combining bayesian beliefs and willingness to bet to analyze attitudes towards uncertainty by peter...

30
Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes towards Uncertainty by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept., Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam (joint with Mohammed Abdellaoui & Aurélien Baillon) RUD, Tel Aviv, June 24 '07 Topic: Uncertainty/Ambiguity.

Post on 21-Dec-2015

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Combining Bayesian Beliefs and Willingness to Bet to Analyze Attitudes

towards Uncertainty

by Peter P. Wakker, Econ. Dept.,Erasmus Univ. Rotterdam

(joint with Mohammed Abdellaoui & Aurélien Baillon) RUD, Tel Aviv, June 24 '07

Topic: Uncertainty/Ambiguity.

2

Making uncertainty/ambiguity more operational:

measuring, predicting,quantifying completely,in tractable manner.

No (new) maths; but "new" (mix of) concepts: uniform sources; source-dependent probability transformation.

1. Introduction

Good starting point for uncertainty: Risk.Many nonEU theories exist, virtually all amounting to:

x y 0; xpy w(p)U(x) + (1–w(p))U(y);

Relative to EU: one more graph …

3

4

inverse-S, (likelihood

insensitivity)

p

w

expected utility

mot

ivat

iona

l

cognitive

pessimism

extreme inverse-S ("fifty-fifty")

prevailing finding

pessimistic "fifty-fifty"

Abdellaoui (2000); Bleichrodt & Pinto (2000); Gonzalez & Wu 1999; Tversky & Fox, 1997.

Now to Uncertainty (unknown probabilities);

In general, on the x-axis we have events. So, no nice graphs …

5

Many advanced theories;mostly ambiguity-averse

6

CEU (Gilboa 1987;

Schmeidler 1989)

PT

(Tversky &

Kahnem

an 1992)Multiple priors (Gilboa

& Schmeidler 1989)

Endogeneous definitions

(Epstein, Zhang, Kopylov,

Ghirardato, Marinacci)

Smooth (KMM; Nau)Variational

model (Maccheroni,

Marinacci,

Rustichini)

Many tractable empirical studies;also inverse-S

Curley & Yates 1985

Fox & Tve

rsky

1995

Biseparable

(Ghirardato &

Marinacci 2001)

Choice-based

Kilka & We-ber 2001

Cabantous

2005di Mauro & Maffioletti 2005

Nice graphs, but x-axis-problem: choice-less probability-inputs there

We connect

Einhorn & Hogarth 1985

next p.p. 9 (theory)

Einhorn & Hogarth 1985 (+ 1986 + 1990).Over 400 citations after '88.

For ambiguous event A, take "anchor probability" pA (c.f. Hansen & Sargent). Weight S(pA):

S(pA) = (1 – )pA + (1 – pA);

: index of inverse-S (regression to mean); ½.: index of elevation (pessimism/ambiguity aversion);

7

Einhorn & Hogarth 1985

Graphs: go to pdf file of Hogarth & Einhorn (1990, Management Science 36, p. 785/786).

Problem of the x-axis …

8

p. 6 (butter fly-theories)

2. Theory

Only binary acts with gains.

All popular static nonEU theories (except variational):

x y 0; xEy W(E)U(x) + (1–W(E))U(y).

(Ghirardato & Marinacci 2001).

For rich S, such as continuum, general W is too complex.

9

Machina & Schmeidler (1992), probabilistic sophistication:

x y; xEy w(P(E))U(x) + (1–w(P(E)))U(y).

Then still can get nice x-axis for uncertainty!

However,

10

Common preferences between gambles for $100:(Rk: $100) (Ru: $100)(Bk: $100) (Bu: $100)

>

11

Ellsberg paradox. Two urns with 20 balls.

Ball drawn randomly from each. Events:Rk: Ball from known urn is red. Bk, Ru, Bu are similar.

Known urnk

10 R10 B

20 R&B in unknown proportion

Unknown urnu

? 20–?

P(Rk) > P(Ru) P(Bk) > P(Bk)

+1

+1 ><Under probabilistic sophistication

with a (non)expected utility model:

Ellsberg: There cannot exist probabilities in any sense. No "x-axis" and no nice graphs …

12

(Or so it seems?)

>

Common preferences between gambles for $100:(Rk: $100) (Ru: $100) (Bk: $100) (Bu: $100)

20 R&B in unknown proportion

Ellsberg paradox. Two urns with 20 balls.

Ball drawn randomly from each. Events:Rk: Ball from known urn is red. Bk, Ru, Bu are similar.

10 R10 B

Known urnk Unknown urnu

? 20–?

P(Rk) > P(Ru) P(Bk) > P(Bk)

+ +1 1 ><Under probabilistic sophistication

with a (non)expected utility model:

13

twomodels, depending on source

reconsidered.

Step 1 of our approach (to operationalize uncertainty/ambiguity):

Distinguish between different sources of uncertainty.

Step 2 of our approach:Define sources within which probabilistic sophistication holds. We call them

Uniform sources.

14

Step 3 of our approach:

Develop a method for (theory-free)* eliciting probabilities within uniform sources; empirical elaboration of Chew & Sagi's exchangeability.

