Transcript
Page 1: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN

PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING

WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES

by

Eleanor Milligan

BA (Hons-1st), Grad Dip Ed, BSc, ADAS (Chem)

Queensland University of Technology

Thesis is submitted in the Humanities Research Program, Queensland

University of Technology, in fulfilment of the requirement for the

degree of Doctor of Philosophy.

2008

Page 2: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

2

Page 3: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

3

Declaration

The work contained in this thesis has not been previously submitted to

meet requirements for an award at this or any other higher education

institution. To the best of my knowledge and belief, the thesis contains

no material previously published or written by another person except

where due reference is made.

_____________________________________

Eleanor Milligan

_____________________________________

Date

Page 4: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

4

Acknowledgments

In the Village

0H 0F

1

There is an old Greek proverb which states ‘It takes a village to raise a child’. It

occurs to me as I reach the end of this project that, similarly, it also takes a village to

write, or raise, a PhD thesis. I have been blessed to live this PhD journey in a village

filled with an abundance of compassion, support and encouragement, overflowing

with intellectual and individual generosity and guidance.

My ‘village’ has been inhabited by many generous mentors, most notably Dr Peter

Isaacs, co-founder of the Applied Ethics Program at QUT, who had the wisdom and

grace to simply listen when I stumbled into his office five years ago as a

disenfranchised scientist, questioning the ethical ramifications of the ‘technological

imperative’. He gently challenged my scientifically embedded ways (which I didn’t

know I had!) and gifted me with the tools to navigate the seemingly overwhelming

ethical terrain in alternative and more insightful ways. The conditions for my

flourishing began to take hold that day. My deepest thanks to you Peter; you have

helped to illuminate to me the destructive myth of rational objectivity that

impoverishes and obscures so much of our human understanding and potential. I

remain profoundly indebted to you. To Dr Astrid Gesche, thank you for having the

confidence to support me during my various ‘distractions’ over the past three years,

while gently reminding me that I had a thesis to write. Your tender tenacity and

commitment to polish any ‘rough edges’ are certainly reflected in this work and it is

a more considered piece of scholarship as a result of your input. My sincere

gratitude to you Astrid.

1 Image from website of Milliken University (www.millikin.edu)

Page 5: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

5

It is rare in a working life to experience that almost magical synergy that comes

from working with dynamic, spirited and passionately focussed colleagues – to my

fellow postgraduate colleagues Jenny Jones and Emma Woodley, thank you for co-

creating this energising environment with your sharp intelligence and curious minds.

We have challenged each others understandings, raised each other up and

maintained a fierce sense of belief in actualising our own and each others

possibilities. It has been an absolute privilege to work with you. From Dr David

Massey, I have learned much about living the ethical life, as opposed to theorising

about one. Thank you David for continuing to inspire by gentle example.

To Professor Daryl Pullman of Memorial University, Newfoundland, Canada, I owe

a tremendous debt of gratitude. From our initial meeting in 2005, your unconditional

generosity, openness and inclusiveness, your willingness to guide and support

through sharing your vast practical experience and insights have opened so many

doors intellectually, practically and personally. My most sincere thanks to you

Daryl.

At times the expectations and hopes from myself and others have seemed almost

insurmountable and I hope this thesis will do justice to those who have invested so

much of themselves in it. My sincere gratitude goes to each of the participants in

this study who gave so generously of their time, but perhaps more importantly of

themselves, their identities and understandings, their hopes, values, commitments

and frailties. Thank you for having the courage to lay those most private concerns

bare, to be picked over, dissected and scrutinised by someone you barely knew. I

hope I have done your trust in me justice. Regardless of their particular perspectives,

they each came to this project in a spirit of trust and collaboration with the honest

intention of contributing to better understandings, to guide more ethically responsive

practices for the future.

It was never the purpose of this study to pathologise, blame, or pit various

stakeholders ‘interests’ competitively against the other and I hope this study will

never be interpreted that way. It was my greatest hope at the outset to bring the

Page 6: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

6

various perspectives together, and engage in genuine dialogue to illuminate and

enhance mutual understandings. Negotiating practice and policy change may then be

approached from a position of genuine appreciative understanding, and this is surely

of potential benefit to all stakeholders. As you read this thesis, you will be the

ultimate judge of whether this has been achieved.

Finally, thanks to my family. To David, my husband of twenty one years (I suppose

that means our marriage has come of age!) - Thank you. There have been countless

times when my absence (physical and mental) has placed extra responsibilities on

your broad and capable shoulders, but you have always strongly defended my

commitment to realising the goals of this research and graciously valued their

importance. I am so grateful to you for your part in helping me embrace this

opportunity. To our three children Claire, James and Grace, your presence in my life

opened a world of possibilities and questions. You fill me with optimism for the

future and joy for the present; I trust that as you grow you will gain a sense of why I

felt this work was important, and embrace the imperative of ethical reflection in

shaping the future that you will inherit.

Page 7: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

7

Abstract Informed consent, based on patient autonomy, is seen as necessary if medical

interventions are to be seen as legally and ethically acceptable. While ‘informed

consent’ protocols within antenatal care, including prenatal screening regimes are

presumed to be robust, emerging research outside of Australia suggests most women

do not adequately understand the medical purpose, limitations or potential ethical

implications, such as selective termination, of the medical procedures ‘consented’ to.

While the consent given in these situations may well fulfil the minimal legal criteria

for informed consent, the required level of knowledge and understanding necessary

to meet the ethical standards informed or understood consent often appears not be

met. The presumption that legally informed consent equates to morally informed

consent inherent within institutional protocols for screening must therefore be

questioned, and the ethical integrity of these increasingly routine interventions

demand further scrutiny.

The purpose of this research was to explore whether the problems identified in

research overseas might also exist locally. Underpinned by a phenomenological

philosophical approach to understanding the ethical dimensions of clinical practice,

the research sought to engage with a small cohort of mothers and practitioners

locally. The study adopted a qualitative narrative methodology, analysing individual

in-depth interviews using the Listening Guide (Gilligan et al, 2003). The

experiences of mothers and health practitioners interviewed exposed a range of

institutional, social, personal and philosophical constraints that mirrored the

overseas research findings and also illuminated how informed consent may be

unintentionally undermined in the clinical setting.

A positive outcome of the study was that it provided a locally informed and

contextually sensitive basis from which to strengthen existing organisational

informed consent protocols and thus support women’s ethical decision making. As

the process of becoming ‘informed’ to consent is largely educational, promoting

patient learning in the clinical context is an ethical imperative. However, there

seems limited awareness at either the clinical or theoretical level of the critical link

between patient education and ethically robust medical intervention. Hence a

Page 8: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

8

significant contribution of this research was to explore this underdeveloped but

practically important link.

As the process of gaining informed consent has far reaching applications across a

broad spectrum of medical interventions, the contextual and educational insights

offered throughout this research may have significant relevance beyond the

immediate context of this research.

Keywords: Ethics, Prenatal Screening, Informed Consent, Education

Page 9: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

9

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Acknowledgements…………………………………………………………………..4

Abstract………………………………………………………………………………7

Prelude……………………………………………………………………………...14

Overview of Thesis…………………………………………………………………18

SECTION A

LAYING THE FOUNDATIONS

CHAPTER ONE – INTRODUCTION…………………………………………….23

Situating Prenatal Screening – Exploring Contexts………………………………..23

Research Questions and Scope…………………………………………………….34

Chapter Summary………………………………………………………………….38

CHAPTER TWO – AN ETHICAL ORIENTATION

Introduction…………………………………………………………………………41

Comparing Ethical Perspectives

Ethics as Philosophy – Epistemology and Ways of Rational Knowing……46

Analytical Philosophy and Science: Expert Outsiders Mutually

Reinforcing the Technological Imperative…………………………53

Ethics as Embedded and Transformative - Re-humanising

and Re-contextualising the Ethical Agenda………………………………..56

Recovering Ontology at the Core of Medical Ethics………………………………57

An Applied Ethics Framework for Research………………………………………59

Narrative and Ethics ……………………………………………………………….63

The Moral Significance of Narrative………………………………………63

Why Ethics? .................................................................................................65

Chapter Summary………………………………………………………………….68

Page 10: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

10

CHAPTER 3 – RESEARCH THROUGH VOICE: A METHOD FOR EXPLORING

EMBEDDED UNDERSTANDINGS

Introduction…………………………………………………………………………71

Why Narrative? .........................................................................................................72

The In–Depth Interview………………………………….…………………………77

Participant Recruitment……………………………………….……………80

Mother Recruitment…………………………………...……………82

Health Care Provider Recruitment…………………….…………...83

Ethical Considerations of Recruitment and Participation ………………….83

The Interviews……………………………………………………………………...85

Transcription………………………………………………………………………..87

Narrative Interpretation……………………………………………………………..89

The Listening Guide………………………………………………………..92

Step 1: Listening for ‘Plot’…………………………………………93

Step 2: ‘I’ Poems……………………………………………………95

Step 3: Listening for Contrapuntal Voices ………………………..103

Contrapuntal Voices – A Window on Individual Moral

Frameworks?...................................................................................108

Step 4: Summary…………………………………………….…….109

Limitations and Challenges………………………………………………….…....111

Chapter Summary…………………………………………………………………112

CHAPTER 4 – PRENATAL SCREENING – THE TECHNICAL LENS

Introduction………………………………………………………………………..114

Blood Tests–Maternal Serum Screening………………………..………………...114

Ultrasound…………………………………………………………………………115

Soft Markers……………………………………………………………………….118

Nuchal Translucency……………………………………………………………...121

Amniocentesis…………………………………………………………………..…124

Page 11: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

11

SECTION B

VOICES IN CONTEXT

ILLUMINATING PRACTICE - IDENTIFYING CONSTRAINTS

Section Introduction……………………………………………………………….127

CHAPTER 5 – VOICES IN CONTEXT: PHILOSOPHICAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction………………………………………………………………..………134

The Autonomous Self …………………………………………………….………135

Autonomous Voices…………………………………………………….…140

Informed Consent and Choice…………………………………………………….143

Presumed Consent…………..……………………………………………………..152

Chapter Summary ……………………….………………………………….…….153

CHAPTER 6 - VOICES IN CONTEXT: INSTITUTIONAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction…………………………………………………………………….….155

Routine Testing and the Normative Pathway………………………………….….155

Institutional Barriers to Education: Blurred Accountability for ‘Informing’….….164

Communication – Commitments and Barriers……………………………………167

Overt and Covert Counselling…………………………………………………….171

Legal Frameworks: Practice and Policy Consequences…………………………..175

Chapter Summary …………………………………………………………….…..180

CHAPTER 7 – VOICES IN CONTEXT: SOCIAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction……………………………………………………………………….182

The Social Construction of Choice……………………………………………….182

Trust in the Medical System, Science and Technology ………………………….188

Responsibility and Culpability……………………………………………………194

Poor Understanding of Disability…………………………………………………198

The ‘Preventable’ Cost of Disability: Cost/Benefit Analysis……………………..206

Chapter Summary ………………………………………………………………...211

Page 12: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

12

CHAPTER 8 – VOICES IN CONTEXT: PERSONAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction…………………………………………………………………….….213

Reassurance and the ‘Desire to Know’………………………………………..…..213

Risk in the Context of Antenatal Care…………………………………………….222

Probability and Risk Perception ………………………………..…………226

Anxiety and the Psychological Impact of Risk……………………………234

Chapter Summary……………………………………………………………...….239

SECTION C

TRANSFORMING PRACTICE: FACILITATING WOMEN’S

ETHICAL CHOICES

CHAPTER 9 – PATIENT EDUCATION IN CLINCAL CARE

Introduction…………………………………………………………………...…..242

From Information to Understanding: the Bridge of Learning………………....….243

Exploring Adult Learning ………………………………………………..…...…..247

Characteristics of Adult Learning………………………………………….……..251

Conditions of Adult Learning in the Clinical Context……………………..……..255

The ‘Need’ to Know……………………………………………….……..255

Integrating Existing Experience …………………………………….……259

The Importance of Prior Learning in Constructing New Knowledge….…261

The Physical Environment and Patient Practitioner Relationships ……..264

Mutually Defined Learning Goals and their Role

in Fostering Active Responsibility and Commitment………………..…..270

Defining Progress and Success………………………………….……..…272

The Shared Ethical Orientation of ‘Patient-Centred Medicine’

and Adult Learning…………………..……………………………….….273

Transforming Patient Learning in Clinical Care……………………………..….274

Chapter Summary……………………………………………………………..…276

CHAPTER 10 – TRANSFORMING PRACTICE

Introduction……………………………………………………………..………..279

Transforming Institutions………………………………………….….…………281

Page 13: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

13

Transforming Institutional Approaches to Ethics………………….…….282

Transforming Practitioner Education……………….……..….….285

The Ethical Role of Patient Educator…………………………………….288

Open Moral Spaces in Institutional Care……………………….….….….291

Transforming Policy…………………………………………….……......294

Injecting Consistency into Data Collection and Analysis……..…298

Transforming Faith in Technology: Challenging

the Sacred Narratives of Science………….…………………………..….303

Transforming Individuals……………………………………………………..….305

Enhancing Patient Participation: Supporting Shared Decision

Making Within a Framework of Patient-Centred Care…………………...306

Enhancing Patient/Provider Communication ………………………..…...310

Communicating What? Promoting Accurate

And Balanced Information…………………………………….….312

Supporting Patient Learning in the Clinical Environment……………..…316

Chapter Summary………………………………………………………………....321

CHAPTER 11 – CONCLUSIONS

Purpose of the thesis……………………………………………………………....323

Contributions of this research……………………………………………………..324

Directions for future research……………………………………………………..329

Summary ……………………...…………………………………………………..331

REFERENCES………………………………………………………..…………..333

APPENDICES

Appendix I - Topic List……………………………………………………….…...356

Appendix II A- Participant Information Pack – Mothers…………………………357

Appendix II B- Participant Information Pack – Practitioners……………..………361

Appendix III - Ethics Approval UHREC 3911H………………………………….363

Appendix IV - Topic List Key …………………………………………..………..364

Page 14: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

14

Prelude

This project initially began as an honours thesis in response to my perception, as a

perturbed scientist, that in our haste to pursue the technological imperative in

medicine, our capacity to form a considered moral response to the potentially

contentious ethical consequences was galloping increasingly beyond our grasp. The

most immediate and glaring place in which I saw this largely unquestioning

commitment to the value of medical science and technology as indisputably “choice

enhancing” was in the routine recruitment of women (many of whom were friends,

family and colleagues), into prenatal testing regimes. On accepting an offer to be

tested (or perhaps more accurately – not objecting to the expectation that they would

embrace testing) these women, my friends and colleagues, were being invited to

consider the quality of their yet unborn children, as Rayna Rapp (2000, p.3)

describes it ‘to make concrete and embodied decisions about the standards of entry

into the human community’.

Within my immediate circle I noted both unquestioning, passive compliance with,

and active pursuit of prenatal screening technologies. Both positions were

apparently accompanied by a lack of clear understanding about the potential

outcomes of screening at the outset, resulting in a range of reactions from mild

bewilderment to deep emotional anguish when it later became obvious that these

tests by no means provided the clear reassurance expected. Often, women’s

compliance flowed from the reassuringly routine way such tests were incorporated

into established and seemingly mundane routine antenatal care, while the distress

emerged from the previously unconsidered realisation that, rather than providing the

much hoped for comfort, the test ‘data’ frequently yielded ambiguous and

inconclusive results that created confusion, uncertainty and for some, deep

psychological distress. Such results often generated more questions than they

answered, leaving women to ponder uncertain and previously unimagined futures,

not only for their prospective children, but also for themselves as parents.

For some when a problem was picked up, they felt their choices had been enhanced,

and the option to terminate the pregnancy of a child with a disability was a

Page 15: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

15

welcomed one. However, others noted that when a problem was suspected, rather

than automatically enhancing choice as presumed, many felt powerlessly funnelled

towards what felt like the ‘choice-less choice’ of further testing, where often, the

ultimate practical ‘cure’ on offer was that of termination of any effected child.

Grappling with the newly dawning realisation that when the expected reassurance

was not forthcoming, and that screening was in effect ‘screening out’, many felt

deeply confronted and affronted by the apparently widely held presumption that they

would reject their child. Some expressed grave concern about the unspoken eugenic

undertones that accompanied this routine practice and were troubled by what felt

like their complicity and collusion in it. At the heart of their unease lay the most

fundamental ethical question, as Rapp (2002, p.3) so eloquently expressed before,

the question of what conditions of entry we impose on those we permit to join our

human community. Thus, the critical questions raised by prenatal screening

technologies such as, who is allowed to be born, under what circumstances and

conforming to which pre-conditions of entry to the human race are inherently ethical

in nature, because they reveal fundamental understandings and prejudgements about

the nature of human ‘being’.

In reflecting on these observations, I began to wonder why the ethical dimensions of

this practice were not more explicitly acknowledged, to question what our current

ethical protocols in clinical care were, and to seek out where and how our current

protocols seemed to be failing women (and health practitioners), the way so many of

my friends and colleagues had expressed feeling let down. I soon realised that the

practical ‘doing’ of ethics demanded more than simply asking pertinent

philosophical questions or exposing unethical practice. Authentically ‘doing’ ethics

demanded a commitment to exposing, contesting and transforming the unethical, by

pursuing achievable means to reform and humanise practice, in support of women’s

ethical decision making. Only in an ethically sensitised and responsive environment

could women genuinely have the freedom and support to honour their own moral

values in the face of these ubiquitous technologies.

However, medical practice does not occur in a social vacuum, and any potential

transformative response would need to be sensitive to the deeply layered personal,

Page 16: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

16

social, historical, institutional, political and cultural lenses through which this

practice had evolved and continues to be interpreted by various stakeholders in it.

Gaining an understanding of these complex underlying and multilayered factors

would therefore be vital in formulating a feasible transformation. Collectively, these

ponderings began to form the basis for the research questions posed in this thesis

entitled ‘Enhancing ethical practice in prenatal screening: Facilitating women’s

ethical choices’.

It became obvious early in the research that, institutionally, the most commonly

accepted means of illustrating1F

2 an ethical sensitivity into prenatal clinical care

regimes was through eliciting women’s ‘consent’ to be screened. Informed consent

is frequently presented as a strong indicator of ethical probity because of the

inherent respect for individual patient autonomy it presumably encapsulates.

However, my preliminary research also starkly revealed that while up to 90% of

women in developed countries receive some form of prenatal screening2F

3, many

could not articulate the purpose or implications of the procedures ‘consented’ to3F

4,

although they had intentionally participated in such testing. Thus, the expectation

that consent to be tested automatically equated to an appropriate level of knowledge

and understanding inherent within the ethical standard of ‘informed consent’

seemed ill founded. Unchecked ‘consent’, or mere compliance, was arguably an

inadequate measure of ethical probity.

In speaking with my friends and colleagues it appeared that one major source of

their distress flowed from an initial lack of understanding of the finer points of the

interventions they had agreed (or acquiesced) to. This realisation raised questions

about the often tacit link between patient education and ethical probity in clinical

care, highlighting the ethical imperative to adequately educate women prior to

testing. As the process of becoming ‘informed’ to consent is essentially educational,

the importance of learning in the clinical context is critical. However, there

appeared to be limited awareness at either a practical or theoretical level that

2 I say ‘illustrating’ because my sense is that the commitment that ethics must be ‘seen to be done’, often expediently trumps the commitment to reflecting on genuine ethical needs or requirements. 3 See Spencer, Spencer, Power, Dawson, & Nicolaides, 2003 4 See Lippman, 1992; Markens, Browner, & Press, 1999; Press & Browner, 1995, 1997; Santhalahti, Hemminki, Latikka, & Ryynanen, 1998; Stapleton, Kirkham, & Thomas, 2002

Page 17: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

17

education, on which reflective understanding is built, is a fundamental pre-requisite

to ethically robust intervention. While the commonly pursued ethical agenda held

‘informed’ consent to be the benchmark of ethicality, the significance of learning for

understanding in preserving moral integrity seemed to be given insufficient weight

by current protocols and the critical link between sound educational opportunities

and ethical probity was under explored and under acknowledged.

Responding to the conflicting observations above, this research project offers an

applied ethics framework to illuminate and give critical insight into the complex

situational considerations that shape and constrain ethical practice. Critically, it

highlights the ethically essential difference between possessing information and

possessing understanding. While this point may signal an educative difference, it

represents a critical distinction ethically as the strong reliance on ‘information

disclosure’ as a legal obligation in care sets out very different expectations than the

‘information understanding’ requirement implicit in the ethical interpretation of

informed consent. The former might be seen as a necessary event, while the latter

emerges from an ongoing relational process.

Finally, mirroring my own learning pathway, this research is intentionally

multidisciplinary in its gaze, drawing on a range of complementary and interrelated

insights flowing from the humanities, education and science. As we are first and

foremost embedded in the human condition, it is the insights and understandings

offered through the humanities that form the basis of understanding the impact of

technology in, and on, our lives. It is from the coherent base of the humanities that

we may make sense of the individual and collective meaning of science and

technology in our lives, to critically analyse and evaluate our apparent willingness to

embrace the technological imperative, and guide our capacity to pursue the humane

use of these burgeoning technologies into the future. Therefore, this research is

anchored in an ‘applied’ view of ethics, as a coherent philosophical framework from

which to identify, evaluate and forge practical strategies of social, cultural,

educational and institutional reform where required. Indeed, the integrated response

required may only be achieved by intentionally adopting an inclusive and co-

ordinated multidisciplinary standpoint.

