clarifying the definition of religion under english law

26
Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law: The Need for a Universal Definition R USSELL S ANDBERG 1 Head of Law and Reader in Law, Cardiff University There is no universal definition of religion under English law. Instead, different definitions have been developed by courts and tribunals in relation to different religious rights. Although there have been moves towards the harmonisation of these different definitions, recent decisions have reversed that trend. This article explores for the first time how this has led to a confused and contradictory case law. It begins by surveying how religion has been defined in registration law, charity law, human rights law and discrimination law, the moves towards harmonisation and the counter-tendencies in the recent decisions. It places the recent decisions within their broader legal context and points out a number of contradictions and uncertainties. Arguing that a universal definition of religion under English law is now needed, it synthesises the case law to identify the elements of a universal definition that already exist. The article examines how these can be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist in different areas of law. Drawing upon insights from the sociology of religion, the article concludes by proposing a new definition. Keywords: definition, religion, charity, registration, discrimination, human rights INTRODUCTION There has never been a universal legal definition of religion in English law, and experience across the common law world over many years has shown the pitfalls of attempting to attach a narrowly circumscribed meaning to the word. There are several reasons for this – the different contexts in which the issue may arise, the variety of world religions, developments of new religions and religious practices, and developments in the common understanding of the concept of religion due to cultural changes in society. 2 A number of definitions exist in law in relation to religion and belief. ... They reflect, to some extent, the different purposes that the laws are intended to have. ... What is, however, common with all those definitions 1 I am grateful to Dr Sharon Thompson, Caroline Roberts and Frank Cranmer for their helpful com- ments on a draft of this article. 2 R (on the Application of Hodkin) v Registrar General of Births, Deaths and Marriages [2013] UKSC 77 para 34 per Lord Toulson. (2018) 20 Ecc LJ 132–157 # Ecclesiastical Law Society doi:10.1017/S0956618X18000030 132 of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0956618X18000030 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 65.21.228.167, on 23 Nov 2021 at 03:17:40, subject to the Cambridge Core terms

Upload: others

Post on 23-Nov-2021

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under EnglishLaw The Need for a Universal Definition

RU S S E L L SA N D B E R G1

Head of Law and Reader in Law Cardiff University

There is no universal definition of religion under English law Instead different definitionshave been developed by courts and tribunals in relation to different religious rightsAlthough there have been moves towards the harmonisation of these different definitionsrecent decisions have reversed that trend This article explores for the first time how this hasled to a confused and contradictory case law It begins by surveying how religion has beendefined in registration law charity law human rights law and discrimination law themoves towards harmonisation and the counter-tendencies in the recent decisions It placesthe recent decisions within their broader legal context and points out a number ofcontradictions and uncertainties Arguing that a universal definition of religion underEnglish law is now needed it synthesises the case law to identify the elements of a universaldefinition that already exist The article examines how these can be refashioned in order toremove inconsistencies that exist in different areas of law Drawing upon insights from thesociology of religion the article concludes by proposing a new definition

Keywords definition religion charity registration discrimination human rights

INTRODUCTION

There has never been a universal legal definition of religion in English lawand experience across the common law world over many years has shownthe pitfalls of attempting to attach a narrowly circumscribed meaning tothe word There are several reasons for this ndash the different contexts inwhich the issue may arise the variety of world religions developmentsof new religions and religious practices and developments in thecommon understanding of the concept of religion due to culturalchanges in society2

A number of definitions exist in law in relation to religion and belief They reflect to some extent the different purposes that the laws areintended to have What is however common with all those definitions

1 I am grateful to Dr Sharon Thompson Caroline Roberts and Frank Cranmer for their helpful com-ments on a draft of this article

2 R (on the Application of Hodkin) v Registrar General of Births Deaths and Marriages [2013] UKSC 77para 34 per Lord Toulson

(2018) 20 Ecc LJ 132ndash157 Ecclesiastical Law Societydoi101017S0956618X18000030

132of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

is that none seeks to define what actual faiths or beliefs are covered by thelaw That is left to the courts to decide which is proper The courts arebest placed to make decisions on these difficult matters taking intoaccount all the information that they will have before them3

Like all definitions legal definitions primarily serve as mechanisms for inclu-sion and exclusion4 Legal definitions demarcate the granting of benefits andburdens of rights and duties those included in the definition are recognisedby law those excluded are denied legal recognition5 Legal definitions of religionwhich are adopted whether explicitly or implicitly determine which individualsand groups should be bestowed with legal advantages by virtue of the fact thatthey are lsquoreligiousrsquo6 Defining religion is therefore lsquoan exercise of powerrsquowhich can have serious repercussions7 It is also something that sometimescannot be avoided Unlike scholars who are able to recognise the complexityof the issue posit a range of partial definitions and then move on legal actorsmay well find that determining the definition of religion is crucial to theclaim that they are dealing with8

The importance of defining religion is felt under English law despite the factthat there is no compulsory registration scheme for religious groups9 Instead amultitude of overlapping laws have been enacted to recognise religious groupsand to enable them to benefit from legal and fiscal advantages most notably inthe form of exceptions from otherwise generally applicable obligationsReligious groups may register their buildings as places of public religiousworship and for the solemnisation of marriage10 In addition such groupsmay seek to register as a charity for the advancement of religion11 Individualsenjoy the human right to freedom of thought conscience and religion and pro-tection from discrimination on grounds of religion or belief12 The definitionand understanding of religion differs for each of these different religiousrights This has led to the situation described by Lord Toulson and BaronessScotland above recognising the lack of a universal definition of religion and

3 Baroness Scotland HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1107ndash11084 R Sandberg Religion Law and Society (Cambridge 2014) p 395 See eg G Thornton Legislative Drafting (third edition Oxford 1987) pp 56ndash57 See also V Crabbe

Legislative Drafting (London 1993) p 1096 See J Beckford lsquoThe politics of defining religion in secular societyrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk

(eds) The Pragmatics of Defining Religion Contexts Concepts amp Contests (Leiden 1999) pp 23ndash407 A Aldridge Religion in the Contemporary World a sociological introduction (third edition Oxford 2013)

p 228 P Edge lsquoDetermining religion in English courtsrsquo (2012) 12 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion

402ndash4239 This article focuses on the law in England and Wales The legal and religious context in Scotland and

Northern Ireland merits separate treatment10 Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 Marriage Act 1949 s 411 Charities Act 201112 European Convention on Human Rights Article 9 Equality Act 2010 s 10

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

the practice whereby the matter is largely left to the courts to adjudicate RichardRobinson distinguished between lsquostipulativersquo (or specific) definitions thatannounce that the subject is to be understood in a certain sense in a certaincontext and lsquolexicalrsquo (or universal) definitions that report the customarymeaning of the word13 Under English law there are several stipulative or spe-cific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each area of lawHowever there is no lexical or universal definition of religion

This article will contend that recent decisions have underscored the need forsuch a universal definition The first part of this article will take a chronologicalapproach exploring how the definition of religion under English law has devel-oped over the last fifty years It will be shown that there have been some movestowards the convergence of the different definitions of religion The second partwill explore how recent decisions by the Supreme Court and the CharityCommission have reversed this trend It will be argued that these decisionshave resulted in a complex and conflicting case law which points to arenewed need for a universal definition of religion under English law Thethird and final part will further this analysis drawing upon insights from thesociology of religion to suggest how a universal definition of religion coulddevelop

TOWARDS A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION OF RELIGION

The common law definitionOriginally the issue of defining religion did not arise Following the EnglishReformation of the 1530s there was only one lawful religion the establishedChurch of England14 A category of religion was therefore meaningless Whenthe Preamble to the Statute of Charitable Uses 1601 stated that gifts for therepair of churches were charitable it was clear that this referred to the buildingsof the established church15 And when subsequent case law recognised thattrusts gifts and institutions for the lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo were charitableand thus entitled to legal and fiscal advantages it was likewise understood

13 R Robinson Definition (Oxford 1954) p 1914 The English Reformation came later and was a different beast from that felt on the Continent The

divorce from Rome in the 1530s under Henry VIII was not a religious upheaval that required politicaland constitutional reconstruction rather it was a political and constitutional act that led in time toreligious upheaval See G Elton lsquoThe Reformation in Englandrsquo in G Elton (ed) The NewCambridge Modern History Volume 2 the Reformation 1520ndash1559 (second edition Cambridge1990) pp 262ndash287 F Maitland English Law and the Renaissance (Cambridge 1901) p 9

15 The Mortmain and Charitable Uses Act 1888 repealed the statute itself but expressly preserved thepreamble The Charities Act 1960 repealed the 1888 Act and thus the preamble However its finalrepeal does not affect the authority of the cases decided on it nor the principles on which futurecases are to be decided Incorporated Council of Law Reporting for England and Wales v A-G [1971]Ch 626 at 644 See also Charities Act 2011 Schedule 7 Part 1

1 3 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that this protected only the established Church of England16 The lsquosuperstitioususersquo ndash that is a trust for false religious purposes ndash was void17 As Newark put itsuch gifts were lsquoagainst public policy as furthering the schisms of nonconform-ity the errors of Rome or the infidelity of Judaism or heathenismrsquo18 The longand piecemeal process of religious toleration whereby disabilities placed onother religions were gradually removed widened considerably the concept ofadvancement of religion and also changed the rationale for protecting religion19

Rather than furthering the mission of the established church and preventingheretical and false religions it gradually became understood that the protectionof religion provided recognition of the psychological and social worth of individ-ual religiosity20 As Lord Reid noted in Gilmour v Coats English law no longerprefers lsquoone religion to anotherrsquo but lsquoassumes that it is good for man to haveand to practise a religionrsquo21

It was not until the latter years of the twentieth century however that domes-tic courts elucidated a definition of religion based upon stated criteria and usedthis definition to determine claims This occurred in two cases concerningregistration and charitable status respectively In the first R v RegistrarGeneral ex parte Segerdal22 the Court of Appeal upheld the decision by theRegistrar General not to register a chapel of the Church of Scientology as lsquoaplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo under section 3 of the Places ofWorship Registration Act 1855 For Buckley LJ and Winn LJ the determinativefactor was that there was no worship Winn LJ held that the adherents did notlsquohumble themselves in reverence and recognition of the dominant power andcontrol of any entity or being outside their own body and lifersquo23 while BuckleyLJ held that worship lsquomust have some at least of the following characteristicssubmission to the object worshipped veneration of that object praise thanks-giving prayer or intercessionrsquo24 He found that the evidence put forward includ-ing the Church of Scientologyrsquos book of ceremonies contained lsquono element of

16 Pember v Inhabitants of Kington (1639) 1 EqCasAbr 95 Tot 34 Special Commissioners of Income Tax vPemsel [1891] AC 531

17 P Edge Legal Responses to Religious Difference (The Hague 2002) p 5 However such gifts were some-times upheld In Da Costa v De Praz (1754) 2 Swan 487n a gift to advance the Jewish religion washeld to be unlawful but Lord Hardwicke left it to the Crown to direct a cy-pres application whereby thegift was applied but for the purposes of the Christian religion

18 F Newark lsquoPublic benefit and religious trustsrsquo (1946) 62 Law Quarterly Review 234ndash247 at 23519 See R Sandberg Law and Religion (Cambridge 2011) chapter 220 F Quint and P Hodkin lsquoThe development of tolerance and diversity in the treatment of religion in

charity lawrsquo (2007) 102 Charity Law and Practice Review 1ndash16 at 321 [1949] AC 426 at 45922 [1970] 2 QB 67923 Ibid at para 70924 Ibid at para 709 He qualified this lsquoI do not say that you would need to find every element in every act

which could properly be described as worship but when you find an act which contains none ofthose elements it cannot in my judgment answer to the description of an act of worshiprsquo (ibid)

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

worship at allrsquo25 By contrast for Lord Denning MR the phrase to be defined waslsquothe combined phrase ldquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprdquo as used in thestatute of 1855rsquo26 For Denning this connoted lsquoa place of which the principaluse is as a place where people come together as a congregation or assemblyto do reverence to Godrsquo lsquoReligious worship means reverence or veneration ofGod or of a Supreme Beingrsquo The decision in Segerdal did not thereforeconcern the definition of religion as such The judgments of Buckley LJ andWinn LJ focused on the definition of worship simpliciter while Lord Denningsought to define the combined phrase lsquoreligious worshiprsquo It is curious there-fore that this case concerning registration law was heavily relied upon in thesecond case which concerned charity law to provide a definition of religion

In the second case Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v AG27 the courtheld that the South Place Ethical Society a society for the lsquostudy and dissemin-ation of ethical principles and the cultivation of a rational religious sentimentrsquowas not charitable for the advancement of religion28 Echoing Lord Denning inSegerdal Dillon J distinguished religion from ethics as being lsquoconcerned withmanrsquos relations with Godrsquo rather than lsquowith manrsquos relations with manrsquo andheld that lsquotwo of the essential attributes of religion are faith and worshipfaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo29 Quoting with approval Buckley LJrsquos def-inition of worship in Segerdal Dillon J concluded that the South Place EthicalSociety did not have the purpose of advancing religion because there was nolsquoworship in the sense which worship is an attribute of religionrsquo lsquoindeed it isnot possible to worship in that way a mere ethical or philosophical idealrsquo30

No explanation was given as to why worship ought to be a definitional aspectof the term lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo

While Segerdal was concerned with defining the phrase lsquoplace of meeting forreligious worshiprsquo under registration law Re South Place Ethical Society was con-cerned with defining lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law Yet the defin-ition for the former was adopted without question for the latter Therequirement for lsquofaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo came to be understoodas the common law definition of religion except in relation to Buddhism whichwas admitted to be an lsquoexceptionrsquo31 And this definition was used to exclude any

