ben winters - the non-diegetic fallacy- film, music, and narrative

Upload: dia-cora

Post on 03-Apr-2018

283 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    1/40

    Open Research OnlineThe Open Universitys repository of research publicationsand other research outputs

    The non-diegetic fallacy: film, music, and narrativespace

    Journal ArticleHow to cite:

    Winters, Ben (2010). The non-diegetic fallacy: film, music, and narrative space. Music & Letters,91(2), pp. 224244.

    For guidance on citations see FAQs.

    c 2010 The Author

    Version: Accepted Manuscript

    Link(s) to article on publishers website:http://dx.doi.org/doi:10.1093/ml/gcq019

    http://ml.oxfordjournals.org/content/91/2/224.full

    Copyright and Moral Rights for the articles on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copy-right owners. For more information on Open Research Onlines data policy on reuse of materials please consult

    the policies page.

    oro.open.ac.uk

    http://oro.open.ac.uk/help/helpfaq.htmlhttp://dx.doi.org/doi:10.1093/ml/gcq019http://ml.oxfordjournals.org/content/91/2/224.fullhttp://oro.open.ac.uk/policies.htmlhttp://oro.open.ac.uk/policies.htmlhttp://ml.oxfordjournals.org/content/91/2/224.fullhttp://dx.doi.org/doi:10.1093/ml/gcq019http://oro.open.ac.uk/help/helpfaq.html
  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    2/40

    1

    The Nondiegetic Fallacy: Film, Music, and Narrative Space

    In a documentary to accompany the DVD presentation ofIndiana Jones and the

    Kingdom of the Crystal Skull (Steven Spielberg, 2008), the director asserts: IndianaJones cannot exist without [his musical] theme. And, of course, that theme would be

    nothing without Indiana Jones.1 It is a statement that few would disagree with, and

    yet it highlights a potentially troubling issue for film musicology. For this musical

    theme is part of what would be called the films nondiegetic music: in other words, it

    is considered an instance of sound, whose supposed source is not only absent from

    the image but is also external to the story world [the diegesis].2 How do we deal with

    this puzzling theoretical distinction when film theory locates other elements that

    might be considered quintessentially Indy-esque (the hat, the bullwhip, the smart

    one-liners for example) within the diegesis? Is it a distinction that is at all useful for

    explaining our experience of this film character, or cinema in general? Or, to invoke

    another iconic example, does it make sense to distinguish the nondiegetic zither

    music we hear in The Third Man (Carol Reed, 1949) from the rest of the narrative: is

    it not just as essential to the fictional world of post-war Vienna presented in the film

    as the image of the Ferris Wheel in the Prater, or the characters of Harry Lime and

    Holly Martins? In this article I want to explore the distinction between what lies

    inside and outside the diegesis; and to suggest that branding music with the label

    nondiegetic threatens to separate it from the space of the narrative, denying it an

    1 Quoted in the Adventures in Post-Production featurette 8:03.Indiana Jones and the Kingdom of the

    Crystal Skull Region 2 DVD PHE 9431. The music is by John Williams.

    2 Michel Chion,Audio-Vision: Sound on Screen, trans. Claudia Gorbman (New York and Chichester:

    Columbia University Press, 1994), 73.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    3/40

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    4/40

    3

    has recently argued for the retention of the terminology,6 scholars continued unease

    with the concepts is clear.7 Crucially, as Anahid Kassabian has recognised, The

    distinction between diegetic and nondiegetic musicobscures musics role in

    producing the diegesis itself.

    8

    Yet, it may be that the problem lies not so much withthe concept of diegesis (at least as it has been used differently in the spheres of

    narratology and film studies), but rather with the way in which it has been applied to

    film music. To assume that music functions primarily as a narrating voice in a

    narratological sense, rather than as an indicator and occupier of narrative space, is

    perhaps to misunderstand the broader nature of cinematic diegesis.

    Defining the Diegesis

    Gorbmans pithy definitions of diegesis as the narratively implied spatiotemporal

    world of the action and characters and diegetic music as music that (apparently)

    issues from a source within the narrative seem straightforward enough.9 But

    cinematic diegesis as a concept has a long and rather complex history, and when

    attempting to apply the term to film music, film musicology has tended to invoke the

    6 See David Neumeyer, Diegetic/Nondiegetic: A Theoretical ModelMusic and the Moving Image

    Vol. 2 No. 1 (Spring 2009) http://www.press.uillinois.edu/journals/mmi.html, accessed 24/06/09.

    7 Binns remarks of a scene in Fallen Angels (Wong Kar-Wai, 1995) that the terms diegetic and non-

    diegetic themselves do a disservice to the operation of music andit is in instances such as these that

    their inadequacies become apparent. See Binns, Desiring the Diegesis, 133.

    8 Anahid Kassabian,Hearing Film: Tracking Identifications in Contemporary Hollywood Film Music

    (London: Routledge, 2001), 42.

    9 Gorbman, Unheard Melodies, 21, 22.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    5/40

    4

    concepts narratological meaning at the expense of its original use in film studies.10

    Gorbmans definition after all, although referencing the work of the French

    aesthetician tienne Souriau, is largely based on Grard Genettes system of

    narratology, in which different narrative voices are characterised as operating atvarious levels of literary diegesis (extradiegetic, diegetic, metadiegetic) in order to

    explain the nested narrative devices encountered in the novel.11 The idea of assigning

    different music to different narrative levels clearly results from a tendency to see

    cinema in overtly literary narrative terms. Thus, Gorbman references Genettes levels

    in her discussion of music, with the term extradiegetic (used in her early work to

    10 The word diegesis has its origins in Aristotle and Plato, where it distinguished a type of narration

    that tells from one that shows (mimesis). Giorgio Biancorosso, David Neumeyer, and others have

    pointed out, however, that the meaning of the term in Genettes system (digse in French) differs from

    Platos concept (digsis). Rather confusingly, though, Christian Metz mentions the Greek origin of the

    word when explaining the concept (Film Language: A Semiotics of the Cinema trans. Michael Taylor

    (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974), 98). See Giorgio Biancorosso, Beginning Credits and

    Beyond: Music and the Cinematic Imagination,Echo Vol. 3 No. 1 (Spring 2001)

    http://www.echo.ucla.edu/Volume3-Issue1/biancorosso/biancorosso1.html, n8, and Neumeyers

    Diegetic/Nondiegetic: A Theoretical Model.

    11 In Genettes formulation, extradiegetic refers to the level of narration below the diegetic or

    intradiegetic (the 2nd level), which in turn is the level below the metadiegetic (the 3rd level). He claims

    any event a narrative recounts is at a diegetic level immediately higher than the level at which the

    narrating act producing the narrative is placed (228). Thus, metadiegetic refers to secondary narration

    by a character at the level of the diegesis, such as the events recounted in Des Grieuxs narrative in

    PrvostsManon Lescaut. Genette acknowledges that his terminology is somewhat in opposition to its

    common usage in logic and linguistics, and most film theorists would think of the terms nested in the

    opposite direction (extradiegetic as a level above or beyond the diegesis, with metadiegetic at a level

    below or contained within the diegesis). See Grard Genette,Narrative Discourse trans. by Jane E.

    Lewin Foreword by Jonathan Culler (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980), 227-243.

    Formatted: NotHighlight

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    6/40

    5

    mean the same as nondiegetic) pertaining to some kind of narrative intrusion into the

    diegesis. Yet while Genettes description of these discrete levels is entirely

    convincing when we are faced with the epistolary narrative of a novel, it is far less

    obviously applicable to most narrative cinema; and while one could feasibly argue forthe existence of a narrator figure in film (whether or not we hear voice-over

    narration),12 Gorbman did not seem to consider the possibility that her extra- or

    nondiegetic music might be part of the narrative as it unfolds (in the same way as

    other parts of the mise-en-scne), not an intrusion that signals an external level of

    narration.

