basis int law naturalism

22
The Necessity of Natural Law as the Basis for International Law

Upload: arnab-pciu

Post on 14-Aug-2015

153 views

Category:

Education


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Basis int law naturalism

The Necessity of Natural Law as the Basis for International Law

070016117

Dr. Lang

29 November 2010

IR 3041

Page 2: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

1. Introduction

Currently, international law is “experiencing a legitimacy crisis,” largely

based on the idea of authority (Cutler, 133). While positive law at the state level

carries clear legitimacy through the sovereign of the nation derived from the

people, international law faces the problem of implementing comprehensive

policy on nations that see exterior restrictions as a threat to state autonomy

(Hommes, 62). As any law requires a source of legitimacy for moral and practical

success, international law requires a legitimate foundation in order to succeed.

This paper will show that natural law exists not only as the basis of positive

international law, but as the reason international law is possible. By recognizing

that natural law is essentially basic codified morality, and understanding that the

point of international law is to promote moral interactions between state actors,

it is clear that natural law is the basis for international law (Zurbuchen, 426).

This paper will rely on natural law theorists, particularly upon the contributions

of Grotius, Pufendorf, and Vattel, who form a meaningful progression in natural

law theory.

This paper will begin with a basic discussion of the general principles of

natural law, including a description of natural law, the link between natural law

and morality, and why natural law must exist. Next, a discussion of international

law and its definition, before considering how natural law and international law

meet in theory. This paper will then proceed to put forth a unique view on the

necessity of natural law as the foundation for international law on the basis of

establishing a system of morality before extrapolating upon the practical use of

this theory in terms of transnational corporations in the realm of international

law. The paper will conclude by reconciling the historical ideas on natural law in

international law theory with the new theory proposed, and include discussion

on how the new view improves on previous principles to become relevant for the

current state of international law considerations.

2. Natural law Theory

Natural law is a sort of law that “imitate[s] nature” as a form of law that

exists without the additional prescription of positive law (Mare Liberum, 22).

The details of natural law are different for every theorist, but include similar

principles, like the golden rule (Mare Liberum, 45; Pufendorf, 61). This section

2

Page 3: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

will proceed by examining the definition of natural law in terms of morality, the

inclusiveness of natural law, and the legitimacy of natural law, examining the

contributions of Grotius, Pufendorf and Vattel.

Grotius defined natural law in terms of the principles his model of natural

law espoused. These principles included, “mine and thine,” “obliged to keep our

promises,” “damages must be repaired,” and “breaches of natural law or other

law must be punished” (Prolegomena, 8). Pufendorf and Vattel had different

interpretations with Pufendorf defining natural law in terms of becoming a

“useful member of society,” and Vattel’s comprehensive definition—“those

[laws] that we derive from nature or those whose rationale is found in the

essence and nature of man, and of things in general” (Pufendorf, 35; Vattel, 474).

In practice, the definition of natural law is simple—natural law is codified

morality.

Natural law only encompasses the most basic of moral principles that

“should be obvious to reasonable men,” and while each of the preceding authors

differed on the scope of natural law, each agreed that it was based on the idea

that individuals “possess…the knowledge of good and evil”—conditioning for

right and wrong is not necessary as the conscience of every individual has an

innate idea of what is right and what is wrong (Edwards, 803; De Jure, 1.1, 8).

Individual knowledge of good and evil is essential in the necessary connection

between natural law and morality, as it predicates natural law as the basis for all

positive individual obligation.

It is important to realize that natural law exists equally for all individuals,

groups, and states (Hommes, 62). Vattel described it best stating that the “law of

nations is originally no other than the law of nature,” suggesting that all tenets of

natural law apply to nations through his concept of the law of nations; however,

natural law does not just extend to individuals and states (Vattel, 68). In his

work, Mare Liberum, Grotius argues that the Dutch East India Company had the

right to defend itself against Portugal when attacked, on the basis that the

company and the state had equal rights under natural law (Mare Liberum). This

argument suggests that all non-state actors are equally subject to the benefits

and restrictions of natural law. Pufendorf viewed inclusiveness slightly

differently by viewing it in terms of the social construct. While all three theorists

3

Page 4: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

believed that no individual could exist without the assistance of other

individuals, such as a parent, Pufendorf viewed the community as natural, and

the means by which natural law should be implemented (Pufendorf, 35). In this

way, Pufendorf means to extend natural law as the foundation of every

community, and by extension, every individual, group and state, in order to

“preserve sociality” (Pufendorf, 35). The inclusive nature of natural law is

essential, especially in terms of modern application, which will be discussed

later.

