choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · induced choice functions given a preference...

50
Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty Arthur Van Camp 5 March 2019

Upload: others

Post on 08-Oct-2020

9 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Choice functionsas a tool to model

uncertainty

Arthur Van Camp

5 March 2019

Page 2: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Imprecise probabilities

=

broaden probability theory in order to deal with imprecision andindecision.

Basic idea of imprecise probabilities: decisions and choice.

Page 3: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Imprecise probabilities

=

broaden probability theory in order to deal with imprecision andindecision.

Basic idea of imprecise probabilities: decisions and choice.

Page 4: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

(Precise) choice functions

A preference relation is ≺ is a strict weak order (irreflexive and transitive,with transitive absence of preference binary relation) on a set of options.

The goal is to observe a subject’s choices to learn about her preferences.

A: set of option (non-empty but finite)

C(A): chosen or admissible or non-rejected options

R(A): rejected options (R(A) = A \C(A))

A choice function C is a map

C : Q→Q∪{ /0} : A 7→ C(A) such that C(A)⊆ A.

Page 5: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

(Precise) choice functions

A preference relation is ≺ is a strict weak order (irreflexive and transitive,with transitive absence of preference binary relation) on a set of options.

The goal is to observe a subject’s choices to learn about her preferences.

A: set of option (non-empty but finite)

C(A): chosen or admissible or non-rejected options

R(A): rejected options (R(A) = A \C(A))

A choice function C is a map

C : Q→Q∪{ /0} : A 7→ C(A) such that C(A)⊆ A.

Page 6: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

(Precise) choice functions

A preference relation is ≺ is a strict weak order (irreflexive and transitive,with transitive absence of preference binary relation) on a set of options.

The goal is to observe a subject’s choices to learn about her preferences.

A: set of option (non-empty but finite)

C(A): chosen or admissible or non-rejected options

R(A): rejected options (R(A) = A \C(A))

A choice function C is a map

C : Q→Q∪{ /0} : A 7→ C(A) such that C(A)⊆ A.

Page 7: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

(Precise) choice functions

A preference relation is ≺ is a strict weak order (irreflexive and transitive,with transitive absence of preference binary relation) on a set of options.

The goal is to observe a subject’s choices to learn about her preferences.

A: set of option (non-empty but finite)

C(A): chosen or admissible or non-rejected options

R(A): rejected options (R(A) = A \C(A))

A choice function C is a map

C : Q→Q∪{ /0} : A 7→ C(A) such that C(A)⊆ A.

Page 8: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Induced choice functions

Given a preference relation ≺, the induced choice function C≺ is definedby

C≺(A) := {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6≺ g}.

A choice function C is rationalisable if there is a preference relation ≺such that C = C≺; if this is the case, then C is rationalised by ≺.

Proposition: if C is rationalised by ≺, then ≺ can be retrieved by

f ≺ g⇔ (∃A ∈Q)f ∈ C(A) and g ∈ R(A).

Page 9: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Induced choice functions

Given a preference relation ≺, the induced choice function C≺ is definedby

C≺(A) := {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6≺ g}.

A choice function C is rationalisable if there is a preference relation ≺such that C = C≺; if this is the case, then C is rationalised by ≺.

Proposition: if C is rationalised by ≺, then ≺ can be retrieved by

f ≺ g⇔ (∃A ∈Q)f ∈ C(A) and g ∈ R(A).

Page 10: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Induced choice functions

Given a preference relation ≺, the induced choice function C≺ is definedby

C≺(A) := {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6≺ g}.

A choice function C is rationalisable if there is a preference relation ≺such that C = C≺; if this is the case, then C is rationalised by ≺.

Proposition: if C is rationalised by ≺, then ≺ can be retrieved by

f ≺ g⇔ (∃A ∈Q)f ∈ C(A) and g ∈ R(A).

Page 11: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Induced choice functions

Given a preference relation ≺, the induced choice function C≺ is definedby

C≺(A) := {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6≺ g}.

