dotson design for community toward a communitarian ergonomics-libre

Upload: ruin2832

Post on 02-Jun-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    1/25

    1

    Pre-Print: Full Article Can Be Accessed: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s13347-013-0100-4 DOI: 10.1007/s13347-013-0100-4

    Design for Community: Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics

    Taylor Dotson

    Science and Technology Studies DepartmentRensselaer Polytechnic Institute

    110 8th StreetSage Building 5th Floor

    Troy, NY 12180-3590Cell: (518) 703-2564Fax: (518) 276-2659

    Email: [email protected]

    Abstract

    This paper explores how the designed world could be better supportive of better communal ways of relating. In

    pursuit of this end, I put the philosophy of technology dealing with the role that technologies play in shaping,

    directing, mediating, and legislating human action in better communication with a diverse literature concerning

    community. I argue that community ought to viewed as composed of three interrelated dimensions: experience,

    structure, and practice. Specifically, it is a psychological sense evoked via a particular arrangement of ties and

    constellation of social practices guided, at its best, by phronetic reasoning. It is a mode of social being that I set in

    opposition to networked individualism. I examine the existent and potential communitarian ergonomics of the

    design of contemporary urban spaces and network devices. However, I conclude that artifacts remain only one part

    of the picture. A communally ergonomic mode of being requires not only compatible artifacts and built spaces but

    also an institutional context supportive of community as an economic and political entity.

    Keywords: Community; Technology; Technological mediation; The good life; Communitaria n ergonomics; Design

    http://sfx-serv.lib.rpi.edu/sfx_troy?__char_set=utf8&id=doi:10.1007/s13347-013-0100-4&sid=libx%3Arpi&genre=articlehttp://sfx-serv.lib.rpi.edu/sfx_troy?__char_set=utf8&id=doi:10.1007/s13347-013-0100-4&sid=libx%3Arpi&genre=articlehttp://sfx-serv.lib.rpi.edu/sfx_troy?__char_set=utf8&id=doi:10.1007/s13347-013-0100-4&sid=libx%3Arpi&genre=articlehttp://sfx-serv.lib.rpi.edu/sfx_troy?__char_set=utf8&id=doi:10.1007/s13347-013-0100-4&sid=libx%3Arpi&genre=article
  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    2/25

    2

    The designed world ought to be more heavily scrutinized in terms of its compatibility with different forms

    of community. This is apparent if one considers the research highlighting the problematic character of increasing

    individualism and social fragmentation within Western, developed societies (Bellah et al. 1985, Taylor 1991,

    Putnam 2000). In same way that Winner (1995) a dvocates that designers take into account the political

    ergonomics of their designs for the practice of democracy, I argue that designers should also consider the

    communitarian ergonomics of their creations for particular experiences, arrangements, and practices of sociality.

    There are already excellent works (e.g., Willson 2006) examining virtual communities vis--vis information

    technologies. This article differs takes a very different tack, however, considering a wider range of technologies and

    directing attention primarily towards offline enactments of community. Furthermore, my purpose is not to

    characterize the discussions concerning technology and community but to argue for a certain conception of

    community and evaluate the compatibility of certain technologies, built spaces, markets and systems of governance

    the designed world broadly defined with that conception.

    The analysis is grounded in the work of three major figures in the philosophy of technology. First,

    Winners (1977, 1980) wor k has illustrated how artifacts may serve as patterning legislations on human actions or

    seem to necessitate or enable particular arrangements of power and authority. Second, Borgmann (1984) has

    elucidated the relationship between technologies and human practice, noting how certain technologies provide goods

    as mere commodities and fail to support the focal practices that center good human lives within meaningful

    contexts of engagement. Third, Verbeek (20 10) has described technologies as materializing morali ty, shaping

    moral decisions and humans as moral actors. In my analysis, questions concerning technology and community

    inevitably involve politics, morality and the good life.

    The concept of community has received a great deal of philosophical attention; I cannot give justice to the

    whole literature herein. Furthermore, I find many contributions from the psychological and social sciences

    concerning community to be equally important and insightful. As such, I have drawn selectively from each of the

    literatures in psychology, sociology and philosophy that deal with what I consider to be the most important

    dimensions of community: the experiential, the structural and the practical. Specifically, I consider the literature

    surrounding the psychological sense of community and the sociology concerning the geometry of communal ties.

    As well, I draw upon sociological work (Bellah et al. 1985) inspired by the civic republican tradition of de

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    3/25

    3

    Tocqueville and Jefferson in addition to the communitarian critique of liberalism , represented by the philosophers

    Taylor, MacIntyre, Barber and Sandel, which together illustrate the moral and practical dimensions of community.

    The first half of this paper is devoted to developing a framework for viewing the connection between

    technological mediations and the good life as well as outlining a conception of community. I argue that the design of

    the artifactual world reflects and reinforces particular ways of being, relating, and viewing the self. That is, it

    reflects and reinforces particular approaches to the good life. Next, I contend that community ought to be viewed not

    only as a subjective feeling of belonging but also as constituted by particular arrangements of social ties and

    practices. As such, I assert that it is a mode of sociality set in opposition to networked individualism, the lifestyle

    in which one strives to exist as an atomized and unencumbered node instrumentally operating a personalized

    network of ties. Rather, community demands a dense and multiplex weaving of social ties as well as a practice of

    relating built upon the partial withdrawal of instrumental reason and application of phronetic judgment.

    I define communitarian ergonomics as the extent to which artifacts and technological systems help sustain

    community as an experience, a social structure, and a practice. Communally ergonomic technologies, that is, do not

    materialize the practice of networked individualism. I attempt to concretize this definition by examining the

    technological forces, persuasions and seductions against community enacted by many contemporary urban spaces

    and network devices as well as design movements aimed at producing more communally ergonomic alternatives.

    Nevertheless, I conclude that artifacts and technological systems themselves are only one aspect of the

    communitarian ergonomics of human societies; it will be necessary to give equal consideration to the design of the

    economy, systems of governance and other institutions that mediate daily living and contribute to the emergence and

    obduracy of many communally non-ergonomic technological designs.

    Technological Mediation and the Good Life

    Too often, the good life is assumed to be merely a matter for individual choice, and technologies become

    viewed as simply value-neutral tools that individuals rationally utilize in their pursuit of the good life. This view is a

    flavor of technological liberalism: the symbiosis of philosophical liberalism and technological instrumentalism so

    often the target of Grants (1986) critiques. However, a great deal of science and technology studies, philosophy of

    technology and social psychological research undermines both the notion of the autonomously and rationally

    choosing self and the instrumentalist view of the technology. Latour (1992), for instance, has examined technologies

    as scripting programs of action. The decision to put on a seatbelt in an automobile is not usually a result of a free

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    4/25

    4

    and independent will making a considered decision about personal safety, but is more often a reaction to the

    annoying beeping that persists until one complies. The situated and pre-rational aspects of human decision making,

    implied in this example, has been clear to psychologists for some time; see Shafir (2007) for a review.