    The first scholar to use the term diegetic in the modern senseand in

    connection with film no lesssuggests little of this idea of narrative levels, and offers

    instead a concept more appropriate for cinema. tienne Souriau used the word to

    describe one of seven levels of filmic reality by which the spectator engages with

    film.13 In that sense, diegesis indicates the existence of a unique filmic universe,

    peculiar to each movie. As Edward Lowry describes it, Souriau conceived of this

    unique universe as containing its own rules, systems of belief, characters, settings

    etc. This is just as true of a Neorealist film like Bicycle Thiefas it is of a fantasy film

    like Ren Clairs I Married a Witch. Souriau refers to this unique realm specific to

    12 The logic being that everything we see and hear in film is guided by the choices of a narrator.

    13 First outlined in a 1950 lecture and published as tienne Souriau, La structure de lunivers filmique

    et le vocabulaire de la filmologie,Revue International de Filmologie Vol. 7 No. 8 (1951), 231-40.

    Whether it was tienne Souriau or his daughter, Anne, who first used the term, is a matter of some

    contention. Although Genette, Metz, Burch and other theorists reference Souriaus essay inRIF, Henry

    M. Taylor notes that Anne Souriau claimed in the Vocabulaire desthtique to have coined the term

    herself in 1950. See Henry M. Taylor, The Success Story of a Misnomer, Offscreen Vol. 11 Nos. 8-9

    (Aug/Sept 2007) http://www.offscreen.com/Sound_Issue/taylor_diegesis.pdf(accessed 21/01/2010)

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    7/40

    6

    each film as its diegesis.14 This, evidently, has little to do with the idea of narrative

    levels encountered in literary fiction, and instead emphasises diegesis as a narrative

    space more suited to the distinct realm of the cinema (Souriaus comparative

    aesthetics, after all, saw each of the nine arts occupying their own individualuniverse). More importantly still, nothing in this description justifies the automatic

    exclusion of music from the diegesis, since the presence of music in the space of the

    filmic universe might be considered an aspect specific to a particular film, whether

    realist or fantastic in its aesthetic. This idea of a unique non-realistic filmic universe

    that may operate according to laws different from our own, where music does not

    underscore our actions or erupt from us spontaneously, is an important one to which I

    will return.

    Like Souriau before him, the semiotician Christian Metz used the term

    diegetic to indicate the reality of the fictional world, a reality that comes only from

    within us, from the projections and identifications that are mixed in with our

    perception of the film.15 However, building on Souriaus statement that diegesis

    encompassed everything which concerns the film to the extent that it represents

    something,16 Metz defined diegesis in typically semiological terms as the sum of a

    films denotation: the narration itself, but also the fictional space and time

    dimensions implied in and by the narrative, and consequently the characters, the

    landscapes, the events, and other narrative elements, in so far as they are considered

    in their denoted aspect.17 According to Metzs definition, then, whether music

    14 Edward Lowry, The Filmology Movement and Film Study in France (Ann Arbor: UMI Research

    Press, 1985), 84.

    15 Metz, Film Language, 10.

    16 Quoted in Lowry, The Filmology Movement, 85.

    17 Metz, Film Language, 98.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    8/40

    7

    belongs rightfully in the diegesis depends on whether it is understood as denotative.

    Although nondiegetic music is widely assumed to be connotative, and to have little

    to do with denoting objects in narrative space, one of Adorno and Eislers chief

    criticisms of Hollywood scoring was precisely musics redundant, almost denotativecharacterin short, its implied role within the diegesis:

    There is no place for [the leitmotif] in the motion picture, which seeks to

    depict reality. Here the function of the leitmotif has been reduced to the

    level of a musical lackey, who announces his master with an important

    air even though the eminent personage is clearly recognizable to

    everyone. The effective technique of the past thus becomes a mere

    duplication, ineffective and uneconomical.18

    There is a favourite Hollywood gibe: Birdie sings, music sings. Music

    must follow visual incidents and illustrate them either by directly

    initiating them or by using clichs that are associated with the mood and

    content of the pictureIllustrative use of music today results in

    unfortunate duplication.in the cinema, both picture and dialogue are

    hyperexplicit. Conventional music can add nothing to the explicitness19

    Nothing about the concept of diegesis, as defined by Souriau and Metz,

    precludes the presence of music. However, although Gorbman references Souriau, her

    18 Theodor Adorno and Hanns Eisler, Composing for the Films (London: The Athlone Press, 1994), 5-

    6.

    19 Ibid., 12.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    9/40

    8

    application of the concepts diegesis and nondiegesis to film musicand the path

    followed by subsequent film music theoristshas more in common with Genettes

    system of narrative levels. Music not attributable to a source in the narrative is

    assigned to an intrusive layer of narration (the nondiegetic), though admittedlyGorbmans 1980 article talks of music functioning as connecting tissueamong all

    levels of narration.20 Yet, I would question whether most films that feature musical

    underscoring have more than one level of narration in quite the way that Genette

    identifies in literary fiction.21 Diegetic music certainly has thepotential to operate on

    a different, nested, narrative level (when characters engage with the narratives

    encountered upon visiting the opera or attending a concert, for example), while the

    music of certain films that feature large periods of imagined narrative punctuated by

    frequent returns to the narrating situationsuch as The Usual Suspects (Bryan Singer,

    1994)may usefully be interpreted in such terms. Yet in films that do not feature

    complex narrative devices, much of the music we encounter might be perceived as

    operating on the same level as the rest of the narrativewhether it seems to be

    produced by the physical actions of the characters (as with mickey-mousing) or to

    express their emotions. If the presence of a separate level of narrative is not required

    for comprehension (as might be the case with literary fiction), is there a good reason

    why the presence of so-called nondiegetic music should be thought of as an

    automatic indicator of a higher narrative level within which the diegesis is nested?

    Might we better understand such music not as a narrating voice but as the product of

    20 Claudia Gorbman, Narrative Film Music, 202.

    21 Where voice-over narration is present, music may indeed be part of the process by which these levels

    are distinguished. See Knut Holstrter, Musik als Mittel der Persepktivierung im narrativen FilmA

    Clockwork Orange von Stanley Kubrick, 103-120 in Victoria Piel, Knut Holstrter and Oliver Huck

    (eds), Filmmusik: Beitrge zu ihrer Theorie und Vermittlung (Zurich: Georg Olms, 2008).

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    10/40

    9

    narration, belonging to the same narrative space as the characters and their world?

    That is not to say, of course, that music cannotbe construed as operating at a higher

    level of narration. I am rather asserting that within existing theories of cinematic

    diegesis the presence of music in underscoring need not be, in itself, an automaticindicator of a narrative act. In this sense, I am in sympathy with Nol Burchs

    identification of a relative autonomy of diegetic and narrative principles in cinema, in

    which the diegetic effect is associated with a sense of being there that is entirely

    independent of narrative process.22 In the same way that the gameplay of video games

    (as opposed to narrative inserts) suggests that diegetic effect is independent of

    narrative, the manner in which music functions in these situations is comparable to its

    place in narrative cinema: that is, its role may often have less to do with narrating

    as such, and be seen more as an indicator of narrative space.

    Evidently, film musicology has been reluctant to consider the possibility of

    music functioning in this way,23 and one reason for this may be the general

    acceptance of Eisler and Adornos assertion that film seeks to depict reality. If the

    characters do not appear to hear it, the argument goes, music cannot be part of their

    world. Yet Eisler and Adornos claim is rooted in Horkheimer and Adornos critique

    of the Culture Industry, which supposedly denied its audience any dimension in

    22 Nol Burch, Narrative/Diegesis Thresholds, Limits, Screen Vol. 23 No. 2 (1982): 16-33.

    23 Michael Long, though, has also questioned recently film musics reliance on language-based models,

    and argues for an approach based on the sociolinguistic concept of register. As he states

    Understanding film music as a parallel narrative tracking a novelistic text seems to be mainly based

    on the popularity in the last quarter of the twentieth century of the notion that all music narrates (or

    might narrate), a position that is hardly central to most understandings of cinemas image track. See

    Michael Long,Beautiful Monsters: Imagining the Classic in Musical Media (Berkeley: University of

    California Press, 2008), 20.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    11/40

    10

    which they might roam freely in imagination, and trained those exposed to it to

    identify film directly with reality.24 Breaking the link with reality was therefore an

    aim of Adorno and Eislers prescriptive study of film music.25 By aiming for a

    Brechtian Verfremdungseffekt that would highlight the unreality of the filmic world,though, Adorno and Eisler seem to have underestimated the willingness of an

    audience to participate in a game of make-believe, and overestimated their propensity

    to be fooled into a state of illusory belief by film. To assume that music the characters

    do not seem to hear does not belong in their narrative space, and must therefore be the

    indicator of an external narrative level, is perhaps to make the same mistake: to deal

    with cinema as an overly realistic medium. This is, in part, how Neumeyer appears to

    characterise diegesis, which he sees in terms of a process that differentiates and sorts

    sound registers experienced in the cinema.26 Indeed, so important is the referencing

    concept of reality to his construction of films narrative space that he even uses the

    term diegetic to refer to noises within the movie theatre, such as the sound of

    someone eating popcorn or shouting Fire!.