25 Ibid at para 70926 Ibid at para 707 He noted that the Chapel of the Church of Scientology was not a lsquoplace of religious

worshiprsquo because the creed of the Church of Scientology was lsquomore a philosophy of the existence ofman or of life rather than a religionrsquo and that there was an absence of lsquoreverence or venerationrsquo andlsquoconsiderable stress on the spirit of manrsquo (ibid emphasis in original)

27 [1980] 1 WLR 156528 It was held otherwise charitable either for the advancement of education or under the fourth head of

charity by analogy with decided cases29 Ibid at paras 1571ndash157230 Ibid at para 157331 R v Registrar General ex parte Segerdal [1970] 2 QB 679 at 707 Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v

AG 1980] 1 WLR 1565 at 1573

1 3 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

religions where there was no evidence of worship For instance in 1999 theCharity Commission held that the Church of Scientology would not be regis-tered as a charity on the basis that the lsquocore practices of Scientology being audit-ing and training do not constitute worship as they do not display the essentialcharacteristic of reverence or veneration for a supreme beingrsquo32

Developments in human rights and discrimination lawAt the turn of the twenty-first century a number of new laws were enacted inEngland and Wales dealing with religious rights33 These statutory provisionsdefined and understood religion in broader terms The Human Rights Act1998 incorporated Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rightsinto domestic law introducing a positive right to freedom of thought conscienceand religion including the manifestation of religion or belief34 The domesticcourts followed the approach of Strasbourg in adopting a broad understandingof religion or belief regarding it not only as lsquoone of the most vital elements thatgo to make up the identity of believers and their conception of lifersquo but also as lsquoaprecious asset for atheists agnostics sceptics and the unconcernedrsquo35

Strasbourg institutions considered claims concerning Scientology36 druidism37

pacifism38 communism39 Nazism40 atheism41 pro-life42 Divine LightZentrum43 and the Moon Sect44 as well as lsquosplinterrsquo groups within larger tradi-tions45 and invariably did so without questioning whether such claims fitted thedefinition of religion or belief46 They considered the term lsquobeliefrsquo to require aworldview rather than a mere opinion it was defined in Campbell and Cosans vUnited Kingdom as denoting lsquoviews that attain a certain level of cogency

32 Church of Scientology Application to Charities Commission (17 November 1999) see httpwwwcharity-commissiongovukLibraryregistrationpdfscosfulldocpdf accessed 14 February 2018

33 See Sandberg Law and Religion chapter 10 Sandberg Religion Law and Society chapter 134 For discussion of the difference between positive and negative religious freedom see M Hill and R

Sandberg lsquoIs nothing sacred Clashing symbols in a secular worldrsquo (2007) Public Law 488ndash506 at490ndash491

35 Kokkinakis v Greece App no 1430788 (25 May 1993) at para 31 R v Secretary of State for Education andEmployment and others ex parte Williamson [2005] UKHL 15 at para 24

36 X and Church of Scientology v Sweden App no 780577 (5 May 1979)37 Chappell v United Kingdom App no 1046183 (30 March 1989)38 Arrowsmith v United Kingdom App no 705075 (12 October 1978)39 Hazar Hazar and Acik v Turkey App no 1631190 (11 October 1991)40 X v Austria App no 174762 (20 June 1963)41 Angeleni v Sweden (1988) 10 EHRR 123 (1986) 51 DampR 4142 Plattform lsquoArzte fur das Lebenrsquo v Austria App no 1012682 (21 June 1988)43 Omkarananda and the Divine Light Zentrum v Switzerland App no 818877 (19 March 1981)44 X v Austria App no 865279 (15 October 1981)45 Eg Serif v Greece App no 3817897 (14 December 1999) (mufti elected by mosque congregations in

opposition to the mufti appointed by the government)46 Though claimants have been required to prove the genuineness of their belief and the existence of

the religion in question X v UK App no 721575 (12 October 1978) Williamson at para 22

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

is that none seeks to define what actual faiths or beliefs are covered by thelaw That is left to the courts to decide which is proper The courts arebest placed to make decisions on these difficult matters taking intoaccount all the information that they will have before them3

Like all definitions legal definitions primarily serve as mechanisms for inclu-sion and exclusion4 Legal definitions demarcate the granting of benefits andburdens of rights and duties those included in the definition are recognisedby law those excluded are denied legal recognition5 Legal definitions of religionwhich are adopted whether explicitly or implicitly determine which individualsand groups should be bestowed with legal advantages by virtue of the fact thatthey are lsquoreligiousrsquo6 Defining religion is therefore lsquoan exercise of powerrsquowhich can have serious repercussions7 It is also something that sometimescannot be avoided Unlike scholars who are able to recognise the complexityof the issue posit a range of partial definitions and then move on legal actorsmay well find that determining the definition of religion is crucial to theclaim that they are dealing with8

The importance of defining religion is felt under English law despite the factthat there is no compulsory registration scheme for religious groups9 Instead amultitude of overlapping laws have been enacted to recognise religious groupsand to enable them to benefit from legal and fiscal advantages most notably inthe form of exceptions from otherwise generally applicable obligationsReligious groups may register their buildings as places of public religiousworship and for the solemnisation of marriage10 In addition such groupsmay seek to register as a charity for the advancement of religion11 Individualsenjoy the human right to freedom of thought conscience and religion and pro-tection from discrimination on grounds of religion or belief12 The definitionand understanding of religion differs for each of these different religiousrights This has led to the situation described by Lord Toulson and BaronessScotland above recognising the lack of a universal definition of religion and

3 Baroness Scotland HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1107ndash11084 R Sandberg Religion Law and Society (Cambridge 2014) p 395 See eg G Thornton Legislative Drafting (third edition Oxford 1987) pp 56ndash57 See also V Crabbe

Legislative Drafting (London 1993) p 1096 See J Beckford lsquoThe politics of defining religion in secular societyrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk

(eds) The Pragmatics of Defining Religion Contexts Concepts amp Contests (Leiden 1999) pp 23ndash407 A Aldridge Religion in the Contemporary World a sociological introduction (third edition Oxford 2013)

p 228 P Edge lsquoDetermining religion in English courtsrsquo (2012) 12 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion

402ndash4239 This article focuses on the law in England and Wales The legal and religious context in Scotland and

Northern Ireland merits separate treatment10 Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 Marriage Act 1949 s 411 Charities Act 201112 European Convention on Human Rights Article 9 Equality Act 2010 s 10

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

the practice whereby the matter is largely left to the courts to adjudicate RichardRobinson distinguished between lsquostipulativersquo (or specific) definitions thatannounce that the subject is to be understood in a certain sense in a certaincontext and lsquolexicalrsquo (or universal) definitions that report the customarymeaning of the word13 Under English law there are several stipulative or spe-cific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each area of lawHowever there is no lexical or universal definition of religion

This article will contend that recent decisions have underscored the need forsuch a universal definition The first part of this article will take a chronologicalapproach exploring how the definition of religion under English law has devel-oped over the last fifty years It will be shown that there have been some movestowards the convergence of the different definitions of religion The second partwill explore how recent decisions by the Supreme Court and the CharityCommission have reversed this trend It will be argued that these decisionshave resulted in a complex and conflicting case law which points to arenewed need for a universal definition of religion under English law Thethird and final part will further this analysis drawing upon insights from thesociology of religion to suggest how a universal definition of religion coulddevelop

TOWARDS A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION OF RELIGION

The common law definitionOriginally the issue of defining religion did not arise Following the EnglishReformation of the 1530s there was only one lawful religion the establishedChurch of England14 A category of religion was therefore meaningless Whenthe Preamble to the Statute of Charitable Uses 1601 stated that gifts for therepair of churches were charitable it was clear that this referred to the buildingsof the established church15 And when subsequent case law recognised thattrusts gifts and institutions for the lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo were charitableand thus entitled to legal and fiscal advantages it was likewise understood

13 R Robinson Definition (Oxford 1954) p 1914 The English Reformation came later and was a different beast from that felt on the Continent The

divorce from Rome in the 1530s under Henry VIII was not a religious upheaval that required politicaland constitutional reconstruction rather it was a political and constitutional act that led in time toreligious upheaval See G Elton lsquoThe Reformation in Englandrsquo in G Elton (ed) The NewCambridge Modern History Volume 2 the Reformation 1520ndash1559 (second edition Cambridge1990) pp 262ndash287 F Maitland English Law and the Renaissance (Cambridge 1901) p 9

15 The Mortmain and Charitable Uses Act 1888 repealed the statute itself but expressly preserved thepreamble The Charities Act 1960 repealed the 1888 Act and thus the preamble However its finalrepeal does not affect the authority of the cases decided on it nor the principles on which futurecases are to be decided Incorporated Council of Law Reporting for England and Wales v A-G [1971]Ch 626 at 644 See also Charities Act 2011 Schedule 7 Part 1

1 3 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that this protected only the established Church of England16 The lsquosuperstitioususersquo ndash that is a trust for false religious purposes ndash was void17 As Newark put itsuch gifts were lsquoagainst public policy as furthering the schisms of nonconform-ity the errors of Rome or the infidelity of Judaism or heathenismrsquo18 The longand piecemeal process of religious toleration whereby disabilities placed onother religions were gradually removed widened considerably the concept ofadvancement of religion and also changed the rationale for protecting religion19

Rather than furthering the mission of the established church and preventingheretical and false religions it gradually became understood that the protectionof religion provided recognition of the psychological and social worth of individ-ual religiosity20 As Lord Reid noted in Gilmour v Coats English law no longerprefers lsquoone religion to anotherrsquo but lsquoassumes that it is good for man to haveand to practise a religionrsquo21

It was not until the latter years of the twentieth century however that domes-tic courts elucidated a definition of religion based upon stated criteria and usedthis definition to determine claims This occurred in two cases concerningregistration and charitable status respectively In the first R v RegistrarGeneral ex parte Segerdal22 the Court of Appeal upheld the decision by theRegistrar General not to register a chapel of the Church of Scientology as lsquoaplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo under section 3 of the Places ofWorship Registration Act 1855 For Buckley LJ and Winn LJ the determinativefactor was that there was no worship Winn LJ held that the adherents did notlsquohumble themselves in reverence and recognition of the dominant power andcontrol of any entity or being outside their own body and lifersquo23 while BuckleyLJ held that worship lsquomust have some at least of the following characteristicssubmission to the object worshipped veneration of that object praise thanks-giving prayer or intercessionrsquo24 He found that the evidence put forward includ-ing the Church of Scientologyrsquos book of ceremonies contained lsquono element of

16 Pember v Inhabitants of Kington (1639) 1 EqCasAbr 95 Tot 34 Special Commissioners of Income Tax vPemsel [1891] AC 531

17 P Edge Legal Responses to Religious Difference (The Hague 2002) p 5 However such gifts were some-times upheld In Da Costa v De Praz (1754) 2 Swan 487n a gift to advance the Jewish religion washeld to be unlawful but Lord Hardwicke left it to the Crown to direct a cy-pres application whereby thegift was applied but for the purposes of the Christian religion

18 F Newark lsquoPublic benefit and religious trustsrsquo (1946) 62 Law Quarterly Review 234ndash247 at 23519 See R Sandberg Law and Religion (Cambridge 2011) chapter 220 F Quint and P Hodkin lsquoThe development of tolerance and diversity in the treatment of religion in

charity lawrsquo (2007) 102 Charity Law and Practice Review 1ndash16 at 321 [1949] AC 426 at 45922 [1970] 2 QB 67923 Ibid at para 70924 Ibid at para 709 He qualified this lsquoI do not say that you would need to find every element in every act

which could properly be described as worship but when you find an act which contains none ofthose elements it cannot in my judgment answer to the description of an act of worshiprsquo (ibid)

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

worship at allrsquo25 By contrast for Lord Denning MR the phrase to be defined waslsquothe combined phrase ldquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprdquo as used in thestatute of 1855rsquo26 For Denning this connoted lsquoa place of which the principaluse is as a place where people come together as a congregation or assemblyto do reverence to Godrsquo lsquoReligious worship means reverence or veneration ofGod or of a Supreme Beingrsquo The decision in Segerdal did not thereforeconcern the definition of religion as such The judgments of Buckley LJ andWinn LJ focused on the definition of worship simpliciter while Lord Denningsought to define the combined phrase lsquoreligious worshiprsquo It is curious there-fore that this case concerning registration law was heavily relied upon in thesecond case which concerned charity law to provide a definition of religion

In the second case Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v AG27 the courtheld that the South Place Ethical Society a society for the lsquostudy and dissemin-ation of ethical principles and the cultivation of a rational religious sentimentrsquowas not charitable for the advancement of religion28 Echoing Lord Denning inSegerdal Dillon J distinguished religion from ethics as being lsquoconcerned withmanrsquos relations with Godrsquo rather than lsquowith manrsquos relations with manrsquo andheld that lsquotwo of the essential attributes of religion are faith and worshipfaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo29 Quoting with approval Buckley LJrsquos def-inition of worship in Segerdal Dillon J concluded that the South Place EthicalSociety did not have the purpose of advancing religion because there was nolsquoworship in the sense which worship is an attribute of religionrsquo lsquoindeed it isnot possible to worship in that way a mere ethical or philosophical idealrsquo30

No explanation was given as to why worship ought to be a definitional aspectof the term lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo

While Segerdal was concerned with defining the phrase lsquoplace of meeting forreligious worshiprsquo under registration law Re South Place Ethical Society was con-cerned with defining lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law Yet the defin-ition for the former was adopted without question for the latter Therequirement for lsquofaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo came to be understoodas the common law definition of religion except in relation to Buddhism whichwas admitted to be an lsquoexceptionrsquo31 And this definition was used to exclude any

25 Ibid at para 70926 Ibid at para 707 He noted that the Chapel of the Church of Scientology was not a lsquoplace of religious

worshiprsquo because the creed of the Church of Scientology was lsquomore a philosophy of the existence ofman or of life rather than a religionrsquo and that there was an absence of lsquoreverence or venerationrsquo andlsquoconsiderable stress on the spirit of manrsquo (ibid emphasis in original)

