills could rationally will,we can show that some principles could not be rationally willed (e.g., a

    maxim whose instrumental success noncontingently depends on its not being

    willed by all). More precisely, the tests are a device of representation, a

    projection of the bare idea of universal form in reasoning into a modality we

    can employ. In speaking of a projection, I have in mind literal projections,

    like maps. We cannot get around the city carrying a three-dimensional

    model of the city, but we can with an abstract two-dimensional map. Using

    the map we judge accurately about how to get from here to there, thoughnot about what well see when we get there. I take the idea of using a law of

    nature as a heuristic to be just such a projection. Thinking about what

    cannot be or be willed a law of (rational) nature allows us to say if a

    principle of volition could not be derived from an a priori law of reason.

    If the formula of the law of nature is a heuristic in this sense, we should

    expect it to contain elements that are not present in the thing it represents, and

    to lack elements that the thing represented has. So it will be no objection at all if

    the argument-forms inside the projection use, for example, prudential orinstrumental practical considerations within the conditions of the device of

    representation. It is what we should expect. In trying to work out what follows

    from the bare idea of a universal law of reason, the materials we have to work

    with are laws of nature, including our psychology, and empirical modes of

    practical reasoning. The two tests allow us to manipulate material that we know

    how to think about to produce conclusions that apply in a domain we cannot

    think about directly.12 Whether the law of nature tests are an accurate device of

    representation is another matter. My purpose here is only to explain the kindof thing they are intended to be such that they could aid us in moral judgment.

    It is important to emphasize that even though the formula of the law of

    nature is a projection of the a priori principle of rational willing, because of

    the limits of what it can show, conformity to its standard is only a necessary

    condition of good willing. Maxims it allows can fail to have a moral premise

    54 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • (this is to say: permissibility is not sufficient for good willing). We will return

    to this.

    Having connected ideas of evaluation with an a priori principle and a

    method of judgment, we can put another set of chronic questions to rest.

    When we think of practical cognition as choice under some evaluative

    concept, given the possibility of knowingly contra-moral choice, it seems

    hard to show that the way we cognize or choose our actual standard of

    choice is, contrary to appearances, not up to us. It can look as though we

    need an additional principle or an act of endorsement to secure the adoption

    of the moral law as authoritative for me, for each individual. But there

    cannot be such an act of principled choosing (there are no terms of choice

    for it), nor is any sort of bare endorsement intelligible.13 But if it is the

    principle of practical reason that makes evaluative or practical cognition

    and so choice possible, it is not a standard we can do without (or replace

    with one of our own). Fundamental powers are normative for their exercise.

    Natural powers determine their effects by necessity, but the rational power

    provides motive grounds that must be interpreted by the agent to play

    their role in choice. This creates room for error, and for the appearance of

    free, contra-moral rational choice. But we should not conclude that our

    permissive psychology can contest the authority of ability-constitutive

    rational standards, nor humpty-dumpty like, embrace falsehood for truth.14

    There is also no gap in the application of rational principles, though there

    can seem to be one, given different and possibly conflicting objects of

    choice: the best means may not be permissible; a moral requirement may be

    costly in terms of ones happiness. This separation is, in the ordinary sense

    of the term, practical, or world-driven: circumstances prompting us to

    separate out objects of choice under the appearance of different evaluative

    concepts. Further, because the same fundamental evaluative concept brings

    order not just to our own desires but to the conditions of desire-satisfaction

    of others the good is not my good any more than cause refers to the order

    of things the way it seems to me there will be occasions when not everything

    one might permissibly want is normatively-speaking available. This doesnt

    show that there is any gap in morality or between morality and the pursuit

    of happiness. That I turn out to want what you happen to have is a

    consequence of limited material resources or our limits as agents (unless I

    want what you have because you have it; then the issue is a moral one). It is

    because our access to the concept is through reflection on the conditions of

    different elements or moments of our practical experience, the side of the

    good present to judgment and choice is circumstance-sensitive, so both

    partial (or perspectival) and not unified into a whole. Nonetheless, like

    reason itself, the good is one. This sets the agent the difficult practical task

    of bringing what she initially encounters as competing elements of value

    under a single practical concept.

    Reasoning to Obligation 55

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • The situation can be improved on the theoretical side by philosophical

    reflection that provides greater clarity and distinctness to the evaluative

    concepts we have, and on the practical side, by experience that directs us to

    a more evaluatively unified life, and by social institutions that make what is

    rational for us to do less likely to come apart. Some things we cannot do at

    all without the intervention of a system of positive law e.g., to give

    possession the moral status of property; other things can be made easier, aswhen welfare institutions assume moral burdens that would overtax our

    well-being if we had to act alone. We might go so far as to cast the role of

    public order or justice as supporting a secular element of the Highest Good,

    in the sense of making it more likely that good intentions lead to overall

    successful action. This would put the state and civil institutions square in the

    middle of Kants moral story just where Hegel thought they should be, but

    werent.

