contemporary critical consciousness peter sloterdijk, oskar negt-alexander kluge

13
7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 1/13 German Studies ssociation  Contemporary Critical Consciousness: Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt/Alexander Kluge, and the "New Subjectivity" Author(s): Leslie A. Adelson Source: German Studies Review , Vol. 10, No. 1 (Feb., 1987), pp. 57-68 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press on behalf of the German Studies Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1430443 Accessed: 27-06-2016 16:02 UTC  Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms  JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. German Studies Association, The Johns Hopkins University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to German Studies Review This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Upload: skl

Post on 28-Feb-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 1/13

German Studies ssociation

 

Contemporary Critical Consciousness: Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt/Alexander Kluge, and

the "New Subjectivity"Author(s): Leslie A. Adelson

Source: German Studies Review , Vol. 10, No. 1 (Feb., 1987), pp. 57-68Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press on behalf of the German StudiesAssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1430443Accessed: 27-06-2016 16:02 UTC

 

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

http://about.jstor.org/terms

 

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusteddigital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about

JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

German Studies Association, The Johns Hopkins University Press are collaborating withJSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to German Studies Review 

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 2: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 2/13

 Contemporary Critical

 Consciousness: Peter Sloterdijk,

 Oskar Negt/Alexander Kluge,

 and the "New Subjectivity"

 Leslie A. Adelson

 Ohio State University

 One of the few things to emerge with any clarity from the

 raging debates on modernism, postmodernism, deconstruction, and

 poststructuralism is that the traditional notion of a subject, defined

 according to the European experience of Enlightenment, is simply

 no longer - if indeed it ever was - a tenable one. Or, as Andreas

 Huyssen has noted, "the discourse of subjectivity has been cut loose

 from its moorings in bourgeois individualism. "I Merely to label the

 quest for or the assertion of subjective identity confining or even

 oppressive is, however, to beg the question as to any conceivable

 moorings for "the subject" at all. Is the term itself obsolete, or is it

 perhaps ground that needs to be reclaimed from the sea of scholarly

 tradition and innovation, ground for "the upright gait" (Bloch) ?

 Huyssen sees in contemporary French theories of post-

 structuralism "a theory of modernism at the stage of its exhaustion,

 [. . .] a modernism all confident in its rejection of representation and

 reality, in its denial of the subject, of history, and of the subject of

 history." "Doesn't poststructuralism," he asks, "where it simply

 denies the subject altogether, jettison the chance of challenging the

 ideology of the subject (as male, white, and middle-class) by

 developing alternative and different notions of subjectivity?"2 A

 "postmodernism of resistance" - Huyssen's phrase3- certainly

 1. Andreas Huyssen, "Mapping the Postmodern," in New German Critique 33

 (Fall 1984), p. 44.

 2. Huyssen, pp. 39 and 44. See also Hal Foster, "(Post) Modern Polemics," in

 New German Critique 33 (Fall 1984), p. 78.

 3. Huyssen, p. 52.

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 3: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 3/13

 58 GERMANSTUDES REVEW

 calls for some notion of human subjectivity anchored in social

 circumstance. This concern is not merely a theoretical one but also

 informs discussions of West Germany's Alternativbewegungen,

 those diverse social movements that refuse easy political

 homogenization or categorization. Seeing these movements as a

 rejection of either a bourgeois or a socialist claim to universalist

 culture, one West German sociologist comments: "Nicht die alte

 Ich-Autonomie soll restauriert werden; es geht,

 gesamtgesellschaftlich gedacht, um Subjektfahigkeit."4 So the

 traditional Enlightenment subject squares off against the as yet

 elusive subject - if indeed there is one - of contemporary social

 movements. What then does it mean to discuss "subjects of

 contemporary critical consciousness"? Subjektfahigkeit is of

 course not Subjektivitit, but the difficulties in discussing one are, I

 think, structurally related to difficulties in discussing the other.

 Precisely these difficulties will provide the focus for this paper.