27 [1980] 1 WLR 156528 It was held otherwise charitable either for the advancement of education or under the fourth head of

charity by analogy with decided cases29 Ibid at paras 1571ndash157230 Ibid at para 157331 R v Registrar General ex parte Segerdal [1970] 2 QB 679 at 707 Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v

AG 1980] 1 WLR 1565 at 1573

1 3 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

religions where there was no evidence of worship For instance in 1999 theCharity Commission held that the Church of Scientology would not be regis-tered as a charity on the basis that the lsquocore practices of Scientology being audit-ing and training do not constitute worship as they do not display the essentialcharacteristic of reverence or veneration for a supreme beingrsquo32

Developments in human rights and discrimination lawAt the turn of the twenty-first century a number of new laws were enacted inEngland and Wales dealing with religious rights33 These statutory provisionsdefined and understood religion in broader terms The Human Rights Act1998 incorporated Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rightsinto domestic law introducing a positive right to freedom of thought conscienceand religion including the manifestation of religion or belief34 The domesticcourts followed the approach of Strasbourg in adopting a broad understandingof religion or belief regarding it not only as lsquoone of the most vital elements thatgo to make up the identity of believers and their conception of lifersquo but also as lsquoaprecious asset for atheists agnostics sceptics and the unconcernedrsquo35

Strasbourg institutions considered claims concerning Scientology36 druidism37

pacifism38 communism39 Nazism40 atheism41 pro-life42 Divine LightZentrum43 and the Moon Sect44 as well as lsquosplinterrsquo groups within larger tradi-tions45 and invariably did so without questioning whether such claims fitted thedefinition of religion or belief46 They considered the term lsquobeliefrsquo to require aworldview rather than a mere opinion it was defined in Campbell and Cosans vUnited Kingdom as denoting lsquoviews that attain a certain level of cogency

32 Church of Scientology Application to Charities Commission (17 November 1999) see httpwwwcharity-commissiongovukLibraryregistrationpdfscosfulldocpdf accessed 14 February 2018

33 See Sandberg Law and Religion chapter 10 Sandberg Religion Law and Society chapter 134 For discussion of the difference between positive and negative religious freedom see M Hill and R

Sandberg lsquoIs nothing sacred Clashing symbols in a secular worldrsquo (2007) Public Law 488ndash506 at490ndash491

35 Kokkinakis v Greece App no 1430788 (25 May 1993) at para 31 R v Secretary of State for Education andEmployment and others ex parte Williamson [2005] UKHL 15 at para 24

36 X and Church of Scientology v Sweden App no 780577 (5 May 1979)37 Chappell v United Kingdom App no 1046183 (30 March 1989)38 Arrowsmith v United Kingdom App no 705075 (12 October 1978)39 Hazar Hazar and Acik v Turkey App no 1631190 (11 October 1991)40 X v Austria App no 174762 (20 June 1963)41 Angeleni v Sweden (1988) 10 EHRR 123 (1986) 51 DampR 4142 Plattform lsquoArzte fur das Lebenrsquo v Austria App no 1012682 (21 June 1988)43 Omkarananda and the Divine Light Zentrum v Switzerland App no 818877 (19 March 1981)44 X v Austria App no 865279 (15 October 1981)45 Eg Serif v Greece App no 3817897 (14 December 1999) (mufti elected by mosque congregations in

opposition to the mufti appointed by the government)46 Though claimants have been required to prove the genuineness of their belief and the existence of

the religion in question X v UK App no 721575 (12 October 1978) Williamson at para 22

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

the practice whereby the matter is largely left to the courts to adjudicate RichardRobinson distinguished between lsquostipulativersquo (or specific) definitions thatannounce that the subject is to be understood in a certain sense in a certaincontext and lsquolexicalrsquo (or universal) definitions that report the customarymeaning of the word13 Under English law there are several stipulative or spe-cific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each area of lawHowever there is no lexical or universal definition of religion

This article will contend that recent decisions have underscored the need forsuch a universal definition The first part of this article will take a chronologicalapproach exploring how the definition of religion under English law has devel-oped over the last fifty years It will be shown that there have been some movestowards the convergence of the different definitions of religion The second partwill explore how recent decisions by the Supreme Court and the CharityCommission have reversed this trend It will be argued that these decisionshave resulted in a complex and conflicting case law which points to arenewed need for a universal definition of religion under English law Thethird and final part will further this analysis drawing upon insights from thesociology of religion to suggest how a universal definition of religion coulddevelop

TOWARDS A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION OF RELIGION

The common law definitionOriginally the issue of defining religion did not arise Following the EnglishReformation of the 1530s there was only one lawful religion the establishedChurch of England14 A category of religion was therefore meaningless Whenthe Preamble to the Statute of Charitable Uses 1601 stated that gifts for therepair of churches were charitable it was clear that this referred to the buildingsof the established church15 And when subsequent case law recognised thattrusts gifts and institutions for the lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo were charitableand thus entitled to legal and fiscal advantages it was likewise understood

13 R Robinson Definition (Oxford 1954) p 1914 The English Reformation came later and was a different beast from that felt on the Continent The

divorce from Rome in the 1530s under Henry VIII was not a religious upheaval that required politicaland constitutional reconstruction rather it was a political and constitutional act that led in time toreligious upheaval See G Elton lsquoThe Reformation in Englandrsquo in G Elton (ed) The NewCambridge Modern History Volume 2 the Reformation 1520ndash1559 (second edition Cambridge1990) pp 262ndash287 F Maitland English Law and the Renaissance (Cambridge 1901) p 9

15 The Mortmain and Charitable Uses Act 1888 repealed the statute itself but expressly preserved thepreamble The Charities Act 1960 repealed the 1888 Act and thus the preamble However its finalrepeal does not affect the authority of the cases decided on it nor the principles on which futurecases are to be decided Incorporated Council of Law Reporting for England and Wales v A-G [1971]Ch 626 at 644 See also Charities Act 2011 Schedule 7 Part 1

1 3 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that this protected only the established Church of England16 The lsquosuperstitioususersquo ndash that is a trust for false religious purposes ndash was void17 As Newark put itsuch gifts were lsquoagainst public policy as furthering the schisms of nonconform-ity the errors of Rome or the infidelity of Judaism or heathenismrsquo18 The longand piecemeal process of religious toleration whereby disabilities placed onother religions were gradually removed widened considerably the concept ofadvancement of religion and also changed the rationale for protecting religion19

Rather than furthering the mission of the established church and preventingheretical and false religions it gradually became understood that the protectionof religion provided recognition of the psychological and social worth of individ-ual religiosity20 As Lord Reid noted in Gilmour v Coats English law no longerprefers lsquoone religion to anotherrsquo but lsquoassumes that it is good for man to haveand to practise a religionrsquo21

It was not until the latter years of the twentieth century however that domes-tic courts elucidated a definition of religion based upon stated criteria and usedthis definition to determine claims This occurred in two cases concerningregistration and charitable status respectively In the first R v RegistrarGeneral ex parte Segerdal22 the Court of Appeal upheld the decision by theRegistrar General not to register a chapel of the Church of Scientology as lsquoaplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo under section 3 of the Places ofWorship Registration Act 1855 For Buckley LJ and Winn LJ the determinativefactor was that there was no worship Winn LJ held that the adherents did notlsquohumble themselves in reverence and recognition of the dominant power andcontrol of any entity or being outside their own body and lifersquo23 while BuckleyLJ held that worship lsquomust have some at least of the following characteristicssubmission to the object worshipped veneration of that object praise thanks-giving prayer or intercessionrsquo24 He found that the evidence put forward includ-ing the Church of Scientologyrsquos book of ceremonies contained lsquono element of

16 Pember v Inhabitants of Kington (1639) 1 EqCasAbr 95 Tot 34 Special Commissioners of Income Tax vPemsel [1891] AC 531

17 P Edge Legal Responses to Religious Difference (The Hague 2002) p 5 However such gifts were some-times upheld In Da Costa v De Praz (1754) 2 Swan 487n a gift to advance the Jewish religion washeld to be unlawful but Lord Hardwicke left it to the Crown to direct a cy-pres application whereby thegift was applied but for the purposes of the Christian religion

18 F Newark lsquoPublic benefit and religious trustsrsquo (1946) 62 Law Quarterly Review 234ndash247 at 23519 See R Sandberg Law and Religion (Cambridge 2011) chapter 220 F Quint and P Hodkin lsquoThe development of tolerance and diversity in the treatment of religion in

charity lawrsquo (2007) 102 Charity Law and Practice Review 1ndash16 at 321 [1949] AC 426 at 45922 [1970] 2 QB 67923 Ibid at para 70924 Ibid at para 709 He qualified this lsquoI do not say that you would need to find every element in every act

which could properly be described as worship but when you find an act which contains none ofthose elements it cannot in my judgment answer to the description of an act of worshiprsquo (ibid)

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

worship at allrsquo25 By contrast for Lord Denning MR the phrase to be defined waslsquothe combined phrase ldquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprdquo as used in thestatute of 1855rsquo26 For Denning this connoted lsquoa place of which the principaluse is as a place where people come together as a congregation or assemblyto do reverence to Godrsquo lsquoReligious worship means reverence or veneration ofGod or of a Supreme Beingrsquo The decision in Segerdal did not thereforeconcern the definition of religion as such The judgments of Buckley LJ andWinn LJ focused on the definition of worship simpliciter while Lord Denningsought to define the combined phrase lsquoreligious worshiprsquo It is curious there-fore that this case concerning registration law was heavily relied upon in thesecond case which concerned charity law to provide a definition of religion

In the second case Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v AG27 the courtheld that the South Place Ethical Society a society for the lsquostudy and dissemin-ation of ethical principles and the cultivation of a rational religious sentimentrsquowas not charitable for the advancement of religion28 Echoing Lord Denning inSegerdal Dillon J distinguished religion from ethics as being lsquoconcerned withmanrsquos relations with Godrsquo rather than lsquowith manrsquos relations with manrsquo andheld that lsquotwo of the essential attributes of religion are faith and worshipfaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo29 Quoting with approval Buckley LJrsquos def-inition of worship in Segerdal Dillon J concluded that the South Place EthicalSociety did not have the purpose of advancing religion because there was nolsquoworship in the sense which worship is an attribute of religionrsquo lsquoindeed it isnot possible to worship in that way a mere ethical or philosophical idealrsquo30

No explanation was given as to why worship ought to be a definitional aspectof the term lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo

While Segerdal was concerned with defining the phrase lsquoplace of meeting forreligious worshiprsquo under registration law Re South Place Ethical Society was con-cerned with defining lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law Yet the defin-ition for the former was adopted without question for the latter Therequirement for lsquofaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo came to be understoodas the common law definition of religion except in relation to Buddhism whichwas admitted to be an lsquoexceptionrsquo31 And this definition was used to exclude any

25 Ibid at para 70926 Ibid at para 707 He noted that the Chapel of the Church of Scientology was not a lsquoplace of religious

worshiprsquo because the creed of the Church of Scientology was lsquomore a philosophy of the existence ofman or of life rather than a religionrsquo and that there was an absence of lsquoreverence or venerationrsquo andlsquoconsiderable stress on the spirit of manrsquo (ibid emphasis in original)

27 [1980] 1 WLR 156528 It was held otherwise charitable either for the advancement of education or under the fourth head of

charity by analogy with decided cases29 Ibid at paras 1571ndash157230 Ibid at para 157331 R v Registrar General ex parte Segerdal [1970] 2 QB 679 at 707 Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v

AG 1980] 1 WLR 1565 at 1573

1 3 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

religions where there was no evidence of worship For instance in 1999 theCharity Commission held that the Church of Scientology would not be regis-tered as a charity on the basis that the lsquocore practices of Scientology being audit-ing and training do not constitute worship as they do not display the essentialcharacteristic of reverence or veneration for a supreme beingrsquo32

Developments in human rights and discrimination lawAt the turn of the twenty-first century a number of new laws were enacted inEngland and Wales dealing with religious rights33 These statutory provisionsdefined and understood religion in broader terms The Human Rights Act1998 incorporated Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rightsinto domestic law introducing a positive right to freedom of thought conscienceand religion including the manifestation of religion or belief34 The domesticcourts followed the approach of Strasbourg in adopting a broad understandingof religion or belief regarding it not only as lsquoone of the most vital elements thatgo to make up the identity of believers and their conception of lifersquo but also as lsquoaprecious asset for atheists agnostics sceptics and the unconcernedrsquo35

Strasbourg institutions considered claims concerning Scientology36 druidism37

pacifism38 communism39 Nazism40 atheism41 pro-life42 Divine LightZentrum43 and the Moon Sect44 as well as lsquosplinterrsquo groups within larger tradi-tions45 and invariably did so without questioning whether such claims fitted thedefinition of religion or belief46 They considered the term lsquobeliefrsquo to require aworldview rather than a mere opinion it was defined in Campbell and Cosans vUnited Kingdom as denoting lsquoviews that attain a certain level of cogency

32 Church of Scientology Application to Charities Commission (17 November 1999) see httpwwwcharity-commissiongovukLibraryregistrationpdfscosfulldocpdf accessed 14 February 2018

33 See Sandberg Law and Religion chapter 10 Sandberg Religion Law and Society chapter 134 For discussion of the difference between positive and negative religious freedom see M Hill and R

Sandberg lsquoIs nothing sacred Clashing symbols in a secular worldrsquo (2007) Public Law 488ndash506 at490ndash491

35 Kokkinakis v Greece App no 1430788 (25 May 1993) at para 31 R v Secretary of State for Education andEmployment and others ex parte Williamson [2005] UKHL 15 at para 24