When is C rationalisable?

Non-emptiness

C(A) 6= /0.

Houthakker’s axiom

If f ,g ∈ A1∩A2, f ∈ C(A1) and g ∈ C(A2), then f ∈ C(A2).

Proposition: C is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom if and onlyif C is rationalisable.

Page 12: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Induced choice functions

Given a preference relation ≺, the induced choice function C≺ is definedby

C≺(A) := {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6≺ g}.

When is C rationalisable?

Non-emptiness

C(A) 6= /0.

Houthakker’s axiom

If f ,g ∈ A1∩A2, f ∈ C(A1) and g ∈ C(A2), then f ∈ C(A2).

Proposition: C is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom if and onlyif C is rationalisable.

Page 13: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Induced choice functions

Given a preference relation ≺, the induced choice function C≺ is definedby

C≺(A) := {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6≺ g}.

When is C rationalisable?

Non-emptiness

C(A) 6= /0.

Houthakker’s axiom

If f ,g ∈ A1∩A2, f ∈ C(A1) and g ∈ C(A2), then f ∈ C(A2).

Proposition: C is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom if and onlyif C is rationalisable.

Page 14: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Example: probabilities

A random variable X takes values in the finite possibility space X .

We have a probability mass function p on X .

What choice function describes my beliefs?

Page 15: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

What we choose between: gambles

A gamble f : X → R is an uncertain reward whose value is f (X ), and wecollect all gambles in L = RX .

X = {H,T}

H

T

1

1

f

= (f (H), f (T))

f (H)

f (T)

Page 16: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

What we choose between: gambles

A gamble f : X → R is an uncertain reward whose value is f (X ), and wecollect all gambles in L = RX .

X = {H,T}

H

T

1

1

f = (f (H), f (T))

f (H)

f (T)

Page 17: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Fair coin

p(T) p(H)

H

T

Assessment: “The coin is fair.”

f <p g⇔ Ep(f )< Ep(g)

Cp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)Ep(g)≤ Ep(f )}= argmax{f ∈ A : Ep(f )}

Cp is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is thereforerationalisable, with ≺=<p.

Page 18: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Fair coin

p(T) p(H)

H

T

Assessment: “The coin is fair.”

f <p g⇔ Ep(f )< Ep(g)

Cp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)Ep(g)≤ Ep(f )}= argmax{f ∈ A : Ep(f )}

Cp is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is thereforerationalisable, with ≺=<p.

Page 19: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Fair coin

p(T) p(H)

H

T

Assessment: “The coin is fair.”

f <p g⇔ Ep(f )< Ep(g)

Cp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)Ep(g)≤ Ep(f )}= argmax{f ∈ A : Ep(f )}

Cp is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is thereforerationalisable, with ≺=<p.

Page 20: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Fair coin

p(T) p(H)

H

T

Assessment: “The coin is fair.”

f <p g⇔ Ep(f )< Ep(g)

Cp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)Ep(g)≤ Ep(f )}= argmax{f ∈ A : Ep(f )}

Cp is non-empty and satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is thereforerationalisable, with ≺=<p.

Page 21: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Sets of probabilities

p(T) p(H)

convex and closed set M of probabilities

Assessment: “H is at least as likely as T.”

CM (A) =⋃

p∈MCp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∃p ∈M )f ∈ Cp(A)}.

CM does not satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is therefore notrationalisable.

Page 22: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Sets of probabilities

p(T) p(H)

convex and closed set M of probabilities

Assessment: “H is at least as likely as T.”

CM (A) =⋃

p∈MCp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∃p ∈M )f ∈ Cp(A)}.

CM does not satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is therefore notrationalisable.

Page 23: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Sets of probabilities

p(T) p(H)

convex and closed set M of probabilities

Assessment: “H is at least as likely as T.”

CM (A) =⋃

p∈MCp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∃p ∈M )f ∈ Cp(A)}.

CM does not satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is therefore notrationalisable.