    But might this not be a rather narrow interpretation of that unique filmic

    universe described by Souriau, one that more neatly aligns with everyday reality but

    which ultimately has little to do with the nature of film? We all recognise that film, is,

    in the final analysis, often far from a realistic medium, and though we may classify

    our initial listening registers according to the rules of everyday reality (that is, in

    identifying what sounds belong in the theatre, and which emanate from the

    24 Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, The Culture Industry: Enlightenment as Mass

    Deception inDialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments ed. Gunzelin Schmid Noerr,

    transl. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 100.

    25 Eisler and Adorno, Composing for the Films, 36.

    26 Neumeyer, Diegetic/Nondiegetic: A Theoretical Model.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    12/40

    11

    loudspeakers), we surely do so with the knowledge that film operates according to

    different rules.27 With filmed musicals, the point is obvious, and we have little

    difficulty in believing that music occupies the same narrative space as the characters,

    whether or not a source is visible. Yet even in such a realistic film as Apollo 13

    (Ron Howard, 1996)which stays close to historical events, bases large parts of its

    dialogue on NASA mission control transcripts, and uses its fair share of NASA-speak

    acronymsEd Harris (as flight director Gene Kranz) still feels the need to explain the

    crucial term free-return trajectory to a group of Apollo flight controllers. He is, of

    course, explaining it for the benefit of the audience (We use the moons gravity to

    slingshot them around); we recognise that in the real world, the explanatory dialogue

    is redundant among a group of techno-savvy NASA scientists with an emergency to

    deal with (and where every second counts). Might not the music, therefore, also be

    part of this unrealistic narrative space? Certainly the sound of the film is: as Apollo 13

    sweeps past the camera, we hear the (impossible) sound of its thrusters in the vacuum

    of space. Clearly, we accept the filmic universe as operating according to different

    rules of reality. It seems perfectly natural, for instance, for the French characters in

    The Day of the Jackal (Fred Zinnemann, 1973) to speak in English and with an

    English accent, though in no way could one describe it as realistic. Similarly, in

    films that use deliberately unrealistic representationsthe marionettes of Team

    America: World Police (Trey Parker, 2004)or The Dark Crystal (Jim Henson/Frank

    Oz/Gary Kurtz, 1982)we accept the reality of these filmic universes rather than

    imagining real people, of whom these puppets are stylized representations. Likewise,

    27 Even documentary film plays fast and loose with concepts of reality, though it reveals that films

    relationship with realism is perhaps best thought of as a continuum. See Jeffrey Ruoff, Conventions of

    Sound in Documentary, Cinema Journal Vol. 32 No. 3 (Spring 1993): 24-40.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    13/40

    12

    in live action film we do not necessarily think of characters occupying our real world

    (where the presence of underscore would be impossible, and music would indeed be

    an automatic indicator of a nondiegetic presence), but instead construct them within

    the boundaries of their unique filmic universe.We may accept the presence of music in the narrative space of the film, then,

    partly as a sign of the fictional state of the world created on screen.28 It is an indicator

    that the universe in which the events we are watching takes place is not real; and

    having accepted that, musics presence seems entirely natural, rather than a troubling

    element that needs to be assigned to a separate level of narrative. This is certainly

    something that filmmakers themselves recognise and seek to exploit when attempting

    to shatter the sense of fiction and create a feeling of verisimilitude. For Gary

    Rydstrom, the sound designer of Saving Private Ryan, musics implicit role as an

    indicator of fiction was essential to his conception of the D-Day sequence that occurs

    early in the film:

    The other choice he [Steven Spielberg, the films director] made that

    was really important to me was to leave the music out and have no

    John Williams [sic] score until the battle was over. In fact, none of

    the battle scenes in that movie had traditional score. The score was

    always used to react to something horrific that we had just been

    through, as a lightning rod for our emotions[]it would be

    something that you could grab on to and your emotions could drain

    28 This may be a reassuring thought. In United 93 (Paul Greengrass, 2006), the presence of John

    Powells music may be something of a relief, a way of convincing us (erroneously, to some extent) that

    what we are watching is fiction.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    14/40

    13

    into it as a reaction. Spielberg was very smart to know that having

    the score, any kind of score, the greatest score in the world, over

    those battle scenes would take away the subjective feeling of it; you

    would no longer feel like you were there, you would feel like you

    were watching a movie.29

    Clearly the search for a kind of verisimilitude has motivated the very strict division of

    music and sound in the opening scenes of this film, since music, for Rydstrom,

    connotes the unreal. While the space of the films diegesis might have been

    deliberately constructed as a music-free slice of reality (at least in these scenes of

    battle), Rydstroms comments seem to suggest that filmmakers and spectators alike

    recognise (at one level) that the presence of music indicates a self-consciously

    fictional world. With this in mind, then, we surely do not assess and categorise the

    presence of music solely according to the rules of everyday life any more than we

    judge the other components of a film on the basis of their realism. Instead, one of the

    chief ways in which a films diegesis is differentiated from our experience of everyday

    life is through the recognition of musics presence.

    Music in Narrative Space: towards a new model

    I proceed, then, from the position that so-called nondiegetic music is often just as

    essential to the identity of the fictional narrative space presented in film as it is in a far

    less realistic fictional genre such as opera, or even in the world of a video game. It

    follows that I cannot adequately recreate the substance of that world in my

    29 Interview with Rydstrom in Gianluca Sergi, The Dolby Era: Film Sound in Contemporary

    Hollywood(Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2004), 178. My emphasis.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    15/40

    14

    imagination without the presence of music, just as I cannot recreate the world of

    Mozarts Don Giovanni without acknowledging that the characters express

    themselves musically (whether or not they are aware of it). A simple thought

    experiment illustrates my point: lets say we are told a story by a friend; later, whenrecalling the world narrated to us, we generally tend to imagine the characters and the

    situations themselves, not the words via which they were conjured into existence, or

    even the person in the act of narratingelements we might legitimately regard as

    nondiegetic. As Gregory Currie notes when positing a fictional character narrating a

    fictional story, imagining that someone imagines P tend[s] to collapse into imagining

    P.30 This suggests that what we might recall as the narrative tends to exclude the

    frame of the person supposedly narrating it. Yet if, after leaving the cinema, we re-

    imagine the filmic world to which we have just been introduced (without necessarily

    re-creating the films editing), do we not also often tend to imagine the films music?

    Whether or not we recall it accurately, we are aware that it should be there, and this

    seems to suggest that music normally belongs (in our imagination) to the same

    diegetic realm as the characters: it is part of the storys world, not an invisible means

    by which the story is narrated. Nor does it seem to me to be normally situated in

    another time and another place than the events directly represented, as Michel Chion

    describes the nondiegetic.31 Quite the opposite: it seems to occupy the same space, at

    least on a perceptual level. Trying to imagine the opening idol-stealing scenes of

    Raiders of the Lost Ark(Steven Spielberg, 1981) without John Williamss music is, I

    would suggest, an unnerving experience: we feel the lack in a way that has prompted

    30 Gregory Currie,Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science (Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 1995), 159.

    31 Chion,Audio-Vision, 217n9.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    16/40

    15

    many film directors to refer to the music in their films as an extra character or, as

    with Spielberg, to acknowledge musics constitutive role in defining a character.

