catenatives or complex vp

17
Catenatives or complex VP - the debate about specific verbs in English by Jan Niehues Paper submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for a graded credit for the course “Problems of English Grammar” in Summer Term 2005 Submission Date: October 10, 2005 Approved by: Prof. Dr. Jürgen Handke Philipps University Marburg

Upload: aperfectcircle

Post on 28-Apr-2015

25 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

DESCRIPTION

Syntax

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Catenatives or Complex VP

Catenatives or complex VP -the debate about specific verbs in English

by

Jan Niehues

Paper submitted in partial fulfillment of the

requirements for a graded credit for the course

“Problems of English Grammar”

in Summer Term 2005

Submission Date: October 10, 2005

Approved by: Prof. Dr. Jürgen Handke

Philipps University Marburg

Page 2: Catenatives or Complex VP

2

Contents

1 Introduction......................................................................................................... 3

2 Catenative Verbs................................................................................................. 4

2.1 Definitions..........................................................................................................4

2.2 Auxiliaries, modals, modifier, operator, quasi-modal........................................6

2.3 From finite to non-finite VP...............................................................................7

2.4 Simple vs. complex verb phrases....................................................................... 7

3 Simple and complex catenatives.........................................................................9

3.1 Simple catenatives............................................................................................10

3.2 Complex catenatives........................................................................................ 11

4 Classes and classification..................................................................................13

4.1 Criteria for classification..................................................................................13

4.2 Syntactical or semantic grouping..................................................................... 13

5 Conclusion / Summary......................................................................................15

6 References.......................................................................................................... 16

Page 3: Catenatives or Complex VP

3

1 Introduction

Most linguists agree that there is a particular feature of certain verbs like e.g.

want, begin, try or seem that sets them apart from other verbs: their ability to be

combined into chains of verbs, to 'catenate' (Lat. catena: chain).

(1) I don't want to have to be forced to begin to try to make more money. (Palmer1987: 172)

The term usually used for these verbs is 'catenative verbs'. There remains

some form of disagreement about almost every aspect of these verbs, however,

ranging from the question which verbs actually are catenative, to the problem of

how to analyse or categorise them. Some linguists even question the need to

define a class of catenative verbs in the first place. Huddleston concedes that:

"This is one of the most difficult areas of English grammar and despite a great dealof intensive study over the last twenty years there remains much disagreement overthe most basic aspects of the analysis."(Huddleston 1997: 209)

The treatment of the grammatical phenomena is further complicated by the

fact that linguists tend to introduce their own categories or descriptions for

existing categories. This is particularly evident in the argument of modals vs.

auxiliaries vs. operators.

An approach differing from that traditionally taken by grammarians is that

presented by Dieter Mindt who bases his observations on the analysis of a corpus

of actual language.

This paper will try to give an overview of the theories concerning catenative

verbs, their relation to the auxiliaries and their features of clause

complementation. Due to the scope of work that has been published, only the

main approaches will be considered. The field of semantics in particular would

merit a much closer look on the effects of sentence taxis1.

1 And indeed there has been a rather fervid debate about this between Huddleston on the one side and Matthiesen and Martin on the other, conducted largely in the 'Occasional papers for systemic Linguistics'.

Page 4: Catenatives or Complex VP

4

2 Catenative Verbs

Here, the main definitions of catenative verbs will be presented, noting their

different approaches to certain features and their treatment of the auxiliaries.

2.1 Definitions

Richard Hudson defines catenatives as "verbs that combine with a following non -

finite verb". He includes "verbs like get, keep, start, help as well as the traditional

auxiliary verbs". (Hudson 2002) Sample sentences given by him include:

(2) a) She was/got chosen for the job.b) She was/kept talking.

Huddleston and Pullum state that a catenative is present in "most cases where

a non-finite clause is an internal complement of a verb". They illustrate this by

giving cases of non-catenative complements: predicative complements (3a),

objects (3b) and PP complements (3c).