Page 24: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Sets of probabilities

p(T) p(H)

convex and closed set M of probabilities

Assessment: “H is at least as likely as T.”

CM (A) =⋃

p∈MCp(A) = {f ∈ A : (∃p ∈M )f ∈ Cp(A)}.

CM does not satisfies Houthakker’s Axiom, and is therefore notrationalisable.

Page 25: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

“Non-Archimedean” beliefs

Assessment: “The coin is infinitesimally biased towards H,but not by any definite amount.”

p(T) p(H)“H is more likely than T.”

p(T) p(H)still biased by some amount

p(T) p(H)“H is equally likely as T.”

(Sets of) probabilities cannot capture this belief.

Page 26: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

“Non-Archimedean” beliefs

Assessment: “The coin is infinitesimally biased towards H,but not by any definite amount.”

p(T) p(H)“H is more likely than T.”

p(T) p(H)still biased by some amount

p(T) p(H)“H is equally likely as T.”

(Sets of) probabilities cannot capture this belief.

Page 27: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

“Non-Archimedean” beliefs

Assessment: “The coin is infinitesimally biased towards H,but not by any definite amount.”

p(T) p(H)“H is more likely than T.”

p(T) p(H)still biased by some amount

p(T) p(H)“H is equally likely as T.”

(Sets of) probabilities cannot capture this belief.

Page 28: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Binary choice: Sets of desirable gambles

Preference relation � on L . For all f ,g,h in L and real λ > 0:

f � g⇔ λ f +h � λg+h.

The subject’s set of desirable gambles: which gambles does she strictlyprefer to 0?

How does that work?

f � g⇔ f −g � 0⇔ f −g ∈ D

for all f and g in L .

To summarise:D = {f ∈L : f � 0}.

Page 29: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Binary choice: Sets of desirable gambles

Preference relation � on L . For all f ,g,h in L and real λ > 0:

f � g⇔ λ f +h � λg+h.

The subject’s set of desirable gambles: which gambles does she strictlyprefer to 0?

How does that work?

f � g⇔ f −g � 0⇔ f −g ∈ D

for all f and g in L .

To summarise:D = {f ∈L : f � 0}.

Page 30: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Binary choice: Sets of desirable gambles

Preference relation � on L . For all f ,g,h in L and real λ > 0:

f � g⇔ λ f +h � λg+h.

The subject’s set of desirable gambles: which gambles does she strictlyprefer to 0?

How does that work?

f � g⇔ f −g � 0⇔ f −g ∈ D

for all f and g in L .

To summarise:D = {f ∈L : f � 0}.

Page 31: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Binary choice: Sets of desirable gambles

Preference relation � on L . For all f ,g,h in L and real λ > 0:

f � g⇔ λ f +h � λg+h.

The subject’s set of desirable gambles: which gambles does she strictlyprefer to 0?

How does that work?

f � g⇔ f −g � 0⇔ f −g ∈ D

for all f and g in L .

To summarise:D = {f ∈L : f � 0}.

Page 32: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Binary choice: Sets of desirable gambles

Set of desirable gambles D = {f ∈L : f � 0} ⊆L

Working with sets of desirable gambles is simple and elegant.

They include lower previsions and sets of probabilities as a special case.

They generalise conservative logical inference (natural extension).

Page 33: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability modelhalfspace: precise probability modelsmallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 34: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability modelhalfspace: precise probability modelsmallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 35: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability modelhalfspace: precise probability modelsmallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 36: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability modelhalfspace: precise probability modelsmallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 37: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability model

halfspace: precise probability modelsmallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 38: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability model

halfspace: precise probability model

smallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 39: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent sets of desirable gamblesA set of desirable gambles D is called coherent if for all f ,g in L :D1. if f ≤ 0 then f /∈ D [not desiring non-positivity]D2. if f > 0 then f ∈ D [accepting partial gains]D3. if f ∈ D then λ f ∈ D for all real λ > 0 [scaling]D4. if f ,g ∈ D then f +g ∈ D [addition]

halfspace: precise probability modelhalfspace: precise probability model

smallest coherent Dv: the vacuous model

H

T

Page 40: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Example: Choice based on desirability

Assessment: “The coin is infinitesimally biased towards H,but not by any definite amount.”