 Two highly unconventional texts that lend themselves to a

 questioning of what it means to be subjects of critical consciousness

 in the 1980s are Peter Sloterdijk's Kritik der zynischen Vernunft

 (1983) and Oskar Negt/Alexander Kluge's Geschichte und

 Eigensinn (1981).5 Both works can be seen - see themselves in fact

 -as an attempt to reinstate the human body to its rightful place in

 critical theory; to do so entails for both a certain distancing from the

 Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School. Sloterdijk ascertains a

 kinship with Adorno and Critical Theory to the extent that the

 latter proceeded dialectically without the "victor's fantasies" that,

 Sloterdijk alleges, mar other theories of modernity (pp. 682 and

 687). He notes further, however, that Critical Theory claimed "a

 provisional ego (Ich)" as the locus of criticism, albeit one defined

 and born in pain (p. 19). Sloterdijk rejects this accession to

 negativity as being incapable of effective social resistance. "Die

 Antithese entfaltet sich nicht zum Gegenpol, sondern bleibt ein

 blosses 'Potential', eine erstickte und schlafende Negation" (p. 693).

 For Sloterdijk, the critical agent capable of duping or foiling the

 cyclops of our times should be properly called, not the "nobody" of

 4. Urs Jaeggi, "Drinnen und draussen," in Jurgen Habermas, ed., Stichworte

 zur 'Geistigen Situation der Zeit', 2. Band: Politik und Kultur, 3rd edition.

 (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1980), p. 468.

 5. Peter Sloterdijk, Kritik der zynischen Vernunft (Frankfurt/Main:

 Suhrkamp, 1983), and Oskar Negt/Alexander Kluge, Geschichte und Eigensinn:

 Geschichtliche Organisation der Arbeitsverm6gen, Deutschland als

 Produktionsoffentlichkeit, Gewalt des Zusammenhangs (Frankfurt/Main:

 Zweitausendeins, 1981).

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 4: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 4/13

 ese A Adeson59

 Homeric tradition, but the "yesbody" (p. 156). This agent of critical

 resistance that affirms life with his body is Sloterdijk's Kyniker, a

 term that remains to be clarified. Negt and Kluge similarly

 acknowledge the achievements of Critical Theory, notably

 Horkheimer and Adorno's radical critique of the functionings of

 consciousness, but the authors of Geschichte und Eigensinn regard

 consciousness as, only one aspect of what they call "die gesamte

 geschichtliche Arbeitskraft selber." For them critical resistance is

 "die Kritik der Arbeitskraft an dem gesamten historischen Apparat

 der Arbeitskraft" (p. 494). To understand what this means and how

 it relates (or does not) to Sloterdijk's Kyniker, we must explore the

 concepts and critiques of subjective identity that inform these two

 texts.

 Sloterdijk's notion of Kyniker is derived from his analysis of

 the role of cynicism in the history of the Enlightenment. Cynicism

 is "das aufgeklarte falsche Bewul3tsein"(p. 37), that fresh vitality

 which has betrayed its original goal of resisting oppression,

 unmasking deception, and attaining freedom. In what he

 characterizes as the ongoing, unequal dialogue between those who

 exercise institutionalized power and those who exercise none,

 Sloterdijk ascertains throughout modern history (at least since

 classical Greek antiquity) the two "constants" (p. 401) of cynicism

 and its opposite, kynismos. The originally intended subject of the

 Enlightenment becomes "the subject," now in quotation marks,

 primarily concerned with self-preservation against everyone and

 everything perceived as other in a reality which has become the

 source of all possible deceptions. The "subject" that must barricade

 itself to survive in the face of such threats becomes instead a

 paranoid Selbsterhaltungs-Ich (pp. 650-651). According to

 Sloterdijk, this leads to an approximation of the ego to a rigidified,

 externalized thing: a weapon. "Zwischen dem Helden und seiner

 Waffe verschwindet der Unterschied; die gigantomanischen

 Selbsterhaltungs-Iche unserer Kultur haben das eigene Dasein als

 Waffe aus sich herausgesetzt"(p. 650). At the height of modernity

 we have, Sloterdijk contends, "die Identitat von Subjektivitat und

 Bewaffnung"(p. 695). The atomic Bomb becomes in this analysis the

 concrete, technical representation of what has become of the

 subject in industrially developed countries (pp. 259, 597, 634, 650,

 695).6 As the intended counterpoint to such a "self-preserving" ( )

 6. For a more elaborate analysis of "the Bomb" in Sloterdijk's text, see my

 article on "The Bomb and I: Peter Sloterdijk, Botho Strauss, and Christa Wolf,"

 forthcoming in Monatshefte.