Page 18: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

18

Overview of the Thesis

The thesis is broadly divided into three sections. Section A, ‘Laying the

Foundations’, consists of Chapters One to Four, in which the scope of the research,

the foundational philosophical orientation, an explanation of why a narrative

methodology was adopted, and a brief description of prenatal screening tests are

outlined.

Chapter One provides a broad overview of the multifaceted and interwoven

considerations that form the social, personal, institutional and philosophical

background from which the questions raised in this work emerge.

Chapter Two gives an account of the ethical orientation underlying the thesis,

prefiguring the interpretive framework that shapes the research. It explores the

dominant rational and analytical philosophical approaches to ethics as practiced and

entrenched within the medical model of care and proposes that these are lacking

when it comes to building understandings of the deeply embedded and relational

nature of moral decision making. An alternative ethical orientation is found in the

phenomenological philosophical account of the human condition. This account

which acknowledges the embodied human condition as one significantly interpreted

through multiple layers of social embeddedness provides a richer and more resonant

ontological foundation from which to explore and transform the ethically

problematic aspects of prenatal screening. This alternative way of approaching

ethics as a way of understanding human ‘being’ and ‘becoming’ rather than focusing

on the dominant epistemologically centred ethics of ‘thinking’ and ‘knowing’ is

outlined.

Chapter Three addresses questions of methodology and provides an account of why

a dialogical, narrative framework of inquiry and analysis is seen as best suited to the

research questions posed. Flowing naturally from the ontological understandings of

human beings as essentially dialogically and relationally constructed, a narrative

methodology comfortably complements the phenomenological view of the human

self as embedded, embodied and relational. This chapter also explores the rationale

Page 19: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

19

underpinning the adoption of semi-structured, in-depth interviews with the seven

mothers and eleven practitioners of this cohort. It describes the recruitment of

participants and the interview and analysis processes adopted. As a method of

narrative analysis that accommodates the plurivocal and multifaceted nature of

narratively structured lives, the Listening Guide (Gilligan et al 2003) was adopted as

a suitable means of analysis. The practicalities and problems of use of the Listening

Guide will also be considered.

Chapter Four provides a brief description and discussion of the prenatal screening

tests commonly encountered by the participants. It gives a short background of the

development of these tests, and considers the potential strengths and weaknesses of

each.

Section B, “Voices in Context”, explores the situated accounts and experiences of

this cohort of participants. Having garnered individual accounts from the nineteen

participants, and considered the emerging themes, plots and contrapuntal voices

through analysis using the Listening Guide, Chapters Five through to Eight situate

these participant voices within the broader context of existing conversations and

understandings, and weave participants’ stories through the ongoing and evolving

conversations between other mothers, practitioners, scholars and researchers

working in this field. Through this process, consideration is given as to where local

experiences fit within the broader context of the globally burgeoning practice of

prenatal screening. This section is structured into four chapters which consecutively

explore the ethical, institutional, personal and social constraints that act to shape

ethical decision making in prenatal screening. In terms of the applied ethics

framework adopted, these four chapters address the hermeneutical and appreciative

dimensions of practice, considering individual choices and behaviours within the

multilayered and interdependent contexts of the personal, social, institutional and

ethical constraints experienced and articulated.

Finally, Section C, ‘Transforming practice: Facilitating women’s ethical choices’

which consists of Chapters Nine to Eleven, highlights the crucial ethical link

between embracing sound educational understandings and strategies in patient

Page 20: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

20

education and the development of the reflective understanding demanded of

ethically adequate informed consent protocols. The necessary transformation of

clinical practice on individual and institutional levels needed to facilitate, support

and enhance women’s ethical choices when confronted with the offer to screen their

unborn children are considered.

Chapter Nine, ‘Patient Education in Clinical Care’, explores the common

foundational ontological stance underpinning both the phenomenological account of

human being and that implicit within educational philosophy. The chapter explores

how learning theory may be applied to educational processes in clinical care in a

way that accommodates the numerous ethical, institutional, social and personal

constraints identified in the previous chapters. Participants’ educational experiences,

whether as teacher, learner or both are incorporated to illuminate where potential

transformative responses to the ethical challenges identified may be strengthened.

The critical differentiation between the minimal legally adequate information

disclosure and morally adequate reflective understanding will also be considered in

light of their critical ethical importance in achieving ‘informed’ consent in practice.

Chapter Ten, ‘Transforming Practice’, addresses the responsive transformative call

of the ethical in two parts; transforming individuals and transforming institutions.

Individual transformation through adopting a patient-centred model of care to

promote the realisation of genuinely shared decision making between patient and

practitioner is discussed, alongside the need to promote communication

competencies, and develop clear, accurate and balanced literature. Several areas of

potential institutional ethical transformation are also discussed, including the re-

humanising and re-contextualising of ethics within appropriate and accessible

institutional infrastructures that promote open and inclusive moral spaces. The need

to develop evidence based culture of practice through pursuing more comprehensive

data collection and analysis in Queensland and the need to undertake law reform to

enable a transparent evidence based culture to flourish in the local context are also

discussed.

Page 21: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

21

Chapter Eleven concludes with a review of the contributions and recommendations

flowing from this research, summarises the outcomes and proposes some directions

for future research in this area.

Page 22: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

22

SECTION A

LAYING THE FOUNDATIONS

Page 23: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

23

CHAPTER ONE

INTRODUCTION

Situating Prenatal Screening – Exploring Contexts

‘Women are situated on the research frontier of the expanding capacity for

prenatal genetic diagnosis, forced to judge the quality of their own foetuses,

making concrete and embodied decisions about the standards of entry into

the human community’ (Rapp, 2000, p.3).

The development of prenatal screening technologies4F

5 has been described as

‘simultaneously liberating and eugenic’ (Rapp, 2000, p.2). They are liberating in

that they can provide a means by which some parents may conceive or give birth to

the healthy child they desire, but also eugenic as, in the absence of the ability to

‘cure’ or treat certain physical or genetic conditions that may be diagnosed, they

predominantly achieve this end through the selective termination of those foetuses

judged to be physically or genetically undesirable. While both vantage points

equally claim theirs as the most socially and ethically responsible course of action,

either by preventing pain and suffering to, or unconditionally accepting, a child with

a disability, it is immediately clear that the burgeoning practice of prenatal screening

uncomfortably straddles a gaping ethical divide.

The presumption that the technologically mediated goal of preventing disability is

‘desirable and defensible’, and a worthy pursuit that in no way passes judgement on

existing people with disabilities is widely disseminated and claimed to be generally

shared in society (Parker, Forbes, & Findlay, 2002, p.10; Savulescu, 2001).

However, the means by which such prevention is achieved, the entrenched social

prejudice it is claimed to instil, and the potentially eugenic stance within are strongly

contested by many commentators writing from a disability rights perspective

(Bridle, 2004; Hubbard, 1988; Kenen, 1999; Newell, 2003, 2007; Parens & Asch,

5 A description of the most common prenatal screening technologies encountered by pregnant women in this study is given in Chapter Four.

Page 24: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

24

2000; Shakespeare, 1998, 1999, 2001). James Lindemann-Nelson (2003, p.3) further

cautions,

‘According people the respect they are due is a matter of general

importance, and we ought be especially scrupulous when people who have

endured a history of negligence and abuse claim that they are yet again

being demeaned’.

When the nature of the much hoped for ‘prevention’ comes in the form of

terminating an existing foetus or embryo, ‘prevention’ takes on a radically different

and increasingly controversial meaning; clearly a more extreme form than a measles

inoculation for example.

Thus, in being invited to embrace the technological intervention of prenatal

screening, women are placed in, what is for many, the uncomfortable and unenviable

position of taking responsibility for making ‘concrete and embodied decisions about

standards of entry in the human community’ as Rapp (2003, p.3) noted earlier.

Markens, Browner and Press (1999, p.367) similarly describe this choice as

‘engag(ing) in risk assessment which can determine the life and birth of future

generations’. Thus, the factors that shape this ethical divide between the culturally

endorsed views of technology as irrefutably choice enhancing and good, and the

moral unease of prejudicial, discriminatory and stigmatising practices directed

against people with disabilities, expose complex ethical questions that challenge our

most fundamental understanding of what it means to be a human being. These are

fundamentally ethical questions and they form the social and cultural backdrop of

this thesis.

Generally across all forms of medical intervention, the widely accepted and

favoured safeguard against possible ethical impropriety, or in the case of prenatal

screening accusations of coercion and eugenic intent, has been to focus on

obtaining a patient’s informed consent prior to any proposed intervention (Marteau

& Dormandy, 2001). A prior consideration to our reliance on informed consent as a

legal and ethical safeguard is that the intervention in question is not contrary to the

Page 25: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

25

accepted public order or shared sense of moral good. Only when an action does not

breach the law, or breach codes of moral action in a society can a person be

considered at liberty to give their voluntary consent. While prenatal screening is

widely practiced and accepted in our society, and provided by public health

institutions which convey societal endorsement of this practice, some disagreement

arguably lingers as to the inherent ethical acceptability of selective termination

(Asch & Wasserman, 2005; Caplan, 1999; Clapton, 2003; Hubbard, 2001; Lippman,

1991; Wertz, 1998; Wertz & Fletcher, 1998). The prefiguring tension surrounding

the ethical acceptability of prenatal screening is acknowledged throughout this work;

however, this work does not seek a definitive answer to these divisions. Rather it

explores the ethical tensions inherent within current practices and seeks to illuminate

practical responses which may support all women to act within their own moral

frameworks when confronted with the moral choices inherent within the offer to

undergo prenatal screening.

When a proposed intervention is legal, conform to public policy and community

standards of ethical behaviour, the conditions of informed consent prior to any

medical intervention articulated in the medical ethics literature generally embrace

the following five 5F

6 criteria;

• that a patient must be competent to decide,

• that all material information about the proposed intervention must be

disclosed,

• that participation in proposed intervention is optional and voluntary,

• that the patient fully understands the nature and potential benefits and risks

of the proposed intervention,

• that consent is active, and given freely without coercion

(Beauchamp & Childress, 2001; Jonsen, 1998; Manson & O'Neill, 2007; Mitchell,

Kerridge, & Lovat, 1996).

6 In law, three pillars are generally cited being competence, information and voluntariness, however, the ethics literature commonly cites the five listed above.

Page 26: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

26

Hence a patient giving their informed consent, granted freely from a position of

knowledge and understanding to undergo a particular ‘treatment’, has come to

represent that any proposed intervention is ethically robust as the above mentioned

conditions of competence, voluntariness and understanding are presumed to be

implicit within its application. Seeking informed consent is further regarded as

proof that patient autonomy has been respected, while the realisation of informed

consent in practice is presumed to support individuals in their capacity to

intentionally make important decisions and pursue their own individual goals in a

way that is consistent with personal moral frameworks, free from control or

manipulation.

The pre-conditions of voluntary and knowledgeable participation are believed to be

inherent within prenatal screening protocols. However, research from around the

globe into the motivations and understandings of women engaging in prenatal

screening suggests that although many women do indeed participate or consent to

screening, a significant number cannot articulate the purpose or potential outcomes

of testing. This well established research into the motivations and experiences of

women participating in prenatal screening programmes commonly reveals a lack of

reflective understanding, passive compliance with a routine normative pathway and

an apparent inability to articulate the purpose, justifications or potential problems of

the testing they have participated in (Bernhardt et al., 1998; Harris, Connor, Bisits,

& Higginbotham, 2004; Kohut, 2002; Markens, Browner, & Press, 1999; Press &

Browner, 1997; Santhalahti, 1999; Santhalahti, Hemminki, Latikka, & Ryynanen,

1998; Stapleton, Kirkham, & Thomas, 2002; Williams, Alderson, & Farsides,

2002c). The tacit expectation of participation that routine screening conveys further

obscures the optional nature of screening while the poor knowledge levels reported

significantly challenges any comfortable presumption of ‘informed’ engagement.

The belief that participation may be equated to ethical integrity as claimed by some

commentators (Cuckle, 1995; Whynes, 2002) thus seems ill founded.

As informed consent protocols have gained precedence primarily through the courts,

a further barrier to fulfilling the ethical intentions of informed consent in an

institutional setting is the strong defensive legal bias which influences how such

Page 27: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

27

protocols are actualised within organisational structures. As flagged previously, the

ethical standard of understood consent cannot be presumed to be inherent within the

minimal legal criteria for informed consent in the area of prenatal screening. The

legal bias which permeates practice often engulfs the more subtle moral or ethical

negotiations required from the patient – physician exchange (Manson, 2007; Wear,

1998). Indeed some commentators openly describe existing informed consent

protocols as merely empty bureaucratic rituals (ibid), the main purpose of which is

to provide a defensive legal document or form of insurance against malpractice

suits, while paying superficial concern to the moral dimensions of care (Gillott

2001; Kenen, 1999; Press & Browner, 1995). When the motivation to procure

consent is primarily driven by the legal goal of averting litigation, rather than

proactively equipping the patient with the necessary understandings to make

decisions that are medically and morally coherent for that individual, the clash of

motivation between those seeking consent and those giving it potentially creates a

conflict of interest that may further widen the existing ethical divide.

Some very real particular and practical problems flow in trying to actualise informed

consent in the clinical context of antenatal care. Entrenched institutional pathways

such as the routine nature of screening may obscure voluntariness; overt and covert

counselling may be subtly coercive while the predefining of certain outcomes as

unacceptable may limit possibilities and narrow the boundaries of tolerance.

Additionally the lack of genuine access to alternative pathways delimits which

choices are permissible; limited time for consultations often prevents the formation

of effective communication partnerships and poor access to adequate education and

knowledge building converge to create a situation in which women’s individual

agency may be practically and profoundly constrained.

Within the wider context of health care, low levels of informed consent are

commonly observed across many fields of medical intervention and compelling

evidence of failure to achieve ‘informed consent’ persists across an extensive variety

of medical interventions and disciplines. Disturbingly low figures in meeting the

ethical requirements of informed consent have been reported at 0.5 % success for

‘complex’ decisions, defined as having extensive effect on the patient with uncertain

Page 28: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

28

and multiple outcomes, and reaching a mere 26% success for simple decisions

where the effect is minimal and the outcomes are clear and singular (Braddock,

Edwards, Hasenberg, Laidley, & Levinson, 1999, p.p.2315-7). Using Braddock et

al’s (ibid) descriptors, the decision to undergo prenatal screening may be regarded as

complex, as the potential outcomes are numerous and uncertain, and the

consequences may indeed be personally devastating for some. Such poor success in

achieving informed consent within medical care generally and within prenatal

screening protocols in particular expose the failure of current approaches. Although

the accepted protocols may meet the minimum legal or administrative requirements,

evidence suggests that they commonly struggle to fulfil their ethical purpose of

preserving patient autonomy and empowering the patient with the right to

intentionally embrace or reject the intervention on offer (Bottrell, Alpert, Fischbach,

& Emanuel, 2000; Braddock, 2002; Braddock et al., 1999; Wear, 1998). The

potential consequences of ill informed compliance in the realm of prenatal screening

for women are identified as short and long term anxiety or depression; alienation

and feelings of coercion (Goel, Glazier, Summers, & Holzapfel, 1998; Kowalcek et

al., 2002; Watson et al., 2003). The failure to implement robust informed consent

protocols that genuinely uphold and promote individual capacity for morally

coherent decision making therefore has real potential to harm.

These observations invite further consideration of the underlying presumptions,

conventions and ethical intentions inherent within ‘informed consent’. Critically,

they also raise questions about the role that ‘informed consent’ may play in

preserving individual autonomy via the right to decide about treatment options, of

protecting individuals from coercion and manipulation. The historical roots of

requiring a patient to give ‘informed consent’ to participate in medical research

were first outlined with respect to medical research in the Nuremberg Code

(Beauchamp & Childress, 2001, p.77; Manson & O'Neill, 2007), and later in the

Declaration of Helsinki 6F

7. These codes significantly position informed consent as a

process of ensuring patient autonomy and freedom ‘from’ control, rather than their

freedom ‘to’ pursue independent and intentional goals. It is the protective ‘freedom

7 See World Medical Association. Ethics Unit Declaration of Helsinki. 2007. www.wma.net./e/ethicsunit/helsinki.htm. Retrieved 20-12-07. See also Goodyear, Krleza-Jeric, & Lemmens (2007) for comment on the most recent changes to the Declaration.

Page 29: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

29

from’ stance that appreciably defines respect for autonomy in the medical ethics

literature, although as outlined above, this appears not to be commonly achieved in

clinical practice either generally or with respect to prenatal screening protocols.

However, some more mainstream philosophers (Dworkin, 1988, 2003; Taylor,

1989), and several feminist scholars (Dodds, 2000; Donchin, 2001; Friedman, 1997;

Sherwin, 1998) further suggest that the typical conception of autonomy, as it is

generally represented, holds overly individualistic, atomistic and detached views of

the human self. These philosophers assert that dominant accounts of autonomy

promote rational self interest and distancing, elevate reason over emotion, and

encourage an adversarial stance towards decision making, all on the (false)

presumption that individuals are unencumbered and unimpeded in ‘choosing’ their

preferred pathway. This dominant account they maintain ignores the deeply

relational, socially embedded and constrained nature of human being (Friedman,

1997). As human experience is principally defined by social connectedness and

relationships, and the inevitable power dynamics therein, each ‘autonomous’ act

clearly has repercussions beyond the immediate decision maker. In elevating

independence from others as the key defining feature of autonomy, the dominant

account lacks ontological coherency and thus silences discussion of the multifaceted

nature of autonomy. Nedelsky (1989, cited by Friedman, 1997, p.45) proposes that

social relationships, contexts and practices are not separate from autonomy or

individuality, rather social context and interdependence are necessary to foster our

capacity for self governance. As all autonomously considered decisions are

significantly prefigured by socially distilled factors external to the individual person

deciding, a view of autonomy that embraces the multiple particular, contextual and

interdependent features of decision making is more appropriate to supporting the

ethical aims of autonomy and informed consent. Autonomy and relationality

therefore need not be positioned as mutually exclusive concepts, but rather as

mutually informing and reinforcing aspects of the human condition.

Despite the mounting evidence that ‘informed consent’ protocols in their current

form have enjoyed limited practical success to date (Manson & O'Neill, 2007; Wear,

1998), or that broader philosophical concerns exist about the defining features of

Page 30: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

30

autonomy or the merit of elevating individual agency and personal choice as the

privileged means of shaping our collective moral direction, the ethical ideals of

informed consent and autonomy hold considerable merit within broader Western

social frameworks. Thus ways to promote their actualisation, by seeking fuller

understandings of the numerous and complex overlapping and interwoven

constraints embedded within the broader social, institutional and personal domains

that have stifled their realisation in practice need to be identified and incorporated

into a more functional and responsive framework. The problems observed in

actualising informed consent may lie not with the conceptual intentions per se, but

perhaps with the thin, reductionist, often cursory and inadequate support and

organisational infrastructure directed at genuinely achieving them in clinical care.

The ethically adequate and socially inclusive ‘process’ of negotiating informed

consent, as opposed to the minimal legally adequate administrative ‘event’ of

obtaining consent, has the potential to equip patients with the necessary

understanding to make ethical decisions in accordance with their own moral

frameworks. Thus informed consent and respect for autonomy remain desirable and

necessary prerequisites to ethically robust medical intervention. The critical question

remains how we may support their actualisation in practice.

A major barrier to informed consent is promoting the desired level of patient

understanding. When sound understanding is achieved within a strong therapeutic

partnership, and the ethical standard of informed consent is achieved, research

shows positive outcomes for patients and practitioners including active acceptance

of outcomes (positive and negative), increased satisfaction and more stable

decisions, higher compliance7F

8 with treatment, lower instances of litigation and fewer

ongoing referrals (Bekker, Hewison, & Thornton, 2003; Levinson, Roter, Mullooly,

& Frankel, 1997; Stewart, 1995; Stewart et al., 2000). Thus achieving informed

consent may provide a valuable and appropriate means for ethically supporting

women and their practitioners in navigating the potentially controversial ethical

terrain of prenatal screening. Charles Taylor (1989) argues that if we value

8 Although Goodwin-Johansson (1988) and Raffle (2001) caution against structuring patient education in overly optimistic terms as a means of ensuring ‘compliance’ as this potentially undermines patient autonomy. Irrespective of whether a patient ultimately ‘complies’ with the preferred medical recommendation, the ethical intentions of informed consent is to promote engaged decision making, not to ensure compliance.

Page 31: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

31

something as a significant ‘good’, we are morally obliged to create the conditions

that support its actualisation. Hence if achieving informed consent is held to be a

communally valued ‘good’ through which ethical care is promoted, if the benefits

outlined above that flow from facilitating informed consent are genuinely ‘goods’

we affirm, we are called upon to carefully examine the sources of the current

failures, to guide the positive transformation of practice to support these ethical

goals.

Within a framework of relationally aware, socially contextualised and inclusive

notions of autonomy and informed consent, practical problems concerning how to

inform (in addition to ‘what’ to inform) arise. Focussing initially on questions of

‘how’, we must first acknowledge that the process of becoming informed prior to

consenting is essentially an educational one. Thus the importance of incorporating

successful teaching, learning and communication strategies into strengthening

informed consent procedures seems a practical route to explore. Until now however,

the complexity of the cognitive processes involved in acquiring a reflective

understanding have been grossly under acknowledged in the ‘informing’ part of

bioethical practice. While the legal obligation of informed consent rests essentially

upon a minimal standard of information disclosure (Manson & O’Neil, 2007), the

fuller ethical obligation hinges upon a person having a contextually appropriate

understanding of the critical implications to them, of any testing entered into. As it

is this fuller account of reflective understanding that better fulfils the ethical

demands of ‘informed consent’, patient learning must be considered a critical

dimension to ethically robust intervention.