Any form of law, or in a broader sense, authority, requires a root of

legitimacy. For government, legitimate authority is generally derived from the

people. Civil law, or “those [laws] that regulate the rights and conduct of the

citizens among themselves,” uses this legitimate authority as the basis for

positive law; however, natural law cannot derive legitimacy from the people, as it

must exist without the consent of the populous for it to remain in the state as it

has been defined here (Vattel, 92). Early theorists, like Thomas Aquinas, view

God as the root of natural law (Hittinger, 15). Pufendorf agrees entirely, believing

that “it is clear by the light of reason that their author [natural laws] is the author

of the universe” (Pufendorf, 29). Grotius, while an earlier theorist agrees, but

takes the bold step towards secularism in saying that natural law would “still

have a degree of validity even if…there is no God;” it should be noted that despite

Grotius’ belief that natural law can be affirmed through reason in the absence of

God, he is clearly a theist (Prolegomena, 11). In understanding natural law in

terms of morality, as previously discussed, natural law can be substantiated in

secular terms. Just as individuals have an instinctive understanding of “good and

evil,” natural law exists within the conscience of every individual. Vattel, as the

most secular thinker discussed here, best describes the true origins of legitimacy

“in the essence and nature of man and things in general” (Vattel, 748).

Individuals may not give explicit consent to natural law, but every individual has

a clear understanding of what is right and what is wrong, which suggests that

there must be some universal principle from which natural law derives

legitimacy.

While Grotius, Pufendorf and Vattel treat the obscure details of natural law

in great detail, natural law does not need to be so complicated—natural law is

4

Page 5: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

simply what is moral. Every individual has a sense of what is right and what is

wrong built into their conscious; it is this principle that requires every individual

adhere to its principles, and gives legitimacy to its cause.

3. International Law

This section will explore the normative connection between natural law and

international law as prescribed through the tradition of Grotius, Pufendorf and

Vattel. First, it is important to understand the definition and purpose of law,

positive law, and international law. Next, a discussion of international law and its

differences from positive law, before continuing on to describe the natural law

and the law of nations described by Grotius, Pufendorf and Vattel. This section

will conclude with a discussion of the traditional argument for the link between

natural law and international law.

Vattel defines law in general as “a rule by which we are obligated to

determine our actions” (Vattel, 747). For Pufendorf, law requires an authority to

which the subject of the law must submit. In any discussion of law, natural,

international, or otherwise, it is necessary to understand what is required to

constitute a law. Vattel’s definition does not stipulate a particular source of law,

nor does he stipulate requirements for upholding natural law—law is simply

rules that guide an individual’s actions. Pufendorf frames the discussion slightly

differently by requiring a source of authority; for Pufendorf, God is the authority,

which legitimizes natural law, though as discussed before, the sense of morality

that exists in the conscience of every individual is sufficient authority as a means

of proving natural law.

Law generally presupposes the state as the primary instrument of positive

law, as a government must derive legitimacy before it can constitute itself as the

rightful government. International law requires that the state give up its

autonomy and submit to a greater authority, which is an unattractive notion for

sovereign states (Cutler, 135). Traditionally, this has led to questionable

legitimacy in terms of international law, since international law required that

states give up a piece of their autonomy in order to submit to the authority of the

collective; however this arrangement does not account for natural law.

The law of nations, according to Vattel, is “the science which teaches the

rights subsisting between nations or states, and the obligations correspondent to

5

Page 6: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

those rights” (Vattel, 67). Vattel and Pufendorf view the law of nations as a re-

imagination of natural law for implementation on states, or a moral law to which

all states are required to subscribe. This is an important principle in that states

are already obligated to a greater authority and do not have complete autonomy

of action within the bounds of their state.