    Moreover, it would be almost as bizarre as trying to imagine an operatic scene or a

    scene in a filmed musical without its orchestral music.Within the context of existing narrative film theory, my point might be

    understood with reference to the distinction made by David Bordwell (invoking the

    Russian neoformalists) between syuzhet and fabula, in which the syuzhet comprises

    all the sounds and images presented in a film, and thefabula the abstracted narrative

    constructed by the spectator.32 Jeff Smith articulates the different types of relations

    between music and narrative space by suggesting that nondiegetic music

    corresponds with a films syuzhet(a welcome reminder as he puts it);33 the musical

    performance of source music exists in both the syzuhet and the fabula; while

    referenced or inferred pieces are found solely in the fabula. Thus inAmadeus (Milos

    Forman, 1984), Mozarts Idomeneo as a piece of music is part of the fabula and not

    the syuzhet, since it is never heard in the film. This implies, then, that the fabula

    that abstracted narrative world wherein all the non-linearity of classical narrative is

    smoothed outexists sans music, or at least without the films underscoring.

    Reconstructing (consciously) the fabula of cinematic memories, however, is

    frequently impossible to do without the music (particularly if it is prominent, as with

    many John Williams scores): does Jaws (Steven Spielberg, 1975), for example, make

    sense without the sharks infamous musical motif, which frequently stands in for the

    presence of the animal? While it may be possible to construct a fabula that is

    independent of the music, it does not feel like it is taking place in the same world: one

    might be able to detach the editing or cinematography from ones construction of the

    32 See David Bordwell,Narration in the Fiction Film (London: Methuen, 1985), particularly 49-57.

    33 Smith, Bridging the Gap.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    17/40

    16

    fabula relatively easily (allowing the imagining of alternative camera angles, for

    instance), but removing the music in this way appears far more problematic. Again

    this suggests that music is not simply narrating the fiction and merely part of the

    syuzhet, but exists in the films narrative space, and therefore belongs to thefabula.As we have seen, this point of view is not entirely without underpinning in

    Souriaus conception of cinematic diegesis. Further support can be found, however, in

    later French theory. Jacques Aumont, Alain Bergala, Michel Marie, and Marc Vernet,

    for example, acknowledge various meanings of diegesis. Although their first two

    descriptions are conventional enoughthe story understood as a pseudo-world, as

    the fictional universe whose elements fit together to form a global unity and, on a

    larger scale, a diegetic universe that incorporates the series of narrative events, and

    their assumed frame (geographic, historical, or social), as well as the emotional

    atmosphere and motivations surrounding those events34their third definition hints

    at a further element that argues for the locating of musical underscore within the

    diegesis:

    Finally, we may understand diegesis as the story caught up in the

    dynamics of reading the narrative, which is to say that it is elaborated

    within the spectators mind from the impression left by the films

    unfolding.the story as my own current fantasies and the memory of

    preceding film elements allow me to imagine it.35

    34 Jacques Aumont, Alain Bergala, Michel Marie, Marc Vernet,Aesthetics of Film trans. and revised by

    Richard Neupert (Austin: UT Press 1992), 8990.

    35 Ibid., 90. My emphasis.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    18/40

    17

    This may well accord in part with the Russian neoformalist idea offabula, but one

    word stands out in this definition: imagine. Imagination was emphasized by several

    philosophers of cinema whose work on more cognitive-based understandings of film

    theory in the 1990s took the discipline further away from the psychoanalyticalillusion-based approaches that characterized 1980s discourse (and, indeed, Gorbmans

    approach to music).36 For Gregory Currie and Kendall Walton (and for me) the ability

    to imagine the world of the story is a cognitive act: rather than being sold an illusion

    that what I am witnessing on screen and hearing is reality, I am engaging in the

    game of watching a film. Whereas David Bordwell and Kristin Thompson believe

    that viewers understand that movie music is a convention and does not issue from

    the world of the story,37 I am more inclined to imagine that it does issue from that

    world; why else would I recall it along with the other elements of a story? Nor do I

    need to look for its visual source to regard it as such. Similarly, when discussing

    what they refer to as the problematic term extradiegetic (sometimes used instead of

    nondiegetic), Aumont, Bergala, Marie, and Vernet invoke the example of music,

    and describe a Western during which violins seem to erupt when the hero is about to

    join the heroine out by the corral at night. During this scene the music plays a role

    within the diegesis by signifying love, yet without really being part of the diegesis in

    the same way that the night, the moon, and the sound of the wind in the trees would

    be.38 Though recognizing that musics function is somewhat different to those other

    naturalistic parts of the world, they nevertheless seem to hint at a musical agency

    36 See, for example, Currie,Image and Mind; and Kendall L. Walton,Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the

    Foundations of the Representational Arts (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990).

    37 David Bordwell and Kristin Thompson, Film Art: An Introduction 8th edition (New York: McGraw-

    Hill, 2008), 278.

    38 Aumont et al.,Aesthetics of Film, 91.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    19/40

    18

    within the diegesis. Likewise, Giorgio Biancrosso, discussing the appearance of the

    monolith in 2001: A Space Odyssey (Stanley Kubrick, 1968), notes that it remains

    unclear whether the music is internal or external to the diegesis and whether the

    primitive creatures first react to the sight or to the soundof the monolith.

    39

    While themonolith is a decidedly non-realistic artefact in 2001, this is a far cry from

    suggesting that music is non-diegetic, closed off from the cinematic world; indeed

    the term extradiegetic may be more suitable if it is understood as something added,

    rather than something external to the world, as Daniel Percheron has suggested.40

    Yet, if we jettison the idea that music that the characters do not seem able to

    hear is an automatic indicator of an extra- or nondiegetic narrator, need we also lose

    the accompanying concept of a musical voice or agency? The idea of a composers

    voice, after all, implies a nondiegetic presence, since John Williams exists

    externally to the world ofStar Wars (George Lucas, 1977) or Saving Private Ryan.

    Might there be another way of thinking about film, though, that allows for the

    presence of a musical voice that is not that of a figure external to the created world?

    Daniel Framptons idea of a filmind provides just that. Framptons Filmosophy,

    unconsciously echoing Souriau perhaps, argues that film is its own world with its

    own rules and proceeds from the position that the filmgoer would be impoverished

    by understanding cinema only in relation to the reality it records.41 As a result, he

    posits the existence of a filmind as the originator of the images and sounds we

    39 Biancorosso, Beginning Credits and Beyond, n32.

    40 Daniel Percheron, Sound in Cinema and its Relationship to Image and Diegesis, Yale French

    Studies No. 60 (1980): 1623; 18.

    41 Frampton, Filmosophy, 5.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    20/40

    19

    experience, and of the films actions and events. This filmind, though, exists within

    the film. As Frampton puts it:

    Filmosophy conceptualises film as an organic intelligence: a film beingthinking about the characters and subjects in the film.The filmind is not an

    external force, nor is it a mystical being or invisible other, it is in the film

    itself, it is the film that is steering its own (dis)course. The filmind is the film

    itself.42

    Framptons filmind expresses itself through film-world creation and film-thinking.

    The former accounts for the objects contained in a filmic world: thus the filmind

    creates everything we see and hear in a film, conjuring it all up.43 As Frampton

    takes pains to point out, however, the basic film-world is not a copy of reality (though

    it may be based on a cameras recording of the real world), meaning that as spectators

    we are ready (conceptually) to accept whatever kind of image-reality the film

    decides to give us.44 Applying this to a films audio-reality, the idea that a filmind

    creates a film-world in which music exists in the air, as it were, would not be

    problematic. In Star Wars, for instance, the film-world created allows for the

    unrealistic (at least in our world) propagation of sound in the vacuum of space

    explosions and the scream of TIE fighters, for instance, are intrinsic to the created

    world. It would not be unreasonable to assume, therefore, that the music is propagated

    42 Ibid., 7.

    43 Ibid., 77.

    44 Ibid.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    21/40

    20

    in the same way. As I have suggested in passing elsewhere,45 music functions in much

    the same way in these films as the mystical force described by Obi-wan Kenobi (Alec

    Guinness): as an energy field that surrounds all living things and binds the galaxy

    together. Luke Skywalker (Mark Hamill) later questions the nature of the force, whentold that a Jedi can feel it flowing through him, by asking: You mean it controls your

    actions? Kenobi answers: Partially. But it also obeys your commands. I cannot

    think of a better explanation of how music seems to respond to and shape characters

    actions in these filmssomething it shares in part, incidentally, with Matt

    Baileysheas conception of the Wagnerian orchestra.46 To imagine the film-world of

    Star Wars created by the filmind as one saturated with the sound of music (whether

    or not the characters hear it as sound) seems perfectly acceptable to me as a film-

    goer. It even seems possible that Lukes engagement with the force allows him to

    hear and manipulate the films musicthough clearly it is a different kind of

    listening from that employed in the films cantina scene, for instance, which would be

    labelled diegetic by film music theorists.47

    45Ben Winters, Corporeality, Musical Heartbeats, and Cinematic Emotion,Music, Sound, and the

    Moving Image Vol. 2, No. 1 (Spring 2008), 8.