To date, there appears to be a limited awareness at either the practical or theoretical

levels of education being a fundamental pre-requisite to ethically robust care or of

the strong interdependence between ethically secure intervention and sound

educational practices. Thus the incorporation of appropriate educational

frameworks, of understanding the underlying nature of teaching and learning in

clinical care needs to be acknowledged as an essential rather than complementary or

optional feature of the ethical care. Understanding and promoting patient education

Page 32: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

32

in the clinic may therefore play a significant role in laying strong foundations for

facilitating ethical decision making for women.

Flowing from the observations above, the questions posed in this thesis are founded

on the combined observations that:

• Prenatal screening, with its invitation to judge which characteristics

are desirable in our future children, raises deeply complex and

sensitive ethical issues which strike at the heart of individual and

collective understandings of human being and becoming. Robust

ethical standards must therefore be applied to this increasingly

routine, but potentially ethically contentious, pregnancy intervention.

• While respecting patient autonomy through eliciting informed

consent is valuable in preserving individual capacity and diminishing

coercion or manipulation, current protocols as described in the

published literature appear to have significantly failed to support

patients in achieving a voluntary, understood and active participation

in medical interventions both generally, and in the specific case of

prenatal screening. The lack of informed consent does not

automatically suggest that the patients’ wishes have been violated

(Schneider, 1996); rather, it flags that the presumed ethical safeguard,

in its current actualisation, may be less effective than believed.

• Developing robust informed consent protocols to support the

humane, ethically inclusive and transparent use of prenatal screening

technology may require us to rethink the current individualistic,

legalistic and ethically reductionist approaches to consent. This will

require a reorientation of collective understandings of autonomy as

unencumbered individual choice, towards acknowledging autonomy

as deeply relationally embedded and constrained, socially

contextualised and subjectively interpreted. It also requires explicit

recognition of the multiple underlying social, personal, institutional

and philosophical constraints that impinge upon the practical

realisation of autonomy, consent and choice. If these obstacles are to

Page 33: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

33

be meaningfully addressed and minimised, they must first be openly

articulated.

• If informed consent is based upon patient understanding, any

commitment to strengthen informed consent protocols demands that

we address the question of ‘how’ to effectively inform. Furthermore,

we must remain cognisant that ‘what’ information becomes worthy of

informing is significantly pre-filtered through various cultural,

historical and institutional interpretive lenses. As becoming informed,

and gaining reflective understanding, is a process of learning, the

insights offered through educational philosophy and cognitive theory

may provide a suitable platform to strengthen informed consent. The

crucial ethical distinction between minimalist forms of information

disclosure and the fuller moral requirement of reflective

understanding of the personal implications of any proposed

intervention may then be supported within the organisational

infrastructures that women encounter during pregnancy.

• The ethical transformation of practice must be acknowledged as

occurring simultaneously at the individual and institutional levels, as

in reality they are interdependent, each partially defining,

constraining or supporting the other.

This thesis seeks to examine the deeply embedded social and ethical elements that

shape the burgeoning practice and unspoken presumptions that fuel our embrace of

prenatal testing. While the applications and inventions of this technology have been

described as a ‘new’ revolution, they are arguably influenced by some very old,

historically significant and deeply entrenched prejudices and practices. As collective

(mis) understandings of new technologies colonise our expectations of the controls

we can expect to impose on the human condition, the criteria of what is an

‘acceptable’ life, and ultimately the choices we make of what constitutes a suitable

body for our children to be born with permeate our judgements. Against a cultural

backdrop in which the value of individual choice is privileged, in which an unborn

Page 34: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

34

child has no recognised legal status 8F

9 and in which consumer demands infiltrate

individual and collective expectations of clinical care, careful consideration of how

and why such tests are developed, offered and accepted demands further reflection.

With respect to this study, as women and their unborn children are the sole

recipients of these prenatal interventions, this research seeks to illuminate how the

ethical dimensions of existing prenatal screening practices and procedures are

received specifically by women within this local cohort. As women’s experiences

may be critically shaped by the presumptions, prejudices and attitudes of their health

practitioners, the motivations, experiences and beliefs of a cohort of health care

providers will also be canvassed. Exploration of the actual experiences of both

groups, mothers and practitioners, may collectively illuminate some of the many

social, cultural, historical and philosophical roots that inform practice today, and

provide a more inclusive and coherent picture from which meaningful and practical

transformation may be forged.

As the underlying tenets of ‘informed consent’, voluntary and understood

participation, are broadly accepted as representing a high standard of ethical care in

medical practice, genuinely facilitating informed decision making remains a critical

concern in the practice of ethics across all forms of medical care. The implications

of this research, while situated primarily in the context of prenatal screening may

therefore add practical insights across numerous sites of medical intervention.

Research Questions and Scope

Based on the concerns outlined above, this thesis seeks to address the practical

question of how we may enhance ethical practice in prenatal screening, support

women’s (embedded) autonomy and facilitate their ethical choices when faced with

the invitation to engage in this increasingly routinised technological intervention in

9 Under the Queensland Criminal Code a charge of manslaughter may be brought for an action that causes the death of a foetus that would otherwise have been born alive. However, the harm from a legal perspective is to the mother, not the foetus. See discussion in Chapter 9.

Page 35: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

35

pregnancy. The structure of this research will build upon four key areas of

investigation.

The first area of research clarifies the nature and significance of the philosophical

concepts of respect for autonomy and ‘informed consent’ within biomedical

practice. Critical aspects of the rise of autonomy, the foundational presumptions of

selfhood and ontology inherent within the dominant understandings, and the

practical consequences of conflating autonomy with informed consent in medical

care will be considered.

The second area of investigation explores the emerging critical literature that

identifies problematic ethical issues inherent within current prenatal screening

practices that constrain, undermine and present barriers to women in exercising their

full moral agency in practice. Most of this research originating from the United

Kingdom, United States of America, Canada and Europe and flags numerous

personal, social and institutional constraints that impinge upon the authentic

achievement of ‘informed consent’ within existing protocols. This critical literature

exposes the evolution of a set of circumstances in which ‘routine’ screening

undermines voluntariness, in which poor understanding results from inadequate

explanation of procedures and illusionary notions of ‘choice’ are perpetuated in a

clinical setting where alternative choices are often not explicitly acknowledged or

offered (Bridle 2001; Jackson, 2000; Lippman, 1999a; Markens et al., 1999; Press &

Browner, 1997; Rapp, 2000; Santhalahti et al., 1998). While the five facets of

informed consent outlined previously9F

10 are assumed to be inherent within the

process of intervention, existing research reveals that although many women

conform to screening routines, their experiences suggest compliance rather than

active and understood informed consent. The reality of these routines may

potentially place women at an ethical disadvantage or risk of physical or

psychological harm.

These first two areas of research illuminate the broader social, cultural and historical

context within which the remainder of the research is based. Australia operates from

10 See p. 25.

Page 36: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

36

a similar Western, liberal, biomedical model of care observed in other countries

discussed throughout the literature review, therefore, it is likely that similar

problems as described above are present in various practice settings in Queensland.

However, the policies that guide such practice locally show no cognisance of the

problems flagged elsewhere and limited research of this nature has been undertaken

locally.

The third area of research will explore whether the observations made in overseas

research are apparent locally within Queensland health systems, to the extent that

they are articulated by members of this cohort. The insights offered by this cohort

will reveal aspects of local practice not previously known. Locally, women and

health practitioners will be invited to engage in dialogue about their experiences of

prenatal screening. Their individual experiences will be compared to and contrasted

with accounts contained in existing published literature. Through inviting individual

narratives, the lived experiences of individual participants in screening regimes

(mothers and health care professionals) were considered with the following

questions in mind.

1. Are the indicators of informed consent, outlined previously, met in

practice?

o Can participants explain the purpose and outcome of any

testing undertaken?

o How do women and practitioners view the voluntariness of

their participation in screening regimes?

o How do women and practitioners regard general levels of

understanding of the practical and ethical contours of such

intervention?

2. What barriers and constraints are identified, individually and

institutionally, as impinging upon the capacity to exercise full

autonomy and promote informed consent in the clinical context?

Page 37: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

37

3. If informed consent is critically linked to gaining appropriate levels

of reflective understanding, what educational opportunities are

accessible to promote this level of understanding in the antenatal

arena?

o Is the role of education being given adequate ethical

significance in antenatal care?

o What are the obstacles to educating or learning in this

context?

The fourth and final area of investigation will examine the potential contribution of

incorporating an educationally grounded response to the weaknesses observed based

on principles of educational philosophy and adult learning. Considerations of moral

choices made in the medical realm have been traditionally considered within

philosophical, social or medical frameworks. Some alternatives to these traditional

perspectives have been developed by feminist researchers for example, narrative

ethics (Tschudin, 2003), the expressive – collaborative model of ethical decision

making (Walker, 1998), or an ‘ethic of care’ (Gilligan, 1982). Currently there is

limited discussion in the published literature about what an educational paradigm

may offer in terms of strengthening the ethical dimensions of medical care. Hence,

this final piece of analysis offers a unique and key contribution to the wider

bioethics discussion. As informed consent forms the basis of ethical intervention

across all forms of medical research and clinical practice, the insights offered here

may contribute well beyond the narrow scope of the specific context of this research

and further contribute to the ongoing bioethical conversations regarding autonomy

and informed consent.

While existing research identifies many inherent limitations within existing

protocols, as yet few practical transformational frameworks to support informed

consent, based on understandings of relationally embedded autonomy have been

proposed. Accordingly, one outcome of this study will be to highlight the

importance of the educational to the ethical. A responsive educational framework

within a supportive organisational infrastructure that is sensitive to the particularities

Page 38: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

38

and constraints of the clinical environment might provide a basis for repairing,

reforming and redressing some of the ethical gaps identified.

Chapter Summary

Based on an initial literature review, it is suggested that the current response of

incorporating legally driven, administratively framed and ethically reductionist

informed consent protocols into existing routines has failed to create an

environment in which the individual and communal ethical concerns about the

potentially socially divisive or eugenic outcomes of prenatal screening technologies

may be meaningfully considered. Numerous overseas studies have revealed that,

while up to 90% of women in developed nations are believed to undergo some form

of prenatal screening to assess the health if their unborn child, significant numbers

do not understand the purpose or potential outcomes of the testing received. The

presumption that participation alone equates to informed consent, which in turn

assures ethical probity, is therefore flawed as the espoused ethical standards required

within the biomedical definitions of ‘informed consent’ of voluntariness and

reflective understanding seem to be rarely achieved in practice.

When the ethical principle of autonomy, realised through the exercising of informed

consent, is applied in a clinical and bureaucratic context that is unresponsive to, or

perhaps unaware of, the personal, institutional and social constraints that exist, a

persons’ capacity to engage fully in the moral decision making process may become

eroded. Indeed, entrenched modes of treatment may leave little room to examine

why certain interventions have become favoured or recommended at the expense of

other options, such as the option not to screen, an alternative which may remain

undisclosed (Pilnick, 2004). Inadequate educational opportunities coupled with the

lack of appropriate organisational infrastructure to support the deeply related,

situationally dependent and embedded process of decision making may therefore

undermine individual capacity to give considered and informed consent.

Additionally procedurally entrenched discriminatory attitudes towards disability

may promote narrowly defined constructions of normalcy that ultimately undermine

a patient’s capacity for full moral engagement and active decision making in the

context of prenatal screening. The subsequent harms which potentially flow on to

Page 39: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

39

women include avoidable anxiety, depression and possibly long term psychological

trauma (Goel, Glazier, Summers, & Holzapfel, 1998; Kowalcek, Muhlhoff,

Bachmann, & Gembruch, 2002; Watson, Hall, Langford, & Marteau, 2003). While

these factors have been alluded to in this introduction, a fuller exploration will be

undertaken in Section B of the thesis.

The objectives of this research are to explore the ethical dimensions of prenatal

screening interventions with a view to establishing whether the failures of informed

consent protocols to provide an ethical safeguard as observed overseas may be

present locally. A further aim is to unravel the multiple and complex interweaving

factors that underpin such failure and consider whether the insights offered through

established educational frameworks may offer an accessible way to strengthen

ethical protocols. Exploration of these issues from an intentionally multi-disciplinary

perspective with the goal of developing a broadly considered, coordinated and

inclusive transformational response is uncommon and largely absent from the

existing literature.

The predominant ethical considerations that emerge in the discussion of prenatal

screening often centre upon whether this technology is eugenic in its gaze (Asch &

Wasserman, 2005; Lippman, 2003; Parens & Asch, 2000), whether treatment offers

of termination are ethically contentious or whether this is yet another discriminatory

form of social gate keeping aimed at selecting what ‘type’ of people are worthy of

birth (Hubbard, 1988; Reinders, 2000; Shakespeare, 1998, 2001). These questions

certainly frame the broader context of why we as a society have pursued the

development of such technologies. We are increasingly challenged by the ethical

reality of balancing the indisputable goods that medical technology may offer

through the prevention of disease, with the very real potential harm that human life,

or potential human life, may be dehumanised, devalued and disrespected in the

process. As Kass (2003, p.3) notes ‘distinguishing well from bad thus intermixed is

often extremely difficult’. While embracing the ‘technological imperative’ may hold

great promise for the relief of pain and suffering, for improving quality of life, and

for enhancing choice and well being for many, the challenge remains of how to

promote the humane and ethical use of such technologies in ways that do not further

re-enforce discriminatory, stigmatizing or de-humanising practices. As the capacity

Page 40: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

40

to prenatally diagnose continues to outstrip the capacity to cure, a commitment to

openly reflect upon the inevitable ethical dissonance created will shape the ethical

landscape we create and the ethical legacy we leave.

The next chapter will outline the philosophical orientation of this work and offer a

foundational framework of ethical understanding and interpretation that underpins

the methodology used.

Page 41: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

41

CHAPTER 2

AN ETHICAL ORIENTATION – SITUATING ETHICAL UNDERSTANDINGS

Introduction

‘Ethicists tend to leave the ‘facts’ of clinical medicine to the doctors; their

task is then to apply elegant and compelling arguments drawn from first

principles of ethics to these undisputed and indisputable facts. Unfortunately

when the relationship between clinical medicine and ethics is conceived in

this way, the result is a very sterile discourse’ (Hoffmaster, 1991. p.213).

Prior to exploring the emergent ethical issues presented by the routine institutional

practice of prenatal screening, or considering the role of ethics in shaping a response

to the perceived moral challenges within, a clear account of ‘ethics’ as it is

understood for the purposes of this research must first be articulated.

According to Beauchamp and Childress (2001, p.1), ethics is best understood as a

‘generic term for various ways of understanding and examining moral life’. Within

these ‘various ways’ there are many conflicting and competing accounts of ‘ethics’

based on different starting presumptions, offering differing explanations of what

ethics is, how it ought to be practised and what its purpose and potential is. Clearly,

the starting presumptions, expectations and understandings we have of ‘ethics’

critically influence how we attempt to ‘do’ ethics, yet as Isaacs (Isaacs, 2003, p.3)

notes, the most fundamental question of ‘how ought one to understand ethics?’ is

largely unarticulated and simply taken for granted as a generally shared and

unproblematic view. However, as flagged by Beauchamp and Childress (2001, p.1)

above, ethics is not so simply categorised as one way of thinking, but rather

incorporates multiple perspectives and foundational assumptions.

Within the multiple definitions and prescriptions of what ethics is, the understanding

that arguably dominates the medical and bioethics literature is that of a ‘theory

centred’, knowledge based, abstract and generalisable application of moral

Page 42: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

42

principles. Such principles10F

11 or theories may be held as points of reflection and

guidance when considering ‘cases’ that present an ethical dilemma or quandary

(Beauchamp & Childress, 2001), and may be applied to reveal a consistent,

considered and rational response to the ethical question ‘what ought I do?’ 11F

12. While

this notion of ethics appears to have permeated collective understandings12F

13 and

expectations in the field of medical ethics and bioethics, deep problems emerge

when ethics is practised as an epistemological quest for moral knowledge and

abstract truth. Most notably perhaps, is the attendant need to reduce the multifaceted

and complex realities of ethical engagement to the sterile prescriptions of what

Caplan (1982, p.8) describes as ‘moral engineering’, an approach which seeks to

overlay moral theories and principles onto the (unproblematic) ‘facts’ to reveal a

dependable and generalisable moral truth.

A further criticism of practising ethics as a form of detached intellectual and

scholarly inquiry, is that this approach segregates ethics as yet another expert

specialty, beyond the grasp of clinicians and patients who often lack the prerequisite

analytical skills or philosophical language deemed necessary to contribute to such

specialised discussions (Komesaroff, 1995; Pellegrino, 2003). In an era of increasing

pressure to embrace collaborative decision making between practitioner and patient

and to implement more ‘patient-centred’ practices (Stewart et al., 2003),

perpetuating the separation of ‘ethics’ as another expert outsider discourse is

ultimately unsustainable, as it potentially distances and excludes practitioners and

patients from full participation in ethical decision making. This familiar approach to

ethics, while firmly entrenched, may seem remote and disconnected from the ‘micro

– ethical’ concerns (Komesaroff, 1995) of the everyday clinic, and hence continues

to attract criticism. The emerging role of the Clinical Ethicist in facilitating the

creation of open moral spaces in organisations, and equipping staff and patients to

11 In Australia, the most commonly referred to principles of medical ethics are those proposed by Beauchamp and Childress (2001); autonomy, beneficence, non- maleficence and justice. It should be noted that Beauchamp and Childress do not regard the four principles as coherent ‘theory’, or prescriptive requirement, but rather a framework to initiate broader contextualised discussion. While this ‘Georgetown mantra’, as it is often referred to, has been heavily critiqued in North America and Canada, it still permeates the majority of professional codes of practice and conduct, and dominates the medical ethics discourse in Australia. 12 It should be noted that the ‘I’ of medical ethics literature predominantly refers to the practitioner ‘I’, rarely the patient ‘I’(Dodds, 2000). 13 And notably numerous Australian health care professional Codes of Ethics.

Page 43: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

43

make morally informed decisions through education and creating appropriate policy

frameworks (Silverman, 2003, Walker,1998), is not yet well established in

Australian public health care but may be a future source of ethical organisational

reform.

An alternative philosophical framework to the detached, objective,

epistemologically centred approach to the ethical described above, an alternative

ontologically centred approach defines the ethical as situated within a foundational

framework of understanding that reflects the fundamentally social and relational,

subjective and engaged nature of human encounters. While the former approach

seeks to articulate those rational theories and principles that might anchor the ethical

form of life as one of rational deliberation and decision making, the latter

phenomenological account with its emphasis on acknowledging the hermeneutics of

making meaning, seeks to intentionally embrace the deeply embedded and

subjective nature of being that shapes individual moral decision making.

The latter account is grounded in the phenomenological or hermeneutic traditions

articulated by Martin Heidegger, Hans George Gadamer, Paul Ricoeur and Maurice

Merleau-Ponty. However, the phenomenological foundations may be further

informed and extended by a rich diversity of influences and contributions on which

fuller, contextualised ethical understandings are built. The understanding of ethics as

a relational, subjective, dialogical, and power directing encounter, incorporates

insights from many quarters enriched by the work of scholars across a range of

academic traditions. The insights of phenomenologists mentioned above permeate

this stance, as does the work of English speaking philosophers such as Charles

Taylor and Stephen Toulmin. Identity and narrative scholars such as Jerome Bruner

and Hilde Lindeman, and feminist philosophers such as Susan Sherwin, Rosemary

Tong, Margaret Urban Walker, and Carol Gilligan also contribute in significant

ways to enrich an account of an engaged ethics. (Abbey, 2004; Bruner, 1986, 1991;

Gilligan, 1982; Lindemann-Nelson, 2001; Priest, 1998; Taylor, 1988, 1989; Tong,

1998; Toulmin, 1990; Walker, 1993, 1998, 2003).

Page 44: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

44

The relational, embedded approach to ethics that will be embraced in this work is

therefore not the detached, discursive or observational account founded in modern

analytical philosophy, but rather an expressive, engaged, situated and transformative

account. Once we embrace the particular ontology of the self as related, dialogical,

interpretative, and embedded in multiple contexts of history, culture, language,

relationships, biology, time and spiritual horizons it becomes apparent that, while

there may be shared moral frameworks, each individual has a unique and particular

moral experience. The unique culmination of these layers of embeddedness shape

individual moral frameworks for patient and practitioner alike and subsequently

defines the plurality of ‘goods’ we affirm. It is the fusion of these multiple goods

that determines how we interpret the ethical significance and meaning of life events.

While strong individual moral frameworks are formed, these inextricably overlap

with the shared social and moral space. It is therefore through accessing these

multiple layers that fuller ethical understandings may be built and transformative

ethical response may be forged at both the individual and societal levels.

A workable applied ethics research framework that incorporates the multiple voices

above is offered by Isaacs and Massey (1994), who propose that engaged ethical

encounters have four dimensions; the appreciative, the appraisive, the hermeneutical

(interpretive) and the transformative. While traditional philosophical approaches

seek theoretical solutions, Isaacs and Massey (ibid) propose that applied ethical

questions are invariably social, not solely intellectual, and therefore invite practical,

not solely theoretical responses. Through embracing the four dimensions above the

ethical question considered becomes ‘how can we respond?’, rather than the

detached individualistic ‘what ought I do?’ that emerges from the analytical model.