* Important because we will use different decision theories for different sources

15

Step 4 of our approach:Decision theory for uniform sources S, source-dependent. E denotes event w.r.t. S.

x y; xEy wS(P(E))U(x) + (1–wS(P(E)))U(y).

wS: source-dependent probability transformation. (Einhorn & Hogarth 1985; Kilka & Weber 2001)

Ellsberg: wu(0.5) < wk(0.5) u: k: unknown known

(Choice-based) probabilities can be maintained.We get back our x-axis, and those nice graphs!

16

We have reconciled Ellsberg 2-color with Bayesian beliefs! (Also KMM/Nau did partly.)

We cannot do so always; Ellsberg 3-color(2 sources!?).

17

18

`c =0.08

w(p)

Fig.a. Insensitivity index a: 0;pessimism index b: 0.  

Figure 5.2. Quantitative indexes of pessimism and likelihood insensitivity

00.11= c

10.89

d =0.11

Fig.b. Insensitivity index a: 0;pessimism index b: 0.22. 

c =0.11

 

d =0.11

Fig.c. Insensitivity index a: 0.22;pessimism index b: 0.

0

d =0.14

Fig.d. Insensitivity index a: 0.22; pessimism index b: 0.06. 

d =01

p

c = 0 0

Theory continued:

(Chateauneuf, Eichberger, & Grant 2005 ; Kilka & Weber 2001; Tversky & Fox 1995)

3. Let the Rubber Meet the Road: An Experiment

Data:

19

4 sources:1. CAC40;2. Paris temperature;3. Foreign temperature;4. Risk.

Method for measuring choice-based probabilities20

EE EEE E

Figure 6.1. Decomposition of the universal event

a3/4

E

a1/2a1/4a1/8a3/8

E

b1a5/8 a7/8b0

a3/4a1/2a1/4

E E

b1b0

E E

a1/2

E

b1b0

E

E = S

b1b0

The italicized numbers and events in the bottom row were not elicited.

21

3025

Median choice-based probabilities (real incentives)

Real data over 19002006

0.035201510

0.8

0.6

0.4

0.2

1.0

Figure 7.2. Probability distributions for Paris temperature

Median choice-based probabilities (hypothetical choice)

0.0

Median choice-based probabilities (real incentives)

Real data over the year 2006

0 1 2 3123

0.8

0.6

0.4

0.2

1.0

Figure 7.1. Probability distributions for CAC40

Median choice-based probabilities (hypothetical choice)

Results for choice-based probabilities

Uniformity confirmed 5 out of 6 cases.

Certainty-equivalents of 50-50 prospects.Fit power utility with w(0.5) as extra unknown.

22

0

HypotheticalReal

1 2 30

1

0.5

Figure 7.3. Cumulative distribution of powers

Method for measuring utility

Results for utility

23

Results for uncertainty ("ambiguity?")

24

0.125

00

Figure 8.3. Probability transformations for participant 2

Fig. a. Raw data and linear interpolation.

0.25

0.875

0.75

1

0.50

0.125 0.8750.25 0.50 0.75 1

Paris temperature; a = 0.78, b =  0.12

foreign temperature; a = 0.75, b = 0.55

risk:a = 0.42, b = 0.13

Within-person comparisons

Many economists, erroneously, take this symmetric weighting fuction as unambiguous or ambiguity-neutral.

25

participant 2;a = 0.78, b = 0.69

0 *

Fig. a. Raw data and linear interpolation.

*

Figure 8.4. Probability transformations for Paris temperature

0.25

0.125

0.875

0.75

1

0.50

0.125 0.8750.250 0.50 0.75 1

participant 48;a = 0.21, b = 0.25

Between-person comparisons

Example of predictions [Homebias; Within-Person Comparison; subject lives in Paris]. Consider investments.Foreign-option: favorable foreign temperature: $40000unfavorable foreign temperature: $0Paris-option:favorable Paris temperature: $40000unfavorable Paris temperature: $0

Assume in both cases: favorable and unfavo-rable equally likely for subject 2; U(x) = x0.88. Under Bayesian EU we’d know all now.NonEU: need some more graphs; we have them!

26

27

Paris temperature Foreign temperature

decision weightexpectationcertainty equivalentuncertainty premiumrisk premiumambiguity premium

0.49 0.2020000 2000017783 6424

1357622175879 5879

7697–3662

Within-person comparisons (to me big novelty of Ellsberg):

28

Subject 2,p = 0.125

decision weightexpectationcertainty equivalentuncertainty premiumrisk premiumambiguity premium

0.35 0.675000 35000

12133159742732

571710257–3099

Subject 48,p = 0.125

Subject 2,p = 0.875

Subject 48,p = 0.875

5000 350000.08 0.52

2268

654 9663–39–4034

–71332078

962419026 25376

Between-person comparisons; Paris temperature

Conclusion:

By (1) recognizing importance of uniform sources and source-dependent probability transformations;(2) carrying out quantitative measurements of (a) probabilities (subjective), (b) utilities, (c) uncertainty attitudes (the graphs), all in empirically realistic and tractable manner,

we make ambiguity completely operational at a quantitative level.

29

The end

30