    46 Matt Baileyshea, The Struggle for Orchestral Control: Power, Dialogue, and the Role of the

    Orchestra in WagnersRing, 19th-Century Music Vol. 31 No. 1 (2007): 3-27. Baileyshea conceives of

    Wagners music dramas from a fully diegetic perspective that is most useful where characters appear

    to exhibit distinct control over the orchestra (8).

    47 Yoda, after all, acknowledges to Luke in The Empire Strikes Back(Irvin Kershner, 1980) that

    through the force, things you will see. Other places. The future, the past, old friends long gone.

    Music, too, is able to achieve this through the use of quasi-Wagnerian leitmotivic structures (see James

    Buhler, Star Wars, Music, and Myth 33-57 in James Buhler, David Neumeyer and Caryl Flinn (eds.),

    Music and Cinema (Hanover, NH: Wesleyan University Press, 2000).

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    22/40

    21

    Frampton provides a way, then, to conceptualise music as part of the diegesis,

    even in a more realistic film world than the fantasy universe encountered in Star

    Wars. He posits that the objects in a film exist totally within the filmind, that strictly

    speaking the film and the filmind are one and the same thing, and that these objectsare subject to the filminds film-thinking. As he defines it, film-thinking is (most

    often) realised, correctly, as an intention towards recognisable objects (characters,

    sunsets, guns);48 as a result, it normally accords with our experience of everyday life.

    Yet Frampton also allows for fluid film-thinking that can alter the time and space of

    objects as we normally experience them,49 as withAmlie (Jean-Pierre Jeunet, 2001)

    in which the heroine is allowed to turn into water. Thus he posits three kinds of film-

    thinking, basic, formal, and fluid:

    Basic film-thinking isthe default attitude the filmind has about its world and

    charactersthe coherent design of the base film-world. The colour tone of the

    image is thought; the fact that the film takes place in a wide image is a

    decision, an intention of the filmind. (p. 82)

    Most film-thinking is formally layered over recognisably normal-looking

    characters and settingsWhile usually plain and realisticthis formal film-

    thinking is exactly that which surrounds recognisable people and objects. (p.

    90)

    48 Frampton, Filmosophy, 78. Further references are given in text.

    49 Ibid., 79.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    23/40

    22

    [F]luid film-thinking is that which alters the basic film-world from the inside

    out; it is re-creative film-thinking. Fluid film-thinking gouges the film-world

    it tears and rips into it, morphing it from within. We are thus confronted with a

    film-being that can imagine anything, can re-create the recognisable world atwill. (p. 88)

    Frampton is largely silent on the issue of music, but as with visual elements, the

    sound of the film is clearly steered by the filmind. In this context, music is similarly

    the product of film-thinking (and thus in the film), and can be used to suggest

    character subjectivity, for instance. Thus, Frampton argues that in Damage (Louis

    Malle, 1992) the film feels the mans romantic concentration on the young woman,

    this time by drowning-out others words with music.50 He also argues that films can

    use music to undercut or counteract the visual element; what he refers to as films

    thinking against the image.51 What this concept offers in our present context, then,

    is a way to justify the presence of music as part of the created world, with all the

    potential fluidity that film-thinking allows.

    The music we hear in film can be attributed to a musical agent in the same

    way as the rest of the diegesis. As Frampton puts it, we cannot see [or hear] what is

    in the film without seeing it [or hearing it] the way the film thinks it.52 As a

    spectator, I believe that music often belongs to the diegesis just as surely as the

    characters; and, furthermore, it may respond to them, or be shaped by them (in the

    way that the filmind dictates). Music appears to permeate the world and (as a product

    50 Ibid, 121.

    51 Ibid.

    52 Frampton, Philosophy, 114.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    24/40

    23

    of the filminds thinking) appears usually to believe in the reality of the fiction; that

    is, music rarely calls into question the believability of the fictive world.53 While this

    may seem to offer tacit support for Eisler and Adornos critique of film music, and its

    nefarious role within the Culture Industry, the presence of music in a films fictiveworld is, as we have seen, one of the means by which films link with reality is

    arguably broken. In other words, by recognizing that the diegesis I am watching

    seems saturated with music in a way that everyday life is not (unless we are

    permanently plugged into an iPod), I am constantly reminded of the differences

    between a fictionalized world and reality. This issue is thematised in self-reflexive

    films such as The Truman Show (Peter Weir, 1998), which in its satire of media

    omnipotence and its anticipation of the advent of reality TV plays with notions of

    cinematic reality and musics role in constructing it. Music assumed to be functioning

    nondiegetically for us, the audience, is sometimes revealed to be functioning in the

    same way for the films internal audience (the audience of the TV broadcast The

    Truman Show).54 For Truman (Jim Carrey), though, reality is something entirely

    constructed by the TV shows enigmatic god-like creator, Christoff (Ed Harris), for

    whom even the weather is controllable. Indeed, who is to say that the atmospheric

    music we hear in the film is not piped into the scene for Truman himself to hear,

    53 Phil Ford has recently written of Cold War films that depict characters struggling to escape from a

    construct of false images (such as the mind-controlled reality ofThe Manchurian Candidate (John

    Frankenheimer, 1962)). Each of these films must suggest for its characters that everything is normal,

    yet reveal the construct to the audience: for Ford, music is something that can define the edge of this

    construct. See Phil Ford, Music at the Edge of the Construct, The Journal of Musicology Vol. 26

    Issue 2 (2009): 240-273.

    54 We even see the composer, Philip Glass, sat at a keyboard providing the music live, almost like a

    silent-era organist.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    25/40

    24

    experience, and react to in the same way? He has grown up in a carefully constructed

    world, after all, and may accept the presence of music as lightly as the sound of rain.

    The character of Christoff might even be read as an example of a filmind portraying

    itself; Truman, on the other hand, stands metaphorically for the character of mostfictions, unaware that his reality (including the presence of music) is entirely the

    product of a filmind.

    What, then, are the implications of this change in perspective for reading a

    film? Just this: accepting musics location in the same realm as the characters as an

    instance of film-thinking potentially allows it far greater agency to influence the other

    aspects of the diegesis; the filmind can suddenly allow the music to be heard by the

    characters, or imagine it influencing their actions, without requiring it to cross what

    Robynn Stilwell called the fantastical gap between the nondiegetic and diegetic.55

    Moreover, this change in perspective resists the notion that the score functions as an

    invisible, interpretative, and thus manipulative force on the audience. It may

    potentially still operate in such terms, yet not on the audiencewho are often

    exposed to a films score before they even enter the cinema, and are surely far more

    aware of a films music than Gorbman suggested in 198756but on the characters in

    the film, who may or may not be aware of its presence in their world. In short, it

    becomes one aspect of the filminds creative arsenal to shape the films narrative

    world. It should be said, however, that musical underscoring is not necessarily to be

    thought of as occupying a realistic physical space: in other words, it need not appear

    55 See Stilwell, The Fantastical Gap Between Diegetic and Nondiegetic.

    56 See, for example, Jeff Smith Unheard Melodies? A Critique of Psychoanalytic Theories of Film

    Music, 230247 in Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies, ed. David Bordwell and Nol Carroll

    (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1996).