As perceptions and judgements are not value free, but rather reflect prior

contextualised understandings and experiences, the hermeneutical dimension invites

us to develop understanding of the multiple interpretive lenses that each stakeholder

brings. The appreciative dimension seeks to promote appreciation of each

stakeholder by actively recognising the others’ humanity, dignity and unique

presence. Isaacs and Massey (ibid) further note that it does not automatically follow

that we agree with, or endorse, every perspective. Rather the aim of any human

Page 45: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

45

encounter is to appreciate and understand the multiple histories that shape it. The

appraisive dimension recognises that ethical engagement ultimately involves

judgement or evaluation. Finally, the transformative dimension calls upon us to take

action to prevent the unethical and respond with strategies for reform from an

informed position of appreciation and understanding. Thus applied ethics research is

focused on ‘continuing enhancing of the other and the self within the social

condition as it is actualised within specific situations, roles, practices, institutions

and cultures’ (ibid, p.2). The applied ethics framework proposed by Isaacs and

Massey (1994) thus provides a theoretically coherent and practically functional

structure from which to explore, describe, understand, explain and potentially

transform the ethical dimensions of clinical practice, in this case the particular

practice of prenatal screening.

In applied ethics research such as this, if we hope to understand individual moral

concerns and respond in a meaningful way, the importance of entering into dialogue

with another as a way of appreciating their unique perspective becomes paramount.

Hence, there is a critical link between the embedded, embodied, related and

dialogical view of ontology offered by the phenomenologists and the importance of

narrative as means of opening the moral space of shared understanding that

underpins ethical care. As narrative invites us to enter and appreciate each other’s

understandings, conversation and dialogue provides an appropriate entry portal into

the world of another’s experience and knowledge. Charles Taylor (1989, p.38)

further explains, ‘the nature of our language and the fundamental dependence of our

thought on language makes interlocution in one or other of these forms inescapable

for us’. The philosophical orientation adopted therefore supports a narrative research

methodology as the most appropriate mode of ethical inquiry. As the aims of this

research were not only to observe and describe, but rather to understand with a view

to transform, the Isaacs and Massey (1994) engaged approach to ethics, coupled

with a narrative method of inquiry is the most appropriate vehicle to critically

explore the complex, subjective and intersubjective factors which shape the ethical

dimensions of prenatal screening.

Page 46: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

46

If, as Arthur Caplan remarks, ‘the resolution of moral issues demands more than the

ability to marry moral theory with the facts’ (Caplan, 1982, p.2), we must challenge

ourselves to define and actualise the ‘more’ Caplan refers to. An approach to ethics

such as that proposed by Isaacs and Massey (1994) above recognises that

interdependence and interconnectedness, as well as detached academic analysis, is

both the starting point and the goal of any ethical conversation. As ‘the individual

is whole only in a world of others’ (Cassell, 1991, p.26), an ethical framework that is

founded on this most basic human understanding may provide a more resonant and

accessible framework from which to respond to the shared ethical consequences of

individual and communal choices.

Comparing Ethical Perspectives

Ethics as Epistemology and Ways of Rational Knowing

‘Someone familiar with moral concepts and with moral judgements, who has

ample time to gather information and to think about it, may reasonably be

expected to reach a soundly based conclusion more often than someone who

is unfamiliar with moral concepts and moral arguments and has little time’

(Singer, 1972 cited by Caplan, 1982, p.7).

The most commonly accepted and practised view of ethics according to Margaret

Urban Walker (1993, 1998), reflected in Peter Singer’s comments above, is the

familiar account of ethics as articulating the logically determined ‘right’ or ‘best’

theory, in response to a particular set of circumstances. Under this modern

philosophical account, ethics is understood as the mastery of epistemic foundations

of theory to provide rational argument in determining the relative merits, limitations

and applications of such theory. Within this framework, the moral dimensions of life

do not flow from a comprehensive, reasoned, or personally reflective account of

morality, but rather, as Walker (1993, p.33) explains

‘On this dominant modern view, proper moral theory is instead a highly

specific kind of account of where moral judgments come from: a compact

code of very general (law like) principles or procedures which, when applied

Page 47: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

47

to cases appropriately described, yield impersonally justified judgments

about what any moral agent in such a case should do. Invocations of theory

and principles in practical medical ethics have tended to reproduce this

conception’.

Flowing from a modernist account based on rational thought and abstract reason,

such theories may be methodically applied in providing consistent answers to the

ethical question “what ought I do”. A consequence of this epistemologically oriented

ethics that seems to dominate much of the medical and bioethics literature is that the

critical questions of ethics have become largely knowledge based, framed as

intellectual problems, and considered in the technical realm of experts. While ethical

problems are arguably more intimately shaped by the social context from which they

emerge, the goal of a theory centred, rationally driven ethics is to decontextualise

such problems, to get to the uncluttered intellectual and unchangeable core of the

problem. However, as Leon Kass (2002, p.63) explains,

‘when rational problem solving solves ethical problems, the solutions

themselves tend to be purely rational, often taking the form either of rules

or of ideals – rational rules that should govern conduct; articulable ideals

toward which practice should strive. Not addressed are moral sensibilities

and affections or habits and customs of moral agents’.

This rational, epistemologically oriented gaze which permeates so many prominent

schools of ethical thought including deontology, utilitarianism and arguably

principlism that dominates much of the ethical discourse will be considered in more

depth.

Beauchamp and Childress (2001), authors of the widely embraced approach to ethics

known as ‘principlism’, describe ‘normative’ ethics as the consideration of ethical

theory, principle and argument which forms a prescriptive guide to moral behaviour.

Within much of the biomedical ethics literature this normative approach regards

ethics as the application of critical philosophical reflection to those problems,

dilemmas and quandaries that are created by medical intervention (or in some cases

the with-holding of intervention). ‘Doing’ ethics under this framework becomes an

exercise in engaging with a long established critical, intellectual and scholarly

Page 48: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

48

inquiry that can be best described as a sub branch of moral analytical philosophy.

Tacitly, this account implies that the unethical predominantly arises from a lack of

appropriate critical reasoning or the absence of rational thought (Isaacs, 2001).

While Beauchamp cautions that principles are a ‘useful but not canonical

framework for health care ethics’ (Beauchamp, 1999, p.148), the ease with which

these four ethical principles are translated into easily accessible, reductionist and

prescriptive ‘rules’ have led to their broad acceptance by practitioners (Pullman,

2005), leading Clouser and Gert (1999, p.156) to describe principlism as an

emerging, though unhelpful, ‘mantra’ or ‘ritual incantation’ in medical care.

Historically, the privileging of rational thought and epistemic knowledge as the

ultimate source of moral wisdom and authority emerged from the period of

modernity. Stephen Toulmin (1991) traces the roots of this commitment to

rationality from its emergence in the mid 1600’s through the philosophy of Rene

Descartes13F

14 , later cemented during the Renaissance through the work of Immanuel

Kant in the late 1700’s. Both philosophers essentially shifted from the humanist

understandings of ‘pre-modern’ times which accommodated plurality and

ambiguity, towards a commitment to the rational method of inquiry as a means of

securing intellectual certainty and harmony (ibid, p.9).

This critical shift in collective thinking, Toulmin (1991) argues, saw fundamental

changes in attitudes to four practical kinds of knowledge which transformed the face

of philosophy. These changes were: the elevation of the written word above the

spoken; the rejection of particular considerations in favour of universal ‘truths’; the

subjugation of localised knowledge in favour of the generalisable and finally;

rejection of contextually laden ‘timely’ understandings in search of timeless truths in

the quest to bring permanency and predictability to the changeable and unpredictable

human condition (ibid, p.30-34). The consequence of these shifts Toulmin argues is

that ‘practical philosophy’ became usurped and replaced by a sanitised and detached

14 In extending Euclid’s (300 BCE) mathematical ‘more geometrico’, Descartes proposed that all forms of knowledge, including philosophical knowledge could be derived from a clear, distinct and indubitable starting point, which he determined was the ‘cogito’. From this certain starting point, the phrase, ‘cogito ergo sum’, or ‘I think therefore I am’ emerged. The privileged mode of enquiry, and thus the privileged forms of knowledge consequently became those which derived from the logic and rational modes of enquiry inherent within, and required by, Euclid’s geometrical method.

Page 49: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

49

form of abstract theoretical philosophy, the residue of which can be seen permeating

many aspects of medical ethics protocols today.

Interestingly, proponents of this dominant account rarely address whether

decontextualised rational considerations of the correct principles and theories are

indeed the ultimately appropriate mode of exploring or articulating the moral life.

Even Clouser and Gert (1999), whom Beauchamp credits with the ‘most sustained

and best argued attack’ (Beauchamp, 1999, p.151) on principlism, do not question

the ultimate privileging of rationality as a shortcoming. Rather, they focus on the

internal systematic inadequacies as the major flaw, exposing logical inconsistencies

within the approach but do not question either the reliance on logical theory to

consider the presumably unproblematic facts, or the potentially flawed inherent

ontological assumptions as potential weaknesses.

Thus the elevation of rationality and reason as the hypergood defining the ethical, as

opposed to considering reason as one of a plurality of goods marks the critical point

of divergence for those who seek to challenge this dominant conception of ethics as

an epistemological, theory based discourse (Taylor, 1989). MacIntyre (1984) further

claims that rationality itself is not necessarily an unchangeable fact, noting that we

must be open to the question of ‘whose’ conception of rationality is privileged in

any situation. Often, as Toulmin (1990, p.30) acknowledges, there is no ‘rational’

way to convert others to an alternative point of view. However, we cannot sustain

ignorance or dismissal of such disagreements. Rather we need an ethical framework

which accommodates a diversity of views in a spirit of tolerance. Yet the quest for

certainty in moral reasoning seems to have diminished our capacity and commitment

to achieve this creating a further barrier to those who seek to contest the rationalist

view, to re-humanise and re-contextualise ethical deliberation.

Hoffmaster (2006, p. 43) further critiques the privileging of rationality saying,

‘in this tradition of moral philosophy [according to Kant], rationality gives

human beings their unique moral status and their incomparable human

worth. Human beings are rational, but human beings also have bodies and

Page 50: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

50

because they have bodies, they are vulnerable. In fact vulnerability is an

even more basic feature of our human constitution than rationality, because

while all human beings are vulnerable, not all are rational or even possess

the potential to become rational…………it is our very vulnerability that

creates the need for morality.’

Thus Hoffmaster concludes,

‘Vulnerability marks the limits of individualism, but the ethos of

individualism doggedly refuses to acknowledge those limits and instead

construes vulnerability to fit its assumptions and goals’ (Hoffmaster, 2006,

p.43).

As alluded to already, there are many criticisms of the dominant view of ethics, most

notably its tendency to reduce the muddy and complex realities of ethical

engagement to the ‘sterile discourse’ identified by Hoffmaster (1991, p.213). In the

quest for universal moral truth, critics of traditional philosophy claim there has been

a temptation to downplay the unique features of each case, as Toulmin (1990, p.210)

explains,

‘the axioms of modernity assumed that the surface complexity of nature and

humanity distracts us from an underlying Order which is intrinsically simple

and permanent’.

However, as experience tells us, the ‘intrinsically simple’ exists only to a limited

degree. Toulmin continues,

‘We may temporarily shelve the contexts of our problems, but, eventually,

their complete resolution obliges us to put these calculations back into their

larger human frame, with all its concrete features and complexities’.

Rather than viewing moral tension as being shaped by the socio-political context,

the dominant account of ethics instead seeks to place narrow boundaries around

Page 51: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

51

what can be considered as legitimate ethical discourse, often reducing a complex

ethical question to the easier ‘medical problem’. In the case of prenatal screening for

example, the deeply complex social, personal and political issues of how we as a

society should care for people with disabilities becomes framed in the reductionist

language of individual choice, of an individual’s right to access or refuse screening

or to further exercise their autonomous choice to terminate or accept their disabled

child. Again, this approach sidelines the specific inherited problems and interpretive

lenses that medical practice has accumulated through its social, historical and

political development and superimposes philosophy onto medical practice without

considering that medicine is itself a ‘special kind of human activity’ (Pellegrino,

2003, p.5). By presuming certain choices are more palatable and rational than others,

by shaping which options are made accessible, by framing ethical decisions in

technical or medical language rather than ‘moral’ language, the social, political, and

cultural subjectivities of the individual participants who relate to each other within

the institutionalised practice of medicine may become silenced. The intrinsic and

extrinsic factors that constrain autonomy and choice, such as, access to care in a

business model of health care delivery, the cost benefit analysis that supports the

routine imposition of screening, the obvious hierarchical and institutional power

dynamics, entrenched societal views of technology as irrefutably good (yet as

Newell (2003) notes paradoxically defended as ‘neutral’), and persistent culturally

entrenched stereotypes of disability as tragedy, are just a few of the many real

influences that the dominant view of ethics may need to discount to reach the belief

in attaining a rationally derived and generalisable moral truth.

In rejecting the ‘engineering model14F

15’ of ethical engagement, Urban-Walker (1993)

claims that the often disappointing and inadequate moral debates generated from

such engagements are inevitable when ethics is practised as the consistent

application of intellectually derived code-like and universal theories. If faith in

systematically applied reason to deliver repeatable and universalisable ethical

outcomes is to be upheld, pressure to dismiss potentially complicating details is

inevitably created (Walker, 1993, p.35), and increasingly thin deliberations

15 See Arthur Caplan (1982). Mechanics on duty: The limitations of a technical definition of moral expertise for work in applied ethics. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Supplementary Volume 8. p.1-18.

Page 52: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

52

masquerade as robust moral debate. However, when context is not given sufficient

weight, consideration of the critical role that context plays in shaping the ethical

terrain and how individuals ascribe moral meaning are also lost.

Notably individualistic in its stance, posing the question ‘what ought I do?’,

problems are routinely presented as atomistic, detached and requiring a rationally

considered response. Although not always clearly articulated, the implicit

presumption of the traditional stance is that the ‘I’ considering the dilemma is the

practitioner or expert who is deciding the moral course for the patient (Dodds, 2000;

Donchin, 2001). As the required mastery of ethical theory often lies beyond the

realm of most patients and many practitioners who lack the expertise to decipher the

philosophical complexities required to reach an expert moral opinion (Komesaroff,

1995) the ethical has perhaps unwittingly become the tool through which patients

are further alienated from collaborating in decisions about their care. The paradox

here is that, while the Modernity project emerged as a revolt against ignorance,

exploitation and oppression, and sought to foster autonomy, freedom and equality,

the prevalent frameworks of bioethics may have unwittingly been instrumental in

closing down discussion of the pressing ‘micro-ethical’ concerns of daily clinical

care, of excluding those it sought to empower.

Although not specifically articulated, the ontology of the human self perpetuated

through the dominant mode of ethical engagement situates persons as primarily

detached rational thinkers, seeking a pure form of knowledge in answer to the

question ‘what ought I do’? , while failing to ask the question ‘what is it good to

be?’ (Taylor, 1988). Urban-Walker (1998) expands this point noting that, in her

opinion, this mode of ethical understanding positions human beings as purely

rational decision makers, whose decisions are by definition unencumbered by

emotions, relationships, social expectations or cultural frameworks of interpretation.

However, as Merleau-Ponty (cited by Priest, 1998) and Lakoff and Jackson (1999)

claim, in the first instance human beings experience and perceive the world as

embodied actors or doers. Embedded in a complex web of relationships, practices,

institutions and cultures that shape our subjective, interpretive frameworks, these

relational considerations are the ones that ultimately shape the meaning of the ‘good

life’ (Isaacs, 2007). Therefore, living an ethical life is not only achieved through

Page 53: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

53

rational deliberation, although this may form part of how we ascribe order and

meaning, but rather is realised within the possibilities and limitations of our

embedded, embodied reality. Indeed, as Slovic, Finucane, Peters and MacGregor

(2004) observe, human decision making is simultaneously interpreted along the

parallel, and co-occurring lines of an immediate, affective experiential way of

knowing and a slower analytical system. However, in analytical philosophy, the

rational appears to have become privileged at the expense of the experiential or

emotional, leading Isaacs (ibid, p.3) to conclude, ‘whatever kind of being the

modernist self might be as detached, individualistic, reflective and purely rational, it

could be argued that it is not a human self; it is not a self that reflects the kinds of

beings we humans are’.

Analytical Philosophy and Science: Expert Outsiders Mutually Reinforcing the

Technological Imperative.

‘Old time progressive politics rested on a long term faith that science is the

proven road to human health and welfare, and this faith shaped the

technological agenda for half a dozen world fairs. This dream still carries

conviction for many people today: what underlies their continued trust in

science and industry is their commitment to the conception of ‘rationality’

that was established among European natural philosophers in the 17th

Century and promised intellectual certainty and harmony’ (Toulmin, 1990,

p.9).

That the analytical philosophical approach struggles to provide a practical

framework to respond to the ethical concerns emerging from technological progress

is perhaps not surprising when we consider the historical genesis of both disciplines.

While medicine, which is strongly influenced by the norms and conventions of

science (Pellegrino, 2003), and analytical philosophy may be viewed as occupying

very different perspectives on first glance, closer examination reveals that they have

much in common. In addition to being essentially academic endeavours that are

colonised by experts, science and philosophy have shared origins in the period of

Modernity. In tandem with developments in the quest for moral certainty emerging

Page 54: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

54

from the philosophy of Descartes’ disengaged reason and Locke’s notions of a

punctual, objectified self 15F

16, developments in understanding the natural world

through rational inquiry and a commitment to logical explanations, away from the

religious and mystical interpretations, also began to take hold through the scientific

endeavours of Galileo and Newton. This foundational shift in thinking from the

religious, and experiential, to the objective and the logical, laid the foundations for

scientific- technological culture that dominates today, privileging objective, rational

and detached theoretical ways of knowing over subjective, embedded and

interpretive ways of knowing. Hence both philosophy and science share a

commitment to the systematic and rational explanation of the human condition

(Toulmin, 1990, p.9). Science is predominantly rationalist, and the dominant

paradigm in ethics is also rationalist (McKie & Gass, 2001).

It is precisely this shared origin of science and analytical philosophy, with a mutual

commitment to the elevation of universal, abstract and decontextualised knowledge,

that makes the dominant account of ethics as described above an inappropriate

framework to foster critical moral debate in medicine because it is premised on the

exclusion of pluralistic ways of knowing. In framing the ethical question in a

skeletal and decontextualised way, the dominant analytical bioethical approach is

fundamentally incapable of countering the biomedical gaze of science as it

ultimately shares the same ontologically flawed values framework.

The foundational commitment to science on which medicine is based invites

practitioners to believe in restoration to wholeness, with technology being the

dominant means through which to counter imperfection. Clearly technological

advances in medicine have brought significant gains to our understandings of the

human condition and overall health, making substantial contributions to human

wellness and wellbeing. Notable examples include the control of infectious diseases,

mass immunisation, reduced infant mortality, higher life expectancy and so on.

However, these gains have been accompanied by an increasing disposition to regard

the body as an object with science being the culturally iconic lens through which we

interpret bodily ‘malfunctions’. The gaze of technology, with its focus on the ‘body

16 See Taylor 1989, pp.143-176.

Page 55: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

55

object’ as a malfunctioning machine, has seductively invited us to redefine our

understandings of what a suitable body is, and through the recruitment of prenatal

and genetic screening has subtly altered our expectations about what constitutes a

suitable body for our children to be born into.

Kass (2002, p.17) notes that ‘not all human dignity consists of reason or freedom’,

but proposes that the source of human dignity is the shared acknowledgment and

appreciation of the undeniable particularities of each person. Therefore, an

alternative ethical response that embraces the contextual characteristics in which

ethical decision making occurs and accommodates the relational, social, cultural and

historical embeddedness of such decisions is sought. Such an account must also

accommodate the realities of medical practice as firmly situated in the personal oral

account, embedded in the concrete and the local, and strongly set in the here and

now. Kass (ibid, p.73) further invites us to ‘think less about doctrine and principles

and the rules to govern behaviour, more about education and institutions and what

sort of people we produce’.

While much first world bioethics appears to centre on respect for autonomy,

safeguarding it against imposed violations of human will, Kass (2003, p.5) argues

that the ethical and moral dangers of unreflective technological progress arise not

from coercion and the imposition of foreign values, but rather from embracing the

firmly held values central to our post-modern way of thinking. Cultural reverence to

technological progress, privileging the economic and commercial drivers of health

care, the cultural canon of individual choice as moral arbiter, and acquiescence to

the inevitability of progress and its consequences (even if we view them with some

trepidation), are some examples of what Kass (2003, pp. 38-49) cautions us to be

wary of. Therefore we must strive to find a balance between potentially unbridled

‘scientism’ and the practical wisdom we need to cultivate and moderate the humane

realisation of the many goods both promised and delivered by technological

advances.

Page 56: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

56

Ethics as Embedded and Transformative - Re-humanising and Re-contextualising

the Ethical Agenda

‘We can reconcile the twin legacies of the exact sciences and the humanities

only by a change in direction; and for that we must first see clearly how the

agenda of modern thought over reached itself. By now, it will be clear that

we need to balance the hope for certainty and clarity in theory with the

impossibility of avoiding uncertainty and ambiguity in practice ’(Toulmin,

1990, p.175).

‘Medicine being simultaneously the scientific and humanistic study of man

cannot escape being based in an explicit or implicit philosophy of human

nature’ (Pellegrino, 2003, p.10).