    III. Premises

    As I have assembled and discussed the elements of the basic story, I have left

    to the side the matter of the premises from which we correctly reason. We

    already have some parts of an account of them. The premises must be a

    priori necessary and constituents or aspects of the concept of good, the

    object of pure practical reason. The concept of the object of pure practical

    reason is the concept of an end a necessary end of reason in its practicalmode. In the Metaphysics of Morals deduction of the basic principle of the

    doctrine of virtue (the account of ends that are also duties), Kant says,

    What, in the relation of a human being to himself and others, can be an end

    [for pure practical reason] is an end for pure practical reason (MS 395).

    This directs us to two obligatory ends, of our own perfection and the

    happiness of others. These are to be the premises, or the general form of the

    premises, of practical reasoning. Towards ourselves we have the task of

    developing and maintaining our rational agency; towards others we are toattend to the agency-related effects of our actions on their pursuit of

    happiness. (At the extreme, making someones life too hard or too easy can

    affect their ability to sustain or value rational activity.) How we should act,

    given these ends, will be determined, or derived, by means of the rules of

    inference of the categorical imperative.15

    Obligatory ends thus set the fundamental norms of correct regard for self

    and other: that is, they make certain considerations permanently salient in

    correct reasoning, and so in our practical thinking about ourselves andothers. If I am considering acting in a way that will deceive you, or cause

    you bodily harm, or obstruct your action, I may not ignore those features of

    my action in favor of a more benign description (as I once put it, they

    provide us with rules of moral salience). Whatever else I am doing, both the

    needs of others and the well-being of my own agency matter.

    56 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • Some will find the moralization of self-concern troubling. I think it is

    arguable that our first duty is to ourselves. In any case, we should avoid a

    foolish reading of what is involved. An obligatory end of ones own

    perfection would not require that when deciding between going to a

    concert and spending an evening with friends I must deliberate about self-

    (or other-) improvement; that would be absurd. But it would imply that if I

    work so much that I have no time for friends or pleasures, that I may beneglecting myself in ways I ought not, or that I have failed to understand the

    material conditions of healthy human agency. It may seem strange to think

    that an erroneous decision about work versus friendship takes us to the

    terrain of the impermissible, but if impermissibility in general marks

    mistakes of reasoning with respect to the objective good about what we

    ought and ought not do it is what we should expect.

    Norms of prudence also bear on all of our actions, though their authority

    operates in a different way Kant says assertorically, in the mode of belief.16

    If the action I propose to take is not consistent with elements of my idea of my

    happiness, but I am both able and willing to revise my idea to accommodate

    the possible effects of this choice (e.g., I will accept greater risks; I will not

    make living in the country a condition of my well-being), then I may act as I

    will without violating the prudential norm. I cannot just tell myself that I will

    accept the risks or costs; the requirement is that I do. It is a requirement

    of belief, in the sense of comporting with the evidence, only here in

    circumstances where I have some say about what the evidence concerningmyself is. By contrast, once we adopt an end, any end, or are in the business of

    acting on ends already adopted, we are under the unconditional authority of

    the norms of correct practical reasoning. We cannot adjust the evidence to our

    ends17; if we do not recognize or correctly identify salient features of our

    circumstances, we will not reason correctly to action.

    To see that reasoning from correct premises is necessary to reasoning

    morally, consider once again the sympathy example. In circumstances of

    need, if I reason to action from a sympathy-grounded premise, I can acteffectively, easing pain. But I cannot, from that premise, capture the rest of

    the normative conditions that apply. Helping in this case must be an

    acceptable end e.g., not inappropriately paternalistic; the helping action

    must be permissible; my doing the helping must be appropriate; I must do it

    in the right way, e.g, not disrespectfully; but also, the possible effect on other

    ends (of mine, and perhaps of the person helped) has to be taken into

    account; I must be prepared to take on the consequences of getting involved,

    both pragmatic and moral (e.g., once one starts, one may not always ceaseat will). Acting from sympathy does not engage me with all the moral

    reasons that bear. Some things can be brought along piecemeal: I can take

    permissibility on as a side constraint; I may learn about the pragmatics of

    dependence. But because I lack the full moral conceptualization of the end

    that fits these circumstances, I cannot reason about or around the action

    Reasoning to Obligation 57

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • correctly; I do not have access to the range of norms that apply. But they do

    apply, whether I apprehend them in the case or not.