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    26/40

    25

    to issue physically from the depicted space in the way that playback of diegetic music

    is often altered to suggest a source in the diegesis. We do not look for the source of

    the music because it has a sound fidelity that distinguishes it from diegetic music; but

    it does not necessarily follow, as Neumeyers emphasis on spatial anchoring wouldsuggest, that we then interpret the sound as external to the diegesis.57 Abandoning the

    notion of cinema as a realistic medium, we could perhaps think of it as a different

    kind of diegetic soundone that is not subject to the physical laws of our reality, but

    exists in a filmic universe of mutable physical laws (as with the propagation of sound

    in the vacuum of space, heard in virtually all science fiction films with the notable

    exception of2001: A Space Odyssey; and with the cinematographic concept of depth

    of field, which plays with the physical laws of focus).

    While many scholars are happy to consider the diegeticnondiegetic axis a

    continuum along which music may sit at various points, the nondiegetic end (if we

    regard it in its narratological context as one implying a separate level of narrative)

    strikes me as a state that is certainly not the norm with film music, and is rarely

    achieved unambiguously. Perhaps only in credit sequences, where the cinematic

    frame and the constructedness of the fiction is openly acknowledged, does the world

    created by the filmind come to an end. In these situations, I admit, the music clearly

    cannot be part of the narrative, though the transition between these states can be

    extraordinarily fluid. This might accord, then, with Edward Branigans extra-

    fictional level of narration in his discussion of the opening credits music of The

    Wrong Man.58 In Branigans model, though, the next level down is the nondiegetic;

    57 Neumeyer, Diegetic/Nondiegetic.

    58 Edward Branigan,Narrative Comprehension and Film (London: Routledge, 1992), 96.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    27/40

    26

    and it is in describing nondiegetic music as music that can only be heard by us,59

    and implying a narrative level removed from the fiction, that existing film theory in

    operating via real-world codes of reality seems problematic to me.

    That said, I do not wish to claim that music cannot operate on a differentnarrative level. Just as Carolyn Abbate sought to distinguish specific morally

    distancing acts of narration in opera from music merely acting out or representing

    narrative events, so I want to differentiate the majority of musical underscoring in

    film from specific distancing enunciations.60 The montage sequence is a case in point.

    As it plays with cinematic time, the montage sequence has traditionally been thought

    of in film theory as part of a films syuzhetbut not its fabula. It seems reasonable to

    posit, therefore, that the music heard in these sequences might be operating on a

    different level from such fabula-defining music as Indiana Joness theme, or Anton

    Karass music in The Third Man. Music that functions to unify a montage sequence

    might well be understood as narrating from an external perspective the events we

    are witnessing, passing in a compressed time frame, and be labelled legitimately

    nondiegetic or, perhaps more appropriately, extradiegetic.

    This is a more restrictive definition of narrative film music than that of

    Jerrold Levinson, who equated nondiegetic music that has a narrative function, and

    [is] thusattributable to a narrative agent, with situations where these things would

    not be established, or not so definitely, without the music.61 But this does not suggest

    that music is operating in a fundamentally different way from other elements in

    59 Ibid.

    60 See Carolyn Abbate, Unsung Voices: Opera and Musical Narrative in the Nineteenth Century

    (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991), xi-xii.

    61 Jerrold Levinson, Film Music and Narrative Agency, Post-Theory ed. Bordwell and Carroll, 259-

    260.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    28/40

    27

    narrative space, such as costume, which establish similar fictional truths. If as

    Levinson claims, making a difference in the narrative is the essential definition of

    narrative film music, then potentially every sound we hear and everything we see may

    also be attributable to a narrative agent. Levinsons view of narrative film music isso broad, then, as to be indistinguishable from anything else that exists within the

    diegesis, and certainly does not imply a separate level. In fact, his non-narrative film

    music, which is assigned to an implied author figure, is closer to my conception of

    narrative film music.

    The essential distinction I wish to introduce, and the one that is most

    important for my perception of filmic diegesis, then, concerns narrative space rather

    than narrative levels: it is not whether or not the characters can hear music that

    dictates whether the music is part of the fictional world (though that distinction is not

    without interest), but whether the music appears to exist in the time and narrative

    space of the diegesis; or whether it appears to narrate at a temporal distance from

    that space.62 Thus we might propose firstly a broad distinction between two types of

    music: extra-fictional and fictional. The former covers music that exists outside the

    films frame (and might include the overture and intermission music to Lawrence of

    Arabia (David Lean, 1962), for example), while the latter broadly includes all other

    music. Within the category of the fictional, howeverall of which is the product of

    Framptons filmindthere are distinctions to be made based on the musics function

    and its imagined location. Firstly, the extradiegetic might be understood as music or

    62 The famous montage sequence in Citizen Kane is unlike many montage scenes in that the music

    changes as a result of the changing time in which we see Kane and his wife eating breakfast. The music

    thus belongs in their narrative space, and what we hear is a series of variations as the narrative space

    changes, rather than a piece of music that appears to exist independently of these jumps in time.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    29/40

    28

    sound whose logic is not dictated by events within the narrative space, and therefore

    does not seem to be part of the films fabula. This is music that accompanies certain

    montage sequences, or seems to be deliberately distanced from the here-and-now of

    the narrative spaces everyday world: it may have a self-consciously narrativefunction or may even be perceived as an expression of the filminds own emotional

    reactionsuch as the use of Barbers Adagio in Platoon (Oliver Stone, 1986) to

    underscore Sgt Eliass death, which in contrast to Georges Delerues underscoring

    seems distanced from the narrative action.63 Secondly, intradiegetic music or sound

    exists in the films everyday narrative space and time, and is thus properly thought of

    as part of the films fabula: it may be considered to be produced by the characters

    themselves (either as a result of their physical movements, as with mickey-mousing,

    as an expression of their emotional state, or as a musical calling-card), or by the

    geographical space of the filmas with the zither music ofThe Third Man.64 This

    category accounts for the majority of music heard in Classical Hollywood film

    usually labelled nondiegetic, and represents my largest change to existing models.

    Finally, music which is heard by the characters as music in the diegesis (much like

    63 The prominence of music in the sound mix, and the fadeout of diegetic sound helps to create this

    sense of an overlaid narrative layer. This, ironically, may accord with Levinsons non-narrative

    music.

    64 Characters occasional acts of narration within film may be accompanied by music in a way that

    corresponds with the overt acts of narration encountered in Wagnerian music drama (see Abbate,

    Unsung Voices). InReturn of the Jedi (Richard Marquand, 1983), C3PO narrates the story of the

    previous two films in the Star Wars trilogy to a group of Ewoks, accompanied by the appropriate

    musical themes. As this music can be conceived of as emanating from the character in the act of

    narration, however, it is still considered to be intradiegetic, though it may better be described as an

    instance of metadiegetic narration.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    30/40

    29

    phenomenal song in opera), along with sounds that the characters seem to hear,

    retains its label of diegetic for continuitys sake.65 Evidently, the music can easily

    cross these boundaries as a result of fluid film-thinking, and music considered

    extradiegetic can easily become intradiegetic without necessarily becoming audible tothe characters. Similarly, diegetic music can easily become partly or wholly

    intradiegetic on the whim of the filmind. Indeed, it is in the liminal space between

    these three categories that Stilwells fantastical gap may be located.66 Crucial in

    this model, though, is the lack of a hierarchy suggestive of layers of nested narrative,

    and the return to a filmic concept of diegesis that is less about narration and more

    about narrative space. This model is depicted in Figure 1.

    While all fictional music is, as the product of the filmind, strictly speaking

    diegetic, it is the music (and sound) that sits in the spaces labelled intradiegetic or

    diegetici.e. in the narrative spacethat has the power to impact on the course of

    the story (fabula). Indeed, one of the reasons for positing musics location within

    diegetic space is precisely to allow the characters access to it, bringing it in line with

    Branigans definition of diegesis as the aspects of the fictional world accessible to the

    characters.67 For an example of the interpretative freedom this allows, we might look

    65 In film theory, the use of the words diegetic and intradiegetic would be considered a tautology. I

    am differentiating them, however, in order to distinguish music that the characters acknowledge they

    hear (diegetic) from underscoring that exists within the world of the diegesis, but is not necessarily

    heard by the characters (intradiegetic).

    66 Stilwell, The Fantastical Gap Between Diegetic and Nondiegetic. Evidently music crosses the

    levels I have outlined just as freely (and problematically) as in previous models. My intention is not

    simply to create an extra level, but to shift the majority of music inside the narrative space.