    Such analyses support a view of technology in which the material world is seen as shaping human

    practice and thereby becomes constitutive of human selves. There are three ways in which technologies may direct

    practice. They may act as a force, a persuasion or a seduction (Verbeek 2011). Technologies act as forces when they

    prohibit or command certain behaviors. Verbeek provides the example of the subway turnstile, which enforces

    responsible fare-paying behavior. A more nefarious instance is the lack of a wheelchair ramp at building entrances,

    which is a discriminatory technological legislation against the disabled. Lato urs (1992) discussion of the scripting

    seatbelt noise is an example of a persuasion. Technological seductions are more complex and subtle, as Turkle

    (2011) illustrates. Technologies are seductive when technological affordances meet too well with human

    vulnerabilities. She describes some users of modern communication devices as modern-day Goldilockses, utilizing

    the technology to support a fear-driven titration of their social intimacies so as to protect themselves from risky

    social commitments. Thaler and Sunstein (2008) describe how human decision making is easily nudged , as when

    special white lines painted across Lake Shore Drive in Chicago are spaced increasingly close as one approaches a

    dangerously sharp curve, leading drivers to instinctually slow down. Such designs are more subtle and often more

    effective than warming signs that would demand more self-conscious rationalization and persuasion.

    This should not be viewed as simply a repackaging of technological or environmental determinism. The

    material world ought to be recognized as constitutive of human practice but not in a totalizing or unidirectional way.

    The shaping and directing power of technology is subtle but nonetheless significant. Small perturbations aggregate

    to become larger social forces as a result of the pervasiveness and obduracy of material structures. As part of the

    cognitive ecology of human decision making, they contribute to the development of ingrained habits, social norms

    and expectations as well as cultural patterns. Recognition of this fact is completely compatible with the view of

    technologies as socially constructed. Technological mediations are asked for, designed, and implemented by

    someone.

    Regardless, the influence of technologies on human practice is also visibly constitutive of human selfhood.

    Baudrillard (1968/2005) recognized that the practices of modern consumption were not merely concerned with

    function or utility but with the assembling of objects as a system of signs through which the consumer could fashion

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    5/25

    5

    a self. The movie Fight Club (Fincher 1999) provides a great illustration of this idea. The protagonist is found, while

    sitting on his toilet and thumbing through an IKEA catalog, describing how his carefully designed apartment reflects

    who he is or, more likely, who he wishes to be. This phenomenon continues to be visible on social networking sites

    such as Facebook. Aspects of ones identity become components of a collection. The user does not so much present

    him or herself as cura te an ideal version. Likewise, one increasingly keeps tabs on Facebook friends and pursues

    direct communication rather rarely, inspecting ones friends as a collector may look upon the prized objects into

    which they root their sense of selfhood.

    Csikszentmihalyi and Rochberg-Halton (1981), however, argue that the relation between the self, things

    and the world are not necessarily so shallow. Indeed, things may contribute to the cultivation of a self when they

    help create order in consciousness at levels of the person , community, and patterns of natural order (p. 16). The

    self-centered, almost solipsistic, practice described by Baudrillard is not universal; there is some room for

    interpretive flexibility. Some of Csikszentmihalyi and Rochberg- Haltons interlocutors pu rsued what they called an

    instrumental materialism rather than a terminal one. For them, some objects were valued not merely as sources

    of personal pleasure but as instrumental in connecting the owner to a larger social, political and natural world. For

    instance, one young girl valued the home refrigerator for the benefits it provided to her as an individual, while it was

    important to her brother because he used it to treat friends to food and drink (p. 98).

    The above work suggests that ones conception of self and the world is reflected in ones technologies and

    ones relationship s with and through them. Furthermore, it seems reasonable to suspect that altering the primary

    means by which people interact with reality will influence their conception or construction of it. Jacques Ellul

    (1964), for example, argued that markets do not simply facilitate trade but contribute to the remaking of humans as

    homo economicus, economic man. That is, the more people interact with one another on the level o f rational and

    self-interested exchange, the more that mode of relation becomes naturalized and internalized as a model for

    interaction. In fact, experimental evidence (Vohs, Mead and Goode 2006) seems to confirm that priming people with

    the concept of money evokes more self-interested and self-isolating behavior. Ellul, of course, is well known for the

    broader argument that a similar priming and internalization of la technique, the view that effici ency trumps all

    other values, dominates technological society.

    Verbeek (2011) has taken this argument further, contending that technologies materialize morality. In

    shaping practice and the interpretation of reality, technologies influence moral decision making about the good life

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    6/25

    6

    how one ought to live. Acting as forces , persuasions and seductions, they impact the Foucauldian practices of the

    self that shape human beings as moral subjects. Verbeeks argument centers on an attempt to connect a real

    ethics (Borgmann 2006) of materiality with practical ethics. He highlights how the addition of an ultrasound and

    amniocentesis procedure into pregnancy or a gun into ones pocket alters the moral and interpretive context of

    decision making the fetus being more easily viewed as a separate person and an object of the medical gaze or a

    man with a gun now having the potential to become an emboldened gunman. Verbeek goes on to maintain that,

    while technologies have moral agency, the good life is not achieved in the attempt to cast off and totally escape their

    influences on decision making aiming at an ideal autonomous self. Rather, one ought to strive to develop a

    productive relationship with these constraints, re-aiming the influence of technologies in more desirable directions.

    Borgmanns (1984) distinction between technological devices and focal things is highly compatible with

    such a conceptualization of the good life. The design of devices promotes the experience of a good as a commodity,

    as a mere end, unencumbered by means (p. 44). Focal things enable and demand focal practices that are aimed at

    engaging users more deeply with others, the environment and the thing itself. They require more than mere

    involvement or interaction but a committed integ ration of ones body and mind towards a larger reality, rather than

    only inward towards the desires of the self. A woodstove not only requires the physical engagement of the user with

    the function of the thing but also with the environment, as in the process of collecting wood, and with others by

    centering social interaction. Central heating, while comfortable and convenient, enables the social fragmentation of

    the household and reduces the depth of the practice of obtaining warmth. Again, the point is not that modern

    technologies be abandoned but that we ought to recognize how they draw humans into certain moral relationship

    with others, the environment and things. The design of the artifactual world reflects and reinforces particular ways

    of being and relating, an actuality that should encourage a more careful and cautious attitude towards technological

    design.