    This gives us the right answer to another common objection to Kants

    ethics that an agent who misses or ignores morally relevant facts will not

    be judged to have acted impermissibly if the maxim she acts on passes the

    categorical imperative tests. We are responsible for getting the moral (and

    morally relevant) facts right by virtue of obligatory ends that require that weattend to what is reasonably obvious and morally salient in their purview

    (ends direct our attention; obligatory ends require it). So if someone is

    plainly in dire straits and in need of aid, it is a culpable mistake not to

    register it.18 It is also a mistake to regard the situation only through the lens

    of sympathy. The circumstances demand to be recognized as falling under

    the duty to aid. That is as much a fact about them as is the injury or deficit

    to be remediated in action.

    IV. The Other Formulas

    Although the interpretation I have offered is designed for the Formula of

    Universal Law, the Formula of Humanity readily folds into the picture. We

    can think about it this way. Being constrained by principles of practical

    reason, or by any principles of reason, is to have reason (the principle of

    rational nature) as an (objective) end. One may think about what one wants,

    or want to satisfy any desire, but the beliefs and intentions one forms shouldnot violate the norms of good reasoning: viz., the correct premises and valid

    principles of inference for cognition and will.

    So how do we, in ordinary action that aims at the satisfaction of desire,

    treat our rational nature as an end? One reasons to desire-satisfaction from

    premises that represent rational nature as an end by way of obligatory ends

    that provide the categories in terms of which material desires can, on

    rational grounds, enter maxims. So even if ones premises refer to desire (the

    pleasure of eating a piece of that pie over there), if they also reflect an over-arching concern for ones rational nature (simple pleasures belong to a

    healthy life a person who takes pleasure when and as she ought is less

    likely to overvalue bad pleasures, or undervalue the pleasure-seeking of

    others), then one can reason from them as premises that instantiate both the

    value of rational nature as an end in itself and pie.

    Respecting rational nature in others is not harder to set in this framework.

    One cannot have good reasoning as an end (an end of absolute, that is, non-

    relative, value) and for the sake of some contingent interest, permit oneselfto reason badly. Nor can one consistently care about good reasoning and

    think it is only ones own reasoning that matters. To put another in a

    position where she will be made to reason from false premises (suppose

    because of my deceit), or to subvert an obligatory end (suppose by

    abandoning her will in the face of my coercive force) is to prefer an outcome

    58 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • over a sound rational process (if I cannot get what I want the right way, Ill

    get it any way I can).

    The Formula of Autonomy can be read in these terms as an expression of

    the agential authority of rational norms. They are at once the principles of

    our reason, and of reason tout court. That is how their authority can be our

    authority over what we do and choose. Absent the rational will and its

    principles, there is no freedom of choice, no imputable action.

    The idea of a Kingdom of Ends follows. If we assume, as Kant does, that

    instantiations of Reason are all in principle compossible, then a realm of

    (human rational) ends (in themselves) willing ends that is, on the same

    principles of rationality is a real possibility. It would be a possible world,

    shaped by humans for human and other rational purposes. Kant expresses

    this clearly in a famous passage in the Critique of Practical Reason: [T]he

    moral law in fact transfers us, in idea, into a nature in which pure reason, if

    it were accompanied with suitable physical power, would produce the

    highest good, and it determines our will to confer on the sensible world the

    form of a whole of rational beings (KpV 43).

    V. Hegels challenge

    In this last section, I will consider, very briefly, some questions about moral

    obligations based in social roles: whether the interpretation advanced here

    makes room for them, and if it does, whether it is in a way that respects

    agents moral autonomy. In addition to addressing yet another set of old

    questions, the discussion will provide some idea of the resources this

    interpretation offers to our thinking about hard cases.

    First, there is nothing at all untoward about locally configured

    obligations. Nothing in the moral theory requires there to be one way to

    organize the family, or the burdens of taking care of those in need, or even

    modes of promise or respectful address, though each local obligation is a

    solution to a general moral problem. We can take it to be a general fact that

    human beings require extended support through childhood, and that adults

    tend to form (relatively) stable affiliations; there will therefore be

    obligations with respect to children and family life because of the impact

    of both on our rational well being. What must be the same across social

    differences is the anchor of reasoning to obligation: our status and needs as

    a rational being. We can see the obligatory ends of good willing as providing

    a form for correct premises, the local variations shaping the matter. It

    will be a real question whether this or that institution of marriage, or

    charity, or friendship satisfies the form; but if it does, then one can reason

    well in reasoning from it. Nonetheless, there is no reason why obligations

    that depend on contingent social roles cannot be bona fide moral

    obligations, and many reasons to expect obligations to have local content.