(3) a) Kim seemed a keen student.b) Kim began the journey.c) Kim hoped for a successful outcome. (Huddleston 2005: 215)

Gramley and Pätzold agree by defining verbs which are followed by non-

finite verb forms but which are not operators as catenative verbs. (Gramley &

Pätzold 1992: 132)

Palmer defines catenatives as verbs that combine with a full verb into verb

phrases of theoretically unlimited length. (cf. 1) Although he applies the term

'complex phrase', he contrasts complex phrases utilising catenative verbs against

examples such as:

(4) I bought the boat to sail the world. (Palmer 1987: 172pp.)

In (4), there is hardly any semantic relationship between the clauses, whereas

catenatives usually imply some semantic restriction on the following verb. Palmer

Page 5: Catenatives or Complex VP

5

sees a much tighter semantic and syntactic relationship, similar to auxiliary verbs,

exemplified by the impossibility of certain constructions:

(5) a) *He kept to talk.b) *He has talking. (Palmer 1987: 172pp.)

He specifically excludes infinitives of purpose and of result, only the usage in(6a) being catenative.

(6) a) I promise to make you happy.b) I promise, to make you happy. (Palmer 1987: 206)

Palmer rejects the approach of analysing the subordinate clause as a nominal

that is the object of the catenative verb, thereby setting the catenatives alike to

transitive verbs. While this analysis may be applicable to certain constructions, it

is by no means a valid description of sentences like (7a). This is obvious from the

fact that a subordinate clause can appear with verbs that do not allow an object.

(7) a) He decided to go. b) *He decided the plan. (Palmer 1987: 212)

The easiest method of distinguishing between catenatives and full verbs are

the TNP tests, namely tense, negation and passivisation. While a catenative can be

marked for tense and negation simultaneously with its main verb, a full verb only

allows this once. This is shown by the following:

(8) a) have remembered seeing...b) remembered having seen... c) have seen...

(9) a) have not remembered seeing...b) remembered not having seen...c) have not seen... [INT1]

The passivisation test helps to distinguish catenatives from transitive verbs

with an object complement. While a transitive verb with a direct object can be

passivised easily, this is not true for catenatives.

(10)a) The girl liked working.b) Working was liked by the girl.

(11)a) The girl kept (on) workig.b) *Working was kept on by the girl. [INT1]

Dragana
Highlight
Page 6: Catenatives or Complex VP

6

2.2 Auxiliaries, modals, modifier, operator, quasi-modal

Often, the definition of a separate class of catenative verbs requires some

redefinitions and further distinctions to be made amongst the auxiliaries. These are

of course different with each approach taken towards the catenatives.

Hudson's decision to include the traditional auxiliary verbs amongst the

catenatives leads him to establishing a class of non-catenative operators, allowing

him to distinguish between catenative and non-catenative uses of be and have.

While the use in (2) is termed catenative, that in (12) is not. (Hudson 2002)

(12)She is ready. - Is she ready?

Despite the fact that "there is no clear line between auxiliaries, catenatives

and other verbs that may have subordination" (Palmer 1987: 29), Palmer dismisses

the suggestion to treat all auxiliaries as full verbs. He argues that, although here

"[t]he TNP tests are ... rather inconclusive" (Palmer 1987: 31), a distinction can be

made on semantic grounds. While the auxiliaries do not cause semantic

restrictions on the choice of subjects, restrictions may occur based on the first full

verb. He contrasts:

(13)a) The water may run down the street. b) *The water intended to run down the street.

Thus, the auxiliaries are only modifiers to the full verb which is the main verb

of the verb phrase. (Palmer 1987: 31)

Huddleston, in his 2005 collaboration with Pullum, revised his position on the

auxiliaries that had been criticised by Palmer (Palmer 1987: 28) stating that

"auxiliaries, when used as markers of tense, aspect, mood or voice, are catenative

verbs, entering into the simple catenative construction", generally taking raised

subjects. (Huddleston 2005: 219) Already in 1997 he had explained his position of

"not applying the term auxiliary to what [he is] calling the operator class".