36 X and Church of Scientology v Sweden App no 780577 (5 May 1979)37 Chappell v United Kingdom App no 1046183 (30 March 1989)38 Arrowsmith v United Kingdom App no 705075 (12 October 1978)39 Hazar Hazar and Acik v Turkey App no 1631190 (11 October 1991)40 X v Austria App no 174762 (20 June 1963)41 Angeleni v Sweden (1988) 10 EHRR 123 (1986) 51 DampR 4142 Plattform lsquoArzte fur das Lebenrsquo v Austria App no 1012682 (21 June 1988)43 Omkarananda and the Divine Light Zentrum v Switzerland App no 818877 (19 March 1981)44 X v Austria App no 865279 (15 October 1981)45 Eg Serif v Greece App no 3817897 (14 December 1999) (mufti elected by mosque congregations in

opposition to the mufti appointed by the government)46 Though claimants have been required to prove the genuineness of their belief and the existence of

the religion in question X v UK App no 721575 (12 October 1978) Williamson at para 22

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

that this protected only the established Church of England16 The lsquosuperstitioususersquo ndash that is a trust for false religious purposes ndash was void17 As Newark put itsuch gifts were lsquoagainst public policy as furthering the schisms of nonconform-ity the errors of Rome or the infidelity of Judaism or heathenismrsquo18 The longand piecemeal process of religious toleration whereby disabilities placed onother religions were gradually removed widened considerably the concept ofadvancement of religion and also changed the rationale for protecting religion19

Rather than furthering the mission of the established church and preventingheretical and false religions it gradually became understood that the protectionof religion provided recognition of the psychological and social worth of individ-ual religiosity20 As Lord Reid noted in Gilmour v Coats English law no longerprefers lsquoone religion to anotherrsquo but lsquoassumes that it is good for man to haveand to practise a religionrsquo21

It was not until the latter years of the twentieth century however that domes-tic courts elucidated a definition of religion based upon stated criteria and usedthis definition to determine claims This occurred in two cases concerningregistration and charitable status respectively In the first R v RegistrarGeneral ex parte Segerdal22 the Court of Appeal upheld the decision by theRegistrar General not to register a chapel of the Church of Scientology as lsquoaplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo under section 3 of the Places ofWorship Registration Act 1855 For Buckley LJ and Winn LJ the determinativefactor was that there was no worship Winn LJ held that the adherents did notlsquohumble themselves in reverence and recognition of the dominant power andcontrol of any entity or being outside their own body and lifersquo23 while BuckleyLJ held that worship lsquomust have some at least of the following characteristicssubmission to the object worshipped veneration of that object praise thanks-giving prayer or intercessionrsquo24 He found that the evidence put forward includ-ing the Church of Scientologyrsquos book of ceremonies contained lsquono element of

16 Pember v Inhabitants of Kington (1639) 1 EqCasAbr 95 Tot 34 Special Commissioners of Income Tax vPemsel [1891] AC 531

17 P Edge Legal Responses to Religious Difference (The Hague 2002) p 5 However such gifts were some-times upheld In Da Costa v De Praz (1754) 2 Swan 487n a gift to advance the Jewish religion washeld to be unlawful but Lord Hardwicke left it to the Crown to direct a cy-pres application whereby thegift was applied but for the purposes of the Christian religion

18 F Newark lsquoPublic benefit and religious trustsrsquo (1946) 62 Law Quarterly Review 234ndash247 at 23519 See R Sandberg Law and Religion (Cambridge 2011) chapter 220 F Quint and P Hodkin lsquoThe development of tolerance and diversity in the treatment of religion in

charity lawrsquo (2007) 102 Charity Law and Practice Review 1ndash16 at 321 [1949] AC 426 at 45922 [1970] 2 QB 67923 Ibid at para 70924 Ibid at para 709 He qualified this lsquoI do not say that you would need to find every element in every act

which could properly be described as worship but when you find an act which contains none ofthose elements it cannot in my judgment answer to the description of an act of worshiprsquo (ibid)

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

worship at allrsquo25 By contrast for Lord Denning MR the phrase to be defined waslsquothe combined phrase ldquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprdquo as used in thestatute of 1855rsquo26 For Denning this connoted lsquoa place of which the principaluse is as a place where people come together as a congregation or assemblyto do reverence to Godrsquo lsquoReligious worship means reverence or veneration ofGod or of a Supreme Beingrsquo The decision in Segerdal did not thereforeconcern the definition of religion as such The judgments of Buckley LJ andWinn LJ focused on the definition of worship simpliciter while Lord Denningsought to define the combined phrase lsquoreligious worshiprsquo It is curious there-fore that this case concerning registration law was heavily relied upon in thesecond case which concerned charity law to provide a definition of religion

In the second case Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v AG27 the courtheld that the South Place Ethical Society a society for the lsquostudy and dissemin-ation of ethical principles and the cultivation of a rational religious sentimentrsquowas not charitable for the advancement of religion28 Echoing Lord Denning inSegerdal Dillon J distinguished religion from ethics as being lsquoconcerned withmanrsquos relations with Godrsquo rather than lsquowith manrsquos relations with manrsquo andheld that lsquotwo of the essential attributes of religion are faith and worshipfaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo29 Quoting with approval Buckley LJrsquos def-inition of worship in Segerdal Dillon J concluded that the South Place EthicalSociety did not have the purpose of advancing religion because there was nolsquoworship in the sense which worship is an attribute of religionrsquo lsquoindeed it isnot possible to worship in that way a mere ethical or philosophical idealrsquo30

No explanation was given as to why worship ought to be a definitional aspectof the term lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo

While Segerdal was concerned with defining the phrase lsquoplace of meeting forreligious worshiprsquo under registration law Re South Place Ethical Society was con-cerned with defining lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law Yet the defin-ition for the former was adopted without question for the latter Therequirement for lsquofaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo came to be understoodas the common law definition of religion except in relation to Buddhism whichwas admitted to be an lsquoexceptionrsquo31 And this definition was used to exclude any

25 Ibid at para 70926 Ibid at para 707 He noted that the Chapel of the Church of Scientology was not a lsquoplace of religious

worshiprsquo because the creed of the Church of Scientology was lsquomore a philosophy of the existence ofman or of life rather than a religionrsquo and that there was an absence of lsquoreverence or venerationrsquo andlsquoconsiderable stress on the spirit of manrsquo (ibid emphasis in original)

27 [1980] 1 WLR 156528 It was held otherwise charitable either for the advancement of education or under the fourth head of

charity by analogy with decided cases29 Ibid at paras 1571ndash157230 Ibid at para 157331 R v Registrar General ex parte Segerdal [1970] 2 QB 679 at 707 Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v

AG 1980] 1 WLR 1565 at 1573

1 3 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

religions where there was no evidence of worship For instance in 1999 theCharity Commission held that the Church of Scientology would not be regis-tered as a charity on the basis that the lsquocore practices of Scientology being audit-ing and training do not constitute worship as they do not display the essentialcharacteristic of reverence or veneration for a supreme beingrsquo32

Developments in human rights and discrimination lawAt the turn of the twenty-first century a number of new laws were enacted inEngland and Wales dealing with religious rights33 These statutory provisionsdefined and understood religion in broader terms The Human Rights Act1998 incorporated Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rightsinto domestic law introducing a positive right to freedom of thought conscienceand religion including the manifestation of religion or belief34 The domesticcourts followed the approach of Strasbourg in adopting a broad understandingof religion or belief regarding it not only as lsquoone of the most vital elements thatgo to make up the identity of believers and their conception of lifersquo but also as lsquoaprecious asset for atheists agnostics sceptics and the unconcernedrsquo35

Strasbourg institutions considered claims concerning Scientology36 druidism37

pacifism38 communism39 Nazism40 atheism41 pro-life42 Divine LightZentrum43 and the Moon Sect44 as well as lsquosplinterrsquo groups within larger tradi-tions45 and invariably did so without questioning whether such claims fitted thedefinition of religion or belief46 They considered the term lsquobeliefrsquo to require aworldview rather than a mere opinion it was defined in Campbell and Cosans vUnited Kingdom as denoting lsquoviews that attain a certain level of cogency

32 Church of Scientology Application to Charities Commission (17 November 1999) see httpwwwcharity-commissiongovukLibraryregistrationpdfscosfulldocpdf accessed 14 February 2018

33 See Sandberg Law and Religion chapter 10 Sandberg Religion Law and Society chapter 134 For discussion of the difference between positive and negative religious freedom see M Hill and R

Sandberg lsquoIs nothing sacred Clashing symbols in a secular worldrsquo (2007) Public Law 488ndash506 at490ndash491

35 Kokkinakis v Greece App no 1430788 (25 May 1993) at para 31 R v Secretary of State for Education andEmployment and others ex parte Williamson [2005] UKHL 15 at para 24

36 X and Church of Scientology v Sweden App no 780577 (5 May 1979)37 Chappell v United Kingdom App no 1046183 (30 March 1989)38 Arrowsmith v United Kingdom App no 705075 (12 October 1978)39 Hazar Hazar and Acik v Turkey App no 1631190 (11 October 1991)40 X v Austria App no 174762 (20 June 1963)41 Angeleni v Sweden (1988) 10 EHRR 123 (1986) 51 DampR 4142 Plattform lsquoArzte fur das Lebenrsquo v Austria App no 1012682 (21 June 1988)43 Omkarananda and the Divine Light Zentrum v Switzerland App no 818877 (19 March 1981)44 X v Austria App no 865279 (15 October 1981)45 Eg Serif v Greece App no 3817897 (14 December 1999) (mufti elected by mosque congregations in

opposition to the mufti appointed by the government)46 Though claimants have been required to prove the genuineness of their belief and the existence of

the religion in question X v UK App no 721575 (12 October 1978) Williamson at para 22

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

worship at allrsquo25 By contrast for Lord Denning MR the phrase to be defined waslsquothe combined phrase ldquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprdquo as used in thestatute of 1855rsquo26 For Denning this connoted lsquoa place of which the principaluse is as a place where people come together as a congregation or assemblyto do reverence to Godrsquo lsquoReligious worship means reverence or veneration ofGod or of a Supreme Beingrsquo The decision in Segerdal did not thereforeconcern the definition of religion as such The judgments of Buckley LJ andWinn LJ focused on the definition of worship simpliciter while Lord Denningsought to define the combined phrase lsquoreligious worshiprsquo It is curious there-fore that this case concerning registration law was heavily relied upon in thesecond case which concerned charity law to provide a definition of religion

In the second case Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v AG27 the courtheld that the South Place Ethical Society a society for the lsquostudy and dissemin-ation of ethical principles and the cultivation of a rational religious sentimentrsquowas not charitable for the advancement of religion28 Echoing Lord Denning inSegerdal Dillon J distinguished religion from ethics as being lsquoconcerned withmanrsquos relations with Godrsquo rather than lsquowith manrsquos relations with manrsquo andheld that lsquotwo of the essential attributes of religion are faith and worshipfaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo29 Quoting with approval Buckley LJrsquos def-inition of worship in Segerdal Dillon J concluded that the South Place EthicalSociety did not have the purpose of advancing religion because there was nolsquoworship in the sense which worship is an attribute of religionrsquo lsquoindeed it isnot possible to worship in that way a mere ethical or philosophical idealrsquo30

No explanation was given as to why worship ought to be a definitional aspectof the term lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo

While Segerdal was concerned with defining the phrase lsquoplace of meeting forreligious worshiprsquo under registration law Re South Place Ethical Society was con-cerned with defining lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law Yet the defin-ition for the former was adopted without question for the latter Therequirement for lsquofaith in a god and worship of that godrsquo came to be understoodas the common law definition of religion except in relation to Buddhism whichwas admitted to be an lsquoexceptionrsquo31 And this definition was used to exclude any

25 Ibid at para 70926 Ibid at para 707 He noted that the Chapel of the Church of Scientology was not a lsquoplace of religious

worshiprsquo because the creed of the Church of Scientology was lsquomore a philosophy of the existence ofman or of life rather than a religionrsquo and that there was an absence of lsquoreverence or venerationrsquo andlsquoconsiderable stress on the spirit of manrsquo (ibid emphasis in original)

27 [1980] 1 WLR 156528 It was held otherwise charitable either for the advancement of education or under the fourth head of

charity by analogy with decided cases29 Ibid at paras 1571ndash157230 Ibid at para 157331 R v Registrar General ex parte Segerdal [1970] 2 QB 679 at 707 Re South Place Ethical Society Barralet v

AG 1980] 1 WLR 1565 at 1573

1 3 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

religions where there was no evidence of worship For instance in 1999 theCharity Commission held that the Church of Scientology would not be regis-tered as a charity on the basis that the lsquocore practices of Scientology being audit-ing and training do not constitute worship as they do not display the essentialcharacteristic of reverence or veneration for a supreme beingrsquo32

Developments in human rights and discrimination lawAt the turn of the twenty-first century a number of new laws were enacted inEngland and Wales dealing with religious rights33 These statutory provisionsdefined and understood religion in broader terms The Human Rights Act1998 incorporated Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rightsinto domestic law introducing a positive right to freedom of thought conscienceand religion including the manifestation of religion or belief34 The domesticcourts followed the approach of Strasbourg in adopting a broad understandingof religion or belief regarding it not only as lsquoone of the most vital elements thatgo to make up the identity of believers and their conception of lifersquo but also as lsquoaprecious asset for atheists agnostics sceptics and the unconcernedrsquo35

Strasbourg institutions considered claims concerning Scientology36 druidism37

pacifism38 communism39 Nazism40 atheism41 pro-life42 Divine LightZentrum43 and the Moon Sect44 as well as lsquosplinterrsquo groups within larger tradi-tions45 and invariably did so without questioning whether such claims fitted thedefinition of religion or belief46 They considered the term lsquobeliefrsquo to require aworldview rather than a mere opinion it was defined in Campbell and Cosans vUnited Kingdom as denoting lsquoviews that attain a certain level of cogency