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 5: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 5/13

 6 GERMANSTUDES REVEW

 ego, Sloterdijk's Kyniker rejects by definition any "fixed form" of

 ego identity (p. 133). Not representing but actually living

 "Selbstverk6rperung im Widerstand"(p. 400), Sloterdijk's Kyniker

 somehow mysteriously manages to elude those market forces or

 other institutionalized forms of social organization that have

 otherwise secured subjectivity as an armed state. In fact,

 Sloterdijk's examples of Kyniker are all steeped in socio-historical

 contexts, which become muted when he abstracts from them his

 "constants"of cynic and Kyniker. The faith he articulates in such

 unscathed, vital human forces furthermore implies the Kyniker's

 capacity to erase, individualistically, the boundaries between

 public and private spheres without, however, attaining to public

 power himself. Let us recall for a moment that Sloterdijk's prime

 example of the Kyniker (albeit certainly not his only one) is

 Diogenes masturbating in the marketplace. The free space of

 monadic resistance so conceived is, to be sure, problematic, not least

 of all because of some of the circumstances of modern existence

 which Sloterdijk himself rightly attacks. Modernity, he argues, is

 characterized by the loss of a common denominator for the

 experience of the self and that of the world (pp. 137, 934); subjective

 reason is reduced to an abbreviated private reason (p. 946). "Auf

 Subjektivitat haben wir uns im wesentlichen deswegen

 spezialisiert, weil wir an den Sinn und das Wohlwollen eines

 Ganzen, selbst wenn wir wollten, nicht glauben k6nnten"(p. 942).

 Although he cites this split between privately defined and

 collectively oriented subjective experience as pivotal to the

 dilemma of contemporary identity, he does not argue for a theory

 or praxis that actively mediates between the two. Instead, he

 implicitly posits the Kyniker as a monadic entity beyond the

 dictates of oppressive social identities but also outside any collective

 capable of organized resistance to social domination. He would have

 us believe that the Kyniker is a non-subject with no fixed social

 identity but at one with his own body. This body becomes both the

 agent and the vehicle of resistance, as Sloterdijk perceives it.7

 The body plays a very different role for Negt/Kluge in

 Geschichte und Eigensinn, as does, consequently, the notion of

 identity. Even a comparison of Sloterdijk and Negt/Kluge's

 treatment of tongues will reveal that Sloterdijk, in contrast to

 7. For a more detailed critique of Sloterdijk's Kritik see my review essay,

 "Against the Enlightenment: A Theory with Teeth for the 1980s," in German

 Quarterly 57 (Fall 1984), No. 4, pp. 625-631.

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 6: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 6/13

 ese A Adeson61

 Negt/Kluge, has no concept of experience as work or process. The

 famous photograph of Einstein sticking out his tongue illustrates

 Sloterdijk's section on "Zunge, herausgestreckt" (pp. 270-273), but

 the picture bears no caption or identification. The reader is given no

 textual clue as to who the person in the picture is or what the

 circumstances were in which he (Einstein) assumed this pose. The

 text itself emphasizes the capacity of the body, in this case of the

 tongue, to say no, "wo es mit Worten allein nicht weitergeht" (p.

 270). Citing Eulenspiegel as a modern Kyniker, Sloterdijk asserts

 that the Kyniker plays the greater moralist by making it clear that

 one must violate moral codes to salvage morals (p. 273). In this

 context, if we may be so generous as to call it that, the tongue

 functions as a symbol of resistance. For Negt/Kluge on the other

 hand, the tongue is an organ of orientation, one that mediates

 between interior and exterior space.