Ultimately, the medical condition is embedded in the human condition and while

moral concepts, principles, and arguments may be appropriate anchor points from

which to direct and guide ethical conversations (Beauchamp, 1999; Pullman, 2005;

Walker, 1993), such principles form only part of the whole ethical conversation, a

conversation which rightfully begins and ends with the deeply contextualised

relational encounters between staff, patients and the organisation (Beauchamp, 1999;

Pullman, 2005; Walker, 1993).

If as Toulmin (1990) believes, philosophy has found itself ‘sidetracked’ by the

dominant rational mode of inquiry, and if the underlying cause of this detour is a

fundamentally flawed account of ontology or being (Isaacs, 2007; Taylor, 1988,

1989; Walker, 2003), our initial task in articulating a different way of doing ethics is

to give a more appropriate account of the ontology of the self. Experience illustrates

that moral understandings are always interpreted and deeply embedded in a

particular time, history and context, all of which creates a unique, not universal,

basis of meaning. Rather than being externally imposed upon the human condition,

moral understandings emerge and radiate outwards from the human condition.

Acceptance of these realities must form the bedrock of any ethical framework

Page 57: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

57

adopted. Therefore, recovering a more appropriate view of ontology is a critical

initial step in articulating a more responsive ethical framework.

Recovering Ontology at the Core of Medical Ethics

Unlike the disengaged, rational and analytical self portrayed in the dominant model

of philosophy and perpetuated in science, Taylor (1989) suggests that the human self

is rather an actor or doer, projected into a complex world in which they seek to make

and find meaning. Capable of interpreting their world and their place in it, human

beings are also capable of creating and re-creating, interpreting and re-interpreting

both themselves and others. Therefore, a unique aspect of the human life is the

capacity to change, grow and become. An individual’s moral knowledge may be

considered not to be static or completely objective, but constantly evolving and

subjectively interpreted. The key failings of the dominant approach may be

summarised as follows:-

• It promotes an overly individualistic and detached view of human

ontology which fails to recognise the situated, interconnected and

engaged nature of human being and becoming (Isaacs, 2007, p.3).

• It entrenches a flawed ‘decisional’ rather than relational approach to

interpreting the moral. In accentuating ethics as a decisional process,

other significant features such as the particular, individual and

conditionalised nature of the good life may become overlooked.

• It falsely elevates the singular value of rationality to that of a

hegemonic ‘hyper good’ when for most people, the good and morally

coherent life is constituted by the fusion of a plurality of goods

(Taylor, 1989). Such goods are socially created and accessed and are

dependent upon a particular time and context that may not exist

independently of this context.

• It provides an inadequate account of the subjective and interpretive

nature of individual morality.

Page 58: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

58

Recovering a more appropriate ontological basis is therefore a critical initial step in

promoting a more responsive ethical framework in health care. As previously

suggested, such an account may be found in the phenomenological philosophical

tradition, the key features of which Isaacs (2003) summarises as follows:

• The human self is not primarily a reflective thinker but an actor or doer,

projected into a complex world, seeking to find meaning.

• The human self is embodied, hence the lived experiences of each person is

significantly mediated through the embodied nature of their being (Lakoff &

Johnson, 1999). This reality has ethical implications in understanding how

physical illness and medical intervention ‘to’, or ‘on’, the body impact

holistically upon personal ethical wellbeing.

• The human self is embedded in the world on multiple levels, these being:

(i) in a natural world, physically, spatially and biologically.

(ii) in a social world of multiple relationships, cultures, politics,

economies, histories, nations and communities all of which shape

moral understanding and identity.

(iii) in a temporal space with strong notions of past (history and memory),

present and future (imaginations and possibilities).

(iv) in language that mediates our relationships with others, our

understandings, shapes our identities and allows us to articulate our

future becoming

(v) in a spiritual horizon that gives direction and meaning to life.

• Human beings have the capacity to be and become, to interpret continuously

both themselves and their place in the world.

Isaacs and Massey (1994, p.2) further suggest that ‘the overall point or purpose of

applied ethics is practical and involves creating and sustaining relationships which

mutually recognise the needs, interests and aspirations of all participants

(stakeholders) as “ends in themselves”’. Ethical encounters are therefore rarely the

Page 59: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

59

result of the external application of abstract philosophical reason upon the human

condition, but rather emerge and radiate outwards and upwards from the human

condition.

An Applied Ethics Framework for Research

Unlike traditional narrow philosophical frameworks, the ethical framework that

underpins this research is inclusive and multidisciplinary, incorporating a range of

complementary and interwoven understandings. This responsive style of ethical

analysis articulated by Isaacs and Massey (1994) describes ethics as primarily a

question of understanding and transforming human actions and practices. Therefore,

as a transformative approach, the features of ethical encounters may be defined as

follows:-

• Ethics transforms the human condition

• Such transformations are first achieved through self transformation

• Ethics has a social and relational dimension

• Ethics acknowledges personal interpretive frames, i.e. persons are

‘conditionalised’

• Ethics involves agency and power, hence ethics has a political and economic

dimension

• Ethical encounters occur in relationships and culture that are shaped by

history, so ethical engagement is also ‘historicised’.

(Isaacs, 2001; Isaacs & Massey, 1994)

As flagged earlier, a sensitive and practical framework for applied ethics research

that incorporates the multiple understandings discussed above has been proposed by

Isaacs and Massey (1994). In considering the ethical, Isaacs and Massey proposed

that four inter-related dimensions of the ethical encounter must be attended to. These

are posited as the appreciative, the appraisive, the hermeneutical (interpretive) and

the transformative. While philosophical approaches often seek theoretical solutions,

Isaacs and Massey (ibid) propose that applied ethical questions are principally social

(not solely intellectual), and therefore invite primarily practical (not only theoretical)

Page 60: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

60

responses. Thus the focus of an engaged, relational and transformative ethics

framework facilitates ‘the continued enhancement and flourishing of both self and

other, within the lived reality of particular human relationships, practices and

institutions’ and seeks to create a practical outcome which is respectful of all

participants (Isaacs & Massey, 1994, p.2). It is thus a framework that sensitively

captures the social and intellectual, the particularities and commonalities of human

encounters.

In attending to the hermeneutical dimension, we are challenged to comprehend what

is really happening, to elicit the complex and multilayered understandings each

participant brings, to unearth the underlying assumptions and limits of individual

perspectives. As perceptions and judgements are not value free, but rather reflect

prior understandings and experiences, the hermeneutical dimension invites us to

develop awareness and appreciation of the multiple, compounding, and perhaps

contradictory, interpretive lenses through which each stakeholder interprets the

ethical. In actively attending to the hermeneutical Isaacs (1998, p.9) explains,

‘ ..there is a need to disclose the initial understandings brought by the

participants to the encounter; there is a need to explore the assumptions and

limits to such understandings; there is need to consider which interpretations

seek to claim hegemony and the basis for such claim; and there is a need to

consider the extent to which a proposed understanding meets the conditions

of inclusiveness and situational “fittingness”’.

The hermeneutic further focuses our attention on the situational; the dynamic

interactions between participants and their contexts or situations. Awareness of the

mutual interaction between a person and their environment is highly pertinent to this

research as ethical decision making in clinical care is pursued within the constraints

of our embedded, embodied reality. It is also clearly constrained by its situatedness

within an institutionalised paradigm of medical practice that may inhibit or deny a

person ability to explore their preferred choices. Therefore, if the purpose of this

research is to articulate ways to support ethical decision making, and create ethically

robust practices within ethically sound organisational infrastructures, we need first

Page 61: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

61

to understand the situational factors that restrict our capacity to achieve this. Thus,

the hermeneutic invites us to embrace the particular, contextual approach to moral

reasoning, to illuminate critical understanding of which factors are shaping the

human condition and, hence, the ethical condition embedded in it. As ethical

encounters happen between people, applied ethics research must embrace the

pluralities of how individuals interpret a given situation. In terms of this research,

exploring the hermeneutic dimension was achieved through individual conversations

with each of the participants. Through the exploration of these individual accounts,

and exploring their links to the broader contexts in which they are embedded, a

fuller understanding of how the practice is received by women and offered by

practitioners may be elicited, providing a stronger basis from which ethical decision

making may be supported clinically.

The appreciative dimension calls upon us to approach each ethical encounter with

an attitudinal disposition of appreciation, care and concern. As Isaacs (2003) notes,

the decision to take an appreciative stance, or dispositional interest, compels us to

actively recognise another’s humanity, dignity and unique presence. In doing so we

are enabled in our ability to relate to another’s complexity, particularity and unique

humanity. In addition to considering where others stand in relation to ‘the good’,

attending in an appreciative way also consciously calls us to appreciate where we

stand in relation to them, initiating the ethical encounter from a stance which

acknowledges our shared humanity. Such willingness to enable the other to reveal

themselves deeply rather than superficially reduces ‘strangeness’ and opens a shared

moral space. In terms of this research, in attending to the appreciative dimension, I

sought to understand the stories of the participants within the broader personal,

social, political, economic, historical and institutional contexts that gave shape and

situational meaning to their individual account.

The next dimension of ethical engagement advocated by Isaacs and Massey (1994)

is consideration of the appraisive dimension which recognises that ethical

engagement ultimately involves some sort of judgement or evaluation. In

considering the literature surrounding the social and ethical aspects of prenatal

screening the appraisive question for this research was initially ‘Is the biomedical

Page 62: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

62

response to the ethical concerns about prenatal screening responsive to the concerns

of stakeholders?’ In researching the existing literature, and incorporating the

individual experiences of research participants, further appraisals were being invited,

i.e. if current ethical protocols are lacking in some way, ought we respond to restore,

broaden and strengthen these protocols? If women are not being supported to reach

an informed understanding regarding the use of this technology, what barriers exist?

Can these barriers be overcome, or even should they be overcome? Do we

communally value informed decision making for patients in medical care and if so

what lengths should we go to in order to ensure its realisation? In answering these

questions, we are brought to the fourth and final dimension of Isaacs and Massey’s

(1994) applied ethics framework, the transformative.

The transformative dimension calls upon us to respond to the unethical with

strategies for reform, from a position of informed appreciation and understanding.

While understanding and appreciating a situation are necessary preconditions for

effective change, these insights alone do not suggest ‘how’ change should be

effected. Therefore the transformative dimension invites to us forge a practical

response mindful of the existing limitations of organisational and individual

priorities and resources that dictate which transformations are achievable. Isaacs and

Massey (1994) further acknowledge that the processes of change can often be

embedded in resistant cultures, hence,

‘Where the ethical situation is symptomatic of entrenched social practices,

institutional settings or hegemonic cultures, strategies of a more

comprehensive kind such as critical social inquiry, education, policy

formation, legislation, or social action may be more appropriate’ (ibid,

p.12).

Thus in addition to individual transformation, organisational reform at the macro

level of legislation or policy reform may be called for. Potential transformative

responses to this study are more thoroughly discussed in Chapter Ten.

Page 63: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

63

Clearly these four dimensions are not realised in a hierarchal or linear way, but must

be considered simultaneously, as each informs the other. They are interconnecting

threads that weave in and around each other in a dynamic fashion. Therefore, the

unique strength of this multifaceted framework is its capacity to respond to the

diverse and complex moral, social and educational issues that emerge from

multidisciplinary research such as this, in a way that more rigid frameworks could

not.

Narrative and Ethics

‘Narratives in moral thinking come before, during, and after moral

generalities (whether of theory, principle, or basic moral concept). They

permit and invite full exploration of what often seems neglected or devalued

on the engineering model: specific histories of individual commitment, of

relationship and responsibility, of institutional practices and evolving moral

tradition…...Emphasis on narrative construction pulls in the opposite

direction--from premature or coercive streamlining of cases toward

enrichment of context and detail’ (Walker, 1993, p.35).

The Moral Significance of Narrative

A significant feature of applied ethics research is that it recognises individual

participants as having unique personal moral values and experiences, all of which

are embedded in their particular historical, cultural, political, economic and social

contexts. Consequently, there is not one rational way to be, but rather a wide

plurality of ways, hence the ‘goods’ we seek are not singular but rather pluralistic.

From a research perspective, if we hope to hermeneutically and appreciatively

engage in another’s story, we may only access this unique perspectival stance

through listening to their voice. Thus if ethics is fundamentally embedded in

relationships, and if we are as Taylor (1989) and Bruner (1991) claim essentially

narratively constructed and dialogical beings, then voice16F

17 must lie at the heart of

ethics (and ethical) research because language underpins our ontological

understandings as moral beings. As shared understandings are sought, the language

17 Among the various voices, the ‘voice of reason’ is just one of the many contributing voices to be heard, rather than the dominating voice.

Page 64: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

64

and discourse that shapes meaning in this context becomes a central focus of ethical

enquiry. Therefore dialogue and narrative analysis form the central strategies of this

approach which seeks to uncover tacit meanings and understandings within the

broader social and particular individual contexts.

Isaacs (2007) explores the link between language, context and moral engagement

saying,

‘Language makes possible our being and becoming. Language mediates the

good life. But language is itself mediated through others. And such

encounters are only possible because we are, or stand in conversations with

these others. We are, accordingly, dialogical beings and our being and

becoming is significantly that of a dialogical being and becoming’ (Isaacs,

2007, p.7).

In considering how human beings construct meaning from the experiences that

weave the fabric of their everyday lives, Bruner makes the point, ‘we organise our

experience and our memory of human happenings mainly in the form of narrative –

stories, excuses, myths, reasons for doing and not doing, and so on’ (Bruner, 1991,

p.4). Andrews further reiterates this point claiming that, ‘if we are constructed by

stories, or are storytellers by nature, or perhaps both, then narrative must surely be

a prime concern of social research’ (Andrews 2000, p. 1).

Thus narrative invites us to enter into the being and becoming of the other in the

totality of their embodied and embedded realities. It opens the possibility of sharing,

understanding and appreciation of the complex and unique lived reality and plural

moral frameworks that are unique to each human self. It further enables the

expression of experiences of loss, suffering, or oppression to be voiced, especially

by those who may feel disempowered or silenced. Finally, narrative opens up new

meanings, new possibilities and new sensibilities for collective and individual moral

insight and growth. Therefore, narrative methods of research complement the ethical

orientation of this work, opening a fitting way to explore the richness, particularity

and uniqueness of individual experiences. In other words, dialogue opens a moral

Page 65: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

65

space to particular ontology, and as this research is concerned with exploring

particular experiences as shaped by broader social contexts, a narrative method of

inquiry practically and theoretically supports the ethical orientation of this research.

Importantly though, narrative is widely recognised as significant in enhancing

ethical understandings (Brody, 2002; McMillan & Gillett, 2002; Tomlinson, 1997;

Walker, 1993, 1998). As sharing experiences through dialogue may improve our

common understandings and open us to the rich complexities of each others lives,

our ethical judgements may be better informed. Tomlinson (1997) further notes that

narrative awakens our moral sensibilities, so that we can better appreciate any

perceived ‘wrongfulness’ of the story being told. Thus narrative and dialogue are

pivotal in shaping the ethical agenda (Taylor, 1989; Widdershoven & Smit, 1996).

Why Ethics?

‘This technology turns every user into a moral philosopher as she engages

her fears and fantasies on the limits of mothering a fetus with a disability’

(Rapp, 2000, p.128).

The title of this work firmly positions it as applied ethics research. The questions

raised by the routine implementation of prenatal screening are ethically significant

because they potentially have an impact on human being and becoming that reaches

beyond the obvious individual consequences. Prenatal screening impacts ethically

upon the status of new human life, on the lives of mothers, couples and families, and

on society generally in terms of the human values that are supported or denied by its

practice.

If the moral form of life is intimately entwined with a sense of the indisputable

uniqueness and ‘inalienable preciousness’ and dignity of each human being as

Raymond Gaita (1999, p.4) suggests, then the critical questions raised by prenatal

screening technologies such as, who is permitted to be born, under what

circumstances and conforming to which pre-conditions of entry to the human race

are imposed, are inherently ethical in nature because they strike at the heart of our

Page 66: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

66

understandings of what it is to be human. To be allowed to exist, for life to be

valued in all its diverse forms solely because it is human life, to be given the chance

to grow and become, to live an embodied, embedded life may no longer be taken as

a human good. With the advent of prenatal screening technologies, the creation of

life may no longer be regarded as a matter of biological chance or of divine mystery,

but increasingly in the mechanical, biological model, viewed through the

reductionist lens of science, nascent human life may become objectified, leaving it

open to technological manipulation and control. This previously untouchable and

seemingly random natural process now falls under human scrutiny, judgement and

control.

Consequently, notions of personal ‘choice’ and preference have become further

entrenched into our reproductive expectations. Not only can we choose when or how

many children we have, there is now a growing expectation that we can also choose

which type of child we are willing to accept. Such choices, framed in socially

entrenched prejudices governing which traits are desirable or undesirable in our

offspring create a moral space in which the destruction or removal of such a life

seems the technically and philosophically rational thing to do. When the ethical

nature of ‘choice’ is considered within an analytical philosophical framework,

rationality becomes the ultimate arbiter of which choice is better, or more rational,

than another, but as MacIntyre (1984) challenged earlier, whose rationality should

we privilege? In trying to forge humane and ethically responsible use of this

technology, will we make the realisation as Kass (2002, p.17) does that ‘not all

human dignity consists of reason or freedom’.

The choices offered or denied, however, are not ours alone to pursue. In order to

make these technologically mediated choices a practical reality, individuals are

dependent upon the technical expertise of others. Clearly technology has brought

significant gains to our understandings of the human condition; however the

potentially dehumanising gaze of technology, driven by a pursuit for perfection and

the rejection of the imperfection of disability, cuts to the core of human dignity and

is already blurring the boundaries of the sanctity, or preciousness, of human life.

We now have the knowledge to detect and diagnose certain disabilities prenatally

Page 67: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

67

and the power to ‘prevent’ the presumed pain and suffering that accompanies them.

Tentatively ‘wanted’ and ‘planned’ children may become unwanted and unplanned

on the strength of a test result (Asch & Wasserman, 2005; Katz - Rothman, 1986).

While some limited conditions may be treatable prenatally, couching prenatal

screening as a means of promoting such early intervention is disingenuous because

the genetic anomalies targeted are, as yet, inherently ‘unfixable’.

With pregnancy and parenthood taking on the overtures of a well executed project,

Kass remarks, ‘ a society that when it does procreate, that sees its children as

projects rather than gifts is unlikely to be open to the question of meaning and

dignity of procreation’(Kass, 2002, p.20). Through technology, we have been

invited to redefine our understandings of what a suitable body is, and for some, the

expectations of what constitutes a suitable body for our children to be born into have

been significantly influenced by access to prenatal and genetic screening. Indeed

some commentators argue that we parents have a moral obligation to choose

children with the best genetic prospects, or even intentionally enhance the genetic

makeup of their future children where technically possible (Aldred, Savarirayan, &

Savulescu, 2003; Green 1997; Savulescu, 2001). Rather than accepting the

wholeness of humanity as incorporating differences, we are perhaps swayed by the

promise of technologically mediated perfection for our children. However, as

previously discussed, our bodies are not merely objects or machines; they are the

site of our human being in the world. As such, any purely mechanistic view of

disease, illness or imperfection detached from the ontological realities of being, will

fail to incorporate the essential humanistic understandings, of the deeply connected,

embedded and relational realities that define the human condition. When

mechanistic understandings of the body are coupled with a similarly mechanistic

approach to ethics, the creation of the required open reflective moral space will be

stifled.

While Kass (2002, p.10) was commenting on the use of human embryos as raw

materials for use in medical research when he stated, ‘we are desensitised and

denatured by a coarsening of sensibility that comes to regard these practices as

natural, ordinary and fully unproblematic’, his comment could similarly apply to

Page 68: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

68

prenatal screening technologies. We should be equally wary of embracing ‘soft’

technologies, such as the non-invasive forms of prenatal screening that encourage

us to judge who is worthy of being born because as Ruth Hubbard (1988, p.234)

notes,

‘We do ourselves an injury, as individuals and as a society, if we let fear of

difference tempt us to decide “who should and should not inhabit the world”

because it is hubris to pretend that we have the knowledge and foresight to

make such judgments well’.

We are faced with the ethical reality of balancing the indisputable goods that

medical technology can offer through the prevention of disease with the potential

harm that human life may be dehumanised and disrespected in the process. Charles

Taylor (1989) further observes that the difficulty in pursuing the ‘good life’ is often

not the need to discern good from bad, but rather negotiating the moral conflict that

arises when judging between competing goods. The questions of how we ought to

consider and respond to these competing goods are ethical questions, thus they

invite ethical answers, but what kind of ethics and how should we consider these

competing potentials for good? While medical science asks ‘can we’, ethics

uniquely challenges us to decide whether what we are doing is affirming or

damaging. Thus the ethical landscape we create and the ethical legacy we leave

doesn’t depend upon free rational choice so much as it depends on which choices are

made, or made available. Therefore, the role of ethics in our society is to provide a

framework through which the moral dimensions of our daily lives may be articulated

and understood, then incorporated into a constructive response to shape better lives,

or as Socrates implored (cited by Kass, 2003, p.75), to seek moral wisdom.