32 Church of Scientology Application to Charities Commission (17 November 1999) see httpwwwcharity-commissiongovukLibraryregistrationpdfscosfulldocpdf accessed 14 February 2018

33 See Sandberg Law and Religion chapter 10 Sandberg Religion Law and Society chapter 134 For discussion of the difference between positive and negative religious freedom see M Hill and R

Sandberg lsquoIs nothing sacred Clashing symbols in a secular worldrsquo (2007) Public Law 488ndash506 at490ndash491

35 Kokkinakis v Greece App no 1430788 (25 May 1993) at para 31 R v Secretary of State for Education andEmployment and others ex parte Williamson [2005] UKHL 15 at para 24

36 X and Church of Scientology v Sweden App no 780577 (5 May 1979)37 Chappell v United Kingdom App no 1046183 (30 March 1989)38 Arrowsmith v United Kingdom App no 705075 (12 October 1978)39 Hazar Hazar and Acik v Turkey App no 1631190 (11 October 1991)40 X v Austria App no 174762 (20 June 1963)41 Angeleni v Sweden (1988) 10 EHRR 123 (1986) 51 DampR 4142 Plattform lsquoArzte fur das Lebenrsquo v Austria App no 1012682 (21 June 1988)43 Omkarananda and the Divine Light Zentrum v Switzerland App no 818877 (19 March 1981)44 X v Austria App no 865279 (15 October 1981)45 Eg Serif v Greece App no 3817897 (14 December 1999) (mufti elected by mosque congregations in

opposition to the mufti appointed by the government)46 Though claimants have been required to prove the genuineness of their belief and the existence of

the religion in question X v UK App no 721575 (12 October 1978) Williamson at para 22

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

religions where there was no evidence of worship For instance in 1999 theCharity Commission held that the Church of Scientology would not be regis-tered as a charity on the basis that the lsquocore practices of Scientology being audit-ing and training do not constitute worship as they do not display the essentialcharacteristic of reverence or veneration for a supreme beingrsquo32

Developments in human rights and discrimination lawAt the turn of the twenty-first century a number of new laws were enacted inEngland and Wales dealing with religious rights33 These statutory provisionsdefined and understood religion in broader terms The Human Rights Act1998 incorporated Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rightsinto domestic law introducing a positive right to freedom of thought conscienceand religion including the manifestation of religion or belief34 The domesticcourts followed the approach of Strasbourg in adopting a broad understandingof religion or belief regarding it not only as lsquoone of the most vital elements thatgo to make up the identity of believers and their conception of lifersquo but also as lsquoaprecious asset for atheists agnostics sceptics and the unconcernedrsquo35

Strasbourg institutions considered claims concerning Scientology36 druidism37

pacifism38 communism39 Nazism40 atheism41 pro-life42 Divine LightZentrum43 and the Moon Sect44 as well as lsquosplinterrsquo groups within larger tradi-tions45 and invariably did so without questioning whether such claims fitted thedefinition of religion or belief46 They considered the term lsquobeliefrsquo to require aworldview rather than a mere opinion it was defined in Campbell and Cosans vUnited Kingdom as denoting lsquoviews that attain a certain level of cogency

32 Church of Scientology Application to Charities Commission (17 November 1999) see httpwwwcharity-commissiongovukLibraryregistrationpdfscosfulldocpdf accessed 14 February 2018

33 See Sandberg Law and Religion chapter 10 Sandberg Religion Law and Society chapter 134 For discussion of the difference between positive and negative religious freedom see M Hill and R

Sandberg lsquoIs nothing sacred Clashing symbols in a secular worldrsquo (2007) Public Law 488ndash506 at490ndash491

35 Kokkinakis v Greece App no 1430788 (25 May 1993) at para 31 R v Secretary of State for Education andEmployment and others ex parte Williamson [2005] UKHL 15 at para 24

36 X and Church of Scientology v Sweden App no 780577 (5 May 1979)37 Chappell v United Kingdom App no 1046183 (30 March 1989)38 Arrowsmith v United Kingdom App no 705075 (12 October 1978)39 Hazar Hazar and Acik v Turkey App no 1631190 (11 October 1991)40 X v Austria App no 174762 (20 June 1963)41 Angeleni v Sweden (1988) 10 EHRR 123 (1986) 51 DampR 4142 Plattform lsquoArzte fur das Lebenrsquo v Austria App no 1012682 (21 June 1988)43 Omkarananda and the Divine Light Zentrum v Switzerland App no 818877 (19 March 1981)44 X v Austria App no 865279 (15 October 1981)45 Eg Serif v Greece App no 3817897 (14 December 1999) (mufti elected by mosque congregations in

opposition to the mufti appointed by the government)46 Though claimants have been required to prove the genuineness of their belief and the existence of

the religion in question X v UK App no 721575 (12 October 1978) Williamson at para 22

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

seriousness cohesion and importancersquo47 In R v Secretary of State for Educationand Employment and others ex parte Williamson the House of Lords confirmedthat this applies to both religious and non-religious beliefs and that lsquoFreedomof religion protects the subjective belief of an individualrsquo48 It was noted thatwhere beliefs are manifested they need to satisfy lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrequirementsrsquo which are implicitly laid out in Article 949 However theirLordships stated that courts should not lsquoimpose an evaluative filterrsquo at thestage of identifying whether there was a belief lsquoexcept in extreme casesrsquo50

An example of such an extreme case concerned the hunting ban In Whaley vLord Advocate their Lordships rejected the appellantrsquos contention that huntingwith hounds constituted a non-religious belief51 For Lord Hope this beliefdid not meet the Williamson threshold since looking at it lsquoobjectively huntingwith hounds is carried on mainly for pleasure and relaxation for those whotake part in itrsquo52 This reasoning was problematic however not only becausethe mention of an objective test contradicted the Williamson dicta thatfreedom of religion protected subjective beliefs but also because it suggestedthat a line was to be drawn between beliefs that fell under Article 9 andothers that did not Lord Hope held that the Strasbourg jurisprudence didlsquonot support the proposition that a personrsquos belief in his right to engage in anactivity which he carries on for pleasure or recreation however fervent or pas-sionate can be equated with beliefs of the kind that are protected by Article9rsquo since that would make it difficult to lsquoset any limits on the range of beliefsthat would be opened up for protectionrsquo However neither his Lordship norany subsequent judgments on Article 9 have articulated where these limitsare to be placed

The case law on religious discrimination has followed the approach of thehuman rights jurisprudence not only in adopting a wide definition of religionor belief but also in struggling consistently to identify the limits that are to beplaced on it Discrimination on the grounds of religion or belief was originally

47 App nos 751176 and 774376 (25 February 1982) at para 36 This was in relation to Article 2 of the firstprotocol to the ECHR However this definition has also been applied to Article 9 in Eweida and Others vUnited Kingdom App nos 4842010 3651610 5767110 and 5984210 (15 January 2013) at para 81

48 Williamson at para 2449 Ibid lsquoThe belief must be consistent with basic standards of human dignity or integrityrsquo lsquoThe belief

must relate to matters more than merely trivial It must possess an adequate degree of seriousnessand importancersquo lsquoThe belief must also be coherent in the sense of being intelligible and capable ofbeing understoodrsquo These were described as lsquoobjectiversquo requirements but that does not require thebelief itself to be assessed objectively but rather that the criterion against which the belief is to beexamined is to be assessed objectively The definition of lsquobasic standards of human dignityrsquo forinstance is an objective one It was also stressed that lsquoOverall these threshold requirementsshould not be set at a level which would deprive minority beliefs of the protection they are intendedto have under the Conventionrsquo

50 Ibid at para 5851 [2007] UKHL 5352 Ibid at para 18

1 3 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

prohibited in England and Wales in relation only to employment under theEmployment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 200353 which definedreligion or belief as meaning lsquoany religion religious belief or similar philosoph-ical beliefrsquo54 Employment Tribunals used the word lsquosimilarrsquo to exclude certainnon-religious beliefs such as nationalistic and political beliefs55 However theEquality Act 2006 which extended religion or belief discrimination to coverthe provisions of goods and services took the opportunity to remove the wordlsquosimilarrsquo and to expressly include lack of belief The current definition nowfound in section 10 of the Equality Act 2010 states that lsquoreligion means any reli-gionrsquo and lsquobelief means any religious or philosophical beliefrsquo56

Ironically a statement by the then government minister Baroness Scotlandthat the new definition should make no difference itself led to a change inapproach by Employment Tribunals Baroness Scotland stated that theremoval of the word lsquosimilarrsquo would make no difference because

the term lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo will take its meaning from the context inwhich it appears that is as part of the legislation relating to discriminationon the grounds of religion or belief Given that context philosophicalbeliefs must always be of a similar nature to religious beliefs It willbe for the courts to decide what constitutes a belief but case law

53 SI 2003166054 Employment Equality (Religion or Belief) Regulations 2003 Reg 2(1)55 Williams v South Central Limited ET Case Number 23069892003 (16 June 2004) Baggs v Fudge

[2005] ET14001142005 (23 March 2005) See R Sandberg lsquoFlags beards and pilgrimages areview of the early case law on religious discriminationrsquo (2007) 9 Ecc LJ 87ndash100

56 Equality Act 2010 s 10 Definitions of religion also exist in the exceptions from discrimination lawafforded to religious groups Under Schedule 19 para 3 of the Equality Act 2010 employers whohave an lsquoethos based on religion or beliefrsquo can discriminate on grounds of religion or belief in rela-tion to employment Under Schedule 9 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 lsquoorganised religionsrsquo candiscriminate on grounds of sex marriage and sexual orientation in relation to employmentThese terms are undefined by the statute but in R (Amicus MSF Section) v Secretary of State forTrade and Industry [2004] EWHC 860 Richards J held that term lsquoorganised religionrsquo was narrowerthan lsquoreligious organisationrsquo he gave the example that lsquoemployment as a teacher in a faith school islikely to be ldquofor purposes of a religious organisationrdquo but not ldquofor purposes of an organised religionrdquorsquo(at para 116) Under Schedule 23 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 there is a general exception forlsquoorganisations relating to religion or beliefrsquo covering discrimination in relation to goods and servicesAn lsquoorganisation relating to religion or beliefrsquo is defined as

an organisation the purpose of which ismdash(a) to practise a religion or belief(b) to advance a religion or belief(c) to teach the practice or principles of a religion or belief(d) to enable persons of a religion or belief to receive any benefit or to engage in any

activity within the framework of that religion or belief or(e) to foster or maintain good relations between persons of different religions or beliefs

See further M Hill R Sandberg and N Doe Religion and Law in the United Kingdom (secondedition Alphen aan den Rijn 2014) pp 154ndash160 R Sandberg lsquoThe right to discriminatersquo (2011)13 Ecc LJ 157ndash181

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 3 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

suggests that any philosophical belief must attain a certain level of cogencyseriousness cohesion and importance must be worthy of respect in ademocratic society and must not be incompatible with human dignityTherefore an example of a belief that might meet this description ishumanism and examples of something that might not would besupport of a political party or a belief in the supreme nature of the JediKnights57

This summary of the human rights case law requirements has paradoxicallybeen used to change the definition Employment Tribunals have interpretedBaroness Scotlandrsquos words as providing a series of tests which apply to determinewhether a belief is capable of being protected The turning point was the decisionof the Employment Appeal Tribunal in Grainger PLC v Nicholson58 which con-cluded that an asserted belief in manmade climate change together with thealleged resulting moral imperatives arising from it was capable of constitutinga lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo for the purpose of the 2003 Regulations because it metthe criteria laid out by the jurisprudence of the European Court of HumanRights which was directly relevant Employment Judge Burton summarisedthe meaning of lsquophilosophical beliefrsquo as including five requirements

(i) The belief must be genuinely held(ii) It must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the

present state of information available(iii) It must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life

and behaviour(iv) It must attain a certain level of cogency seriousness cohesion and

importance(v) It must be worthy of respect in a democratic society be not incompat-

ible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rightsof others59

Although these five principles can be found in the case law of the Strasbourgcourt they have not been articulated in such a watertight way by the EuropeanCourt of Human Rights The application of the Strasbourg definitions is alsoproblematic since unlike domestic discrimination law Article 9 does not distin-guish between philosophical and non-philosophical beliefs Following Graingerthe five requirements have taken on an elevated importance EmploymentTribunal chairs have subsequently applied these requirements as if theywere a statutory test and have forgotten the warning in Williamson that

57 HL Deb 13 July 2005 vol 684 cols 1109ndash111058 [2009] UKEAT 021909ZT (3 November 2009)59 Ibid at para 24

1 4 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

these should be lsquominimumrsquo and lsquomodestrsquo requirements60 They have inter-preted the tests in different ways to reach inconsistent and arbitrary decisionsEmployment Tribunals have considered the tests to be met in cases concerningbeliefs in spiritualism and psychic powers61 anti-fox hunting beliefs62 beliefs inthe virtue of public service broadcasting63 and humanist beliefs64 In contrastother Employment Tribunals have concluded that the tests have not been metin cases concerning MarxistTrotskyite beliefs held by trade unionmembers65 beliefs in conspiracy theories regarding 91166 and a belief thatbelief that a poppy should be worn during the week prior to RemembranceSunday67 Drawing any points of principle out of this case law is difficult tosay the least68

The confusion is epitomised by the way that it is now unclear as to whetherpolitical beliefs are protected under discrimination law69 In Grainger it was sug-gested that Baroness Scotlandrsquos choice of words referring only to lsquosupport for apolitical partyrsquo as something that might not be protected left open the question ofwhether lsquoa belief in a political philosophy or doctrinersquo might now fall within thedefinition70 In Kelly v Unison it was suggested that a distinction could be drawnbetween lsquopolitical beliefs which involve the objective of the creation of a legallybinding structure by power or government regulating othersrsquo which are not pro-tected and the beliefs that lsquoare expressed by his own practice but where he hasno ambition to impose his scheme on othersrsquo which may be protected71