    My concern here is with only one, quite important, aspect of being. How do different technological forces,

    persuasions and seductions contribute to the maintenance of social practices that are overly individualistic and

    atomistic? How can they be more communal? If one takes the good life as not purely an object of individual

    construction, but rather negotiated with particular technological, social and institutional contexts, how can the

    modernity be more supportive of the pragmatic kind of good life referred to by Csikszentmihalyi and Rochberg -

    Halton (1981): the cultivation of a self able to create and pursue goals that are guided by some moral standard and

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    7/25

    7

    are redirected by a discerning practical judgment about the potential consequences for ones wider community and

    environment?

    These kinds of questions concerning technology and community, of course, are not unprecedented. The

    works of Mumford and Simmel immediately come to mind. Indeed, sociological characterizations of the transitions

    from pre-modernity to modernity (Tnnies 1887/2001) and from modernity to post- modern network societies

    (Castells 2000) clearly outline a substantial role play by technological progress in co -shaping human social

    arrangements and practices. There appears to be a pattern to (post)modern design that emphasizes the increased

    distancing, compartmentalization, flexibility and specialization of social ties that may be too enabling of their

    instrumentalization. That is, one can argue more broadly that social bonds have become more cognitively and

    geographically distant, more limited in purpose and less demanding of commitment. Such an arrangement permits

    sociality to be increasingly an object of control and subjected to instrumental reason. Studies pointing to the effects

    of suburbanization and television (Putnam 2000) or the decline of the local pub or caf (Oldenburg 1999) lend

    themselves to such an argument. Furthermore, others have done important work in search of exemplary alternatives.

    Borgmann (2006) has described farmers markets and minor league bal lparks as providing centers for the practice of

    communal celebration and better situated in [their] context of time, space and community than their alternatives:

    supermarkets and sports video games. Nevertheless, before proposing what communally ergonomic designs would

    do, I must cl arify what I mean by community.

    Defining Community

    Within scholarship and popular thought, there is an immense diversity in definitions of community, many

    of which deprive the concept of much of its potential depth. Community is often used as simply a more affectively

    pleasant way describing a lifestyle enclave (Bellah et al. 1985) or some ethnic, socioeconomic, sexual or racial

    category as if those within that category actually interacted daily with each other as a coherent social unit. Or, as in

    the case of network models, community is depicted as simply the web of people one knows and communicates with;

    community, thus conceived, is a collection of ties providing some degree of social support but not necessarily

    demanding ones moral obligation .

    I will argue instead that community ought to be conceived as having three interrelated constitutive

    dimensions: the experiential, the structural and the practical. That is, community should be viewed as not only

    containing subjective and organizational elements but also agential. Experiential elements of community involve a

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    8/25

    8

    sense of belonging and mutual trust that contributes to an ability to view oneself as part of a larger social body. The

    structure of community is manifested in a particular geometry or topology of social ties. Additionally, community is

    defined by particular practice of relating and mode of moral reasoning; one cannot be an unattached individual but

    must exist as a socially embedded person. By including this, too often neglected, practical dimension, my definition

    is more strongly normative. It serves to better conceptualize community as something more substantive than a

    subjective feeling of belonging or network of social support.

    Admittedly, there is a general sense of discomfort surrounding projects aiming to construct more morally

    and politically thick notions of community. The idea of community is in many areas associated wi th narrow-

    minded parochialism and even the rise of 20 th century European fascism. However, this view fails to distinguish

    community as a mode of social organization from its symbolic use in political and cultural pathology. The argument

    can be made that such pathologies are not necessarily a natural outgrowth of community but rather a phenomenon

    that emerges in the vacuum left by the disappearance of communal modes of organization, a tragic outcome that

    Nisbet (1953/2010) called the modern quest for community. Indeed, many have documented how contemporary

    fundamentalist movements and resistance identities have arisen in parallel with the culturally flattening effects of

    a globalized network society (Barber 2001; Castells 2004). As Bauman (2001) also points out, identity is

    increasingly a surrogate for community (p. 15). That is, people are strongly drawn to the sense of stability that the

    idea of an authentic identity provides in response to a mode of living that feels increasingly insecure. As such,

    identity may be a more apt target for such criticisms than community per se. I for one do not find it difficult to

    imagine just and democratic communities that are, nonetheless, morally demanding of its members.

    Again, the whole lineage of thought on community is too large to be considered within a single journal

    article. What follows is an admittedly partial review of an expansive area of thought that synthesizes a diverse swath

    of research from across the social sciences and philosophy. The spirit of my definition will be in opposition to the

    notion of networked individualism; community ought to be viewed as an mode of relating that limits social

    fragmentation and the degree to which relationships are pursued through the lens of self-serving instrumental reason,

    relying on the production of people capable of building high levels of mutual trust, phronetically reasoning about

    their place and relationships, and being encumbered by a sense of mutual obligation.

    The Experiential

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    9/25

    9

    Community is experienced as a psychological sense of belonging. Tnnies (1887/2001) conceptual

    distinction between community (gemeinschaft) and society (gesellschaft ) reflects this. In Gemeinschaft [people]

    stay together in spite of everything that separates them; in Gesellschaft they remain separate in spite of everything

    that unites them (p. 52). As such, community requires the viewing of ones relations as part o f a unity that exists in

    spite of but is not necessarily effacing of difference. Furthermore, a community ideally serves as a source of

    personal meaning and sense of purpose as well as promoting the development of feelings of mutual trust and

    obligation.

    Unsurprisingly, this aspect of community is most often studied social psychologically. Sarason (1974)

    argued that being part of a psychological community involves more than existing within a geo-political space; one

    exists as part of a mutually supportive network of relationships , w hich are dependable and prevent one from

    feeling sustained feelings of loneliness or adopting a style of living masking anxiety (p. 1). McMillan and

    Chavis (1986) definition of the sense of community remains the most widely accepted. They argue that it depends

    on feelings of membership, influence, fulfillment of needs and shared emotional connection. Not only does one feel

    as if one belongs but also that one has a sense of agency in mutually fulfilling each others needs . A shared

    emotional connection among members develops from the frequency and quality of social interactions as well as

    experiencing shared events and feeling as if oneself and others are personally invested in the group.

    Nevertheless, consideration of the experiential dimensions of community alone is insufficient. Beniger

    (1987) noted how feelings of connection with others may be produced through the manipulation of media; an

    increasing level of personalization and simulated sincerity enables the sense of belonging to what inevitably remains

    a pseudo -community. Certainly, teenagers across the country share the experience and can influence the outcome

    of the television show American Idol, but most would hesitate to call it a community though, to be fair, McMillan

    and Chavis would likely hesitate as well. While the subjective sense of communality is important, the definition of

    community ought to also include a strong structural dimension, which would further illuminate some of the

    characteristics of community as a unique means to gain emotionally security and ward off loneliness.