(Huddleston 1997: 143)

In their 'Comprehensive Grammar of the English Language', Quirk et al. argue

for a gradient of modality, ranging from the central modals consisting of one verb

phrase (can, may, shall &c.) to main verbs with non-finite clauses that are

Page 7: Catenatives or Complex VP

7

analysed as two verb phrases (e.g. hope with to-infinitive). The catenatives occupy

a position between the semi-auxiliaries (have to, be about to ...) and the main

verbs. (Quirk 1985: 137) While they resemble the auxiliaries in that most of the

catenatives share the independence of subject, they are "nearer to main verb

constructions than are semi-auxiliaries, patterning entirely like main verbs in

taking do-support". (Quirk 1985: 146)

2.3 From finite to non-finite VP

There are four basic non-finite forms of main verbs: the bare infinitive, the to-

infinitive, the -en and the-ing form (the latter summarising gerunds and present

participles). These occur in simple as well as in complex catenative verb phrases.

A rather isolated position towards the to-infinitive is taken by Richard

Hudson who suggests the analysis of to as a non-finite auxiliary verb on its own.

(Hudson 1998: 68)

2.4 Simple vs. complex verb phrases

A rather straightforward definition for the distinction between simple and complex

VP is given by Quirk et al. who define the finite verb phrase as being simple when

it consists of one word and complex when it consists of more. (Quirk 1985: 151)

According to Palmer, the three criteria that can be used to distinguish between

simple and complex verb phrases are: tense, negation and passivisation; called the

TNP tests. In a simple verb phrase both tense and negation can occur only once

and a simple phrase can be passivised without problems. Sequences of such

phrases are then complex verb phrases. (Palmer 1987: 28) He summarises that:

"Phrases involving primary auxiliaries are fairly clearly simple, while those withcatenatives are complex (though not all pass all the tests). Phrases with modals liesomewhere between the two, sharing characteristics of both simple and complexphrases." (Palmer 1987: 28)

This is not completely congruent with the more traditional approach of

applying the term 'complex verb group' to the combination of one to three

Page 8: Catenatives or Complex VP

8

auxiliaries with a lexical verb or a complex verb (i.e. a lexical verb with a

complement). [INT1]

Instead of arguing for a clean cut distinction between cases involving one or

two verb phrases, Quirk et al. argue the gradient from auxiliary to main verb

implies a similar gradience in the analysis of verb phrases, resulting in catenatives

having intermediate status between a single and a multiple verb phrase analysis.

They suggest that (14) "consists syntactically of two verb phrases would have had

and to have arrested, but semantically only of one". (Quirk 1985: 154p.)

(14)...we would have had to have arrested you.

Quirk et al. are accused by Huddleston of not being too precise on their point

of modality and he suggests they use "one analysis in which auxiliaries and related

expressions are treated as verbs taking non-finite complementation, so that a more

comprehensive and systematic account could be given of the verb/adjective + non-

finite construction". (Huddleston19882: 350)

Huddleston criticises Halliday's definition of verbal groups put forward in his

'Introduction to functional Grammar', where a sequence of words of the primary

class verb constitutes a verbal group (the sample given is: didn't know how to

spell), as this definition implies, according to Huddleston, "that to and not are

either verbs or not words". (Huddleston 19881: 172)

Page 9: Catenatives or Complex VP

9

3 Simple and complex catenatives

Most linguists agree on four basic forms of catenative constructions that can be

distinguished, based on the type of non-finite construction that is employed.

The four basic types of catenatives as exemplified by Palmer:

(15)a) bare infinitive He helped wash up.b) to-infinitive He wants to go to London.c) -ing form He keeps talking about it. d) -en form He got shot in the riot. (Palmer 1987: 173)

The choice, which non-finite construction to use, is largely dependent on the

catenative verb, while some allow variation others allow only one type of non-

finite construction. (Huddleston 1997: 210) When there is a choice of

constructions, there is generally some difference in meaning. Palmer contrasts the

-ing form and the to- infinitive, obviously carrying different meanings:

(16)a) He was seen walking away.b) He was seen to walk away. (Palmer 1987: 189)

Huddleston notes that only the bare infinitive and the to-infinitive "occur with

significant numbers of catenative verbs", and additionally, clauses involving the

-en form are invariably passive. (Huddleston 1997: 211)

As with the VP, the catenative verbs can occur in simple or complex

constructions.