However this distinction has not found favour with subsequent EmploymentTribunal decisions with Employment Tribunal chairs in several cases ignoringthe question of whether the belief might have been lsquopoliticalrsquo or stating that theappellate courts had not definitely determined the question of whether politicalbeliefs could now be included

The confusion here results from the partial harmonisation of the definition ofreligion or belief in human rights and discrimination law contexts EmploymentTribunals have followed Baroness Scotland in adopting the wide approach to thedefinition of belief found in human rights law but they have come unstuck given

60 Williamson at para 2461 Greater Manchester Police Authority v Power [2009] EAT 043409DA (12 November 2009)62 Hashman v Milton Park (Dorset) Ltd [2011] ET 31055552009 (31 January 2011)63 Maistry v The BBC [2011] ET 12131422010 (14 February 2011) The definition point was not challenged

on appeal [2014] EWCA Civ 111664 Streatfield v London Philharmonic Orchestra Ltd [2012] 23907722011(22 May 2012)65 Kelly v Unison [2009] ET 220385408 (22 December 2009)66 Farrell v South Yorkshire Police Authority [2011] ET 28038052010 (24 May 2011)67 Lisk v Shield Guardian Co Ltd amp Others [2011] ET 33008732011 (14 September 2011)68 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 38ndash46 R Sandberg lsquoA question of beliefrsquo in N

Spencer (ed) Religion and Law (London 2012) pp 51ndash6369 See further R Sandberg lsquoAre political beliefs religious nowrsquo (2015) 175 Law and Justice 180ndash19770 Grainger at para 2871 Kelly at para 114 This distinction is odd however given that many religions proselytise and so could

be said to have an ambition to impose their beliefs on others

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

that discrimination law explicitly protects only religious or philosophicalbeliefs72 As with the adaption of the registration law definition of religion forcharity law purposes in Re South Place Ethical Society the pragmatic appropri-ation of definitional criteria is problematic given that significant differencesbetween the definitions have been ignored The problem is that the movetowards a universal definition has been half-hearted

Developments in charity lawThis problem has increased in the context of charity law itself The Charities Act2006 in providing the first codification of centuries of case law stated that reli-gion includes lsquoa religion which involves belief in more than one god and a reli-gion which does not involve belief in a godrsquo73 This removed theoreticaluncertainty surrounding whether the SegerdalndashSouth Place Ethical Societyformula excluded those faiths which do not believe in a god such asBuddhism The inadequacy of the common law definition had been shown inthe judgments themselves where the judges had accepted that Buddhism wasclearly a religion despite being outside the letter of the articulated definitionAnd so again like the removal of the word lsquosimilarrsquo in the discrimination lawcontext the purpose behind the partial definition in the Charities Act was toclarify rather than change the law However here too the revised definitionprompted a change in the interpretation of the right In determining whetheran application satisfied the definition of advancement of religion the CharityCommission came to the conclusion that there were now lsquofour characteristicsof a religion for the purpose of charity lawrsquo curiously relying exclusively onits own guidance to modernise the common law test in light of the 2006Act74 In its decision on an application by the Gnostic Society75 the CharityCommission held that the four characteristics of a religion were

a belief in a god (or gods) or goddess (or goddesses) or supreme beingor divine or transcendental being or entity or spiritual principlewhich is the object or focus of the religion (referred to aslsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)

72 This uncertainty is even more problematic given the changes as a result of the Legal Aid Sentencingand Punishment of Offenders Act 2012 and a hike in costs For discussion of the effect of legal aidcuts upon the religious disputes see R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoThe sharia debate the missingfamily law contextrsquo (2016) 177 Law amp Justice 188ndash192 R Sandberg and S Thompson lsquoRelationalautonomy and religious tribunalsrsquo (2017) 6 Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 137ndash161

73 Section 2(3)(a) This is now to be found in section 3(2)(a) of the Charities Act 201174 Charity Commission lsquoAnalysis of the law underpinning Public Benefit and the Advancement of

Religionrsquo December 2008 httpswwwgovukgovernmentuploadssystemuploadsattach-ment_datafile358534lawrel1208pdf accessed 14 February 2018 lsquoThe 2006 Act provided thatthe Commission could issue guidance but there is nothing in the Act to suggest that this guidancewill be binding The Commission is subject to the existing law of charities just as it was before enact-mentrsquo J Hackney lsquoCharities and public benefitrsquo (2008) 124 Law Quarterly Review 347ndash350 at 350

75 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre (16 December 2009) at para 23

1 4 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

b a relationship between the believer and the supreme being or entityby showing worship of reverence for or veneration of the supremebeing or entity

c a degree of cogency cohesion seriousness and importanced an identifiable positive beneficial moral or ethical framework76

The first two characteristics elaborated and developed the common law defin-ition of religion which required belief in and worship of a god Although thiswas presumably intended to reflect the provisions of the Charities Act 2006the first characteristic is inconsistent with the statute While belief in multiplegods was mentioned the statutory language of lsquoa religion which does notinvolve belief in a godrsquo is missing The provision seems to have been interpretedrestrictively by the Charity Commission to only include lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscen-dentalrsquo beliefs that did not involve a belief in a god rather than beliefs that deniedthe existence of God The language of the Act seemed to include atheism thelanguage of the Charity Commission excludes atheism and questions whetherhumanism is protected The Charity Commission simply introduced synonymsfor God summarised in the phrase lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo

The Commissionrsquos second characteristic updated the common law test con-cerning worship It is notable that parts of the common law definition ofworship (lsquoreverencersquo lsquovenerationrsquo) were now considered to be interchangeablewith the term itself Presumably the Charity Commission considered itselfbound by South Place Ethical Society to include this characteristic despite thefact that logically there is no reason why worship should be a definitional attri-bute of lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo under charity law (as opposed to lsquoa place ofmeeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship Registration Act1855) Although secular belief systems may still enjoy the fiscal and legal benefitsof being charitable provided that they come under another head of charity77

their exclusion from the head of advancement of religion may well infringeArticle 9 ECHR which talks of the right to manifest religion or belief inworship teaching practice or observance78

This point is underlined by the third characteristic articulated by the CharityCommission which brought charity law in line with the requirements found inthe Article 9 jurisprudence requiring lsquocogency cohesion seriousness andimportancersquo again without the Williamson warning that lsquotoo much should not

76 Ibid77 In 2002 the Charity Commission recognised the lsquopromotion of religious harmonyrsquo as a new charit-

able purpose which is not restricted to lsquoreligionsrsquo hitherto recognised under charity law but alsoincludes lsquobeliefsrsquo as recognised by the ECHR See httpswwwgovukgovernmentpublica-tionspromotion-of-religious-harmony accessed 14 February 2018 also now Charities Act 2011 s3(1)(h)

78 See further P Edge lsquoCharitable status for the advancement of religion an abolitionistrsquos viewrsquo (19956) 31 Charity Law amp Practice Review 29ndash35

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

be demanded in this regardrsquo and that these are to be interpreted as lsquominimumrsquoand lsquomodestrsquo requirements79 As with discrimination law aspects of the defin-ition of religion for Article 9 purposes became part of the charity law definitionbut no attempt was given to square the fact that charity law does not protect lsquoreli-gion or beliefrsquo but only religion (and beliefs in a lsquosupreme being or entityrsquo)Indeed both the third and fourth characteristics were new and lacked any statu-tory or judicial authority The fourth characteristic introduced a public benefitrequirement into the Charity Commissionrsquos definition of religion muddyingthe Commissionrsquos own distinction between identifying whether a trust hasmet a description of charitable purposes and identifying whether there is apublic benefit80

As with the five tests laid out in Grainger the Charity Commissionrsquos four char-acteristics have led to seemingly arbitrary decisions The decision in relation tothe Gnostic Society relied heavily upon the fourth characteristic and seeminglyrejected the application on the basis that the Society did not correspond with theCommissionrsquos expectations of an institutional religion Although the GnosticSociety prayed for humanity and followed Christian teachings such as lsquolovethy neighbourrsquo the Commission found it striking that lsquothere was no evidenceof consistent application of such codes on their website or in the literaturersquo81

The dismissal of the application of the Gnostic Society was followed by the suc-cessful application by the Druid Network82 In this decision the Commissionagain applied its four characteristics of religion83 Here however in relationto the fourth characteristic the Commission referred to the Networkrsquos lsquoprincipleof honourable relationshipsrsquo and the way in which the promotion of ethicalcodes were integrated explicitly in its objects and through its website84 TheCommission therefore concluded that there was lsquoevidence of an identifiablepositive beneficial ethical framework promoted by the Druid Network that iscapable of having a beneficial impact on the community at largersquo85 Theweight afforded to the presence of doctrinal statements on the Internet is con-cerning It is difficult to disagree with the assessment of Luxton and Evansthat the reasoning of the Commission in both the Gnostic Society and DruidNetwork applications was reached lsquoin reliance on the Commissionrsquos own guid-ance with virtually no mention let alone analysis of the underlying case law and

79 Williamson at para 2480 Peter Luxton and Nicola Evans have pointed out that the guidance document which the Commission

cites lsquocuriously makes no mention of the fourth characteristic and so not surprisingly makes noattempt (at least directly) to provide legal authority for itrsquo P Luxton and N Evans lsquoCogent and cohe-sive Two recent charity commission decisions on the advancement of religionrsquo (2011) 752Conveyancer and Property Lawyer 144ndash151 at 146

81 Application for Registration of the Gnostic Centre at para 4482 Application for Registration of the Druid Network (21 September 2010)83 Ibid at para 2084 Ibid at paras 50 and 5185 Ibidt at para 53

1 4 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

its application to the case in handrsquo86 For Luxton and Evans these two decisionsdemonstrated lsquothe Commissionrsquos lack of awareness of the need for legal rigourwhen making a legal decisionrsquo

The two decisions also show further the problems resulting from the partialappropriation of definitional criteria from the human rights jurisprudence Thefour characteristics represented a confused cocktail of criteria adapted from theCommissionrsquos own guidance the human rights jurisprudence the Charities Act2006 and the common law definition which itself appropriated the registrationlaw definition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo Ironically although this last criterion wasthe most legally binding upon the Commission given the South Place EthicalSociety judgment it was also the criterion that felt most out of sync with theother developments given the wider adoption of the human rights approachIndeed the House of Lords in Williamson held that the lsquotrend of authority(unsurprisingly in an age of increasingly multicultural societies and increasingrespect for human rights) is towards a ldquonewer more expansive readingrdquo of reli-gionrsquo87 It could therefore have been expected that any new judicial decision onthe definition of religion would take the opportunity not only to place the SouthPlace Ethical Society judgment aside but also to further harmonise the definitionof religion following the approach taken by both the Charity Commission andEmployment Tribunals in terms of bringing the law in line with the humanrights jurisprudence Unfortunately when the opportunity arose for the judi-ciary to reconsider the matter in R (on the Application of Hodkin) v RegistrarGeneral of Births Deaths and Marriages88 it was in the context of registrationrather than charity law and the Supreme Court did not go as far as it couldhave done

THE MOVE AWAY FROM A UNIVERSAL DEFINITION

The decision in HodkinThe decision in Hodkin was on the exact same point as Segerdal89 namelywhether a chapel of the Church of Scientology could be registered as lsquoa placeof meeting for religious worshiprsquo under the Places of Worship RegistrationAct 1855 Given that the lower courts were bound by the previous decision thecase ultimately found itself in front of the Supreme Court It was unsurprisinggiven the legal and social changes since 1970 that Lord Toulson in Hodkin notedthat lsquothe understanding of religion in todayrsquos society is broadrsquo and overruled thedecision in Segerdal90 It was surprising however that the Supreme Court

86 Luxton and Evans lsquoCogent and cohesiversquo p 15087 Williamson at para 5588 [2013] UKSC 7789 [1970] 2 QB 67990 Hodkin at para 55

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

considered arguments based on human rights to be unnecessary deciding tooverrule Segerdal on other grounds and created a definition that could onlyapply for the purposes of the Places of Worship Registration Act 185591

In some respects Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointed towards a universal defin-ition of religion In contrast to the judgments in Segerdal Lord Toulson heldthat the question of whether there was religious worship was lsquoinevitably condi-tioned by whether Scientology is to be regarded as a religionrsquo92 Lord Toulsonupheld the High Courtrsquos decision that Scientology was a religion and stressedthat the phrase lsquoplace of meeting for religious worshiprsquo found in the 1855 Acthad to be interpreted in lsquoaccordance with contemporary understanding of reli-gion and not by reference to the culture of 1855rsquo93 This meant that in theabsence of lsquosome compelling contextual reason for holding otherwise religionshould not be confined to religions which recognise a supreme deityrsquo sincethis would lsquobe a form of religious discrimination unacceptable in todayrsquossocietyrsquo94 His Lordship held that confining religion in such a way would leadthe court lsquointo difficult theological territoryrsquo in a way that was inappropriate95

And he noted that the fact that Lord Denning in Segerdal recognised the needto make an exception for Buddhist temples and the absence of a satisfactoryexplanation for the rule were lsquopowerful indications that there is somethingunsound in the supposed general rulersquo96 The statutory language insteadcalled for an lsquointentionally broad sweeprsquo97

However in articulating what religion meant Lord Toulsonrsquos speech pointedagainst a universal definition of religion by providing lsquoa description and not adefinitive formularsquo of religion which could only serve for the purposes of the1855 Act Drawing upon the jurisprudence of other common law jurisdictions98

his Lordship held that religion could be described in summary as

a spiritual or non-secular belief system held by a group of adherents whichclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationship with theinfinite and to teach its adherents how they are to live their lives in conform-ity with the spiritual understanding associated with the belief system99