    The Structural

    Many would no doubt agree that a deeper sense of community demands at least occasional bodily co-

    presence, maintaining that there remains something experientially valuable about embodied interaction with another

    being. Rheingold (2000, p. xvi), for instance, credited the authenticity of the virtual community he was a part of in

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    10/25

    10

    light of the frequent face-to- face encounters pursued by its members and its grounding in the physical world. The

    fact that most people use the Internet mainly to supplement and support their offline connections rather than to

    replace them, suggests that there remains something special and often irreplaceable about bodily co-presence when

    it comes to social intimacy.

    The importance of bodily co-presence is also clear from situations in which it is avoided. That is to say, it

    serves a role in the social practice of both communion and exclusion. For instance, Wiltses (2007) social hi story of

    the American swimming pool illustrates how municipal pools once permitted a degree of public and leveling

    interaction as well as a substantive mixing of different racial groups. Yet, they eventually developed into sites of

    active discrimination and racial violence. Wiltse found that some 20 th century whites were so adverse to interracial

    bodily contact that they even objected to swimming in the same water. His account suggests that physical distancing

    is not only the typical result of discrimination but also serves to reinforce racism as a cultural pathology. The

    elimination of the possibility of embodied interaction helps enable the treating of others as abstract objects rather

    than genuine human beings. The clear importance of co-presence for feelings of communion suggests the need for

    places and technological arrangements that encourage or even demand some degree of embodied interaction, though

    propinquity alone is certainly far from sufficient to promote a sense of community.

    The experience of community also depends on a particular arrangement of social ties. Calhoun (1980)

    criticized early studies of community for overemphasizing the experiential dimension because it often then

    overshadows the social bonds and political mechanisms which hold communities together and make them possible

    (p. 69). He argued that communal bonds are dense, multiplex and systematic. Ties are dense when, more often than

    not, any potential tie between members is actually present. The degree of separation between any two community

    members tends toward one, and there are multiple linkages. Bonds are multiplex whenever they are defined by more

    than one kind of relationship. That is, ties are not strictly compartmentalized along functional lines. For instance,

    one would interact with many of the same people from ones neighborhood also at work, while shopping downtown

    or at a school meeting. Furthermore, communal bonds are systematic in that individuals are linked to groups which

    are well incorporated into some larger unity in turn.

    This geometry of community can be contrasted with that of networked individualism (Castells 2001;

    Wellman 1999; 2001). The network model of community was pioneered by Wellman (1979; 1987), who describes it

    as a form of community liberated from local solidarity or place -based roots. To Wellman, communities are and

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    11/25

    11

    perhaps have always been egocentric networks of intimate ties. Networked individualism redefines community in,

    arguably inappropriate, market-metaphorical terms ; individuals are entrepreneurial operators of networks and

    build portfolios of social ties. It seems that in the slide from viewing community as dense, multiplex and

    systematic webs of bonds to primarily dyadic, diffuse and primarily voluntary networks of individuals, one is neither

    really studying the same social structure nor considering community in the same moral or practical sense. While it is

    clear that a great deal more socializing especially among well-off, (sub)urban and educated elites occurs today

    across networks, to call them communities is to render the concept shorn of much of its potentially more substantive

    meaning. Oldenburg (1999) goes so far as to suggest that network theorists recast an artifact of atomization as an

    advanced form of society (p. 265).

    The Practical

    Returning to Tnnies (1887/2001) distinction between gemeinschaft and gesellschaft , what seems

    important about community is not merely its structure but that it is characterized by mutual obligation rather than

    self-serving instrumental reason. This has been illustrated in sociological studies of individualism and commitment.

    Bellah and his co-authors (1985) argued that Americas increasingly dominant language of individualism and its

    concomitant practices of separation posed a threat to commitment and the habits of the heart underlying civic

    democracy. Contemporary relationships are increasingly defined according to the logic of therapeutic

    contractualism, an integration of economic and bureaucratic modes of interaction as a model for personal

    relationships. Ties are no longer commitments but voluntaristic arrangements aimed at individual utilitarian or

    expressive self-fulfillment. They are to exist only as long as they provide a personal return on investment and do not

    threaten ones sense of self -efficacy. Of course, Bellah and his coauthors also noted that for many people the first

    language of individualism was often supplemented by a second language of commitment. Indeed, most

    contemporary marriages, domestic partnerships, families and friendships would not be able to sustain themselves if

    they were subjected to such a persistent and instrumental calculation of personal cost and benefit. Nevertheless, the

    ethic of therapeutic contractualism appears to be at the root of the emerging practice of networked individualism.

    Community, on the other hand, seems better characterized by a constellation of relational practices from

    idle socializing to community organizing that are guided by an ethic opposed to therapeutic contractualism .

    Building upon the concepts of practice developed by both MacIntyre (1984) and Borgmann (1984), community

    practices can be viewed as cooperative activities through which a sense of belonging and social support is realized;

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    12/25

    12

    like the practices of friendship, they are defined and enabled by the possession and exercise of relevant excellences

    and virtues. Furthermore, a practice of community extends ones capacity for these excellences and ones

    conceptions of the ends and goods internal to it. Community is also a focal practice that in being a unity of

    achievement and enjoyment centers ones life within a meaningful way and engages one deeply with others.

    Community, like friendship and familial love, is a social practice that appears to depend upon a partial

    withdrawal of instrumental reason and choice. The argument is not that community cannot be an object of

    contemplation, as Bauman (2001) seems to suggest, but rather that it demands a different mode of reasoning. The

    Aristotelian virtue of phronesis, or practical wisdom, offers a balanced option between tacit understanding and

    instrumental scrutiny. It is to be distinguished from episteme: the instrumental rationality associated with scientific

    knowledge, and techne: intuitive craft know-how. Phronesis is achieved through the practice of considered, intuitive

    and empathic deliberation about what would be the right or virtuous action within a particular set of circumstances.

    Schwartz and Sharpe (2010) have examined phronesis in the daily living of working professionals: teachers, judges,

    lawyers and doctors. They argue that rigid bureaucratic rules or market-like incentive schemes do not evoke the kind

    of thinking that leads to good teaching, advocating and doctoring; such rules and incentives prevent the intelligent

    trial and error necessary for learning how to exercise phronetic judgment and frequently produce overly self-

    interested and uncaring actions. In the same way that phronesis appears necessary for the pragmatic, caring and

    relationship-building behavior that is characteristic of good professionals, it is likely an essential element in the

    practice of cultivating and maintaining good communal relationships.