 Ob etwas zu mir paBt, ob es roh oder gekocht ist, ob es mich

 vergiftet, das pruift sie intim. Sie beteiligt sich an der Sprache,

 alle ihre Gewohnheiten sind kollektiv. Es gibt Landschaften in

 Deutschland, in denen hat sich der Freiheitsgedanke nicht

 entwickelt, wohl aber die Esslust - die Intelligenz ist in die

 Zunge abgewandert (p. 1005).

 But Negt/Kluge do not accord the tongue, or any other organ for

 that matter, the capacity to yield orientation. Orientation, they

 argue, depends on the production of a public sphere that links what

 is public with what is intimate (p. 1005). For Negt/Kluge the body is

 an ever open door to experience of the self and the world; indeed,

 their analysis does not allow for the distinction between the two

 since they exist, not as entities unto themselves, but as mutually

 constitutive components of social reality as process.

 Uns interessiert die Natur der Zellen, die Haut, die Korper, das

 Hirn, die fuinf Sinne, die daruf aufgebauten gesellschaftlichen

 Organe: Lieben, Wissen, Trauern, Erinnern, Familiensinn,

 Hunger nach Sinn, die gesellschaftlichen Augen, die

 kollektiven Aufmerksamkeiten. Einiges davon gibt es

 wirklich; anderes davon existiert als nicht ausgeubtes

 Vermogen, als Protest oder Utopie (p. 45).

 The body is seen concretely as that through which all human

 experience is filtered, processed, and pursued; it is at once personal

 and social. Never privy to a fixed, permanent identity, it can

 sometimes be the battleground for conflicting social antagonisms in

 the same person (p. 782). This understanding of multiple,

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 7: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 7/13

 62 GERMANSTUDES REVEW

 conflicting subjectivities within the same body is something for

 which Sloterdijk does not fully allow. It is, however, central to

 Negt/Kluge's theses on what it means to be a subject. At the same

 time, it should be noted that they studiously eschew such simplistic

 terminology. They speak of Arbeitskrdfte (in the broadest sense),

 not "subjects."

 How is it then that Negt/Kluge cite the very real need for

 identity, identity as tYberlebenskategorie (pp. 502-503)? Like

 Sloterdijk and other theorists of the 1980s, Negt/Kluge reject the

 classical Enlightenment configuration of identity.

 Einer kann sich identisch verhalten; dies ist aber die Summe

 seiner Schwankungen, Nicht-Identitaten, und eines Restes an

 Notwehr hiergegen, in dem sich beharrliches, identisches

 Festhalten an einem Rest oder einem Vorbehalt zeigt. Dies

 ware im klassischen Sinne Nicht-Identitat, namlich nach der

 Vorstellung, in der innerhalb der gebildeten und besitzenden

 Oberschicht im 18. und frtihen 19. Jahrhundert sich das

 Konzept der Personlichkeit herausgebildet hat, die zwischen

 Aussenwelt und ihrem inneren Souveran integrierte. Das hat

 es auch in der Oberschicht und im Zeitraum der Klassik nur

 unter enormen Kosten (d.h. Ausgrenzungen) gegeben. [ ...]

 Radikale Versuche zur Identitat kosten das Leben oder Teile

 der Kommunikation (Holderlin, Kleist). Fur die proletarische

 Klasse sprechen wir nirgends von solcher Identitat.

 Soweit wir von Identitat handeln, sprechen wir von einer

 Eigenschaftskette, die sich im Zustand radikaler Bedtirfnisse

 befindet, also der Substanz nach: von Nicht-Identitat (p. 376)8.

 This being the case, Negt/Kluge ask, not so rhetorically: "Wer hat

 aber die Vorstellung vom Paradies, den falschen Glauben, oder

 sein Gegenteil, wenn Staat, BewuB3tsein, Identitats-Geftihle nicht

 die subjektiven Trager sein konnen?" Their own reply: "Es sind

 lebendige, d.h. subjektive Splitter die Traiger (p. 395). This is

 indeed a radical challenge to traditional notions of subjective

 agency. As Negt/Kluge see it, identity becomes a "Kategorie des

 Mangels" (p. 376). It cannot be attained, affirmatively, by merely

 filling in the gaps in existing structures. Aneignung oder

 Wiederaneignung ist nicht der Gegenpol zu Enteignung. Bei Marx

 8. See Negt/Kluge, Offentlichkeit und Erfahrung: Zur Organisationsanalyse

 von burgerlicher und proletarischer Offentlichkeit (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp,

 1972), for their expanded understanding of the term "proletarian."