This description is problematic in three respects First the reference to lsquospiritualor non-secularrsquo creates a distinction between secular and non-secular beliefs

91 Ibid at para 6592 Ibid at para 3193 Ibid at para 3494 Ibid at para 5195 Ibid at paras 52ndash5396 Ibid at para 5197 Ibid at para 5698 See ibid at paras 35ndash4999 Ibid at para 57

1 4 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

which is not compatible with Article 9 ECHR discrimination law and arguablythe Charities Act 2011 (though not the Charity Commissionrsquos interpretation ofit) As Lord Toulson pointed out the exclusion of secular belief systems is appro-priate under the Places of Worship Registration Act 1855 because there are otherlegal provisions which allow for secular wedding services on approved prem-ises100 Yet this means that Lord Toulsonrsquos description cannot and should notbe used in other areas of the law where alternative and equal provision is notafforded to secular beliefs His Lordshiprsquos distinction between spiritual andsecular is also challenging because it would again seem to open the door toinappropriate theological debates This is ironically Lord Toulsonrsquos reason foromitting any reference to a supreme being He clarified that he intended torefer to lsquoa belief system which goes beyond that which can be perceived bythe senses or ascertained by the application of sciencersquo and preferred not touse the term lsquosupernaturalrsquo to express this lsquobecause it is a loaded word whichcan carry a variety of connotationsrsquo However this would seem to overlook thefact that this same criticism would also apply to the word lsquonon-secularrsquo101 Thesame criticism can be applied to Lord Toulsonrsquos reference to lsquothe infinitersquo Itis difficult to see how this is a significant improvement upon talk of alsquosupreme beingrsquo It would have been preferable not to state what a belief is tobe about but rather to adopt the human rights approach that beliefs areworldviews

Second Lord Toulsonrsquos definition viewed religion as being necessarily a col-lective affair it is something lsquoheld by a group of adherentsrsquo102 Again this isappropriate in the context of the 1855 Act but should not have wider applicationHuman rights discrimination and charity law decisions have all protected indi-viduals who develop their own religious beliefs including in ways that differfrom the mainstream of the religious group103 Such beliefs would be excludedby Lord Toulson and so it is questionable whether the description is compliantwith Article 9 Third while Lord Toulsonrsquos speech is helpful in that it underlinedthat the definitions of religion and worship for the purpose of the 1855 Actshould be dealt with distinctly it is regrettable that further clarity on the defin-ition of worship was not provided Lord Toulson dealt with the question ofworship separately but briefly He held that even if the meaning given toworship in Segerdal lsquowas not unduly narrow in 1970 it is unduly narrow

100 Ibid at paras 58ndash59101 The matter is confused further by the way in which terms such as lsquosecularrsquo lsquosecularisationrsquo and lsquosecu-

larismrsquo are used interchangeably See eg J Casanova lsquoThe secular secularizations secularismrsquo in CCalhoun M Juergensmeyer and J Van Antwerpen (eds) Rethinking Secularism (Oxford 2011) 54ndash74

102 Hodkin at para 57 emphasis added103 This would include for example Christians who felt obliged to wear crosses even though the major-

ity do not feel so obligated The European Court of Human Rightsrsquo decision in Eweida suggests thatsuch persons should be protected under Article 9 In the context of charity law see the decision inThornton v Howe (1862) 31 Beavan 14

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

nowrsquo104 The term lsquoreligious worshiprsquo should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious services whether or not the form of service fallswithin the narrower definition adopted in Segerdalrsquo105 Unfortunately hisLordship gave no further guidance as to how wide the definition of worshipwas to be now only quoting from dictionary definitions which definedworship as including performing acts of adoration feeling or expressing rever-ence and adoration and taking part in religious services religious rites andceremonies106

Although it provided some clarity in making a number of general remarksabout the need for a broad definition of religion Lord Toulsonrsquos descriptionwas deliberately applied solely for the purposes of the Places of WorshipRegistration Act 1855 There are several elements of the description whichcould lead to unfortunate results if applied in relation to human rights discrim-ination law or even charity law This is to be regretted since despite LordToulsonrsquos insistence that he was providing a description not a definition thefact that this description was given in a Supreme Court judgment means thatit is likely to be very influential in a number of areas of law This is especiallytrue in relation to charity law given that the definition of religion in SouthPlace Ethical Society was based upon the Segerdal decision which Hodkin over-ruled Unlike in Segerdal the Supreme Court in Hodkin did not regardlsquoworshiprsquo as part of the definition of lsquoreligionrsquo It would be expected that thisshould have implications for the charity law definition of advancement of reli-gion However when it fell to the Charity Commission to decide the extent towhich Hodkin would affect its fourfold definition of religion theCommissionrsquos decision further muddied the waters Given the complex waysin which the various case laws concerning the definition of religion have over-lapped it was perhaps fitting that the first opportunity for the CharityCommission to determine this came not in relation to the Church ofScientology (which is yet to reapply for charitable status for the advancementof religion) but in relation to one of the examples given by Baroness Scotlandof what lsquomight not constitute a religion or beliefrsquo Jediism

Return of the JediDespite Baroness Scotlandrsquos remark the question of whether Jediism (a belieflsquoin the Forcersquo that is linked to ideas found within Star Wars film series)

104 Hodkin at para 61105 Ibid at para 62106 Indeed it was curious that instead of following South Place Ethical Society in regarding worship as a

definitional attribute of religion Lord Toulson identified lsquoteachingrsquo as part of his description Thisraises similar concerns as the old common law definition given that Article 9 ECHR refers to reli-gion or belief being manifested lsquoin worship teaching practice and observancersquo Lord Toulsonrsquos def-inition only seems to relate to teaching and observance

1 4 8 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

constitutes a religion is not as outlandish as it may first appear107 An academicliterature exists on so-called lsquohyper-real religionsrsquo that is lsquohow some sciencefiction horror and fantasy narratives can be understood as cultural reservoirsfor the construction of religion by spiritual consumersrsquo108 And even if a signifi-cant number of those who declared their religion as Jediism in recent UK cen-suses did so as a joke or protest the fact that the size of those numbers wascomparable to other groups such as the Church of Scientology meant that itcannot be completely ignored109 Moreover regardless of the subject matter ofthe claim the Charity Commissionrsquos decision to reject an application for regis-tration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (TOTJO) provided the first opportunity tosee how Hodkin has affected its understanding of the definition of religion110

The decision noted that the lsquodefinition and characteristics of religion for the pur-poses of charity law are distilledrsquo from statutes and cases on charity law and theirpublished guidance which is now lsquoinfluencedrsquo by Hodkin although it lsquodid notrelate to a matter of charity lawrsquo111 The influence of Hodkin led the CharityCommission to re-formulate certain aspects of its four characteristics of a reli-gion in ways that were often startling

The influence of Hodkin was most visible in the reformulated first character-istic that now spoke of a need for a lsquoBelief in one or more gods or spiritual ornon-secular principles or thingsrsquo Following Hodkin the lsquofaith in a godrsquo testnow does not include reference to supreme beings but rather talks of lsquoprinciplesor thingsrsquo and distinguishes between spiritual and secular belief systems Thisallowed the Charity Commission to continue its narrow interpretation despitethe fact that as it noted lsquothe statutory definition of religion includes religionswhich do not involve belief in a godrsquo112 For the Charity Commission religionsthat do not involve belief in a god will only be religions if the principle orthing they believe in is spiritual and non-secular This follows Hodkin butignores the fact that the exclusion of secular belief systems made sense in thecontext of the registration of premises for the solemnisation of marriagebecause there are other legal provisions which allow for secular wedding ser-vices on approved premises In contrast there is no argument for making a dis-tinction between secular and non-secular beliefs for the purpose of charity law

107 For an account of Jediism as a religion see B Singler lsquoInternet-based new religious movements anddispute resolutionrsquo in R Sandberg (ed) Religion and Legal Pluralism (Aldershot 2015) pp 161ndash178

108 A Possamai Religion and Popular Culture a hyper-real testament (Brussels 2005) p 58 See alsoC Cusack Invented Religions imagination fiction and faith (Aldershot 2010) Other hyper-realreligions inspired by science fiction include neo-Pagan groups such as the Church of All Worldsas well as largely Internet-based movements such as Matrixism (based on The Matrix film trilogyby Larry and Andy Wachowski)

109 The number of Jedis was 390127 in the 2001 census and 176632 in the 2011 censusScientologyrsquos numbers in the UK censuses were 1781 in 2001 and 2418 in 2011

110 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order (16 December 2016)111 Ibid at para 9112 Ibid at para 15

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 4 9

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

(although Charity Commission decisions before Hodkin had distinguishedbetween lsquospiritualrsquo or lsquotranscendentalrsquo beliefs and beliefs that denied the exist-ence of a supreme being or entity) It is true that secular beliefs can still be char-itable if they fulfil a different charitable purpose such as the promotion of moralor ethical improvement However this seems out of sync with the general direc-tion of human rights and equality laws protecting both secular and non-secularworldviews and an argument could be made that the narrow approach taken bythe Charity Commission is incompatible with Article 9 ECHR The influence ofHodkin in removing the synonyms for God is to be welcomed but its influence indistinguishing secular and non-secular belief systems seems to have oversha-dowed what that judgment also said about the need for a broad approach todefinition

The second requirement seems unaffected by Hodkin other than the removalof the mention of supreme beings The lsquoworship of a godrsquo test from Re SouthPlace Ethical Society has been revised so that now there must be alsquoRelationship with the gods principles or things which is expressed byworship reverence and adoration veneration intercession or by some other reli-gious rite or servicersquo It is questionable whether worship should be a compulsorydefinitional attribute for the purposes of charity law especially given thatSegerdal (the case upon which Re South Place Ethical Society relied) is nolonger good law It is also noticeable that this section of the CharityCommissionrsquos decision on Jediism does not cite Hodkin The CharityCommission appears to have ignored the fact that the Supreme Court did notregard worship as part of the definition of religion Even if it is accepted thatthis test should still apply in charity law the Hodkin dicta that the Segerdal testwas lsquounduly narrowrsquo and that the term should be interpreted as being lsquowideenough to include religious servicesrsquo has also been disregarded by the CharityCommission In contrast the Commission decided that despite evidence ofmeditation sermons and lsquotranscripts of the Live Servicesrsquo Jediism did notmeet this second requirement Curiously two factors were singled out in thispart of the decision the fact that lsquoTOTJO is an entirely web based organisationrsquoand lsquothat Jediism may be adopted as a lifestyle choice as opposed to a religionrsquo113

This seems to be a conservative approach rejecting the possibility that religiousactivity can occur online and policing a rigid and artificial line between religionand lifestyle choices which is out of sync with the approach under English law toregard religious groups like any other voluntary associations114

The fact that Hodkin did not rely upon the ECHR case law has not affected theCharity Commissionrsquos third characteristic of religion which is now framed aslsquoCogency cohesion seriousness and importance in the form of the belief

113 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at paras 19ndash20114 See most recently Shergill v Khaira [2014] UKSC 33 at para 46

1 5 0 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

systemrsquo The reference to lsquobelief systemrsquo is interesting here given that charity lawprotects lsquoreligionrsquo rather than lsquoreligion or beliefrsquo This underlines that someforms of belief are to be included as part of the definition of religion The inclu-sion of this ECHR requirement is preferable to its exclusion in Hodkin given therequirements of the Human Rights Act 1998 However again the Williamsonwarnings about these requirements needing to be set at a lsquominimumrsquo andlsquomodestrsquo level are omitted115

Furthermore the way in which the Charity Commission articulated thisrequirement is problematic in two respects First the Commission stated thatJediism is not a lsquosufficiently cogent and distinct religionrsquo116 No authority isgiven for this requirement that a religion needs to be lsquodistinctrsquo and althoughecumenical and interfaith groups could instead seek charitable status for thepromotion of religious harmony117 this novel requirement would prove prob-lematic given that many religions have much in common and religions oftendevelop from one another Second the Commission stated that there lsquois insuf-ficient evidence of an objective understanding of Jediism as opposed to a self-defining system which may be pursued outside the confines of a religion andin a secular mannerrsquo and placed weight on the fact that lsquoit is not obligatory tointerpret and follow the Jedi Doctrine as a religionrsquo118 The Commission consid-ered that lsquoAny cogency and cohesion that is present is eroded by the individualrsquosability to develop themselves within a loose framework and follow an individualexperiential philosophy or way of life as a secular belief systemrsquo119 This wouldrule out individualised religious experiences contrary to the principle expressedin Williamson that lsquoFreedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an indi-vidualrsquo120 and the general approach that individuals can manifest their religionby practices that they do not share with their co-religionists and which are notobligatory according to their faith121

The fourth requirement that lsquoDoctrines and practice are of benefit to the public[and are] capable of providing moral and ethical value or edification to the publicrsquoremained unchanged and continued the Charity Commissionrsquos suspect practiceincorporating a public benefit requirement into the Commissionrsquos definition ofreligion

The Jediism decision clearly represented a development in the CharityCommissionrsquos understanding of the definition of religion It revealed that theCommission has relied upon Hodkin in deeply selective ways that are

115 Williamson at para 24116 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 24117 Charities Act 2011 s 3(1)(h)118 Application for Registration by the Temple of the Jedi Order at para 29119 Ibid at para 30120 Williamson at para 22121 As articulated in Eweida

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 1

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

problematic Without questioning the actual decision elements of the reasoningby the Charity Commission are cause for concern In relation to the first require-ment the influence of Hodkin has been significant and has led to the adoption ofa distinction between the secular and non-secular that is not appropriate outsidethe registration context By contrast in relation to the second requirementHodkin has been ignored and worship remains a definitional attribute of reli-gion for charity law purposes as if Segerdal were still good law Further a ques-tionable distinction has been made between religions and lifestyle choices thatseems to apply only in relation to charity law The Charity Commissionrsquos articu-lation of their third characteristic shows that they are not only deriving guidancefrom the ECHR case law but are embellishing it in ways that are problematicadding a requirement that religions need to be lsquodistinctrsquo and operating froman assumption that religions can be objectively described that they are obliga-tory upon members and that members are uniform in how they manifesttheir religion The Jediism decision underscores how the definition of religionunder English law is now hideously confused