A different approach is taken by Mindt in his 'Empirical Grammar of the

English Verb', who not only recognises the four classes mentioned above, but also

defines catenative auxiliary constructions (e.g. is going to be, are allowed to do)

and catenative adjective constructions(e.g. were able to escape). He states that the

last two classes are far less frequent than the four 'central catenative constructions'

and backs up his claim with data from his corpus analysis1 (Mindt 1995: 285). His

description of the function of modal verbs and catenative verbs is criticised by

Kamphuis as being "in fact identical". (Kamphuis 1996: 89) The classification of

catenative verbs proposed by Mindt is severely criticised by de Haan according to

1 This data, however, is somewhat problematic as he does not give any sources for his corpus, stating only that he "had access to more than 240 million words of English". (Mindt 1995: 6)

Page 10: Catenatives or Complex VP

10

whom he "fails to justify the existence of the category of catenative verbs"; while

he acknowledges that there are good reasons for wishing to distinguish such a

category, he accuses Mindt of not presenting "any convincing arguments for this",

and not being consistent in his argumentation. (de Haan 2002) One of Mindt's

definitions is that "catenative verbs allow the overlap of two meanings within one

verb phrase. This overlap cannot be achieved by modal verbs alone, because a

verb phrase cannot contain more than one modal verb." (Mindt 1995: 469) This, in

turn, is rejected by de Haan as well.

3.1 Simple catenatives

The identification of the subject in simple catenative sentences is usually

unproblematic. Here the subject of the subordinate clause is identical with that of

the main clause. Huddleston, however, notes that there are one or two exceptional

verbs, giving say as an example:

(17) Your mother said to meet her at two o'clock. (Huddleston 2005: 216)

In (17), the subject cannot be determined syntactically, it has to be inferred

from the context.

Whereas Huddleston's 'Introduction to the Grammar of English' only

distinguished between the verbs of the seem and expect classes (noting that most

verbs belong to the latter) (Huddleston 1997: 212pp.), Huddleston and Pullum

specify this by distinguishing between ordinary and raised subjects in simple

catenative phrases. While an ordinary subject is in semantic relation to the verb, a

raised subject belongs semantically to the subordinate clause. While (18a)

contains an ordinary subject, the subject in (18b) is raised. A simple passivisation

test illustrates the difference: While (18b) and (18d) have the same meaning, the

passivisation of a sentence containing an ordinary subject will result in a change

of meaning, e.g. from a) to c). (Huddleston 2005: 216)

(18)a) Sara wanted to convince Ed.b) Sara seemed to convince Ed. c) Ed wanted to be convinced by Sara.d) Ed seemed to be convinced by Sara.

Page 11: Catenatives or Complex VP

11

3.2 Complex catenatives

The same constructions as in (16) are also possible with an intervening noun

phrase between the catenative and the following verb.

(19)a) bare infinitive He helped them wash up.b) to-infinitive He wants them to go to London.c) -ing form He kept them talking a long time. d) -en form He had the rioters shot. (Palmer 1987: 174)

The identification of subjects in complex catenative phrases is not as

straightforward as it is in simple ones. Palmer shows the subject of the

subordinate clause to be identical with the intervening noun phrase by contrasting

sentences with reversed NP.

(20)a) The farmers want the hens to lay eggs.b) *The hens want the farmers to lay eggs. (Palmer 1987: 178)

The identity relations are not, however, the same with all verbs. It is argued

by Palmer that for some verbs "The intervening noun phrase is both the object of

the verb of the main clause and the subject of the subordinate", noting this

difference on the example of:

(21)a) I wanted the doctor to examine the boy. b) I persuaded the doctor to examine the boy. (Palmer 1987: 179)

By application of the passivisation test it is shown that the doctor in (21) is

indeed the object of persuaded but not of wanted:

(22)a) The doctor was persuaded to examine the boy.b) *The doctor was wanted to examine the boy.c) I wanted the boy to be examined by the doctor. d) I persuaded the boy to be examined by the doctor. (Palmer 1987: 179)

Passivisation of the main clause shows that (22a) is possible but (22b) is not.