Chapter Summary

There are many core differences between the various approaches to ethics discussed

throughout this chapter. The dominantly accepted view on the one hand is a ‘top

down’ approach, an external expert discourse concerned with intellectual mastery of

the right principles and theories to be applied rationally and universally to guide

Page 69: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

69

behaviour towards a generalisable truth. Conversely, the other is a ‘bottom up’

approach, starting with the richly contextual, nuanced, embedded and embodied

particularities of each individual, building the moral picture upwards and outwards

from each unique situation. The former is engaged in the detached intellectual

mastery of principles and ideals, while the other is actualised by participants

working towards an enhanced understanding which transforms human interactions

and practices (Isaacs, 2003). While the range of philosophical theories and practical

approaches may enrich our ethics knowledge in different ways, as the ethical

orientation of this work aims to produce research that is responsive, collaborative,

inclusive, transformative and empowering, to promote ethics as generally accessible

and practically useful in real situations at micro and macro ethical levels, the thesis

more strongly resonates with the phenomenological view. In aligning this work with

the phenomenological stance, it is important to note that the significance and value

of reason and abstract thought is not rejected. However, the strong resonance

between the relational focus and ontological coherency of the phenomenological

account of the self with the ontological foundation of educational philosophy that

will be described later in the thesis17F

18 provides a strong platform for interpretation

and analysis.

If the moral goods we seek are shared through intersubjective relationships with

others, language must be acknowledged as significant in the actualisation of these

goods. As no two people will seek exactly the same life of meaning, significant

evaluations differ for each person. The most appropriate way to access each person’s

unique moral frameworks is, therefore, through attending to their particular

narrative, through inviting a shared dialogue. Consequently, ‘narrative’ must lie at

the heart of the ethical encounter. Attending to the ethical in health care therefore

requires us to step outside the thin morals of obligatory action bound by abstract

principles to understand the constitutive goods that frame collective and individual

moral decision making (Taylor, 1989).

A critical pre-requisite in crafting such a humane response to the many complex

ethical challenges inherent within prenatal screening technologies may begin with

18 See Chapter 9.

Page 70: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

70

the rejection of the individualistic, detached and atomistic self that dominates

modern moral philosophy. Once we start to accept that the self is not essentially a

disconnected individual, but rather a deeply related, embedded, embodied, and

historically and culturally situated self, we can more accurately respond to the

intricately layered nature of human ‘being’. With this understanding at the core, we

will surely be in better position to develop more comprehensive, compassionate and

humane approaches to technology use.

In Chapter Three, exploration of narrative as an ethically and methodologically

appropriate research tool is explored in more detail. The link between narrative and

ethics is reinforced and the benefits, challenges and limitations of adopting a

qualitative, narrative research method of inquiry are considered.

Page 71: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

71

CHAPTER 3

RESEARCH THROUGH VOICE: A METHOD FOR EXPLORING EMBEDDED

UNDERSTANDINGS

Introduction

‘[We cannot underestimate] the importance of having research strategies

that can work with the narratives people use to understand the human world.

Although this perspective presents a problem for the research models to

which we have grown accustomed and in which we take pride, it opens up a

realm for understanding human beings that will, I believe, make our

research considerably more successful’ (Polkinghorne, 1988, p.xi).

This work seeks to explore a range of critical ethical questions emerging from

individual stakeholders experiences with prenatal screening. In terms of the applied

ethics framework proposed earlier by Isaacs and Massey (1994), this research may

be seen as attending to the hermeneutic, appraisive and transformative dimensions of

the ethical encounter. It is not therefore specifically concerned with finding ‘the’

definitive answer to specific research questions, or as Darbyshire suggests to ‘lay

out causal explanations in theoretical terms’ (Darbyshire, 1994, p.860). Rather, the

aim of this project is to embrace a hermeneutic approach which fosters deeper

understanding of the lived experiences of individual participants as a conduit to

uncovering the ethically problematic aspects of the prenatal screening protocols and

practices. In turn, new insights and possibilities from which to transform and

strengthen the ethically challenging aspects of prenatal care may be gleaned and

potentially relevant sites of future inquiry may be identified.

The previous chapter proposed an approach to ethics which centred upon ways of

understanding the unique and particular, embedded and embodied experiences of

individuals. In understanding the hermeneutically layered nature of human being

and becoming, the phenomenological account of ontology embraced throughout this

work further acknowledges the core importance of language and narrative in the

Page 72: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

72

construction of the self as essentially a dialogical self (Taylor, 1988, 1989).

Language and narrative significantly mediate the plurality of goods we affirm

individually, but importantly, they also mediate and define the communal ethical

encounter. Inviting participation in a shared moral space, narrative accommodates

the pluralities of understandings of what is ethically ‘good’ and thus promotes the

emergence of collectively negotiated, respectful and inclusive ethical conversations.

As it is through such shared understandings that a more appropriate and inclusive

moral response may be sought when navigating the ethical tensions inherent within

the burgeoning practice of prenatal screening, a narrative research methodology is

most fitting to this research as it provides an ontologically coherent and ethically

inclusive means of hearing, appreciating and responding to the individual stories

offered.

This chapter will expand upon the crucial role of narrative in opening a shared

ethical space and outline the narrative method of inquiry and analysis adopted for

this research. The limitations of a narrative research methodology will also be

discussed.

Why Narrative?

[From Latin narrāre, narrāt - from gnārus, knowing]

‘Our ultimate goal as social scientists is to learn about the substance, make

theoretical claims through methods and learn about the general from the

particular. Individual action and biography must be the starting point of

analysis, not the end’ (Riessman, 1993, p.70).

‘The phrase “experiencing the experience” is a reminder that for us

narrative inquiry is aimed at understanding and making meaning of

experience. This is the baseline ‘why’ for social science inquiry. Why use

narrative inquiry? Because narrative inquiry is a way, the best way we

believe, to think about experience’ (Clandinin & Connelly, 2000, p.80).

Page 73: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

73

‘perhaps we attain the truth of the matter only by stories’ (Zaner, 2005,

p.200).

Human beings are inherently storytellers, we interact with, and construct meaning

from, the narratives we create around our lives every day (Bruner, 1991;

Lindemann-Nelson, 2001; MacIntyre, 1984; Mishler, 1986; Taylor, 1989). We craft

our own narratives and appear in others’ narratives, co-authoring the larger

collective cultural narratives of which we are all a part (Bruner, 1991; Lindemann-

Nelson, 2001; MacIntyre, 1984). It is through narrative, therefore, that we reveal

our moral evaluations, create meaning in our lives and construct our own and others

identities (Andrews, 2000; Bruner, 1986; Lindemann-Nelson, 2001; Taylor, 1989).

Taylor (1989, p.47) further remarks that the ‘basic condition of making sense of

ourselves is that we grasp our lives in narrative’, concluding that narrative

represents an ‘inescapable structural requirement of human agency’ (ibid, p.52).

The central importance of narrative and language in constructing and mediating the

human condition is echoed by Mishler (1986) and further reinforced by Bruner

(1991, p.5) who claims that narrative not only represents reality, but constitutes it as

well. Indeed for Bruner ‘a life as lived is inseparable from a life as told … not

“how it was”… but how it is interpreted and reinterpreted, told and retold’ (1987,

p.31). Thus individual experience, our narrative accounts of such experience and the

ethical significance of narrative in framing our being and becoming are inextricably

linked. Indeed, narrative lies at the core of the ethical.

Educationalist John Dewey (1938, cited by Clandinin and Connelly 2000, p.2),

suggests that understanding is grounded in experience and prior learning, making the

further observation that such experience and prior knowledge always have both a

personal and a social dimension. The ontological orientation underpinning Dewey’s

claims significantly resonates with the phenomenological account embraced in this

work which acknowledges that meaning is shaped by multiple interpretive

frameworks. Thus Dewey (1938, cited by Clandinin and Connelly 2000) claims that

people may not be fully understood as individuals alone, but rather must be

considered in relation to their wider social frameworks. The deeply contextualised

and communally situated nature of individual experience therefore necessarily

Page 74: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

74

creates a direct entry portal into understanding the overarching social, cultural and

historical frameworks that shape the ethical dimensions of each individual’s

experience. A narrative research method of inquiry based upon engaging participants

in conversations about their individual experiences therefore provides an appropriate

vehicle from which to consider the research questions posed in this work. As

experience does not occur in a vacuum, each recounting of a person’s story is

necessarily situated in the context of past experiences, prior knowledge, future

imagined possibilities, in addition to individual and communal understandings that

lie on the continuum of personal growth. It is this continuum that shapes individual

ethical interpretations.

As embedded and embodied discourses, the study of personal narratives gives access

and insight into broader socio-cultural understandings (Clandinin & Connelly, 2000;

Laverty, 2006; Thomas, 1999, p.78) bringing together ‘past, present and future

meanings in an evaluative way’ (Bridle, 2004, p.135). Eliciting a personal narrative

is therefore a potentially powerful investigative tool which facilitates the mining of

the complexities and multiple layers of interconnectedness that define and guide

individual and communal moral frameworks. As Gilligan notes (1996, p.253) ‘voice

is the barometer of relationships because it connects the inner and the outer world’.

Within a theoretical framework which actively acknowledges the symbiotic

relationship between narrative and ethics, a narrative research methodology, as

adopted in this work, is not approached as an interrogative process, but rather one

which honours participants as having moral expertise in their own stories. By

allowing participants to speak in their own words, determine the flow of topics

explored, and emphasise or elaborate points of particular significance to them, the

complexity and particularity of each account can be preserved to more accurately

reflect their interpretations of their experiences (Strickland, 1994, cited by Bridle

2004, p.135). Thus narrative is both a product and a process of inquiry (Clandinin &

Connelly, 2000), a technique that emphasises the stories people tell to account for,

and make meaning from, events in their lives (Bryman, 2004). It is not the claim of

this research therefore to ‘give voice’ to participants but rather, more cautiously, to

Page 75: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

75

hear, to listen and to forge an ethically informed response which is respectful of the

many and varied contributory voices present.

Qualitative methodologies, such as exploring personal narratives, lend themselves to

the provision of thick descriptions and comprehensive accounts, rich with context

and detail, which more rigid quantitative methods may exclude, as Charles Ragin

remarks,

‘Most quantitative data techniques are data condensers. They condense data

in order to see a big picture….Qualitative methods, by contrast, are best

understood as data enhancers. When data are enhanced it is possible to see

key aspects of cases more clearly’ (Charles Ragin 1994 cited by Hesse-

Biber & Leavy, 2006).

While such methods of inquiry have been criticised for lacking generalisability,

lacking intellectual rigour, or being biased or unreproducible (Hesse-Biber & Leavy,

2006; Tomlinson, 1997), it is not the aim of this thesis to produce or reproduce

objective or generalisable ‘data’. Rather the purpose of the narrative method

adopted in this research is to illuminate particular experiences from which potential

areas of wider research may be identified.

Acknowledging the hermeneutic layers of interpretation brought by each participant

is therefore pivotal in enhancing our understandings of the broader ethical

dimensions of prenatal screening. In considering the embedded nature of prenatal

screening, individual interpretations are significantly shaped by a range of

communally endorsed ‘master narratives’ (Lindemann-Nelson, 2001), or ‘canonical

scripts’ (Bruner, 1991). These collective canons of understanding including faith in

science as ‘transcending’ (Noble, 1999, pp.9-11), or in the context of this thesis, the

portrayal of disability as tragedy (Clapton, 2003; Reinders, 2000; Shakespeare,

2001), the belief in rationality as a source of moral agency or the prescriptive

expectations of how ‘good mothers’ ought behave (Lippman, 1991) combine to

further mould and dictate the practices, presumptions and ethical terrain of

technological intervention in pregnancy. A narrative research method more

Page 76: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

76

sensitively captures the situated social context of prenatal screening, illuminated

through the telling of specific, situated and individual accounts in a way that other

methods may fail. Hence, while the starting point of this research is the combined

personal experiences of mothers and health care practitioners of this cohort, due to

the deep and multi-layered nature of human embeddedness, these individual

experiences quickly spiral beyond the private particularities of each person, touching

extensively on the overarching social, personal, institutional, and ethical aspects of

screening.

Bruner (1986, p.11) suggests that qualitative and quantitative methodologies need

not be viewed as competitive discourses, but rather as complementary lenses, each

illuminating a different, though equally important part, of the whole picture. While

different modes of inquiry maintain their own very different standards of validity or

verisimilitude, each may inform, extend or challenge the understandings revealed by

the other. Bruner (1986, p.11) further cautions ‘efforts to reduce one mode to the

other or to ignore one at the expense of the other inevitably fail to capture the rich

diversity of thought’. Recognising the complementary strengths of different modes

of inquiry, while resisting the temptation to transfer the presumed rigour of one

mode directly onto the other, leaves open the prospect of seeing ‘possible formal

connections before one is able to prove them in any formal way’ (ibid).

Just as each member of this participant cohort brings a unique perspectival stance,

reinforcing Bruner’s (1991, p.3) claim that ‘knowledge is never point of view-less’,

the capacity of social researchers to objectively stand apart, detached from that

which they seek to give account of, must also be challenged. Riessman (1993, p.v)

notes ‘the construction of any work always bears the mark of the person who

created it’. The questions posed in this thesis have therefore been significantly

formed and filtered through the multiple interpretive ‘eyes’ of the researcher as

mother, former scientist, partner, educator, social researcher, friend, daughter,

sister , colleague and so on. In countless ways, these multiple interpretive lenses are

central in shaping why these particular research questions were distilled at the

expense of others. Hesse-Biber and Leavy (2006, p.15) further reinforce this aspect

of social research noting,

Page 77: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

77

‘…social reality is not ‘out there’ waiting to be discovered and measured but

rather it is relational and subjective, produced during the research process.

The researcher is not assumed to be value neutral and objective, but rather

an active participant, along with the research subjects in building the

exploratory and explanatory knowledge. Likewise, the value of the research

is not based on whether it is replicable but rather how it adds to our

substantive knowledge on a particular subject’.

Thus it is clear that in social research of this nature, it is impossible to segregate the

multiple contributing individual interpretations from both researcher and participant,

from the ‘facts’ to produce a neutral account of the truth. The aim of this research is

rather, as Hesse-Biber and Leavy (2006) suggest, to contribute to our collective

substantive knowledge.

As situated, context dependent, qualitative research, the purpose of this thesis is not

to make far reaching generalisations about all women and all practitioners in

Queensland. Nor is it to quantify how many women have had fulfilling, distressing,

confusing or uplifting encounters with prenatal screening, nor to calculate how many

practitioners have solid understandings of the impact that embracing this technology

has in their patients’ lives. Rather, it is to enhance our understanding of how each of

these stakeholders experiences their role in the broader social framework. In turn,

these individual insights may add to our collective understandings of how the ethical

challenges of prenatal screening may be more successfully negotiated. The

importance of narrative in this process thus emerges not only as a means of

accessing and understanding the various stakeholder perspectives present, but as a

viable instrument to negotiate ethical transformation (Bruner, 1991; Lindemann-

Nelson, 2001; Walker, 2003).

The In–Depth Interview

‘The opportunity to tell one’s own story as one wants to tell it – in one’s own

voice – is a kind of grace’ (Frank, 1995, pp.134-135).

Page 78: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

78

‘If we believe that social reality exists as meaningful interaction between

individuals then it can only be known through understanding others’ points

of view, interpretations and meanings. If meaningful human interaction

depends on language, then the words people use and the interpretations they

make are of central interest to the researcher. In –depth interviewing is an

appropriate method to gain access to the individual’s words and

interpretations’ (Minichiello, Aroni, Timewell, & Alexander, 1995, p.73).

The choice of in-depth interviewing as a narrative research technique reflects a

particular philosophical and methodological stance (Mishler, 1986) as outlined in

the previous discussions throughout this work. Engaging in an in-depth interview,

therefore, opens a window onto how individuals position themselves in the wider

social context (Minichiello et al., 1995; Widdershoven & Smit, 1996), illuminating

the ‘nexus of social relationships’ (Doucet, 2006, p.66) that shape the social and

cultural dimensions of, in this case, prenatal screening.

The impulse to narrate is inherent and provides the connection between ‘knowing

and telling’ (White 1980 cited by Mishler, 1986, p.145). Furthermore, as description

and justification combine in narrative, the ethical dimensions and context of each

person’s experience can be revealed (Widdershoven & Smit, 1996). As Minichiello

et. al (1995, p.61) note, it is through this conversation that the researcher can gain

access to and understanding of the ‘private interpretations of social reality that

individuals hold’. Thus, in-depth interviewing provides a valuable vehicle through

which to engage with an individual’s experiences, beliefs and interpretations and is,

therefore, an appropriate means through which to explore the questions of this

research.

In-depth interviewing can be seen as a conversation between researcher and

participant with a specific purpose, which is to explore perceptions of self, life and

experience (Minichiello et al., 1995). Minichiello et al (ibid) make the further point

that there are no concrete rules of how to conduct an in-depth interview, thus a

variety of strategies exist. These strategies range from standardised, highly

Page 79: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

79

structured questions, through to completely unstructured, recursive dialogue

between researcher and participant. On one end of this continuum, the rigid,

standardised questions of a structured interview format may impose too narrow a

focus on individual accounts. On the other end, the completely unstructured

approach could result in participants veering beyond the scope of the research to

recount experiences not central to the aims of inquiry. While rejecting a

standardised question interview format for this research may have reduced the

comparability of the interviews, a semi-structured question format strikes a balance,

preserving participants’ ability to freely contribute while not completely presuming

to limit the permissible experiences sought (Minichiello et al., 1995, p.64).

In opting for a semi-structured format, the flexibility to accommodate the dynamic

realities of the conversation was preserved, while the content and direction of the

interview remained focused. Cathy Riessman (1993, p.3) has commented that ‘…

respondents (if not interrupted with standardised questions) will hold the floor for

lengthy turns and sometimes organise replies into long stories’. The more flexible

format of a semi-structured interview, therefore, better supported a more thorough

telling of individual accounts. Consequently, in-depth interviews may become more

conversational in style, allowing the listener and teller the freedom to seek

clarification when either party felt it strengthened the discussion. While this

conversational flow may allow the researcher to influence the narrative told, the

primary aim of ‘listening’, and the focal point of participants ‘telling’, coupled with

the Listening Guide18F

19 analysis, which intentionally calls for researcher reflection on

this very point, supports the authenticity of participants’ account and lessens

researcher influence.

With the aim of encouraging respondents to stay ‘on track’, as suggested by

Minichiello et al (1995, p.82), an interview guide was developed as a back-up

prompt to keep the interview focused. The interview guide took the form of a scatter

list of topics such as that proposed by Minister (1991, p.37), compiled after a

comprehensive literature review, exploring the broader issues surrounding ethical

19 The Listening Guide will be more thoroughly considered on pages 89-108.

Page 80: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

80

decision making in prenatal screening19F

20 (see Appendix I). The topics on this list

were arbitrarily arranged on the page, and provided a starting point for conversation.

Each individual was invited to choose a starting point, enabling the flow of open

dialogue which was clearly focussed on issues central to the research aims. Some

examples of the topics included in the list were voluntariness of testing, need for re-

assurance, ethical concerns, learning in a medical environment and informed choice.

While this method of presenting points for discussion is claimed to reduce the

impact of the researcher’s framework on the content of the interview (Minister,

1991), as the researcher inevitably influences which topics make it onto the list, it

is impossible to separate the influence of the researcher on any account given

(Glesne, 1999). However, while the researcher’s role may influence the scope of the

inquiry agenda pursued, adopting a semi-structured, in-depth interview within a

narrative framework did give participants the opportunity to articulate their own

stories in their own words, inviting researchers to think with rather than about the

stories offered (Frank, 1995, p.23).

Participant Recruitment

The cohort of this study included nineteen participants in all. The cohort comprised

of seven mothers who had undergone prenatal screening and had given birth to a

child within the last two years, alongside eleven health care professionals from

various disciplines involved in the support and education of women facing the

decision to embark upon prenatal screening. In addition, one disability support

group volunteer whose role was to provide telephone support to families who had

received a positive (or potential) prenatal diagnosis of Down syndrome was

interviewed. The rationale behind the selection of participants, in line with the

qualitative narrative methodology adopted, was to provide a pool of experiences to

heighten understanding and knowledge through the telling of specific but

comprehensive accounts20F

21.

20 This scatterlist was devised from research into the ethical dimensions of prenatal screening that emerged from previous honours research (Milligan, 2004). 21 The issue of how these findings may apply in a broader sense or whether the outcomes can be generalised across a larger community may be addressed through further research.

Page 81: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

81

A purposive approach to sampling was adopted in which participants with a specific

experience were sought, rather than looking for a random, statistically generalisable

cohort. Purposive sampling is therefore useful for situations where a limited group

needs to be targeted and where sample representativeness is not of primary concern

(Neuman, 2000) with the intensive and focused interviews generated from purposive

sampling being ideally suited ‘for gathering insights, anomalies and paradoxes’

(Hoschild, 1981, cited by Neuman, 2000, p.198).

In designing the recruitment phase of this project, particular attention was paid to

participants being fully informed and consulted throughout the length of their

involvement. Interestingly, like the many women who entrust practitioners with their

‘informed consent’, one health care provider participant made the following

revealing remark on being asked to give her informed consent to participate in this

project.

‘Why do we have informed consent... …? I suppose it’s putting in a bit of a

check and balance, but it certainly doesn’t cover all aspects of risk, for

example, I couldn’t know as much about this project as you do….you have

the background, so when I sign the consent form , I’m entrusting you to

have some integrity …’ Midwife 4.

This comment strikes at the heart of a key issue being explored in this research. The

success of informed consent as a process for ensuring ethical probity ultimately

relies not on ‘information’ alone, nor on procedural checks and balances, but equally

upon the integrity of those involved. In giving consent, we ultimately trust others to

act with integrity in a responsible and respectful manner.