H

T

CD(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)g− f /∈ D}, so f ∈ CD(A)⇔ A−{f}∩D = /0.

Page 41: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Example: Choice based on desirability

Assessment: “The coin is infinitesimally biased towards H,but not by any definite amount.”

H

T

CD(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)g− f /∈ D}, so f ∈ CD(A)⇔ A−{f}∩D = /0.

Page 42: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Example: Choice based on desirability

Assessment: “The coin is infinitesimally biased towards H,but not by any definite amount.”

H

T

CD(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)g− f /∈ D}, so f ∈ CD(A)⇔ A−{f}∩D = /0.

Page 43: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Disjunctive statements

Assessment: “The coin has two identical sides of unknown type.”

Consider the coherent sets of desirable gambles

DH = {f ∈L : f (H)> 0}∪L>0 and DT = {f ∈L : f (T)> 0}∪L>0.

H

T

H

T

Then D = DH∩DT = L>0 is the vacuous set of desirable gambles.

Page 44: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Disjunctive statements

Assessment: “The coin has two identical sides of unknown type.”

Consider the coherent sets of desirable gambles

DH = {f ∈L : f (H)> 0}∪L>0 and DT = {f ∈L : f (T)> 0}∪L>0.

H

T

H

T

Then D = DH∩DT = L>0 is the vacuous set of desirable gambles.

Page 45: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coherent choice functions

We call a choice function C on L coherent if for all A,A1,A2 in Q, f ,g inL and λ in R>0:

C1. C(A) 6= /0; [non-emptiness]

C2. if f < g then f ∈ R({f ,g}); [non-triviality]

C3a. if A ⊆ R(A1) and A1 ⊆ A2 then A ⊆ R(A2); [Sen’s condition α]

C3b. if A1 ⊆ R(A2) and A ⊆ A1then A1 \A ⊆ R(A2 \A); [Aizerman’s condition]

C4a. if A1 ⊆ C(A2) then λA1 ⊆ C(λA2); [scaling]

C4b. if A1 ⊆ C(A2) then A1 +{f} ⊆ C(A2 +{f}). [addition]

First axiomatisation: Seidenfeld, Schervish and Kadane, 2010.

Page 46: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Reasoning with choice functions

C1 is not more informative than C2 if C1(A)⊇ C2(A) for all A.

The smallest coherent choice function is

Cv(A) = max(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6< g}= CDv(A).

Page 47: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Reasoning with choice functions

C1 is not more informative than C2 if C1(A)⊇ C2(A) for all A.

The smallest coherent choice function is

Cv(A) = max(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)f 6< g}= CDv(A).

Page 48: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Coin with identical sides

Assessment: “The coin has two identical sides of unknown type.”

DH = {f ∈L : f (H)> 0}∪L>0 and DT = {f ∈L : f (T)> 0}∪L>0.

H

T

H

T

CH(A) = {f ∈ A : (∀g ∈ A)g− f /∈ DH}= argmax{f ∈max(A) : f (H)}CT(A) = argmax{f ∈max(A) : f (T)}

But

C(A) = argmax{f ∈max(A) : f (H)}∪argmax{f ∈max(A) : f (T)}.

Page 49: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f

Overview

Fair coinProbability

H at least as likely as T(Convex and closed) sets of

probabilities

infinitesimally biasedSets of desirable gambles

disjunctive statements(Arbitrary) sets of probabilities

unificationChoice functions

Page 50: Choice functions as a tool to model uncertainty · Induced choice functions Given a preference relation ˚, theinduced choice function C ˚is defined by C ˚(A):=ff 2A :(8g 2A)f