Likewise, the passivisation of the subordinate clauses results in a difference of

meaning between the two sentences.

A further feature of complex catenative verbs is that they frequently occur

with prepositions. Here, the choice of preposition is determined by the catenative

verb. These constructions can be classified according to the same patterns as

catenatives without prepositions. Thus, Palmer likens 23a) to 23b),

Page 12: Catenatives or Complex VP

12

(23)a) I long for John to come. b) I want John to come. (Palmer 1987: 185pp)

Analogous to the distinction between ordinary and raised subjects with simple

catenatives, Huddleston distinguishes ordinary and raised objects in complex

catenative constructions. While the raised object, although it belongs semantically

to the catenative complement, is syntactically embedded in the superordinate

clause, the ordinary object is related semantically to the verb of the superordinate

clause. Again this can be tested by means of passivisation: The meaning of (24b)

remains the same when passivised to (24c), thus it is a raised object, that of (24a)

does not, (24a) therefore having an ordinary object.

(24)a) We urged a specialist to examine Ed.b) We wanted a specialist to examine Ed.c) We urged Ed to be examined by a specialist. d) We wanted Ed to be examined by a specialist. (Huddleston 2005: 221)

Some verbs allow construction with a PossP instead of a NP. While all PossP

can be replaced by NP, not all verbs that take a NP allow the possessive

construction. Huddleston notes that the difference between the two forms is

stylistic, (25b) being the more formal one. (Huddleston 1997: 221)

(25)a) Ed resented your father opening the mail.b) Ed resented your father's opening the mail.

Page 13: Catenatives or Complex VP

13

4 Classes and classification

There is an obvious interest in grouping catenative verbs into distinct classes of

verbs. This can be done according to a variety of criteria, both semantic and

syntactic. An important decision that is to be made is whether to allow multiple

class membership for certain verbs.

Rather of theoretical importance is the decision, if verbs are allowed multiple

class membership, whether to treat this as cases of homonymy or polysemy.

Palmer acknowledges his decision as "often fairly arbitrary", judging on practical

reasons on a case to case basis.

4.1 Criteria for classification

Two distinct approaches toward the classification of catenatives can be seen. One

method is to compare the syntactic patterns exhibited by each construction, from

the type of infinitive used to the patterning of intervening NP. Another approach is

to define groups of related meanings together, e.g. verbs of report, perception,

attitude or need.

4.2 Syntactical or semantic grouping

Gramley and Pätzold distinguish "some thirty different classes of catenatives",

grouped according to their meanings. They count 500 - 600 verbs that are

involved. This high number is partly due to the fact that some verbs are counted

twice or more as "multiple class membership is common". (Gramley & Pätzold

1992: 168)

Palmer distinguishes three classes of catenative verbs according to the pattern

of subject identification, one class of verbs without, and two classes that take an

intervening NP, labelled the persuade and the want pattern respectively. (Palmer

1987: 179pp.) He admits that this is no ideal solution as there are several verbs

that do not fit either of this patterns. Examples he gives for such complicated

Page 14: Catenatives or Complex VP

14

cases include: order, believe, expect and promise. In the case of order, he states

that the distinction between the two classes is simply not valid, believe can be

handled if the concept of subject raising is applied. He summarises that:

"There is a great deal of indeterminacy here; the best we can do is to state the facts -that there are verbs that may occur with either construction, ie may or may not havethe NP as the object of the main clause, though often with no clear distinctionbetween the two, and that there are others such as BELIEVE that permit main clausepassivization, even though semantically the NP is not the object of the main clause."(Palmer 1987: 183)

According to Palmer, the use of all possible criteria for the classification of

catenatives (i.e. the type of non-finite form, the pattern of identity relation and the

specific features of tense, phase, aspect and voice) would result in "a vast number

of classes", making it preferable "simply to approach the problem lexically, to list

the verbs and to state for each individually, its characteristics in terms of the

criteria." (Palmer 1987: 187) Reducing the number of criteria would lead to verbs

being either placed in multiple classes or borderline cases not really fitting

anywhere.