    Furthermore, the practice of community is reliant on and enabling of a kind of phronetic judgment that is

    rooted in the conception of the self as a communal being. Through communal practices of the self, one learns to

    better embed and conceive of oneself as embedded within a constitutive community. Indeed, the communitarian

    critique of philosophical liberalism pursued by Taylor, MacIntyre and Sandel has focused on emphasizing how

    humans are born into a web of relationships and a living tradition that cannot easily be detached but nevertheless

    provides the horizon of signific ance against which ones selfhood may dialogically emerge. Yet, the unencumbered

    self, which Sandel (1984) described as forever lurching between detachment and entanglement and without moral

    depth, appears to be manifest in the networked individualism described by Castells and Wellman. Many modern

    people do, in fact, conceive of themselves as so unencumbered, or champion it as a laudable goal. It would seem that

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    13/25

    13

    modern technologies, in so far as they afford networked individualism, enable practices of the self that promote a

    view of human beings as unencumbered individuals rather than socially embedded persons.

    If the practices of community are to be sustained, there must be appropriate supportive structures in place.

    MacIntyre (1984) argued that a practice is supported by institutions and through the activities necessary in

    maintaining them, and Borgmann s (1984) philosophy emphasizes the important role of focal things in sustaining

    focal practices. At the heart of what I am calling communitarian ergonomics is exactly that examination of how the

    various institutional and technological structures of everyday living collude to promote or inhibit the practice and

    experience of community. In the next section, I will consider a number of examples of communication technologies

    and urban spaces that highlight what Taylor (1991) has referred to as the bent of technological society that, if left

    unopposed, lends itself to the modern malaises of individualism, fragmentation and instrumental reason as well as

    design movements striving for change.

    Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics

    In light of the above arguments, I define communitarian ergonomics as the fit between technological

    mediations and the experiential, structural and practical dimensions of community. Built spaces or communications

    technologies not only need to evoke a subjective sense of belonging, but they also must serve support a particular

    spatial and functional arrangement of social ties. Though they are even more demanding, the best designs also

    promote the development of people able to phronetically reason about their social relations and to engage in

    communitarian-enhancing interactions within their local social ecology.

    An examination of the communal ergonomics of a technology would begin by asking : D oes this design

    enable the disembedding of persons from their local contexts or does it encourage them to exist more collectively

    and collaboratively as groups? Sclove ( 1995) provides an illustrative example. In the Spanish village of Ibieca, the

    introduction of indoor plumbing disrupted the fabric of communal life. While the new network of pipes afforded

    them relief from arduous labor and provided each household with an individual water source, the village lost a

    structure that had served as a focal point for the community and encouraged social congregation and intermixing.

    The village fountain was not merely a source of water but also a technological mediation promoting communal

    bonding. However, the point is not to advocate a return to the days of the communal water pump; rather, it is to

    recognize that the alluring conveniences of personalized networks of goods and service provision, transportation or

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    14/25

    14

    social support often come at a cost to community. Communally ergonomic technologies, on the other hand, will

    likely be similar in kind to the village fountain.

    I have deliberately chosen the term communitarian to describe technologies compatible with community

    in virtue of its association with various political and philosophical movements critical of contemporary liberalism.

    As the works of Winner and Verbeek suggest, technological design is a mode of political and moral legislation.

    Designing for community would be no exception. For the kind of democratic communitarianism that Bellah

    advocates (1995), for Kemmis (1990) politics of inhabitation , or for Barbers (1984) strong democracy to be

    able to serve as a corrective to the excesses of contemporary liberalism, their thoughtful proposals must take greater

    account of the principles and practices of supportive social structures and technologies in daily living. Meaningful

    collective deliberation about what constitutes desirable directions for public action is better supported when citizens

    have the experiential and structural grounds necessary to conceive of themselves as belonging to collective entities.

    The kind of affect-laden talk that Barber views as necessary for building the sense of mutuality and affiliation

    necessary for the enactment of strongly democratic political communities like requires suitable places and

    institutions in which to pursue such talk. A politics of engagement (Kemmis 1990) relies on citizens who are

    already deeply engaged with one another on street corners, at pubs and in voluntary association.

    Yet, such supportive structures and technologies in turn may rely on compatible economic and political

    arrangements. Nisbet (1953/2010), for instance, blamed the relative weakness of communal institutions on the

    growing economic and political centralization within western nations.

    As such, the communitarian ergonomics of built spaces and technological devices ought not to be

    considered independently of the ergonomics of markets and systems of governance, an issue I take up later in the

    article. First, I will describe more concretely how certain contemporary technological-mediations are non-ergonomic

    for community, and I will examine alternative designs that begin to ameliorate these deficiencies.

    The City and New Urbanism

    Suburbanization is a frequent target for those who view community as in decline with good reason.

    Modernist urban design has resulted in cities built around the model of a network, aiming to segregate, distance and

    compartmentalize different aspects of daily activity and connect them through arterial networks of highways and

    interstates. Jacobs (1961/1992) has emphasized the need for zones of mixed primary uses for city vitality, attributing

    the decline of modern downtowns t o the decontamination of uses: Modern cities too often and too strictly separate

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    15/25

    15

    cultural, governmental, residential and commercial spaces. Lynch (1984) conceptualized the degree of this

    separation as the grain of the city, arguing that too coarse a grain leads to areas virtually devoid of activity for

    much of the day. This leads to a d ecline in transparency; t he interdependent functions, activities and processes

    within locales that help to evoke a sense of place become less visible. Unsurprisingly, many critiques of suburbia

    argue that they cannot generate a sense of rootedness the reason why Kunstler (1993) entitled his study of suburbia

    The Geography of N owhere. Furthermore, coarse -graining increasingly compartmentalizes the city along

    functional and spatial lines. This diminishes the degree to which ties can be multiplex and, along with the increasing

    distances introduced by sprawl, limits the potential density of social bonds. Different aspects of daily living and sets

    of social ties remain sequestered to different areas of the city, encouraging a more diffuse, network-like structure

    upon the geometry of social ties.

    The specialization and functional compartmentalization of daily living within many cities may also inhibit

    communal practices. Work, entertainment, shopping, and socializing become activities not only occurring in

    spatially distinct areas but also involving wholly different sets of ties. These sets of relationships become

    increasingly specialized, each one governed by its own particular logic. This arrangement too easily lends itself to

    the application of instrumental rationality, as the ties in each compartment become evaluated mainly in terms of how

    well they fulfill a narrowly prescribed functional purpose i.e., commodified. The compartmentalized city risks

    becoming a macro-device as communal relationship building is replaced by the shuttling of bodies between various,

    unrelated commodity-spaces.