Clandinin and Connelly (2000, p.73) describe the initial phase of entering new

research and recruiting participants as ‘negotiating purpose’. This entails the process

of explaining the research, justifying and clarifying its point and hopefully making

the process meaningful to potential participants. With the aim of ‘negotiating

purpose’ in mind, an information pack was developed for participants (see Appendix

II A, II B) to outline the aims, risks, benefits and requirements of involvement in the

project prior to nominating. The information pack also included the topic list of

themes for discussion to enable potential participants to assess the scope and nature

Page 82: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

82

of the project before committing to participate. A description of the expectations of

participation, coupled with a clear message that consent could be withdrawn at any

time and an open invitation for each participant to discuss the project with me at any

time were included in the information pack. The Information Pack also gave contact

details of Queensland University of Technology’s independent Research Ethics

Committee, in the event that any participant was concerned with any aspect of their

participation. Finally, all documents associated with the recruitment process were

approved by the University Human Research Ethics Committee as part of the ethical

clearance protocols of the university (UHREC Approval no.3911H- See Appendix

III).

Mother Recruitment

As previously noted, eligible participants from the mothers’ cohort were women

who had undergone some form of prenatal screening, either ultrasound, nuchal

translucency screening or serum screening in the last two years and who were no

longer pregnant.

After a radio interview about this project on ABC Brisbane in October 2005, several

women made contact and volunteered to participate in this research. Through these

initial contacts, a snowballing effect occurred which resulted in the recruitment of

the seven mothers interviewed. In response to their initial contact, an information

package was sent (Appendix II A). All eligible participants from the mothers’

cohort who were sent an information pack participated in the study. This mode of

recruitment was chosen as a risk management strategy to enable only interested

parties to volunteer. As each volunteer was in control of the contact they were in a

position to decline at any time minimising potential feelings of coercion to

participate. Women who were no longer pregnant were also chosen to reduce the

risk of unnecessary anxiety about the outcome of their pregnancy as this was already

known. As reflections of past experiences were being sought the risk of

psychological distress could be minimised. While directly sensitive questions were

not asked during the interview, if the interviewee raised sensitive issues they were

given the latitude to freely expand upon their impressions. All contributors were

Page 83: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

83

made aware that all discussions were strictly confidential; hence pseudonyms are

used throughout the subsequent analysis and discussion.

Health Care Provider Recruitment

A direct letter of introduction with an information package (Appendix IIB) was sent

to a selection of health care professionals working locally in the field of antenatal

care and prenatal screening. The letter outlined details of the project and invited

practitioners to personally contact me if they were interested in participating. The

final composition of the health professionals’ group included three midwives

working in public health hospitals, three general practitioners working in private

practice, two genetic counsellors based in public hospitals, a geneticist, a midwife

educator and an obstetrician, also working in a large public hospital.

This method of recruitment does not ensure representation of the complete range of

possible experiences; however, the unique and particular collection of experiences

considered in this work may illuminate specific areas of practice which may suggest

further areas of investigation.

Ethical Considerations of Recruitment and Participation

While this project explores the ethical dimensions of informed consent in the

medical setting with respect to prenatal screening, significant ethical issues

concerning informed consent arise in the research process itself (Thorne, 2004).

Thorne (ibid) notes that in order to gain access and rapport, sometimes full

disclosure of the research goals and aims are not made saying,

‘self introductions are bound up with efforts to gain access, and the practical

motive, weighted heavily by investments of time, money and career, tends to

squeeze honesty to the side’ (ibid, p.162).

This point exposes a very real ethical tension within social research. Researchers

must ultimately make the judgement of how much information may realistically be

given. They are also immersed in a potential clash of purpose in which they are the

Page 84: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

84

both the potential beneficiary of the research in a professional sense, but are also

often the sole arbiter of whether appropriate levels of understanding and

voluntariness are exhibited by participants. Additional considerations of whether

participants should have the final ‘approval’ on how their words are interpreted, or

whether consent should be re-established at various stages in the process raise

further ethical issues which shape the ethical tone of research. Finally if the research

is conducted in a way that causes participants to withdraw their consent, the desire

to protect the researcher’s considerable ‘investments of time, money and career’, as

Thorne (2004) notes above, may negatively influence researcher behaviour in an

attempt to protect the substantial professional investment made. In seeking to

sensitively and transparently negotiate these potentially competing considerations, a

research protocol that sought a genuine shared dialogue between myself and all

participants was developed. Every effort was made to ensure all participants were

competent and knowledgeable about the aims and potential outcomes of this

research. In addition, recruitment was specifically designed to be non-coercive,

giving control over contact to the participants thus ensuring, to the best of my

ability, that any collaboration was voluntary and intentional. By giving all

participants the final approval of their transcript, and by remaining in contact with

each person to elucidate particular points and to ask for further clarifications, the

potential for misinterpretation or misrepresentation was minimised.

However, just as administrative protocols of informed consent alone cannot address

all the ethical complexities of prenatal screening, seeking the informed consent of

research participants unearths similar layers of complexity. Thus, with respect to

informed consent to participate in research Thorne (2004) concludes,

‘By itself, the doctrine of informed consent does not do full justice to the

complexity of ethical judgement field workers confront’ (ibid, p.172).

As this project involved in-depth interaction with participants, covering issues with

the potential to invoke emotional responses, internal conflicts or professional

tension, the recruitment process and the actual interview was structured in a way to

enhance participant agency by controlling the flow of the topics covered. This

agency extended to a very clear commitment to participants that they would be given

Page 85: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

85

the opportunity to prohibit use of any part of the interview that they later deemed

unsuitable. All participants were given a copy of their interview transcript with the

invitation to add further comments, or delete comments they wished to exclude 21F

22.

Confidentiality for both the mothers’ cohort and the practitioners’ cohort was critical

in the research design. For the practitioners, preserving confidentiality was

particularly important in the relatively small antenatal medical community in

Brisbane. For this reason mothers are identified with a pseudonym and practitioners

by a descriptor of their professional role such as midwife, obstetrician or GP etc.

Finally, while the mandated channels of ethics research approvals and committees

were diligently followed, complying with the technical, often legalistic requirements

that such committees requested did not necessarily capture the essence of trust,

integrity or moral obligation to honour each of the participants’ intention. The

intentions of these participants was to contribute to a mutually appreciative

understanding as a shared basis of practice and policy reform, negotiated from a

mutually respectful, inclusive and informed stance for the benefit all stakeholders.

The Interviews

Individual, in-depth interviews were held with all nineteen participants over a period

of 10 months from October 2005 through to July 2006. An open – ended approach

to questioning was adopted with all participants to enable them to direct the flow

and significance of what they felt was ‘worthy’ of sharing about the topics on the

scatterlist (Appendix I). For the women, their experiences of prenatal screening,

their understandings of this practice, their perceived barriers to ethical decision

making and an account of how they became educated about the prenatal tests

accepted or rejected were sought. For the health professional cohort, perspectives

were sought on what they felt the challenges were in delivering ethically sensitive

care in what is considered by some to be a potentially morally contentious practice.

Their insights into the perceived barriers to achieving ethical intervention in prenatal

22 Very few participants sought to alter the original transcript, mainly adding comments to clarify questions I had posed, or to strengthen or reiterate a particular point. No significant changes to the interview transcripts were requested by the participants.

Page 86: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

86

screening and the potential links of patient education to informed consent were

sought.

In opting for in-depth interviews, as Laverty has similarly observed (2006, p.4), the

following underlying features are acknowledged:-

• Individual stakeholders have unique and particular insights into the

processes of prenatal screening as either a provider or recipient.

• The combined analysis of each of the nineteen stories told

contributed to the shaping of a larger, collective story.

• The end result of this process is that enhanced understanding of the

broader context may be made through the in-depth exploration and

telling of individual accounts.

The interviews lasted between 60 minutes and 90 minutes and all were recorded for

later transcription. For the mothers, the interview began with an invitation to tell the

story of their pregnancy, including the significance of prenatal screening in their

experience. For practitioners, the interview began with an invitation for each person

to clarify their role in prenatal screening protocols. After the initial invitation to

speak, both groups engaged in fluid and open explanations which flowed easily and

fluently through the many themes on the topic list. Beginning the interview with an

open ended question allowed the construction of answers, in collaboration with me

as listener, resulting in a flowing and meaningful conversation as described by

Mishler (1986). In that regard, the interview was co-constructed by both parties, by

the researcher providing a predetermined list of topics that were ‘on the table’ and

by participants collaborating with the research process as presented. Thus the jointly

constructed conversation and meanings that flowed reflected a particular dynamic

between two particular participants, at a historical point in time, a ‘snapshot’ as

described earlier.

Page 87: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

87

Transcription

‘All we have is talk and texts that represent reality partially, selectively, and

imperfectly’ (Riessman, 1993, p.15).

After recording, each interview was transcribed into written format for further

analysis. The transcription of spoken language into written discourse may not fully

capture the nuances, gestures or non-verbal forms of communication that are an

integral part of a ‘real’ conversation (Clandinin & Connelly, 2000; Mishler, 1986;

Riessman, 1993, 2002). This reality is captured eloquently by Miller and Crabtree

(2004, p.200) who note,

‘the interview is an oral, visual, and kinaesthetic dance between two living

bodies with multiple levels of communication. The transcription of this

reality will never capture this reality’.

Thus while narration is an interpretive act, transcription too is a process in which we

may not assume the transparency of language with Bell (1988) further claiming that

‘transcribing discourse, like photographing reality, is an interpretative act’ (cited

by Riessman 1993, p.40). In transcribing a narrative, many features of the original

reality may become excluded such as non verbal communications, gestures and

looks. Attention to features of speech such as pitch, pace, volume, overlaps and

animation of the voice may also become lost in transcription. However while

‘transcripts are not fully equivalent to the talk’ (Riessman, 1993, p.13), they are

nonetheless valuable and a foundational part of narrative analysis.

At the end of each interview field notes were made of the impressions of each

interview, including feelings about the rapport developed. If particularly strong

reactions to specific topics were given, these were noted in addition to immediate

impressions of, or inconsistencies in, the accounts offered. Although Mishler (1991,

p.47) makes the bleak prediction that ‘transcribing tape recorded interviews is

complex, tedious, and time consuming work that demands careful listening and re-

listening’, I opted to personally transcribe the interviews, and this became a critical

Page 88: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

88

initial phase of the analysis. This process of transcribing became a valuable early

familiarisation with each person’s story as the process of interpretation and finding

links and meanings were beginning to form during each listening, re-listening and

typing of their words. While transcribing these interviews was an exercise in

becoming immersed within them and beginning the formations of analysis, it also

preserved methodological integrity by removing the additional interpretive layer of

yet another person deciding what (perhaps critical) words might be filtered out or

misinterpreted22F

23. The transcription phase therefore formed a vital element in

formulating the interpretations, links and connections within each story, and

collectively across all stories.

Initial transcription began with the words and other striking features such as

laughing, long pauses, hesitation, tone of voice and so on. Mishler (1991) proposes

that multiple listenings are required to ensure as accurate as possible a representation

of the dialogue, and this advise was followed. After the initial transcription, two

consecutive ‘re-listenings’ of the recording were undertaken and the inevitable

corrections made. However, in the analysis phase that followed, Mishler’s

cautionary advice to be wary of ‘taking the transcript too seriously as the reality’

(ibid, p.48) resonated strongly. Through the subsequent analysis the original

recordings were continually referred to in order to confirm the aptness of any

interpretations made. Finally however, while these transcripts clearly represent

participants’ own words, as Bridle (2004, p.137) notes, it cannot be presumed that

these words are necessarily spoken on the participants’ own terms. This insight is

further echoed by Mauthner and Doucet (1998) who note that the ability to hear

individual stories ‘in and on their own terms’ is to some extent impossible as each

story is significantly already situated in the wider social and cultural contexts which

may delimit and define both the story and its narrator.

23 Clandinin & Connelly, 2000; Mishler, 1986; and Riessman, 1993, all note the experience of having texts mis-transcribed, and emphasise the importance of several re-listenings to ensure the written texts matches the spoken conversation.

Page 89: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

89

Narrative Interpretation

‘the best hope of hermeneutic analysis is to provide an intuitively convincing

account of the text as a whole in light of the constituent parts that make it up’

(Bruner 1991, p.7).

Numerous definitions of the term ‘narrative inquiry’ exist, leading Riessman (1993,

p.17) to conclude that ‘there is no binding theory of narrative but instead great

conceptual diversity’. ‘Narrative’ may therefore be thought of as an umbrella term

which incorporates a range of activities. The descriptions of narrative offered vary

widely, and are often oriented towards the specific professional discipline of the

author proposing them (Riessman, 2004). ‘Narratives’ may range from the broad

‘illness narratives’23F

24 of medical sociology through to the highly regimented

structural analysis such as that offered by Labov (1972, cited by Riessman 1993,

p.18). While broad interpretations of narrative such as the illness narratives are

compelling and aid our phenomenological understandings, they provide little

structure or form for the systematic analysis required from a research methodology

(Riessman, 1993, p.17).

Narrative scholars generally agree that narratives are stories about specific past

events that have a clear beginning, middle and end. Some argue for chronological

sequencing, while others reject this rigidity noting that not all narratives are ‘stories’

in the linguistic sense (Riessman, 1993, p.18). Labov’s (1972) structural approach

focuses on short narrative segments and seeks the presence of six defining properties

of a narrative being (1) an abstract, (2) an orientation in time and space, (3) a

complicating action, (4) an evaluation of the significance and meaning of the action,

(5) a resolution and finally (6) a coda that returns the listener to the present. Others,

such as Labov (1972), adopt a more technical linguistic approach looking for the

shape and form of the language, such as pitch, fall, repetition, emphasis and syntax

in exploring the features of narrative for analysis. In some of her work, Riessman

(1993) has adopted an analysis style that creates stanzas of form, looking for

emerging rhythms and patterns, while Clandinin and Connelly (2000) define 24 See for example Cassell, 1991; A. Frank, 1995; Kleinman, 1988; Sparkes & Smith, 2005; Toombs, 2001 .

Page 90: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

90

narrative as both a phenomenon under study and a means or method of study. Some

researchers such as Bell (1988 cited by Riessman, 1993) talk of narratives in terms

of reducing the whole story to a ‘core narrative’ (in a process that Riessman, (1993,

p.43) describes as ‘radical surgery’), that can be extracted and compared with other

reduced core narratives, while Bruner (1991) further defines narrative in terms of ten

key distinguishing features24F

25. While features of plot, scene, temporality, breach and

agency flow through these different approaches, not all narratives fall so obligingly

into these categories.

In thinking about narrative interpretation, Riessman (2004) makes a further (loose)

categorisation of narratives into four types of analysis these being 1.Thematic (what

is said); 2. Structural (how it is said); 3.Interpretive (dialogical co-construction) and

4. Performative (analysis of social action). As Riessman (ibid) notes, the boundaries

between these forms of analysis is hazy, and various approaches may be combined,

hence, narrative methodologies are not recipes to be followed to the letter, but may

themselves evolve. This view is echoed by Andrea Doucet (2006, p.278) who writes,

‘while methods begin with particular ontological and epistemological conceptions,

these can be transformed as they move through the hands and minds of varied

researchers’.

Others propose that every narrative is ‘plurivocal’ (Gilligan, Spencer, Weinberg, &

Bertsch, 2003; Riessman, 1993), or open to several readings/listenings or

constructions and interpretations, even for the same reader. From a

phenomenological ethical stance such as that adopted in Chapter Two, the notion

that narrative texts may contain several threads or layers of meaning was particularly

resonant. As the phenomenological tradition accepts a multilayered, interpretive and

relationally embedded account of human ontology, a narrative mode of inquiry that

specifically recognises multiple co-occurring narrative threads presents a

philosophically and methodologically coherent means of inquiry. Additionally, from

a linguistic sense, a word may evoke different responses from the listener/reader on

25 Bruner’s ten features of narrative are 1. Events that occur over time, 2. Particularity, 3. Intentional and agentic, 4. Hermeneutic composability, 5. Canonicity and breach, 6. Referentiality, 7. Genericness, 8. Normative ness, 9. Context sensitivity and negotiability, and 10. Narrative accrual.

Page 91: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

91

different readings. In that sense, the reader is a collaborator in how the text is

interpreted (Riessman, 1993, p.14), thus the listener (or reader), the researcher and

the narrator all exhibit some agency in what story is told. Acknowledging the

plurality of stories being told within ‘a’ story, and the dialogically constructed

nature of our understandings thus resonates strongly with the phenomenological and

hermeneutical orientation of this work.

One such mode of narrative analysis which intentionally embraces the multifaceted,

subjective and relational nature of narrative is the Listening Guide (Gilligan et al.,

2003). This guide has been in development and use by Carol Gilligan and numerous

colleagues (Brown & Gilligan, 1991; Brown, Tappan, Gilligan, Miller, & Argyris,

1989; Gilligan, 1982, 1996; McLean-Taylor, Gilligan, & Sullivan, 1995),

undergoing some refinements and transformations since its original form was

published in the late 1980’s. Drawing on Gilligan’s (1982) work on identity and

moral development, viewed through the professional lens of psychology, the method

acknowledges the multilayered nature of the human psyche as expressed through a

multiplicity of voices. As a voice-centred, relational method of narrative analysis

the ‘Listening Guide’ ‘draws on voice, resonance, and relationships as ports of

entry in to the human psyche’ (Gilligan et al., 2003, p.157). Gilligan et al (ibid)

further explain,

‘because every person has a voice or a way of speaking or communication

that renders the silent invisible inner world audible or visible to another, the

method is universal in application….Thus each person’s voice is distinct - a

footprint of the psyche, bearing the marks of the body, of that person’s

history, of culture in the form of language, and the myriad ways in which

human society and history shape the voice and thus leave their imprints on

the human soul’.

Thus the ‘Listening Guide’ provides a particularly appropriate framework in this

project, because it holds an embedded, embodied, relational and subjective view of

human ontology at its core. Furthermore, it places emphasis on individual

participants who are best equipped to articulate their own personal accounts. Many

Page 92: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

92

social researchers have embraced and adapted this method to their particular

research goals (Balan, 2005; Doucet, 2006; Kersten, 2007; Lewthwaite, 1999;

Mauthner, 1998; Mauthner & Doucet, 1998; Raider-Roth, 2005; Spencer, 2002;

Waithe, 2005; Woodcock, 2005). Use of the Listening Guide has similarly

facilitated a multilayered and systematic course of analysis in this research.

The Listening Guide

After transcription, the collected interviews were analysed and interpreted using

Gilligan’s relational ‘Listening Guide’ method (Gilligan et al., 2003). Doucet

(2006, p.65) describes the Listening Guide as an approach to data analysis that

‘combines reflexivity and subjectivity while also focussing on narrative and story

telling’. In keeping with the hermeneutic theoretical orientation towards ethics

embraced throughout this work, the ‘Listening Guide’ provided a framework of

analysis which acknowledged that humans develop in relation to one another, living

embodied lives that are deeply embedded in social contexts. Therefore, the

experiences offered are inextricably linked to and defined by the broader social,

cultural, and historical relationships to others (Balan, 2005; Doucet, 2006;

Mauthner, 1998; Mauthner & Doucet, 1998; Raider-Roth, 2005; Waithe, 2005).

Rather than coding and quantifying the interview text, this method of qualitative

analysis focuses on a series of three sequential ‘listenings’ to each interview as an

intentional and deliberate strategy of analysis (Gilligan et al., 2003). The purpose of

the three, consecutive ‘listenings’ stems from an acknowledgement that

simultaneous and sometimes conflicting stories can co-occur within the same

narrative text, therefore the freedom to interpret multiple times preserves the

complexity and situatedness of each story told (ibid). This analysis differs from

traditional narrative analysis25F

26, and recognises that much of the meaning conveyed

within an in-depth discussion cannot be successfully captured by ‘reducing to codes’

(England, 1994, p.212. cited by Bridle, 2004, p152) as embracing the embedded

context of the narrative is crucial in preserving its intention.

26 Traditional analysis includes rigid coding and computer generation of themes, which often preclude access to the multifaceted and plurivocal feature of narrative.

Page 93: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

93

Within the Listening Guide, each listening focused on a different aspect of the

narrative.

• The first listening focused on ‘plot’ and the listener response to the

interview.

• The second focused on the “voice of ‘I’”, and sought to understand how the

interviewee regarded themselves by examining statements made in the first

person.

• The third listening searched for the counterpoint of the story put forward,

which Gilligan calls the ‘contrapuntal voice’.

• The fourth and final stage of this guide was to compose a summary in which

all three ‘listenings’ were pulled together and summarised in relation to what

they reveal about responses to the research questions (Gilligan et al., 2003).

Each of these listenings will now be considered in more detail.

Step 1: Listening for ‘Plot’

Ginsberg (cited by Riessman, 1993, p30) determines the plot to be the point at which

a narrative turns away from that which is expected, while Bruner (1991) explains

plot in terms of ‘trouble’ or ‘canonicity’ and ‘breach’ with respect to the dominant

cultural story. However, ‘plot’ is a rich and versatile word that has many nuances

depending on the context of its use. As a noun, it may be interpreted as a thing of

intrigue, with conspiratorial undertones. It may also be defined as the area or section

on which our attention is focussed. Gilligan et al. (2003) regard plot as what is

happening and attend to the multiple contexts in which the story is embedded.

Gilligan et al (ibid) further describe ‘the plot’ as defining where we are on the

landscape, what features are on the landscape, and what is happening in relation to

the larger social and cultural context within which stories are situated. Thus

questions relating to plot include: What themes are emerging? Are the themes

related? Are there contradictions in the themes? Are certain perspectives silenced?