Palmer proposes to apply a semantic grouping of verbs that, actually, bears

close correspondence with the syntactic categories. He introduces nine classes

with a total of 31 subclasses. (Palmer 1987: 191pp)

Page 15: Catenatives or Complex VP

15

5 Conclusion / Summary

There remain the different approaches of whether to apply strict categories in

analyses, or to allow for some gradience between two points (most prominently

concerning finiteness and modality). Also, how to assess the importance of syntax

or semantics, as an analysis will frequently differ in results based on whether a

syntactic or a semantic approach was favoured.

Due to the fact that there is no agreement yet (nor is there likely to be) over

even the broader points of the analysis of catenative verbs, nor are there definite

solutions for a number of problems associated with them, certain implications

arise. It is obvious that the topic of catenative verbs will not feature very

prominently in language learning, thus beginning learners (i.e. in schools) will

most likely never come into contact with the more detailed points of their analysis.

It will be enough to note that some verbs can 'introduce some sub-clause', but

teachers will not have to be able to explain catenatives in detail.

Another factor is the presentation of information in dictionaries: Huddleston

states that "there is no getting away from the fact that the lexical entries for verbs

must specify which kinds of complements they take and, where more than one is

involved, the semantic differences (if any)". (Huddleston 1997: 210p.) While

traditional dictionaries mark all verbs as transitive, intransitive or both,

Huddleston suggests that this distinction is not very comprehensive stating the

need for syntactically adequate lexica giving specific information on valid

complements where "the transitive/ intransitive contrast will have a good deal less

of importance". (Huddleston 1997: 223) This would then merit a closer look at the

concept of valeny and extensive valency deicionaries.

Page 16: Catenatives or Complex VP

16

6 References

de Haan, Pieter. 2002. "Review article on An empirical grammar of the English verb:Modal verbs, by Dieter Mindt." In Journal of English Linguistics. 30. pp. 274-280. http://www.let.kun.nl/~p.dehaan/reviews/Mindt_2000_review.php.

Gramley, Stephan / Pätzold, Kurt-Michael. 1992. A Survey of Modern English. Londonand New York: Routledge.

Halliday, M.A.K. / Matthiesen, M.I.M. 2005. An Introduction to Functional Grammar.London: Arnold.

Huddleston, Rodney. 19881. "Constituency, multi-functionality and grammaticalizationin Halliday's Functional Grammar." In Linguistics. 24. pp.137-174.

Huddleston, Rodney. 19882. "Review article on A comprehensive Grammar of theEnglish Language, by Randolph Quirk, Sidney Greenbaum, Geoffrey Leech, andJan Svartvik. Index by David Crystal." In Language. 64. pp. 345-354.

Huddleston, Rodney. 1997. Introduction to the Grammar of English. Cambridge et. al.:Cambridge University Press.

Huddleston, Rodney / Pullum, Geoffrey. 2005. A Student's Introduction to EnglishGrammar. Cambridge et. al.: Cambridge University Press.

Hudson, Richard. 1998. English Grammar. London and New York.:Routledge.

Hudson, Richard. 2002. Linguistics Association of Great Britain - Language FactSheet: Auxiliary Verbs. http://www.phon.ucl.ac.uk/home/dick/aux.htm.1

Kamphuis, Vera. 1996. "Review article on An empirical grammar of the English verb:Modal verbs, by Dieter Mindt." In ICAME Journal. 20. pp. 86-90.

Mindt, Dieter. 2000. An empirical Grammar of the English Verb System. Berlin:Cornelsen.

Palmer, Frank Robert. 1987. The English Verb. London and New York: Longman.

Quirk, Randolph / Greenbaum, Sidney / Leech, Geoffrey / Svartvik, Jan.1985. Acomprehensive Grammar of the English Language. London and New York:Longman.

1 html document without page numbering, thus references are given to entire document

Page 17: Catenatives or Complex VP

17

Internet Sources

[INT1] www.linguistics-online.de; module: Formal Aspects of the Verb - catenatives,accessed: September 10, 2005.