    67 Edward Branigan, The Spectator and Film Space: Two Theories, Screen Vol. 22 No. 1(1981): 55-

    78.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    31/40

    30

    briefly at the way in which characters engage with both intradiegetic and diegetic

    music in Saving Private Ryan.

    Figure 1. Layers of Music in Film (greyed areas indicate liminal spaces)Extra-Fictional

    Fictional(All music imagined by the Filmind)

    Extradiegetic Intradiegetic(including metadiegetic68)

    Diegetic

    ------------------------------------------------------------------------------(Fabula)

    -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------(Syuzhet)

    Saving Private Ryan

    The filmind of Saving Private Ryan uses music as a force for subverting the

    expected roles of a Hollywood soldier, making it an essential element in shaping the

    world presented to the audience. By allowing the characters to engage with both

    intradiegetic and diegetic music, the film strips away the semi-heroic aura

    surrounding them in the music-free D-Day sequence mentioned above, and opens

    them up to dangerous emasculating emotions that, in having little to do with

    Hollywood soldiery, threaten their very lives. This emasculating danger is associated

    specifically with music and is first introduced in the scene where Caparzo (Vin

    Diesel) is shot by a sniperthe first death amongst the squad sent out to search for

    and bring home Mrs Ryans fourth son (the Private Ryan of the films title). As the

    shot rings out, it is accompanied by a low, pedalled piano-note cluster

    68 See note 12.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    32/40

    31

    (intradiegetically), anticipating the diegetic chord sounding as Caparzo falls against

    an on-screen piano. Furthermore, it is Caparzos compassion for a French girl that

    proves his undoing, strengthening the implicit link the film has already made between

    music, death, and the compassionate emotions associated with femininity. Thus theviolence of the music-free D-Day battle is followed by a contrasting sequence in

    which we hear the first music for some twenty minutes; see several lingering close-up

    shots of the women of the typing pool preparing telegrams for unfortunate families

    (Figure 2); and witness Mrs Ryan receiving the news of her sons deaths.

    Figure 2. Emphasizing the feminine in Saving Private Ryan

    Caparzos death thus triggers the collapse of the mechanism by which music is

    separated from the world of the soldiers. From this moment on, the characters engage

    with music, both diegetically and intradiegetically, and in partaking of the feminine

    emotions it represents, are led further from the soldierly idealwith fatal

    consequences.

    Diegetically, Mellish (Adam Goldberg) sings to himself and is killed in the

    final battle, and Sgt Horvath (Tom Sizemore) articulates the danger of an dith Piaf

    record to a soldier (of which, more below), remarking that any more songs like this,

    the Krauts arent going to have to shoot me. Im just gonna slit my own wrists. He,

    too, is killed. It is Corporal Upham (Jeremy Davies), though, who demonstrates most

    clearly the inherent dangers of the films diegetic music to the Hollywood soldier.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    33/40

    32

    During the climactic battle scene, he becomes paralysed with fear and can do nothing

    to prevent the death of Mellish, murdered by the German PoW that Captain Miller

    (Tom Hanks) had earlier set free. His failure to act is partly prepared by his

    characterisation as a sensitive man of literature, an outsider whose introduction to thesquad of combat-hardened veterans seems to endanger the group, and Captain Miller

    in particular, with whom he shares his literary education. Yet there is a degree to

    which Upham has begun to bond with the others, becoming more soldierly in his

    manner (smoking) and adopting the slang of the squad. Mellish makes the in-joke of

    the group so obvious that Upham finally understands; Fubar is not a German word,

    as he had been told, but a typical soldiers acronym: Fucked Up Beyond All

    Recognition. So great is this bonding, in fact, that Uphams failure comes as

    something of a surprise to the viewer; we expect the filmind to transform him from

    nervous, effeminate map-maker to heroic combat soldier. What, then, happens to

    precipitate his spectacular fall?

    Upham, I suggest, is undone by the power of music, and his impending failure

    is well signposted in the sequence leading up to the final battle. Specifically, it is the

    diegetic playing of the dith Piaf record that brings about his undoing.69 Though the

    whole squad can hear the record, Upham not only listens, he engages with the music,

    translating the lyrics for his comrades:

    Even life itself only represents you

    Sometimes I dream that Im in your arms

    And you speak softly in my ear

    And you say things that make my eyes close

    69 The 1943 song Tu es partout.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    34/40

    33

    And I find that marvellous70

    In so doing, he makes the mistake of translating in the first person, becoming

    feminised to the point where Mellish jokes: Upham, to be honest with you, I findmyself curiously aroused by you. Uphams feminisation at the hands of dith Piaf

    seems to remove the heroic aura that he has absorbed from the squad, and re-inscribe

    the sensitive emotions of compassion, mercy, and remorse that are implicit in his

    character and that are so dangerous to the Hollywood soldier. 71 It should be no

    surprise therefore that he fails in combat: music has marked him as other to the

    normative world of the Hollywood soldier established in the films music-free D-

    Day sequence.

    If Upham has engaged with music diegetically, Captain Miller suffers equally

    by engaging with the films intradiegetic music. By that I mean that he seems to

    respond to the presence of underscoring; that his emotional crisis triggers the presence

    of music in the narrative space of the film and is, in turn, fed by it in a kind of self-

    destructive feedback loop. This process begins in the immediate aftermath of the D-

    Day assault as the filmind imagines the entrance of a chorale theme 72music that

    70 The original French lyrics are: Mme la vie ne represente que toi/Des fois je rve que je suis dans

    tes bras/Et qu loreille tu me parles tout bas/Tu dis des choses qui font fermer les yeux/Et moi je

    trouve a merveilleux.

    71 In episode three of Spielbergs 2001 HBO mini-seriesBand of Brothers, Lt. Spiers (Matthew Settle)

    outlines how a real/reel soldier should function: Without mercy, without compassion, without

    remorse. All war depends upon it.Upham embodies these qualities: when the rest of the squad want to

    execute the German PoW, it is Upham who appeals to Miller, claiming this is not right.

    72 The music is, of course, written by John Williams, but it is not Williamss musical voice that is

    operating here, but that of the film itself.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    35/40

    34

    seems to say so much about the brotherhood of war (a condition to which Upham

    aspires, and about which he is writing his book). Miller is, however, able to silence

    this music, initially banishing it from his everyday activities as a solider in his scenes

    with Lt. Col. Anderson (Dennis Farina) and Capt. Hamill (Ted Danson). Music,though, becomes ever more pervasive in his world. By the time that the squad are

    searching for Ryan among some passing airborne troops, Miller is actively

    underscored with musicthough as this cues orchestration is dominated by the

    trumpet, an instrument that retains its connection with the military, it suggests he

    maintains at least some measure of control. As he begins to lose his grip on the

    mission, however, he is increasingly underscored by instruments that perhaps connote

    a more feminine musical voice. In the scene where he breaks down and weeps, for

    example, we hear low clarinets and strings, and it is only by pulling himself together

    that he silences the music seemingly emanating involuntarily from him. He might

    seem to engage with his music in ways that traditional film music theory, in labelling

    it nondiegetic and assuming that it is a passive reflection of, or commentary on, his

    actions would perhaps deny.