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 8: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 8/13

 ese A Adeson63

 heiBt der Gegenpol zu Selbstentfremdung und Enteignung

 Verwirklichung" (p. 42). The fact is that Negt/Kluge do not allow,

 categorically, for individual resistance or even individual

 subjectivity." The common assumption that subjectivity consists of

 all things private (wishes, hopes, feelings, etc.) merely reproduces,

 they argue, structures of domination. Das Anhangsel des

 Anhangsels, naimlich das, was kompensatorisch Menschen

 brauchen, um es in diesem zudiktierten Verhaltnis auszuhalten,

 wird subjektiv genannt" (p. 784). Yet even the societal maintenance

 of this misconception requires a great deal of subjective

 engagement (p. 784). The need for identity cannot be met

 individualistically or on purely subjective ground. "Es bleibt dann

 ungegenstandlich, wenn nicht die kollektiven Bedingungen fir

 Identitit hinzuproduziert sind. Das ist die gesellschaftliche Seite

 der Identitat" (pp. 503, 519).

 A related critique of the equation of subjectivity with things

 private as well as the consequent call to treat subjectivity as a

 collective, social process can be found in Herbert Marcuse's

 favorable analysis of the politics of Rudolf Bahro, once an industrial

 manager in the GDR imprisoned for writing The Alternative in

 eastern Europe and now a Green activist in the West.9 Marcuse

 praises Bahro's shift from "the objectivity of political economy to

 subjectivity, to consciousness as a potential material force for

 radical change" (p. 26). The subject of the revolution becomes in

 this case not the ego, but instinctual structures working "in unison

 with an emancipatory consciousness" (p. 45). This must be, by

 definition, a collective undertaking. Given that the individual is a

 "species being" (p. 45), Marcuse insists, the ego cannot be authentic,

 and any political theory that stops at the ego merely succumbs to

 commodity fetishism (p. 46). "The cult of immediacy is reactionary"

 (p. 43). Marcuse designates solidarity as "the force of the life

 instincts (p. 45). It is this notion of collective-individual

 subjectivity, he claims, that allows for the "realm of freedom

 within the realm of necessity" (p. 47).

 While Negt/Kluge do not seem inclined to credit emancipatory

 consciousness per se with so much potential for radical social

 change, they do seem to share the conviction that there is a "realm

 of freedom" - even beyond mere resistance - within social givens.

 9. Herbert Marcuse, "Protosocialism and Late Capitalism: Toward a

 Theoretical Synthesis Based on Bahro's Analysis, in Ulf Wolter, ed., Rudolf Bahro:

 Critical Responses, (White Plains, New York: M.E. Sharpe, Inc., 1980), pp. 25-48.

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 9: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 9/13

 64 GERMANSTUDES REVEW

 One should say more properly, moments of freedom, not from

 social constraints but in social process. After all, if the carriers of

 ideas of paradise or consciousness are not subjects but "subjektive

 Splitter," it stands to reason that there are no whole lives - such as

 Sloterdijk's Kyniker might embody - but moments in constantly

 shifting subject-object relationships that attest to self-regulation in

 the face of domination. An analysis of the "social side of identity"

 (Negt/Kluge, p. 503) must take these shifting relationships into

 account.

 This is where the difficulties in discussing Subjektfdhigkeit and

 Subjektivitat merge. Both Kritik der zynischen Vernunft and

 Geschichte und Eigensinn are informed by a critique of those social

 and theoretical processes which systematically silence or exclude

 facets of reality. The exclusion of or distinction between subjects

 and subjectivity on the one hand and society and social processes on

 the other is only one such Ausgrenzung. "Das was vorgibt Realitat

 zu sein, unter diesem Namen auftritt, ist fiktiv. Es ist unter

 Trennung von wesentlichen Anteilen der Geschichte erbaut. Es ist

 aber Geschichte darin versteckt" (Negt/Kluge, p. 32; see also p. 505).