    New Urbanism offers a more communitarian alternative to the macro-device model of the city. New

    Urbanist planners propose the reintroduction of traditional elements of urban design: mixed-use, large sidewalks,

    pedestrian areas, small set-backs, moderate density and so on. It is a design movement intimately concerned with the

    communal affordances of physical spaces. A number of studies find a positive correlation between New

    Urbanist/traditional design features and the psychological sense of community (Bothwell, Gindroz and Lang 1998;

    Lund 2002; Kim and Kaplan 2004; Pendola and Gen 2008). These studies also emphasize the importance of spaces

    that allow for and encourage serendipitous public social interaction. A residence set too far from the sidewalk and

    with too little space in front to sit and converse is a persuasion against venturing a conversation and lingering,

    lowering the probability of the occurrence of neighboring. Without pleasant interfaces between the public and

    private, inhabitants may too often recede to the comfort of their dens and living rooms.

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    16/25

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    17/25

    17

    Network Devices and Relational Design

    Yet, the built environment is not the only technological mediation that affects community. One could argue

    that the more recent attraction to social networking and communication devices is partially a byproduct of the

    decline of physically ergonomic physical spaces in many technological societies. As Willson argues (2006), they are

    technologies sought to solve the problem of compartmentalization and disconnection that is partly a consequence of

    extended and abstracted relations brought about by the use of technology (p. 80). The appeal of network devices

    lies in the fact that they are, to some degree, social technologies, providing some relief from a built environment and

    society that are increasingly atomizing. Still, as Willson also contends, network devices simultaneously enable the

    increasing compartmentalization and individualization of social activity. R ecall Turkles (2011) illustration of how

    users of network devices often use them to tincture their exposure to social intimacy. Computerized self-checkout

    kiosks are a more mundane example, often enabling the sometimes fearful avoidance of public social interaction

    with strangers. With such avoidance, the kind of public intermixing and local relationship building that helps

    cultivate the structural and practical dimensions of community never occurs, and the opportunity to be practice

    communal sociality is lost.

    The influence of network devices, such as mobile phones, similarly affects the communitarian ergonomics

    of social spaces. As Wellman (2001) notes, they enable the privatization of public spaces. Someone on their cell

    phone on a bus or engrossed in instant messaging on their laptop in a coffee shop has a public physical presence but

    is not practically engaged in public sociality. There are several modes of mediation at work here. First, network

    devices can serve as a barrier or a force. One cannot as easily converse with a stranger if they are already fixated on

    their device. Second, it persuades against chance encounters. By maintaining the gaze, the probability of making

    eye-contact is diminished. Since eye-contact is a welcoming signal to potential social interaction, socializing is

    discouraged. For users, the device is often a seduction. They afford cocooning. The ability to immediately connect

    with a more safe and reliable contact whenever desired is alluring, likely reducing the willingness to strike up a

    conversation with a stranger or passing acquaintance.

    Furthermore, by enabling the increased compartmentalization and privatization of social relationships,

    network devices often undermine the moral practice of community and materialize a good life premised on

    networked-individualism. Once commodified through devices, sociality becomes available as an object of personal

    control and instrumental reason. The dynamics of social ties are increasingly dictated by their ability to provide a

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    18/25

    18

    personal return on investment, since the agency for determining if, when and where contact will occur increasingly

    lies with the user of the device. Social interaction may be encouraged to follow the model of the commodity more

    than the focal practice. Part of what traditionally sustains communal groups has been the extent to which members

    interact with one another in spite of whether or not it provides an immediate return on investment. That is, such

    relations are more guided by phronesis than instrumental reason.

    Nevertheless, in spite of their tendency to afford private sociability at the cost of public engagement, there

    are laudable efforts to mobilize network devices in the service of community. For instance, Community Informatics

    aims to enable local economic development and political empowerment through the use of Internet communication

    devices. The fields definition of community is largely compatible with the one outlined above; it is distinguished

    from the fragmented and largely contractual or rule based relationships of individualism based networks

    (Gurstein 2007, p. 21-2). However, early attempts to apply Community Informatics community computing centers

    and local service delivery of Internet access left much to be desired. As Stoecker (2005) argues, it is unclear

    whether those efforts were as much in the service of community as technological and market-oriented thinking. If an

    intervention mainly permits greater access to the consumptive lifestyle of networked individualism, it may be

    addressing the digital divide but hardly advances community. However, many Community Informaticians (e.g., Foth

    2003) are fully aware that connectivity does not ensure community and aim towards interventions could better

    promote a sense of social ownership, increase mutual trust and reciprocity, and provide more substantive support for

    the growth of offline social networks.

    In this regard, there have been some promising efforts towards communally ergonomic network devices

    in the area of social innovation for sustainability (Meroni 2007; Jegou and Manzini 2008; Cipolla and Manzini

    2009). The relational design of service provision aims to encourage the development of personal relationships and

    mutual trust through face-to-face interactions; network devices play a supportive rather than terminal role in such

    designs. The aim of these interventions is to enable product and service infrastructures outside of traditional market

    arrangements. By relying explicitly on collective organization and sharing, such designs depend on and reinforce the

    multiplex bonding and phronetic reasoning that I have argued to undergird communal practices. One project

    involves the creation of a common shop space and tool sharing scheme facilitated and regulated by the community

    through electronic keys. This relational design engages tool borrowers in the practice of communally governing their

    resources as well as building social relationships between neighbors that promote trust and interdependence. E-

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    19/25

    19

    Stop projects utilize small network devices to put pedestrians in contact with local drivers headed the same

    direction. While not directly promoting deeper the sense of community as a practice, E -Stop projects could

    promote a growth in the density and multiplexity of social relationships that may not otherwise happen. At a

    minimum, they help promote the sense of place and mutual trust from which more substantive practices may

    emerge.

    In spite of these advances, the communitarian ergonomics of most contemporary network devices remains

    uncertain at best. The same devices that are appropriated to facilitate neighborhood tool or ride sharing also enable

    and encourage the acquisition of products, services and social connection from afar. They connect people with

    commodities that are cheaper, more specialized and less demanding trust. Thus, they contribute to neighborhoods

    less rich in serendipitous interaction and cooperation. Nevertheless, as should be clear by the above discussion, the

    communitarian ergonomics of human societies is as much a reflection of economic and political arrangements as

    technological contexts. In fact, the contemporary design of economic and political systems may be one of the most

    significant sources of modern atomization.

    Economic and Political Dimensions

    If community as a social and material entity is to be supported, it must also be maintained as an economic

    and political reality. The dominance of individualized means of relating, inhabiting, communicating and traveling

    has not developed in a vacuum but is reinforced by the design of economic and political systems that they reinforce

    in turn. The vibrancy of communal interactions depends not only on supportive built-spaces and technologies but

    also the awareness and practice of political and economic interdependency. DeFilippis (2001), in this vein, critiques

    Putnams (2000) concept of social capital for failing to note power asymmetries and economic capital. He goes on to

    argue that economic capital needs to be developed and controlled within communities, through community land

    trusts and credit unions, in order to encourage local financial interdependence. Additionally, it has been shown that

    economic inequality is significantly to blame for the low levels of trust associated with declining social capital

    (Pickett and Wilkinson 2010), suggesting that it increases feelings of social distance and disunity.