CONCLUSION THE NEED FOR A UNIVERSAL DEFINITIONOF RELIGION

In Hodkin Lord Toulson stated that there were several reasons why there hadnever been a universal legal definition of religion in English law namely the dif-ferent contexts in which the issue may arise and increased religious pluralismand diversity122 These factors though important are not fatal to the quest fordefinition123 Although religious pluralism and diversity renders the definitionof religion more difficult it also renders it more important The sociologicalfact that religion lsquocan no longer be equated with familiar mainstream churchand denominational forms but takes a plurality of guidesrsquo renders lsquothe boundar-ies between religion and non-religion bewilderingly fuzzyrsquo124 It also makes thelegal definition of religion increasingly vital Legal decision-makers rarely havethe luxury of a lsquofuzzyrsquo outcome and the decisions they make affect not just theclaims in front of them but those who will bring and will not bring claims in thefuture Defining religion is an exercise in power that has significant legal pol-itical economic social and cultural effects125 As James Wiggins has argued reli-gious diversity requires the conclusion that the definition of religion lsquomust

122 Hokdin at para 34123 See further Sandberg Religion Law and Society pp 30ndash38124 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 13125 For an example of how definitions evolve over time within both legal and cultural contexts see S

Thompson lsquoIn defence of the ldquogold-diggerrdquorsquo (2016) 66 Onati Socio-Legal Series 1225ndash1248

1 5 2 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

become more expansive and elastic than ever before in human historyrsquo126 Yet anoverly expansive approach may render the term lsquoreligionrsquo meaningless Thecentral problem remains that identified by the sociologist Georg Simmel man-aging to craft a definition of religion that is both precise and sufficientlycomprehensive127

The approach generally taken by English law has been to regard the difficul-ties surrounding the definition of religion as requiring the crafting of several sti-pulative or specific definitions of religion developed by the case law on each areaof law rather than crafting a lexical or universal definition of religion Yet thisapproach has proved to be inadequate From South Place Ethical Societyonwards there has been a tradition of pragmatically appropriating parts of defi-nitions of religion from one legal context into another The incorporation ofArticle 9 into domestic law and the requirement to read legislation where pos-sible in a Convention-compliant way has given legal force to this harmonisationHowever in recent years legal decision-makers have swum against this tide andin so doing have created waves that may well torpedo future claims In HodkinLord Toulson noted the need for a broad definition of religion but only provideda description of religion for the purpose of the 1855 Act The limitations of thiscame to the fore in the Charity Commissionrsquos decision on Jediism which under-scored how confused and arbitrary the case law has become There Hodkin wasrelied upon to erect a problematic distinction between secular and non-secularbelief systems that now applies under charity and registration law but not underhuman rights and discrimination law Hodkin was then ignored to state thatworship remains a definitional attribute of religion for charity law purposesdespite the fact that the Segerdal decision upon which South Place EthicalSociety relied is no longer good law

Unlike in Hodkin the Charity Commission applied ECHR standards aboutthe nature of a religion or belief This followed the trend set by EmploymentTribunals whereby those standards apply in discrimination law despite thatarea of law protecting only religious and philosophical beliefs (rather thanbeliefs per se) and these standards have been interpreted in a more demandingway outside the context of human rights law128 The level of uncertainty the arbi-trary distinctions drawn and the questionable interpretation of the new testscreated by the Charity Commission and Employment Tribunals are matters ofconcern not only in terms of whether the reasoning is compatible with Article

126 J Wiggins lsquoWhat on earth is religionrsquo in T Idinopulos and B Wilson (eds) What is Religion Originsdefinitions amp explanations (Leiden 1998) pp 133ndash139

127 G Simmel lsquoA contribution to the sociology of religionrsquo reprinted in G Simmel Essays on Religion(New Haven CT 1997) pp 101ndash120

128 The decisions of the Charity Commission show that these standards also apply in charity law despitethat area of law protecting only religious beliefs which have been understood to possibly includenon-secular beliefs

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 3

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

9 A number of statements made by courts and tribunals are troubling on closerinspection and constitute the lsquostuff of theological debatersquo which Lord Toulsonwas keen to avoid as a matter of principle129 The time is therefore apt to recon-sider a universal definition of religion under English law

The case law reveals that elements of a universal definition already existThese need to be refashioned in order to remove inconsistencies that exist indifferent areas of law The Charity Commission in its recent decisions hasspoken of there being four characteristics Re-examining these in turn takinginto account developments in registration human rights and discriminationlaw may point to a way forward drawing upon insights from the sociology ofreligion130

The first characteristic is that there is a belief While registration and charitylaw decisions (and legislation) have sought to define what the belief is about (bytalking about supreme beings or lack of such beings and from Hodkin onwardsdistinguishing between secular and non-secular beliefs) human rights law hasfocused on what beliefs do (by looking for a worldview and ruling out mere opi-nions or beliefs that are not genuinely held) Discrimination law has adopted ahalfway approach generally following the human rights case law but specifyingthat beliefs must be religious or philosophical and may or may not be politicalThe differences here are reminiscent of a distinction often drawn by sociologistsof religion between substantive definitions which identify religion for what it isand functional definitions which identify religion for what it does131 While regis-tration and charity law have generally adopted a substantive definition of reli-gion human rights and discrimination law have adopted a functionalapproach There are elements of a functional definition of religion in LordToulsonrsquos description in Hodkin where the language of supreme beings isdropped and it is stated that a religion is held by a group of adherents andthat it lsquoclaims to explain mankindrsquos place in the universe and relationshipwith the infinitersquo and to teach each others how to live their lives132 Howeverthis assumes that religious activity is collective and also ignores the otherways in which religion can be manifested (by worship practice and observance

129 Hodkin at para 52130 For discussion of how the sociological and legal study of religion should interact see Sandberg

Religion Law and Society131 Examples of substantive definitions in sociology include Edward Burnett Tylorrsquos lsquominimum defin-

itionrsquo of religion as lsquothe belief in Spiritual Beingsrsquo (E Tylor Primitive Culture (2 vols London1920) vol I p 424) and Steve Brucersquos list that religion lsquoconsists of beliefs actions and institutionswhich assume the existence of supernatural entitiesrsquo (S Bruce Religion in Modern Britain (Oxford1995) p ix) The most famous functional definition in sociology is that provided by Durkheimwho defines religion as lsquoa unified set of beliefs and practicesrsquo for Durkheim religion is lsquosomethingeminently collectiversquo it links people together in communities providing lsquosocial solidarityrsquo (EDurkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (Oxford 2001) p 46)

132 Hodkin at para 57

1 5 4 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

as well as by teaching according to the letter of Article 9)133 However this couldbe fashioned into a definition that protects both individual and collective reli-gious freedom One of the Grainger tests requiring a belief to be on lsquoaweighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviourrsquo appears to go inthe right direction134

A functional definition is to be preferred for the very reason that Lord Toulsongave for why a universal definition should not be adopted His Lordshiprsquos refer-ence to lsquothe different contexts in which the issue may arisersquo raises the issue ofwhy law protects (or at least facilitates) religion Post-Toleration the rationaleis no longer the promotion and enforcement of religious uniformityRather law regulates religion as part of human behaviour Sociologists of reli-gion often refer to their approach towards studying religion as being one oflsquomethodological agnosticismrsquo135 In the words of Georg Simmel methodologicalagnosticism requires a distinction to be drawn between the lsquometaphysical eventthat is readily capable of implying or forming the basis of religionrsquo and lsquothe sub-jective attitude of human beingsrsquo136 Methodological agnosticism requires themaking of that distinction and the bracketing aside of the question of thestatus of religious claims137 As Berger has put it lsquoreligion is to be understoodas a human projection grounded in the specific infrastructures of humanhistoryrsquo138 Methodological agnosticism as a principle could inform the interestin definitions taken by lawyers as well as sociologists139 As Roger Cotterrell hasnoted lsquoboth law and sociology must define and conceptualize very elusiveaspects of human behaviourrsquo140 Sociologists and lawyers are primarily inter-ested in religion as a human activity and take an ultimately lsquopragmatical contex-tualised approachrsquo to defining religion141 Law does not seek to describe religionas a phenomenon but simply seeks to establish rules to regulate and facilitate itsexercise within wider social life

133 A clearer functional definition can be found in the definition of lsquoan organisation relating to religionor beliefrsquo provided by Schedule 32 para 2 of the Equality Act 2010 which states that this is lsquoan organ-isation the purpose of which is lsquoto practice advance and teach the principles of that religion toenable persons of the religion to receive benefits and engage in activities and to improve relationsbetween religious groupsrsquo This too assumes that religious activity is collective (given that it is defin-ing an organisation for the purpose of creating exceptions from discrimination law)

134 Grainger at para 24135 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 35136 G Simmel lsquoContributions to the epistemology of religionrsquo reprinted in Simmel Essays on Religion

pp 121ndash133137 M Hamilton The Sociology of Religion theoretical and comparative perspectives (second edition Oxford

2001) p 5138 P Berger The Sacred Canopy (New York 1969) p 180139 Sandberg Religion Law and Society p 36140 R Cotterrell Law Culture and Society legal ideas in the mirror of social theory (Aldershot 2006) p 2141 A Molendijk lsquoIn defence of pragmatismrsquo in J Platvoet and A Molendijk (eds) The Pragmatics of

Defining Religion contexts concepts amp contests (Leiden 1999) pp 3ndash19 at p 4

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 5

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

It follows that a functional approach to defining religion should be taken Theapproach of Williamson should be followed it should generally be accepted thatfreedom of religion protects the subjective beliefs of the individual and arbitrarydistinctions should not be drawn There should be no requirement that beliefsmust be religious or philosophical (as in discrimination law) or spiritual andnon-secular (as in Hodkin and the Jediism decision) or that non-philosophicalor political beliefs (as in discrimination law) lifestyles and activities performedfor recreation can be clearly distinguished from manifestations of religion orbelief (as in Whaley and the Jediism decision) Instead the word lsquoreligionrsquoshould be interpreted as including all forms of belief including beliefsdefined by a lack of belief There will of course be some claims that legaldecision-makers will need to exclude but the reason for the exclusion willrelate to the human behaviour ndash the manifestation of the belief ndash rather thanthe nature of the belief itself These claims will typically be excluded not ongrounds of the definition of religion but in relation to other tests that need tobe satisfied in order for the religious right to be enjoyed In the context ofcharity law the focus will be on the public benefit test in human rights lawthe emphasis will be on the Article 9(2) limitations on the manifestation of reli-gion and in discrimination law the importance will be based on proportionalityA functional definition will not protect religious practices that are beyond thepale but such practices will be excluded as manifestations of human behaviourrather than on grounds of the nature of the belief An approach based on meth-odological agnosticism would allow legal decision-makers to avoid making diffi-cult and inappropriate theological interpretations

The second characteristic of religion as articulated by the Charity Commissionndash worship ndash should no longer be a definitional attribute The appropriation of thedefinition of lsquoreligious worshiprsquo from Segerdal by South Place Ethical Society in theattempt to define lsquoadvancement of religionrsquo was questionable at the time and iseven more questionable now given that Hodkin has overruled Segerdal LordToulsonrsquos opinion makes it clear that in defining the term lsquoa place of meetingfor religious worshiprsquo separate consideration is to be given to the definitions ofreligion and of worship It follows that in every other context the definition ofworship should not form part of the definition of religion Rather it should beaccepted that religion can be manifested through worship teaching practiceand observance (as the text of Article 9 makes plain) and as Williamsonreminds us the standard here should not be too rigid A purported religionthat carried out acts of cannibalism or terrorism would be denied legal protectionnot because the nature of such activities did not constitute worship but because ofthe social harm that they cause A functional approach based on methodologicalagnosticism would retain the third characteristic of a religion requiring a certainlevel of cogency seriousness cohesion and importance but would followWilliamson in assessing this subjectively stressing that these requirements are

1 5 6 C L A R I F Y I N G T H E D E F I N I T I O N O F R E L I G I O N U N D E R E N G L I S H L AW

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition

understood to be set at a lsquomodestrsquo and lsquominimumrsquo level and by not creating con-servative thresholds requiring institutional presences or for each religion to bedistinct The Charity Commissionrsquos fourth requirement that of public benefitis especially important from a functional methodological agnostic perspectivebut should not form part of the definition of religion as such unless perhaps itneeds to be stated that religious activities that cause social harm are not to belegally protected The final limb of the Grainger test may be useful here as maythe guidance in Williamson that a belief must be consistent with basic standardsof human dignity or integrity142 In short adopting a functional methodologicalagnostic approach to defining religion could lead to the following universal defin-ition under English law

Freedom of religion protects the subjective belief of an individual Religionincludes all forms of belief including lack of belief The belief must be agenuinely held worldview that relates to a weighty and substantial aspect oflife and attains a minimum and modest level of cogency seriousnesscohesion and importance The belief can be manifested or advancedthrough worship teaching practice or observance It must be consistentwith basic standards of human dignity or integrity

142 Grainger at para 24 Williamson at para 24

E C C L E S I A S T I C A L L AW J O U R N A L 1 5 7

of use available at httpswwwcambridgeorgcoreterms httpsdoiorg101017S0956618X18000030Downloaded from httpswwwcambridgeorgcore IP address 6521228167 on 23 Nov 2021 at 031740 subject to the Cambridge Core terms

  • Clarifying the Definition of Religion Under English Law The Need for a Universal Definition