    Reasoning to Obligation 59

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • As we have seen, some social or political institutions are arguably morally

    necessary the law and a system of enforcement, certainly, but also some

    form of public education, welfare, and health care. Some morally necessary

    institutions allow individuals in defined roles to act in ways they would not

    be permitted to act on their own (e.g., police use of coercive force; a hospital

    policy of triage). We can explain this by noting that actions forbidden in the

    pursuit of ones own ends that are permitted in the service of a morally

    necessary institution are not the same action: in the latter case the agent

    reasons (or could reason) to her action from a different end her social role,

    not her private ends. But not everything required by an institution is

    permissible; at the extreme, some things mass murder, torture of innocents

    are morally impossible. Here we should say that the moral rationale for

    the institutions sphere of permission would be undermined by allowing such

    actions. A similar explanation applies in cases where the permitted and

    forbidden acts might seem comparable. Public officials are permitted, even

    required, to use force to gain compliance with the law, but they may not use

    bribes as a means to the same purpose. If we think of the limits on the duties

    of station as internal to the justification of the institution that defines them,

    since the justification of the institution is that it serves the moral needs and

    requirements of free, rational beings thats what makes its premises

    legitimate we can see why the impartial use of force can be a condition of

    free action, whereas bribery would undermine the conditions of cooperation

    that a states existence is to make possible. This way of showing how it is

    that some duties of some stations are not real duties creates room for the

    exercise of individual autonomy within the sphere of institutions and

    practices. If the reasoning from the institutions premises to the putative

    obligation does not go through, the agent cannot be morally obligated to

    act. So although social roles shape the obligations we have, they do not

    change the form of reasoning that supports them.

    By way of conclusion, let me mark four things I have tried to do with the

    good reasoning interpretation. The first is to de-psychologize Kants view

    of moral action and motive, freeing the moral theory from a variety of old

    objections, as well as making it cohere better with Kants theory of rational

    agency. Second and third, to make sense of the negative role of the

    categorical imperative within a full account of sound moral reasoning, and

    to explain why obligatory ends complete that account. And last, to indicate

    how to capture the interdependence of moral obligation and social role

    within canonical Kantian theory. The progress made on all four fronts is

    evidence that the interpretation has some merit.

    Notes

    1. The example is from the Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 2728.

    60 B. Herman

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015

  • 2. An action from duty has its moral worth not in the purpose to be attained by it but in

    the maxim in accordance with which it is decided upon that is, in accordance with its

    principle of volition (G 399).

    3. Kant remarks in the Anthropology (p. 253), that sympathy and honor can guide us

    provisionally: that is until reason achieve[s] the necessary strength.

    4. Cf. Herman (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge: Harvard University

    Press), pp. 910.

    5. Unless the conditional commitment alters the agents reasoning-to-action; then she will

    be engaged in a different activity.

    6. Cf. R 2628 and the essay, Conjectural beginning of human history (1786).

    7. Only in some cases does a human being lack the power of free choice, e.g., in the most

    tender childhood, or when he is insane, and in deep sadness... (A 255).

    8. Because it is the concern that is subordinated, it remains an open question what the effect

    on the pursuit of happiness will be.

    9. We dont, of course, usually perform these operations explicitly; but we dont need to in

    order for this to be an accurate representation or model of the process we use.

    10. One might argue that happiness is formally the end of our ends, and so distinctive. But in

    that sense it is also indeterminate, or empty.

    11. One would say something like this of any norm-constituted activity its concept must be

    represented by a principle for action.

    12. Rawls Original Position is in just this sense a device of representation: self-interested

    reasoning behind the veil of ignorance provides a representation of fairness. In this,

    Rawls follows Kant.

    13. Kant will speak in the Religion (pp. 2325) about a timeless adoption of a most

    fundamental maxim, a Gesinnung. As related to choice, this can only be about the

    constitution of the power that is the rational will our will and from no point of view

    is that an act at a time.

    14. Kant denies that we have a real ability to act contrary to the moral law (MS 226227).

    15. Of course the same fundamental principle or law is the source both of obligatory ends

    and the principle of rational inference. This is the point of Kants Paradox of

    Method(KpV 6262): the moral law is a positive synthetic a priori principle for the

    correct use of the faculty of free willing it objectively determines the good wills willing

    and also is the object of good willing.

    16. This fact alone should raise eyebrows in thinking about prudence as a practical norm.

    17. Though we can of course abandon ends in the face of the evidence.

    18. As with any standard where there is the possibility of negligence, it may be difficult to

    say whether the agent is culpably or innocently mistaken.

    References

    References to Kants writings are given by abbreviated title G (Groundwork for the

    Metaphysics of Morals); KpV (Critique of Practical Reason); A (Anthropology from a

    Pragmatic Point of View); MS (Metaphysics of Morals); R (Religion within the Limits of

    Reason Alone) and cited by the page numbers of the appropriate volume of Kants

    gesammelte Schriften, Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin: de Gruyter [and predecessors],

    1902).

    Reasoning to Obligation 61

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [U

    nivers

    idad A

    utono

    ma M

    etrop

    olitan

    a] at

    08:10

    05 M

    arch 2

    015