Grotian implications of equality are the most effective means to understand

the link between natural law and the law of nations. According to Hommes,

Grotius views natural law as “equally valid for individuals and states,” meaning

that the principles of natural law and basic morality are not exclusive to the

individuals (Hommes, 62). States have a responsibility to act morally, as the

point of positive law is “to promote men’s security or convenience” (Pufendorf,

53). Any state that violates the moral natural law is “guilty of a crime against her

own conscience” (Vattel, 76).

The advantage of using natural law as the basis for international relations is

that “if certain actions are right or wrong by nature…at least there is a corpus of

moral truth that is beyond dispute;” the morality of natural law is beyond

dispute, and it provides a means of viewing international law free from the

questions of legitimate authority (Bull, 72).Natural law requires that all

individuals and states prescribe to its precepts, which binds all individuals and

states together through the principle of equality. So long as individuals and

states are equal and natural law exists, natural law does form a necessary

foundation of international law with an authority that is greater than the states.

4. International Law: New View

This section will put forth a unique notion on the place of natural law in

international law, using support from the theoretical tradition of Grotius,

Pufendorf and Vattel. It will proceed by reestablishing the necessary existence of

natural law, then continue to discuss the contribution of natural law to positive

law and its link to international law. It will conclude by recognizing the benefits

of this analysis in terms of the inclusive nature of viewing international law as

the product of natural law and the differences from the theories previously

discussed.

Doubts on the validity of natural law lay at the crux of the argument against

natural law as the basis of international law, but this is due mainly to a

6

Page 7: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

misunderstanding of the definition of natural law. It is important to see natural

law in its secular sense as being derived from innate individual nature and as the

equivalent of morality. As long as natural law includes the contested idea of God,

it is vulnerable and cannot conclusively prove its necessary existence. Natural

law does exist within the conscience of every individual, which acts as legitimate

authority for its implementation. It follows that any other law must not violate

the morality recognized by the conscience of every individual as described by

Vattel. After accepting natural law in its secular sense, and equating its nature as

the legal corollary of morality, natural law can provide the basis for all law, as it

has “true legal character” (Hommes, 69).

Positive law, or civil law, is the means by which the morality of natural law

may be augmented. Pufendorf believed that “it is the duty of sovereigns to lend

[natural law] force and effectiveness of civil law,” in an effort to maintain the

“effectiveness” of natural law (Pufendorf, 155). It is important to recognize that

while civil law exists as an opportunity to legislate above and beyond natural

law, any form of positive law must not violate the principles of natural law. In

this way, civil law should support the tenets of natural law and require no

obligation contrary to the tenets of natural law as that would be immoral and not

be in the best interest of the people.

International law follows logically from civil law and is subject to the same

restrictions in term of morality that restricts civil law—international law must

also conform to the tenets of natural law. Natural law is necessary for the

possibility of international law for two reasons:

First, it is commonly accepted that laws “ought to relate to the welfare of the

state and its citizens,” that it should be moral, and that its purpose is to benefit

those obligated to follow it (Vattel, 92). This morality is inherent in every

individual, suggesting that there is some natural morality that exists in the world

without the addition of positive law. As this exists in every person, it must

constitute the highest morality, and any discussion of just law must come from

natural law. International law is an extension of this.

Second, if there were no fundamental basis for morality in the world, there

would be no reason to have any sort of law. While stronger groups could

subjugate smaller groups and bend them to their will, this would not be derived

7

Page 8: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

from any legitimate authority and could not constitute law. States could willingly

give up autonomy in order to legitimize international law, but the laws created

would not be based on what is moral, nor would the sovereign governments

constitute a legitimate authority without the legitimate backing of just morality.

So long as international law exists, natural law is the only means by which it can

be legitimate.