    Designing working situations to be more locally rooted and craft-like could also help foster community

    relationships. Economic localism not only reinvigorates downtown areas and local social ties but more enables local

    workers to witness the fruits of their labor being used in the locality and by people they know. Crawford (2009, p.

    187) makes this exact point, arguing that the distancing of production from consumption is a significant contributor

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    20/25

    20

    to alienated labor. Furthermore, as Castells (2001) contends , the individualized relationship to societyis rooted,

    first of all, in the individualization of the relationship between capital and labor, between workers and the work

    process (p. 128). Indeed, an early UNESCO study (Scott and Lynton 1952) argued that community was

    undermined by practices of industrial firms that increasingly drove a wedge between the social and economic

    aspects of local activity. Factories were becoming increasingly governed from afar. Even when locally owned,

    owners and employees were seldom interacting outside the factory.

    Another factor may simply be that most people work too much. It is hard to be motivated towards local

    involvement when overly stressed or exhausted. Calls for a 21-hour work week (Coote, Simms and Franklin 2010)

    and similar downshifting movements are, no doubt, partially motivated by this observation. As well, the level of

    mobility demanded by the modern job also discourages community involvement, and long commutes eat away at

    time that could be spent neighboring or joining a local association (Putnam 2000).

    At the same time, community depends on the cultivation of styles of reasoning that are more phronetic and

    less instrumental. Unfortunately, it may be difficult to cultivate phronesis once a practice becomes associated with

    instrumental rationality, as in markets or bureaucracies. Behavioral research (Gneezy and Rustichini 2000) suggests

    that once an action becomes marketized it is often difficult for people to return to viewing the behavior as guided by

    social or moral norms. Cultivating a communally- minded moral economy (Thompson 1971) resilient enough to

    counter the atomizing but alluring promises of the market economy is an imposing problem. It does not help that

    goods are almost inevitably cheaper on Amazon according to todays limited accounting practices, while

    Facebook and Youtube promise risk-free access to a greater diversity of interesting and amusing people.

    Nevertheless, community time banks and local currencies can serve as useful intermediaries, insulating local

    productive activity from the influence of globalized markets and explicitly designing local reciprocity into the

    medium of exchange.

    Finally, communal practices can be supported by the existence of participatory political systems. Nisbet

    (1953/2010, p. xxx) argued that community was the product of people working together to solve problems, fulfill

    common objectives, and build the codes of authority under which they live. The design of contemporary systems of

    governance, however, allows politics to be increasingly personalized, procedural or avoided altogether. First,

    Lichterman (1996) has differentiated traditional communitarian social movements from an emerging politics of

    personalism. While the former were rooted in place attachment, personalistic participants remain active only as long

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    21/25

    21

    as their involvement contributes to a personal sense of self-actualization. Activist politics is increasingly sought

    more as a means towards self-fulfillment than as a way to help and engage with others. Second, many (Sandel 1984,

    Kemmis 1990) lament the degree to which modern political interaction is framed strictly in terms of procedural

    justice because it limits the extent to which citizens engage with one another as anything other than self-interested

    individuals or partisan interest groups. Under proceduralism, political interaction works under the paradigm of the

    device: I t does not demand focal engagement with ones fellow citizens as authentic others. The state becom es

    simply a machine for turning tax dollars into valued services for whichever groups that can best mobilize their

    private interests. In addition, the scale and speed at which current governments strive to act likely prevents the

    development of the kind of local, participatory and practice-based politics that Barber (1984) refers to as strong

    democracy, instead calling for a bureaucratic and technocratic model of organization. It is likely through a renewed

    practice of decentralized politics that groups of citizens could best realize and more phronetically practice a common

    existence. Third, as Reich (1991) has noted, those affluent enough to exist as networked individual have increasingly

    seceded from the public to their own personal enclaves. They flee the process of politics entirely by escaping to

    gated communities in which public services and public engagement are eschewed in favor of purchasing private

    alternatives.

    Conclusion

    I have argued that community is a vector outcome not only of experiences, structures of social ties and

    moral practices, but also of artifacts, technological systems, built spaces, economic structures and forms of

    governance. Such systems and spaces vary substantially in the degrees to which they are forces, persuasions and

    seductions for the enactment of community. Some technologies are designed as if to legislate against communal

    practices, often by materializing the practice of networked individualism. Although it is somewhat straightforward

    to recognize how built spaces can discourage or encourage the social interactions for the practice of community, it is

    harder to understand the more subtle anti-communitarian role played by many network devices. As social

    technologies, they may seem inherently to be communally ergonomic. There is potential for a relational design of

    product and service infrastructure utilizing network devices that could serve communal ends; but in actual practice

    network devices too frequently facilitate the unweaving of dense communal webs into simplified, personalized

    networks.

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    22/25

    22

    A number of important questions merit further analysis. Invariably, there are conceptual issues to be

    resolved. The above developed definition of community will likely need a more systematic presentation of its

    conditions, characteristics and manifestations. Furthermore, having raised a number of doubts concerning the

    communitarian ergonomics of network-centric designs, I believe that a fuller ethical analysis of the network as it

    appears in contemporary technologies, institutions and modes of thought is in order. Other concerns are more

    empirical. An examination of the conditions for evoking communally-oriented habits of thought and practice may be

    best pursued through a more thorough integration of the findings of studies of human decision-making and

    environmental psychology within the philosophy of technology. Additionally, a continuing dialogue with social

    constructivist and reconstructivist (Woodhouse 2005) approaches to technology studies can help situate questions

    concerning technology and community with respect to the cultural, political and economic processes that underlie

    the creation, implementation and reform of artifacts and technological systems.

    Papanek (1984) once claimed that t here are professions more harmful than industrial design, but only a

    very few of them (p. ix). If my account finds agreement among academics, scholarship ought to be not only

    concerned with the influence of the designed world on human and environmental health or societies arrangement of

    power and authority but also on the character of contemporary social relationships.

    Acknowledgments

    The author thanks his reviewers and E.J. Woodhouse for their helpful comments.

    References

    Barber, B. (2001). J ihad vs. McWorld. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Barber, B. (1984). Strong democracy. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Baudrillard, J. (2005). The system of objects. (J. Benedict, Trans.). Brooklyn, NY: Verso. (Original work published1968).

    Bauman, Z. (2001). Community. Malden, MA: Polity Press.

    Bellah, R.N. (1995/1996). Community properly understood. The Responsive Community, 6(1), 49-54.

    Bellah, R. N, Madsen R., Sullivan W. M., Swidler A., & Tipton S. M. (1985). Habits of the heart. Berkeley:University of California Press.