    Alongside this growing lack of control (of both himself and his men, and his

    musical voice), Millers home life, which he has so assiduously guarded, gradually

    intrudes. Having deduced that he does not have a (living) mother, the men have

    characterised him as some sort of ideal soldier: Captain didnt go to school. They

    assembled him at OCS out of spare body parts of dead GIs. Once his mysterious

    past is revealed to include a wife, to whom he is emotionally attached, and an

    unremarkable schoolteacher background, he is further removed from the soldierly

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    36/40

    35

    ideal, warranting ever more underscoring.73 In fact, a music cue enters immediately

    after the following dialogue: Im a schoolteacher. I teach English composition in this

    little town called Addley, Pennsylvania. The last 11 years Ive been at Thomas Alva

    Edison High School. I was the coach of the baseball team in the springtime.Significantly, the cue begins with the same low clarinet theme heard in a previous

    scene as Wade the medic (Giovanni Ribisi) voices his concern for Mellish, Jackson

    and Reibens irreverent search through the dog tags of dead soldiers in full view of

    onlooking airborne troops. Undone by his concern for the decent thing to do, Wade

    is also marked as other by intradiegetic music that contrasts with the normative

    sound world of Hollywood soldiery, and in the very next set piecethe attack on the

    radar positionit is Wade who is shot. During his death scene, Wade begins to call

    for his mother, prompting another intradiegetic music cue and leading into a period of

    emotional crisis for the whole squad as they grapple with the implications of his

    demise. This othering from the normative world of Hollywood soldiery through

    music thus endangers Miller too, and offers a clue to his eventual fate. Though he is

    portrayed in the final battle in the heroic, self-sacrificing role of the traditional

    Hollywood soldier, it is perhaps no surprise that he does not survive: his developing

    characterisation, shaped by his underscoring, has decreed that he no longer belongs to

    the machismo world of warfare. The associations in Saving Private Ryan thus seem

    clear: decency/femininity leads to/is caused by intradiegetic/diegetic music and,

    ultimately, results in death. Only with the increasingly heroic actions of Private

    Reiben (Edward Burns) are these associations challenged.

    73 Miller has also admitted that every man I kill, the farther away from home I feel. This is in stark

    contrast to the squads earlier portrayal of him as the ideal soldierly machine, or of Jacksons own

    claim to be a fine instrument of warfare.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    37/40

    36

    Reiben is the only member of the squad around whom some musical

    association fails to materialise until the very end of the film, and it is his character that

    emerges as the archetypal soldier of the generation that Spielberg so obviously wishes

    to commemorate. It is Reiben who, having conquered his mutinous tendencies, seemsto take control in the final battle as Miller, undone by his musical characterisation,

    slips further from the soldierly ideal. It is Reiben who ultimately saves Ryan; and it

    is Reiben who takes control when Miller is incapacitated by shock. Only in his last

    appearance on camera is the character underscored by music. Crucially though, it is

    not the feminised sound world of strings or clarinets that surrounds him, but the

    nobility of trumpets. Reiben, it seems, has replaced Miller as the ideal soldier in the

    filminds film-thinking, and assertively claims the only music that carries with it a

    sense of military dignity, bringing the errant music back under control. Furthermore,

    he is identified closely with an overtly heterosexual, masculine position, as his story

    about Rachel Troubowitz attests, and the only compassion he displays is for fallen

    Americans (Miller), once the battle is over. If, as Catherine Gunther Kodat suggests,

    Saving Private Ryan can be seen as a reaffirmation of patriarchy, and particularly the

    patriarchy of the founding fathers (as it is presented in the film, the premise of the

    mission to save Ryan is inspired by Abraham Lincolns Bixby letter),74 then it is

    Reiben who is able to tame the films music, and emerge as its hero.

    Conclusion

    74 See Catherine Gunther Kodat, Saving Private Property: Steven Spielbergs American Dream

    Works,Representations No. 71 (Summer, 2000): 77105. The passage discussing the Bixby letter can

    be found on pages 8688.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    38/40

    37

    Musics perceived cultural power to undo masculinity and evoke pacifying emotions

    is thus used by the filmind ofSaving Private Ryan to shape the world it has created

    to trigger the removal from the film-world of characters that do not fit its idea of the

    soldierly ideal.

    75

    Crucially, though, it is not just through the films diegetic music thatthis is achieved (the dith Piaf song), but also through the intradiegetic underscoring:

    while the characters do not appear to hear it, music seems to inhabit the same

    narrative space they occupy and is thus able to influence the course of the fabula.

    Music might be envisaged as a kind of energy field imagined by the filmind, which

    surrounds the space of the film and responds to the presence of characters, or to other

    elements of the diegesis. Concepts such as brotherhood may trigger a musical

    response; characters undergoing extremes of emotion may cause large waves of

    musical energy to traverse it (as with Miller); or the filmind may induce its own

    ripples in its musical fabric to induce a reaction in the characters. In that sense, it

    demonstrates the greater interpretative freedom offered by a model of film music

    unconstrained by an overly-realistic philosophy of film, or by models of narratology

    arguably more appropriate to literature.

    Evidently, as recent theorisations of the nondiegetic by such scholars as

    Neumeyer, Stilwell, and Smith reveal, the use of the term nondiegetic does not

    straight-jacket film musicology entirely into invoking a set of pre-conceived functions

    75 Peter Franklins exploration of musics role in negotiating tropes of gender and subjectivity in King

    Kong suggests that these associations are, to a degree, inbuilt in films of classical narrative cinema. See

    King Kong and Film on Music: Out of the Fog, 88-102 in Film Music: Critical Approaches, ed. K. J.

    Donnelly (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2001). See also Catherine Clment, Opera, or the

    Undoing of Women, trans. Betsy Wing (London: I. B. Tauris, 1997); and Lawrence Kramer,After the

    Lovedeath: Sexual Violence and the Making of Culture (Berkeley: University of California Press,

    1997).

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    39/40

    38

    for music; and yet I find the term unhelpful for what it implies about the cinematic

    object. Indeed, separating music as a matter of course from the events occurring in the

    fictional world, as the expression of a critical or narrating voice, may even be

    unconsciously reinforcing modernist paradigms. Music, according to Adorno, onlyfulfills its social function when it presents social problems through its own material

    and according to its own formal laws,76 thus implying a separation, or a least a

    distancing, from such problematic arts as film. My reconceptualising of musics role

    in film, therefore, is in part motivated by an instinctive reaction to the modernist tenet

    of Adorno and Eislers criticisms. In their advocacy of a Brechtian

    Verfremdungseffekt and their rejection of redundant musical illustration, they

    suggest a composers voice able to stand apart from the fictive world, much in the

    way that Adorno talked about the role of an artist in society. Evidently, for Adorno

    and Eisler, films relationship with reality was a crucial issue, but as I have argued I

    do not believe film should be evaluated in terms of its fidelity to reality. Perhaps with

    that postmodernist shift in attitude that sees and embraces music as deeply implicated

    in our messy every-day world, so we can also regard the worlds created by filminds as

    open to the influence of musicrather than positing underscore as something akin to

    a modernist critical voice, operating above and beyond their (filmic) worlds. I believe

    that we construct cinematic diegesis not according to the everyday rules of our (real)

    world, in which music does not underscore our actions, but rather with reference to

    the conventions of film. Theorising music as nondiegetic denies it the agency in film

    that it has enjoyed throughout much of its history, and which it enjoys in other

    fictional genres, such as opera and musical theatre.

    76 Theodor W. Adorno, On the Social Situation of Music, Telos 35 (Spring 1978), 130.

  • 7/28/2019 Ben Winters - The Non-diegetic Fallacy- Film, Music, And Narrative

    40/40

    39

    By replacing nondiegetic with extradiegetic and intradiegetic in my

    reconceptualisation, I have not only suggested that background music plays a

    constitutive role in shaping our construction of the diegesis, but also revealed musics

    potential to play an active role in the diegesis while still appearing to remainunheard by its characters (though this is not an essential condition of its existence).

    While this may be a controversial move in our understanding of musics role in

    cinema, aligning film with a less realistic medium such as opera, it potentially allows

    a more flexible approach to film music criticism. We may speak of characters

    radiating music and thus accidentally revealing their presence,77 or of underscoring

    revealing the falsity of a characters verbal utterances, much in the way that film

    scholars might talk of a characters body language betraying their intentions. More

    than that, though, we are no longer required to imagine that the fantastical fictional

    film worlds and characters we enjoy in the cinema exist in some realistic world,

    separated from the music that defines them.

    This is a pre-copy-editing, author-produced PDF of an article accepted for publication

    in Music & Letters following peer review. The definitive publisher-authenticated

    version The Non-diegetic Fallacy: Film, Music, and Narrative Space, Music &

    Letters Vol. 91, No. 2 (May 2010): 224-244 is available online at:

    http://ml.oxfordjournals.org/content/91/2/224.full

    77 In episode three ofBand of Brothers, for instance, the sensitive Private Blithe (Marc Warren) despite

    appearing to maintain noise discipline cannot help but radiate Michael Kamens music, revealing his

    position to a German sniper. He is shot through the throat, which silences his whispers and the

    intradiegetic music that appears to originate from his body.