This argument also has the benefit of inclusive nature. All natural law is

based on the idea that all individuals, groups and states are equal. Traditionally,

this equality has been discussed in terms of individuals and states, but there is

no reason not to include groups, like corporations, in this discussion. If an

individual and a state have equal rights, then corporations should have the same

benefits and restrictions as individuals and states. In Mare Liberum, Grotius

argues that the Dutch East India Company should have equal rights to the

Portuguese, advocating for the right of self-defense (Mare Liberum). This marked

the beginning for the inclusion of non-state actors in natural law, but it makes

sense. The actions of a non-state actor have the same effects and are governed by

the same moral principles to which individuals and states are obligated. By

accepting natural law as the basis for international law, all actors of any sort

must be afforded the benefits and restrictions of moral natural law.

This argument differs from the traditional argument for natural law as the

basis of international law by discussing the necessity of moral legitimacy in

creating an authority capable of instituting international law and modernizing

the ideas of the traditional thinkers discussed in this paper. Regardless of its

origins, natural law is the same as morality. Just as genocide tends to make an

individual feel something is wrong, natural law exists in every individual’s

conscious to moderate actions.

5. Modern Link: Transnational Corporations

Non-state actors have traditionally fallen under a separate category in

discussion of law, which has resulted in a blind spot that has allowed

transnational corporations to “benefit from their international nonstatus”

(Cutler, 142). International law based on the consent of sovereign nations does

not generally consider transnational corporations, as they tend to fall subject to

the law in the countries in which they operate, despite their activity across state

8

Page 9: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

lines (Cutler, 141). Frequently “national governments are willing to insulate

them from…international pressures” (Cutler, 143). International governing

bodies, like the UN have sought to include transnational corporations in policy by

creating a special category for them; this is viewed as a threat to the autonomy of

the sovereign nations from which some academics incorrectly derive the

legitimacy of international law.

While states jealously guard their autonomy in terms of policing the actions

of transnational corporations existing within their boarders, these non-state

actors clearly fall outside of the bounds of traditional civil law (Cutler, 142).

Without some comprehensive, universal law to which all corporations across the

world are required to subscribe, there can be no meaningful law set down to

moderate the actions of transnational corporations. Legitimate authority derived

from the consent of the states fails to offer a solution.

Cutler notes “one solution is the recognition of the transnational

corporations as a legal subject, bearing rights and responsibilities linked directly

under international law” (Cutler, 146). It is clear that states are not the source of

legitimacy in international law, and that natural law provides the moral

foundation on which international law exists, giving transnational corporations

the legal status referred to by Cutler. Natural law prescribes all actors as equal,

and as Grotius shows in Mare Liberum, non-state actors are obligated to the

benefits and restrictions imposed by the tenets of natural law.

In practice, this means that transnational corporations must be held to the

same moral standard as individuals and states. For each of the theorists, this

means a slightly different thing, from contracts, to freedom of choice, but it is

more than that; if natural law is the basis for the application of positive

international law that is based on moral principles, which it must be as morality

must stem from natural law, then the international community has the right to

create positive law that applies to the actions of transnational corporations.

States are still within their rights to police the actions of any actors within their

boarders, but all positive laws, created by the state or the international

community must meet the standard of morality set by natural law.

6. Conclusion

9

Page 10: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

Many academics dismiss the idea of natural law on the basis that it is not

necessary, lacks legitimacy, and has no means of enforcement; however, this is

an error (Mumford, 265). Natural law does exist, and provides the basis for just

law at any level, including international law.

Grotius, Pufendorf and Vattel represent a significant piece of international

law theory through their contributions to natural law and the law of nations, but

it is important to bring their into the twenty first century and find a way to make

it applicable today. Removing God as a necessary precondition in Grotius, and

removing God entirely in Vattel represents the first step in modernizing these

thinkers, but more is required.

The unique natural law theory put forth in this paper represents a

culmination of these three thinkers works with a modern twist. While each of

these three thinkers connected their ideas to the concept of morality, none

realized that morality is the necessary characteristic, which clearly links natural

law to positive law.

The modern implications of international law in general are wide, and

transnational corporations represent a small portion of the potential of natural

law in international law, but it is an important place to start. In this paper, each

section has sought to define terms by establishing a definition, to whom the law

pertains, and what makes it legitimate. Natural law is clear in its definition and

its legitimacy, but establishing the universal coverage that could not be reached

by legitimacy from sovereign nations represents an important first step in

international law. By establishing the subjects of the law, implementation can go

forward and have legitimate meaning.