 History is, however, not only the silenced partner in what passes as

 contemporary reality; it is also the silenced partner in what passes

 for subjectivity. Another way of asking the question as to the

 subjects of contemporary critical consciousness is to ask what

 constitutes Gegenwartsbewdltigung. I would suggest that coming

 to terms with the present can only mean coming to terms with the

 past in the present. For how else are we to grasp the present and the

 role of contemporary critical consciousness if not as that

 bequeathed to us by and through history? The subject - be it

 Negt/Kluge's "subjektive Splitter" or even Sloterdijk's Kyniker

 is the locus where past and present meet.

 Walter Benjamin speaks of "unterdrtickte Vergangenheit"

 which historical materialism can, so to speak, liberate.10

 Vergangenes historisch artikulieren heiB3t nicht, es erkennen

 'wie es denn eigentlich gewesen ist.' Es heiB3t, sich einer

 Erinnerung bemachtigen, wie sie im Augenblick einer Gefahr

 aufblitzt. Dem historischen Materialismus geht es darum, ein

 Bild der Vergangenheit festzuhalten, wie es sich im

 Augenblick der Gefahr dem historischen Subjekt unversehens

 einstellt (p. 253).

 10. Walter Benjamin, 'Ober den Begriff der Geschichte, Illuminationen:

 Ausgewahlte Schriften, 2nd edition. (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1980), p. 260.

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 10: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 10/13

 Lese A Adeson65

 The present is, Benjamin stresses, an "experience" with the past

 (pp. 259-260). To what extent do Sloterdijk and Negt/Kluge allow for

 such an experience qua experience? Like the authors of Geschichte

 und Eigensinn, Sloterdijk is mindful of that which tradition

 excludes or severs from our reception of history. Das

 Geschichtliche zerfallt in das Erledigte und das, was nur

 vergangen, aber nicht voruber ist - das Unerledigte, Imperfekte,

 das Erbubel, den historischen hangover (p. 539). One of the

 motivations to write his Kritik was to counter the modern doubts

 about living in a meaningful history (p. 10). But experience?

 Citing as positive examples the contemporary emancipation

 movements for women and for homosexuals, Sloterdijk maintains

 that the history of that which has been left ar written out of history

 can only be written by those who have been so excluded (pp. 538-

 539). While there is certainly much to be said for that, Sloterdijk's

 analysis includes no concrete sense of what that process of

 reinstatement would entail in terms of social experience. How

 history is appropriated remains unclear. Memory is accorded

 similarly nebulous status in Sloterdijk's study. Die innerste

 Erinnerung fuihrt nicht auf eine Geschichte, sondern auf eine

 Kraft. Sie bertihren, heiBt ekstatische Flut erfahren. Diese

 Erinnerung mtundet nicht in eine Vergangenheit, sondern in ein

 uberschwengliches Jetzt" (p. 526). Indeed, memory does not seem

 to be constitutive or even particularly significant for Sloterdijk's

 now-oriented Kyniker. Winston Smith's tormentor in George

 Orwell's 1984 tells him he is "non-existent" because the state has

 rendered him "outside history.""1 Sloterdjik does not so much posit

 the Kyniker outside history as he posits history outside the

 Kyniker.

 Unlike Sloterdijk, Negt/Kluge ground their discussion of

 exclusionary maneuvers in an analysis of material processes of

 social relations. They note that Geschichte und Eigensinn begins

 where their earlier work on Offentlichkeit und Erfahrung ended:

 "d.h. mit der materialistisch gewendeten Organisationsfrage" (p.