    Beniger, J. R. (1987). Personalization of mass media and the growth of pseudo-community. CommunicationResearch, 14(3), 352-371.

    Borgmann, A. (1984). Technology and the character of contempora ry life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    23/25

    23

    Borgmann, A. (2006). Real American ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Bothwell, S. E., Gindroz R., & Lang R. E.. (1998). Restoring community through traditional neighborhood design.Housing Policy Debate, 9(1), 89-114.

    Calhoun, C.J. (1980). Community. Social History, 5(1), 105-129.

    Castells, M. (2000). The rise of the network society (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Castells, M. (2001). The Internet galaxy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Castells, M. (2004). The power of identity (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Cipolla, C., Manzini, E. (2009). Relational services. Knowledge, Technology & Policy, 22, 45-50.

    Coote, A., Simms, A., & Franklin, J. (2010). 21 hours. London: New Economics Foundation.

    Crawford, M. B. (2009). Shopclass as soulcraft. New York: Penguin.

    Csikszentimihalyi, M., & Rochberg-Halton, E. (1981). The meaning of things. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

    DeFilippis, J. (2001). The myth of social capital in community development. Housing Policy Debate, 12(4), 781-806.

    Ellul, J. (1964). The technological society. New York: Knopf.

    Fight Club. (1999). Directed by D. Fincher. Produced by A. Linson, C. Chaffin & R. G. Bell. 20th Century Fox.

    Foth, M. (2003). Connectivity does not ensure community. In S. Marshall & W. Taylor (Eds.), 5 th International

    Conference on Information Technology in Regional Areas (pp. 31-40). Caloundra, QLD: ITiRA.

    Gneezy, U., & Rustichini, A. (2000). A fine is a price. Journal of Legal Studies, 29, 1-18.

    Grant, G. (1986). Technology & justice. Concord, ON: Anansi.

    Gurstein, M. (2007). What is community informatics (and why does it matter)? Milan: Polimetrica.

    Jacobs, J. (1992). Death and life of great American cities. Westminster, MD: Vintage Press. (Original workpublished in 1961).

    Jegou, F., & Manzini, E. (2008). Collaborative services. Milan: Edizioni POLI.design.

    Kemmis, D. (1990). Community and the politics of place. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press.

    Kim, J., & Kaplan, R. (2004). Physical and psychological factors in sense of community. Environment andBehavior, 36(3), 313-340.

    Kunstler, J. H. (1993). The geography of nowhere. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Latour, B. (1992). Where are the missing masses? In W. E. Bijker & J. Law (Eds.), Shaping Technology/BuildingSociety (pp. 225-258). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    24/25

    24

    Lichterman, P. (1996). The sear ch for political community. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Lund, H. (2002). Pedestrian environments and sense of community. Journal of Planning Education and Research,21, 301-312.

    Lynch, K. (1984). Good city form. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    McMillan, D. W., & Chavis, D. M. (1986). Sense of community. Journal of Community Psychology, 14, 6-23.

    Meroni, A., ed. (2007). Crea tive communities. Milan: Edizioni POLI.design.

    Mumford, L. (1970). The culture of cities. New York: Harcourt Brace & Company. (Original work published 1938).

    Nisbet, R. (2010). The quest for community. Wilmington, DE: ISI Books. (Original work published 1953).

    Oldenburg, R. (1999). The great good place. Cambridge, MA: Da Capo Press.

    Pappanek, V. (1984). Design for the real world (2nd ed.). Chicago: Academy Chicago Publishers.

    Pendola, R, & Gen, S. (2008). Does "main street" promote sense of community? Environment and Behavior, 40(4),545-574.

    Pickett, K., & Wilkinson, R. (2010) The spirit level. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Putnam, R. D. (2000). Bowling alone. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Reich, R. B. (1991). The work of nations. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Rheingold, H. (2000). The virtual community. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Sandel, M. J. (1984). The procedural republic and the unencumbered self. Political Theory, 12(1), 81-96.

    Sarason, S. (1974). The Psychological Sense of Community. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Schwartz, B., & Sharpe, K. (2010). Practical wisdom. New York: Riverhead Books.

    Sclove, R.E. (1995). Democracy and Technology. New York: Guilford Books.

    Scott, J. F., & Lynton, R. P. (1952). The community factor in modern technology. International Study, Paris: UnitedNations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization.

    Shafir, E. (2007). Decisions constructed locally. In A. W. Kruglanski & E. T. Higgins (Eds.), Social P sychology:Handbook of Basic P rinciples (pp. 334-352). New York: The Guilford Press.

    Stoecker, R. (2005). Is community informatics good for communities? Community Informatics, 1(3). http://www.ci- journal.net/index.php/ciej/article/viewArticle/183. Accessed 5 April 2012.

    Taylor, C. (1991). The malaise of modernity. Tornoto: Anansi.

    Thaler, R. H, & Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Nudge. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

  • 8/10/2019 Dotson Design for Community Toward a Communitarian Ergonomics-libre

    25/25

    Thompson, E. P. (1971). The moral economy of the English crowd in the eighteenth century. Past & Present, 50,76-136.

    Tnnies, F. (2001). Community and civil society. J. Harris (Ed.). ( J. Harris & M. Hollis, Trans.). Cambridge, UK:Cambridge University Press. (Original work published in 1887).

    Turkle, S. (2011). Alone together. New York: Basic Books.

    Verbeek, P.-P. (2011). Moralizing technology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Vohs, K. D., Mead, N. L., & Goode, M. R. (2006). The psychological consequences of money. Science, 314, 1154-1156.

    Weisman, L. K. (1992). Discr imination by design. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Wellman, B. (1979). The community question. American J ournal of Sociology, 84(5), 1201-1231.

    Wellman, B. (1987). The community question re-evaluated. Research Paper, University of Toronto, Toronto: Centrefor Urban and Community Studies.

    Wellman, B. (1999). From little boxes to loosely-bounded networks. In J. Abu-Lughod (Ed.), Sociology for thetwenty-first century (pp. 94-114). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Wellman, B. (2001). Physical place and cyberplace. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, 25,1201-31.

    Whyte, W. H. (1988). City. New York: Doubleday.

    Willson, M. A. (2006). Technically together. New York: Peter Lang.

    Wiltse, J. (2007). Contested waters. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.

    Winner, L. (1977). Autonomous technology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Winner, L. (1980). Do artifacts have politics? Daeda lus, 109(1), 121-136.

    Winner, L. (1995). Political ergonomics. In R. Buchanan & V. Margolin (Eds.), Discovering design (pp. 146-170).Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Woodhouse, E.J. (2005). (Re)Constructing technological society by taking social construction even more seriously.Social Epistemology, 19(2-3), 199-223.