The case for natural law is clear—natural law exists in the conscience of

every individual who is capable of telling right from wrong which constitutes a

basic moral code; laws must be based on human conceptions of morality; and

without a sense of morality, there could be no legitimate law. Natural law is

necessary in order to define law in moral terms.

10

Page 11: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

Works Cited

Cutler, A. Claire. “Critical reflections on the Westphalian assumptions of

international law and organization: a crisis of legitimacy.” Review of

International Studies (21) 2001: 133-150.

Edwards, Charles. “The Law of Nature In the Thought of Hugo Grotius.” The

Journal of Politics (32), 1970: 784-807.

Grotius, Hugo. De Jure Belli Ac Pacis. The Constitution Society. Web. 3 October,

2010.

Grotius, Hugo. Mare Liberum. United States: Liberty Fund, 2004.

Grotius, Hugo. “Prolegomena.” The Laws of Nature and Nature’s God. Web. 20

October, 2010.

Hittinger, Russell. “Natural Law in the Positive Laws: A Legislative or

Adjudicative Issue?” The Review of Politics (55) 1993: 5-34.

Hommes, Hendrik van Eikema. “Grotius on Natural and International Law.”

Netherlands International Law Review, 30, 1983: 61-71.

Mumford, Stephen. “Normative and Natural Laws.” Philosophy (75) 2000: 265-

282.

Pufendorf, Samuel. On the Duty of Man and Citizen. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 1991. Print.

Vattel, Emer de. The Law of Nations. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2008. Print

Zurbuchen, Simone. “Samuel Pufendorf and the Foundation of Modern Natural

Law: An Account of the State of Research and Editions.” Central European

History (31.4): 413-428.

11

Page 12: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

Bibliography

Boucher, David. The Limits of Ethics In International Relations. Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2009. Print.

Boucher, David. Political Theories of International Relations. Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 1998: 209-219.

Bull, Hedley. “Natural law and international relations.” International Studies (5)

1979: 171-181.

Cutler, A. Claire. “Critical reflections on the Westphalian assumptions of

international law and organization: a crisis of legitimacy.” Review of

International Studies (21) 2001: 133-150.

Edwards, Charles. “The Law of Nature In the Thought of Hugo Grotius.” The

Journal of Politics (32), 1970: 784-807.

Grotius, Hugo. De Jure Belli Ac Pacis. The Constitution Society. Web. 3 October,

2010.

Grotius, Hugo. Mare Liberum. United States: Liberty Fund, 2004.

Grotius, Hugo. “Prolegomena.” The Laws of Nature and Nature’s God. Web. 20

October, 2010.

Henham, Ralph. “Theorising law and legitimacy in international criminal justice.”

International Journal of Law in Context, 2007: 257-274.

Hittinger, Russell. “Natural Law in the Positive Laws: A Legislative or

Adjudicative Issue?” The Review of Politics (55) 1993: 5-34.

Hommes, Hendrik van Eikema. “Grotius on Natural and International Law.”

Netherlands International Law Review, 30, 1983: 61-71.

Hurd, Heidi. “Moral Rights and Legal Rules: A Natural Law Theory.” Legal Theory

(6) 2000: 423-455.

May, Larry. “Habeas Corpus and the Normative Jurisprudence of International

Law.” Leiden Journal of International Law (23) 2010: 291-310.

Mumford, Stephen. “Normative and Natural Laws.” Philosophy (75) 2000: 265-

282.

Pufendorf, Samuel. On the Duty of Man and Citizen. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 1991. Print.

Vattel, Emer de. The Law of Nations. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2008. Print

12

Page 13: Basis int law naturalism

070016117

Young, Jeffery. “Law and Economics in the Protestant Natural Law Tradition:

Samuel Pufendorf, Francis Hutchenson, and Adam Smith.” Journal of the

History of Economic Thought (30), Sepember 2008: 283-296.

Zurbuchen, Simone. “Samuel Pufendorf and the Foundation of Modern Natural

Law: An Account of the State of Research and Editions.” Central European

History (31.4): 413-428.

Words: 3, 300

13