 32). For them history is a set of relationships that must be treated as

 concrete if it is to be appropriated. Die Erfahrungen, die in

 Bewegung setzen, mtissen nicht nur durch den Kopf hindurch,

 sondern durch Korper, die Nerven, die Sinne, die Gefuhle; sie

 mtissen am Geschichtsverhaltnis als einem faJ3lichen Gegenstand

 arbeiten k6nnen (p. 777; my emphasis, LAA). Here again,

 11. George Orwell, 1984: A Novel (New York: Signet Classic, 1949), p. 222.

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 11: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 11/13

 66 GERMANSTUDES REVEW

 experience is regarded as work: a collectively, historically

 determined process undertaken by real individuals. Just as

 subjectivity is historically determined, Negt/Kluge contend, so is

 history subjectively determined. The individual reception ("im

 individuellen Lebenslauf ) of the historical determination of

 subjectivity they call "die Bedingung dafuir, daB Subjektivitat als

 geschichtlich bestimmte, als subjektiv-objektives Verhaltnis

 wiederangeeignet werden kann" (p.783). Without the individual

 participation of those subjektive Splitter, history remains

 objectified, beyond experience (p. 783). The organization of

 contemporary West German society does not, however, encourage

 the unabashed and unimpeded active appropriation of history.

 Die Nahesinne arbeiten, an den Fernsinnen ist nicht gearbeitet

 worden. Sie bilden vor allem keine Gesellschaft. Das ist

 politisches Problem der Gegenwart und Verzerrung des

 Grundverhaltnisses zur Geschichte. Es existiert kein

 menschliches Verhaltnis zur Geschichte, wenn daran nicht

 gearbeitet wird; ein sachliches Verhaltnis ist tiberhaupt

 keines. Das Problem liegt daran, daB nicht einmal die

 Sensibilitat unterstellt werden kann, daB dies als ein Problem

 empfunden wird. Es sich als Problem vorzustellen setzt bereits

 Arbeitskraft der Phantasie voraus (p. 597).

 Interestingly enough, one of the human capacities which they cite

 as crucial to the process of appropriating history (as a set of

 relations) is the ability to forget, something which computers

 cannot do (p. 60). The ability to forget is necessary, they maintain,

 for the production of "lebendige Arbeit." "Wiurden wir aber alles

 vergessen, so gabe es keine Erfahrung tiber Raum und Zeit" (p. 60).

 The paths beaten through the debris of a bombed-out city provide

 one graphic example of such lebendige Arbeit : Es sind

 Selbstregulierungen des Verhaltnisses von Aktualitat und

 Geschichte" (p. 67).

 While Kritik der zynischen Vernunft and Geschichte und

 Eigensinn both reject traditional notions of personal identity and

 subjective agency, their authors are nonetheless motivated by a

 concern for human emancipation from structures of domination.

 The main difference between the two works is that Sloterdij k posits

 resistance or freedom in the embodiment of an attitude: a gesture.

 For Negt/Kluge these things can never be embodied per se, since

 they always take the form of socio-historical, that is to say,

 subjective-objective processes. Such distinctions in their

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 12: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 12/13

 Lese A Adeson67

 theoretical work are also echoed in Sloterdijk and Kluge's writing

 of historical fiction. In an article entitled Geschichten und

 Geschichte: Reflexionen zum westdeutschen Roman seit 1965,

Rainer Nagele calls for a subversion of "the traditional humanist

 and metaphysical concept of history,"'12 arguing against literary

 analysis structured around oppositional pairs such as

 realism/formalism, exteriority/interiority, politics/subjectivity

 and the like (p. 236). He cites the work of Alexander Kluge and

 Herbert Achternbusch as "Antigeschichten," a radically different

 breed of story that explodes the false dichotomies of such

 oppositional pairs (p. 247). We are reminded of Negt/Kluge's call for

 "Dialektik nicht paarweise, sondern durch tYbersprung" (GuE, p.

 44). Sloterdijk's recent publication, Der Zauberbaum, with the

 lengthy subtitle Die Entstehung der Psychoanalyse im Jahr 1785:

 Epischer Versuch zur Philosophie der Psychologie,13 is no

 Antigeschichte in Nagele's sense. This tale of how a young Austrian

 medical student discovers and integrates sensuality and spirituality

 into his otherwise rational life in a politically charged atmosphere

 (the eve of the French Revolution) poses a counter-story/history

 but not an anti-story/history. Sloterdijk weaves a different tale

 from the traditional Bildungsroman, but he does so by adding more

 threads to the warp, filling in those gaps otherwise excluded from

 our experience of history. Kluge's texts address those gaps without

 filling them in.14

 I would like to conclude with some more general comments as

 to how we might read the "newly subjective" literary texts of the

 1970s and 1980s. I shall do so by taking reference to Judith Ryan's

 recent study on The Uncompleted Past: Postwar German Novels

 and the Third Reich.15 The book deals with a number of German

 12. Rainer Nagele, Geschichten und Geschichte: Reflexionen zum

 westdeutschen Roman seit 1965, in Manfred Durzak, ed., Deutsche

 Gegenwartsliteratur: Ausgangspositionen und aktuelle Entwicklungen (Stuttgart:

 Reclam, 1981), p. 235.

 13. (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1985).

 14. See for example his Lernprozesse mit todlichem Ausgang

 (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1973) and Neue Geschichten: 'Unheimlichkeit der

 Zeit,' Hefte 1-8 (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1977). We are reminded here of Sigrid

 Weigel's warnings against contemporary feminist aesthetics too eager to fill in the

 gaps, where women's experience has been excluded, with positive images to counter

 the absence of image altogether. See her "Overcoming Absence: Contemporary

 German Women's Literature," in New German Critique 32 (Spring-Summer 1984),

 p. 11.

 15. (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1983).

This content downloaded from 202.41.10.3 on Mon, 27 Jun 2016 16:02:32 UTCAll use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Page 13: Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

7/25/2019 Contemporary Critical Consciousness Peter Sloterdijk, Oskar Negt-Alexander Kluge

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/contemporary-critical-consciousness-peter-sloterdijk-oskar-negt-alexander 13/13

 68 GERMANSTUDES REVEW

 texts from the late 1940s into the 1970s, Ryan's main thrust being to

 write against the fatalism that infuses allegorical treatments of

 German fascism. Her primary concern is the question of individual

 responsibility in and for the Third Reich. What literary forms, she

 asks, are best suited to asking how history could have been

 different? What she means here is how the outcome of history could

 have been different. There is an implied tendency in Ryan's

 otherwise very useful book to assume that literary models she

 deems appropriate for coming to terms with the Nazi past would

 also be appropriate for dealing with the contemporary dilemma of

 subjective agency. I would argue instead with Negt/Kluge that our

 attention should be properly focused, not on history as outcome but

 as process specific to a given set of social relations. How do literary

 texts of the 1970s and 1980s mediate between the historical

 determination of subjectivity" and the "subjective determination

 of history"? Ryan borrows as her leitmotif the figure of Heracles,

 missing from the Pergamon frieze with which Peter Weiss begins

 his Asthetik des Widerstands.16 She appropriates this figure for her

 own purposes, as a symbol of that missing agent of individual

 responsibility for which she combs the texts. Such an

 appropriation, however, rides roughshod over the specific,

 contextual function of the Heracles cipher in Weiss' own text.

 There it serves as a concrete object of historical appropriation

 whereby the young boys studying the frieze collectively struggle

 toward their own proletarian Subyektfihigkeit in a very particular

 historical present. To abstract the motif of Heracles from this

 literary and historical context is to render it "outside history" - yet

 another Ausgrenzung - or as Negt/Kluge would have it, abstract,

 objectified, inaccessible to the work of the living. Rather than

 debating the individual's role in history, I would suggest that we

 would do better in studying contemporary literary texts to examine

 history's role in the individual. To be subjects of contemporary

 critical consciousness means, I contend, to engage in the work of

 appropriating historical experience in now-time. To what extent,

 we must ask, do contemporary literary texts of the New

 Subjectivity enact those social-individual processes

 problematized by Negt/Kluge in Geschichte und Eigensinn? The

 question is less one of "who" and "where" than it is one of "how." As

 Rainer Nagele suggests, text is always context.17

 16. 2nd edition. (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1983).

 17. Rainer Nagele, Heinrich B611: Die groBe Ordnung und die kleine

 Anarchie," in Hans Wagener, ed., Gegenwartsliteratur und Drittes Reich: Deutsche

 Autoren in der Auseinandersetzung mit der Vergangenheit, (Stuttgart: Reclam,

 1977), p. 183.