And, what is the story’s subtext?

Page 94: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

94

As a verb, the word ‘plot’ can allude to how one charts, navigates or negotiates a

course across a landscape or around various obstacles. Applying the analogy of a

landscape further, it can be helpful to consider ‘plot’ (v.) as how the various

stakeholders navigated their way around the various themes (from the topic list) or

features on the landscape. As the plot or direction of each person’s journey is

influenced by and filtered through the multiple interpretive lenses of culture,

tradition, institution and community, the course of the journey, which is shaped by

these pre-existing interpretive frameworks, may provide further links into the

broader social dynamics that define the cultural and medical master narratives of

prenatal screening. Thus ‘plot’ can be simultaneously thought of as a verb, how we

travel, and as a noun, focussing attention on the terrain and themes we cross.

In the analysis phase, a key was developed from the scatterlist of topics to classify

them into four broad categories, each directly related to the research questions (see

Appendix IV). The four narrative categories related to informed consent, agency or

constrained agency, comments made about the effectiveness or adequacy of the

educational opportunities, or role of education in the process, and finally all thoughts

or ideas offered about how the process may be transformed in the future. An

additional column was added to identify the contrapuntal voices 26F

27 present.

Condensing the texts in this way enabled me to look for repeat metaphors and

images, and draw comparisons between all accounts.

Gilligan et al (2003) advocate a second phase of the first listening, which compels

the listener/researcher to reflect upon, acknowledge and appreciate the impact the

story has upon them (Gilligan et al., 2003). Because the researcher is never a

completely neutral observer, being always already constituted themselves, it is

through this reflective step that the researcher can orient themselves both socially,

culturally and intellectually in relation to the participant (Mauthner & Doucet,

1998). This step encourages the researcher to acknowledge their own emotional

response to the participant’s story, to consciously consider how the theoretical

interpretations of the respondent’s narrative are formed. This step invites a

systematic way of alerting the researcher to ‘who’ is speaking, in what context and

27 See Step 3 of the Listening Guide.

Page 95: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

95

within which societal or cultural framework (Gilligan et al., 2003). It was in this

‘listening’ that the necessary links to situate the individual narratives within the

wider cultural framework could be made. In this sense, the analysis was, as Laverty

(2006, p. 14) describes it, ‘a cyclical process’, that involved making meaning from

individual stories by ‘revisiting, re-interpreting and finding deeper meaning in the

texts’.

Step 2 – ‘I Poems’

The purpose of the ‘I’ poem as described by Gilligan and Spencer et al. (2003) is to

intentionally focus ‘the listener’ on the first person voice of ‘the teller’, and

actively attend to what this person, the “I” in the story, has to say about themselves

before presuming to be equipped to talk about them (ibid, p.162). This step further

invites the listener to acknowledge a relational dialogical stance to the interviewee

rather than viewing the research as a distanced and objectified monologue.

While Gilligan et al (2003) advocate the production of ‘I poems’ by extracting all

instances of the ‘I’ in the transcript with its accompanying verb, following the brief

and decontextualised example provided in the above mentioned paper created

disjointed ‘poems’ that were often contradictory to the clear intention of the whole

text. For that reason, a fuller account of the ‘I poem’ was formed which included

contextual clarification anchoring the ‘I’ statements to the context in which they

were made. Similar approaches to extending the ‘I poem’ have been taken by other

users of the Listening Guide (Balan, 2005; Doucet, 2006; Mauthner & Doucet,

1998) and in this instance, the extended approach provided a more meaningful

account of the ‘I’ story, which more truly represented the intention of focussing the

researcher on each individual’s situated account of themselves. The extended ‘I’

poem became a crucial and powerful part of the analysis, succinctly illuminating the

often conflicting and contradictory thought processes that were occurring in the

participants being interviewed. As a condensed story within a story, it was often

through reading the ‘I poem’ that the plurivocal and multilayered nature of each

narrative became highlighted, uncovering the various internal tensions and

contrapuntal voices contained within.

Page 96: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

96

Another striking observation flowing from the ‘I poem’ was the realisation that the

‘I poem’ paradoxically dispelled the myth of the punctual autonomous, individual ‘I’

that flows through some philosophical understandings of ontology in medical

practice and bioethics as discussed in Chapter Two. A common feature of all the

interviewees’ ‘I poems’ was that the ‘I’ statements were inevitably accompanied by

relational qualifiers, linking the ‘I’ to their embedded world of relationships with

significant others27F

28, and explaining their actions in terms of preserving or

negotiating these relationships. Therefore the ‘I poems’ unexpectedly supported a

key orientation of this research that argues against the rationalist presumptions of

detached, autonomous, and atomistic beings and acknowledges that individual

decisions are not remote, rationally constructed autonomous choices, but rather

deeply embedded, embodied and deeply relationally constrained.

To illustrate the power and relevance of the ‘I poem’, the following section of

narrative is taken from an interview with Terri, who at 38 found herself

unexpectedly pregnant with her fourth child. Terri’s cousin had recently given birth

to a child with Noonan’s disease, a relatively uncommon genetic disorder occurring

in around 1 in 1000 to 1 in 2500 live births (Tartaglia et al., 2003). In the back of

her mind, Terri held concerns for her baby that focussed on the potential presence of

Noonan’s that had recently occurred in her extended family, and she expressed these

specific concerns to her doctor. She was advised to have a nuchal screen with

accompanying blood tests and on the basis of this result was further advised to

undergo amniocentesis. The ‘risk’28F

29 of having a child with Down syndrome was

presented to Terri as 1:500, considerably lower than the published risk of 1:177

based on age alone (DSAQ), so Terri was clearly at lower risk than her age alone

would indicate. She declined the offer of amniocentesis due to concerns about

miscarriage and was asked to sign a consent form outlining her rejection of further

testing. During the following weeks, Terri undertook her own investigations during

which she discovered that none of the testing she had been offered would have

answered her specific concerns about her child having Noonan’s Syndrome. All

28 For example, references to ‘they’, ‘them’, ‘he’ , ‘she’, and ‘it’ reflect a relational stance to the others who significantly shape each individual’s story. 29 The encumbered language of ‘risk’ will be more thoroughly explored in Chapter Seven.

Page 97: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

97

testing carried out was centred primarily on detecting a child with Down syndrome,

a possibility Terri had not previously considered and had not directly inquired about.

She describes her frame of mind for the remainder of her pregnancy as ‘a tender

state’, ‘almost depressed’ and ‘vulnerable’ right up until the birth of her son. She

concluded that she had been through this experience ‘for nothing’, both because the

testing did not address her specific concerns and because her son was born ‘beautiful

and perfect in every way’.

Terri’s narrative account of her experience began like this:

T: I went public to XXX public hospital and I had Dr XXX there, and I guess

because I was a bit older… … there were questions asked and it was almost

assumed that there were certain things I should do. I was asked quite a few

times whether I wanted these tests done, I was also a little bit concerned

myself because my cousin had recently, in similar circumstances with a

surprise pregnancy, had a child who was severely handicapped, to the degree

that he spend the first few years of his life almost constantly in hospital or

some sort of care. I was a little bit concerned about that, because that’s the

first child in our family to ever be born with that sort of thing. I guess being

older, I was 38… … because I had gone over the 35 ‘hill’, over the hill

……[laughs], …..A lot of the doctors & nurses who saw me were saying

‘what sort of tests would you like … … we need to be careful.’

E: Was it presented as an option or was it more presented as something you

were expected to do?

T: I felt it was a case of I ‘should’ have the tests … I ended up having the

blood, the triple test, I was concerned about what my cousin’s child had – I

believe it was Noonan’s Syndrome? I talked to the doctors about that and

they said I should have the blood test, and another ………..the nuchal fold

test on ultrasound. With the blood test, it came up that I had a 1:500 chance

of having a baby with Down syndrome, but the ultrasound showed no signs

at all.

E: How was that risk explained to you?

T: It was presented as high risk; definitely, they said ‘it’s a high risk’… …

Page 98: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

98

E: Who explained the result to you……what did it mean to you?

T: I had 3 separate doctors ring me from XXX hospital, I believe they were

registrars, I had never spoken to any of them before, and they all said that to

me. There was one lady in particular who was quite adamant that I needed to

come in and have an amnio – it was very much put to me that I needed

[emphasis] to do that, and I needed to do it as soon as possible [emphasis]

because if there was to be a decision made, it had to be made quickly29F

30.

The ‘I’ poem that emerged from this section of the text follows:-

I went public

I had Dr XXX

I guess because

I was a bit older

[Things] I should do

I was asked

[Whether] I wanted these tests done,

I was also a little bit concerned

I was a little bit concerned about that,

I guess being older,

I was 38

I had gone over the 35 ‘hill’, over the hill [laughs]

I felt it was a case of I ‘should’

I ended up having the blood, the triple test,

I was concerned about what my cousin’s child had

I believe it was Noonan’s Syndrome

I talked to the doctors about that

[They said] I should have the blood test, and the nuchal fold

I had a 1:500 chance of having a baby with Down syndrome

I had 3 separate doctors ring me from XXX hospital, 30 Note the use of impersonal third person language here that depersonalises and detaches ‘the decision’ from any person who may make ‘it’.

Page 99: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

99

I believe they were registrars,

I had never spoken to any of them before

[They were quite adamant]

I needed to come in and have an amnio

[They said]

I needed [emphasis] to do that

I needed to do it as soon as possible

This ‘I’ poem reveals several key points of interest that capture the complexity of

the competing considerations that influence decision making of whether to embark

upon a prenatal screening regime. The first and most obvious observation that Terri

makes about herself is that she, and others, interpret her age as a significant issue.

This automatic assignation of ‘high risk’ for women over 35, as Lippman (1991)

notes, ensures compliance with screening, which is presented as a risk lowering

strategy. Terri’s existing level of anxiety about her age, coupled with her cousin’s

recent experience of having a child with a somewhat rare genetic disorder and strong

recommendations from medical staff, all contributed to her perceived pressure to

embrace testing. Although this is a relatively short extract, it clearly speaks to a

broad range of issues across the research questions posed in this thesis. For example,

the routine nature of screening is identified, as is her physicians’ expectation of what

the responsible course of action should be30F

31. In addition, trust in medical staff and

the sometimes pressured and overtly directive nature of advice all feature in this

short extract, all themes around which the plot weaves. Terri repeatedly notes that

she felt she should engage in the screening on offer, frequently giving reference to

the strong directions of what ‘they’, her doctors, said should be happening, despite

her own uncertain feelings. Terri’s account reveals her embeddedness in her culture

which entrenches that she is ‘over the hill’ at 38, her embeddedness in her family (in

which her cousin has recently had a child with a genetic disorder), a cultural norm

that entrenches a normative expectation of what responsible mothers ‘should’ do to

prevent disability in the community and a cultural norm in which the medicalisation

of pregnancy is automatic and largely unquestioned.

31 Chapter Seven explores the social expectations of responsible pregnant behaviour.

Page 100: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

100

The remainder of the interview revealed that Terri’s presumption that her doctors

had listened to her specific concerns, although it later transpired that in her opinion

they hadn’t, created distrust and distress, resulting in what Bruner would call

‘breach’ (Bruner, 1991). She had begun the process seeking re-assurance but

instead found ongoing confusion as a result of the unclear results and malleable

interpretations of what constitutes a ‘high’ risk.

The remainder of Terri’s ‘I’ poem is worthy of inclusion because it provides a clear

insight into the interview and highlights the crux of her thoughts on the whole

experience, touching on other key features related to the research question posed

such as informed consent, the education process she experienced, the constrained

nature of agency and her competing interpretations of her situation.

I was over 35

I was very concerned (that three doctors had called within 24 hours)

I said I didn’t want to do that (amnio)

I knew there was a 1:200 chance

I could have a miscarriage

I decided 1:500 was better odds

I just said no

I think they made me sign a consent form

I had said ‘no’

I did my own research

I found that out

I just got on the internet

I thought I’ve done this for nothing

I was quite anxious

I had known children with Down syndrome

I was concerned because of the severity of my cousins’ child

(Now) I wasn’t as concerned about Noonan’s

I was more concerned about Downs

Page 101: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

101

(After) I did have him

I was looking at him through the crib

I was looking

I just thought - has no-one else noticed that?

I couldn’t see he wasn’t Downs

I had never considered it in the past

I was so disappointed

I would never have thought of that

I definitely wasn’t prepared for other problems being flagged

I really wasn’t interested in finding that out

I had the attitude if God had given me this child then…………

(maybe) I was being selective

I could see how hard it was from her [cousin] to cope

I wasn’t planning on being pregnant

I was having trouble coming to grips

I was in a bit of a tender state

I did ask questions

(maybe) I just didn’t ask the right questions

I certainly mustn’t have

I was concerned

I would say there was a lapse in communication

I put trust in the midwives

I had a very difficult delivery

I do think communication issues are a bit of a problem here

I think it comes down to speed of service

I think maybe it was worse than I thought

I felt there had been a communication breakdown

I thought I did at the time [have enough understanding]

Page 102: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

102

I thought I was informed

I obviously wasn’t as informed as I should have been

I certainly wasn’t informed

I would have to make choices

I’m sure there are lots of women in the same boat

I think each parent should get a piece of paper, so they can read and

re-read

I guess I was a bit muddled

I would really have filtered it

I wouldn’t have told him ( her partner) everything

It was a worrying time for me……

I couldn’t put it out of my mind

I got to the end

I just wanted it to be over

I think I was almost depressed

I was wondering if I had a child with Down syndrome

I suppose it all comes back to being informed

I was pretty much up on the language

I just felt conscious of trying to ask the right questions

The ‘I poem’ also strongly illuminated the presence of ‘others’ shaping the story,

‘they’ to whom she stands in relation to, as well as revealing the distancing and

detached language of ‘a decision’, and ‘it would have to be made’. These

observations also uncovered some of the underlying power dynamics that shape

behaviour and provided further connections to the broader cultural dynamics at play.

As Gilligan et al (2003, p.164) suggest, the ‘I poem’ clarifies the ‘hearing’ of a

range of potential variations in the first person voice, including ‘a range of themes,

harmonies, dissonances and shifts’, which prepared the groundwork for the next

phase of analysis, which was listening for contrapuntal voices.

Page 103: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

103

Step 3- Listening for Contrapuntal Voices

Gilligan et al (2003) contend that each person expresses their experience through a

multiplicity of voices, hence, listening for ‘contrapuntal’ voices or counterpoints in

the story forms an important part of the Listening Guide. Contrapuntal voices are

likened by Gilligan et al (2003) as akin to a musical chord in which several notes

may be played simultaneously creating harmonic or dissonant sounds. Thus, these

concurrent threads or ‘melodic lines’ that run through each narrative may be

complementary or contradictory, and are not necessarily regarded as in opposition to

each other (ibid, p.165). In drawing attention to the counterpoints of the main story

different ways of ‘hearing and developing an understanding of several different

layers of a person’s expressed experience as it bears on the questions posed’ (ibid.

p.164) are offered. Balan (2005, p.6) makes the further claim that identifying and

incorporating the contrapuntal voices contained within participants’ stories provides

an additional layer of richness to the overall interpretation and findings.

The initial two listenings of the Listening Guide focused attention on becoming

attuned to the multiple distinct voices contained within the text (Balan, 2005;

Gilligan et al., 2003; McLean-Taylor et al., 1995; Raider-Roth, 2005). From these

observations, as Gilligan et al (2003, p.168) suggest, an initial description of the

distinct ‘other’ voices was made and their relevance to the research scope and

analysis was assessed. Each identified contrapuntal voice was then listened for, one

at a time, throughout the whole transcript. Like the observations made by Balan

(2005) and Raider-Roth (2005), the number and nature of the contrapuntal voices

heard in this research differed between participants, and participant groups, varying

from between two and five contrapuntal voices running through each text, but

containing many overlaps and similarities. The following tables summarise the

prevalence and type of contrapuntal voices, the descriptors of which are largely self

explanatory, present in the participants’ narratives.

Page 104: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

104

Table 1. Contrapuntal Voices – Mothers Table2. Contrapuntal Voices - Practitioners.

Within the mothers’ cohort three contrapuntal voices dominated. They were;

• The Voice of Care

• The Voice of Capitulation/Acquiescence

• The Awakened Voice

While within the practitioners’ cohort, two voices clearly dominated the texts being:

• The Voice of Professional Objectivity/Clarity, and

• The Voice of Care

The most markedly prevalent voices from each group will now be briefly discussed.

• The Voice of Care (Mothers)

The voice of care was characterised in mothers in each recounting of how they had

acted to preserve their child’s well being, illustrated by the actions taken to protect

Mothers (7 )

Present

Care

IIIIIII

Capitulation

IIIII

‘Awakened’ voice (Balan, 2005)

IIIII

Voice of Clarity

IIII

Voice of Resistance

IIII

Voice of Reproach

III

Voice of Contradiction

II

Self Doubt

II

Voice of Self interest/ control

I

Practitioners (11)

Present

Professional objectivity/clarity

IIIIIII

Care

IIIIIII

Self doubt

IIII

Dismay/despair/disappointment

IIII

Self preservation

III

Detachment/disconnection

III

Professional Defensiveness

II

Condescension

I

Control

I

Page 105: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

105

the welfare of their unborn child. This voice was identified in the narratives of all

mothers. Some examples included,

This child is my child, whether there is something wrong with it or not….My goals as a mother are much more personal, it’s about the love for the child, the desire to have the child and its well being naturally…….but, that the child is mine and it’s about looking to the future with joy and excitement that a new child brings. Anne; You could lose a healthy baby, when there was only a 1:300 chance of the baby having Downs…….it was too big a risk to lose a possibly healthy baby, Danielle; I came home, sat on the couch for 2 days and didn’t move’ (to minimise the risk of miscarriage after amniocentesis).Leanne; I just think that everyone has a value, regardless of what that may be; who can say someone is a less valuable person in our community than a child who doesn’t have special needs? Elizabeth.

• The Voice of Capitulation (Mothers)

An example of the Voice of Capitulation was present in five of the mothers’ stories,

defined as the voice of surrender or submission. This contrapuntal voice spoke

clearly to the constrained nature of presumed agency and illuminated the multiple

sources that undermined or disempowered women in their interactions with their

health practitioners and their significant others. Markers of the contrapuntal voice of

capitulation were use of words like should, or have to, or language of excuse that

revealed an unease, unrest or disquiet. Some examples of this voice follow taken

from various transcripts.

I guess because I was a bit older… … it was almost assumed that there were certain things I should do. I guess being older, I was 38, because I had gone over the 35 ‘hill’, over the hill [laughs], a lot of the doctors and nurses who saw me were saying ‘what sort of tests would you like - we need to be careful’. Terri; I said……Do I really have to?………………..because I’d seen the same obstetrician for all my (three) pregnancies he said ‘Well, we need to because of what happened last time….just to rule anything out’. Mary; It was assumed I take it that they thought I wanted the ultrasound done but I wasn’t aware of the medical reasons why. Penny; I honestly thought it was just a routine exercise that you had to do……….the hospital said you had to do certain tests at certain times…Danielle.

Page 106: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

106

• The Awakened Voice (Mothers)

Nicole Balan (2005, p.11) describes the ‘awakened voice’ in the context of her

research as the voice which emerges when the person acknowledges and affirms

their own needs. This descriptor similarly resonated with the ‘awakened’ voice

identified in the narratives of some mothers. The awakened voice is therefore a

voice of empowerment, marking a change in orientation from the perception of

subjugation to the wishes and expectations of others, towards claiming an intentional

direction towards ones own needs. Some examples follow,

I just got on the internet; it took 15 minutes, it’s amazing what you can find there. I thought I've done this for nothing. I said no …I just said no. Terri; It was like I had to say ‘yes I have decided not to take that option’………….I never regretted not having the amnio. Danielle; I just felt like screaming…………at everyone…………….just for the whole….I was really glad that everything was OK, but I didn’t like the way it was done. Mary; We just tended to dig our heels in …..rather than be pressured…..it wasn’t that we had more questions, we just said no…..no discussion…no matter what you say….we didn’t need more education or information at that stage, we just said no…… we’re not doing it…Penny.

For health practitioners the two dominant contrapuntal voices were those of

professional objectivity and clarity and again, the voice of care.

• The Voice of Professional Objectivity/Clarity

This voice was defined as the detached, methodical and objective professional voice.

While this voice may represent an attempt by the practitioner to distance themselves

from the complex moral terrain of cultures, prejudices, histories, vulnerabilities and

emotions inherent within reproductive medicine, a successful therapeutic partnership

requires some degree of objectivity. Some examples follow,

I would, in broad terms, discuss the validity matrices that are used, the combination of both imaging and serology being used to form a matrix. I would discuss the fact that these are predictive in nature but not conclusive. General Practitioner 1; Well, the nuchal translucency has about a 75% pick up for Down syndrome, it can pick up other chromosomal abnormalities that are a bit more common such as trisomy 13 and 18, but it was really geared towards Down syndrome. In fact I think

Page 107: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

107

it’s about 90% pick up for those, but that’s not many people know about that, so that’s not the advertised part of it, or well known. If you combine the blood test with the ultrasound (NT), that gives around a 90% pick up for Down syndrome, and similarly 95% for trisomy 13 and 18. Obstetrician.

• The Voice of Care

The voice of care for patients strongly resonated through many of the practitioners’

narratives, expressing care that patients be nurtured and supported through this

unfamiliar and potentially alienating process, and care that any potential harms that

may arise in the process of any medical interventions be minimised. The committed

voice of care is illustrated below,

Its also part of my job to be an advocate for them, and not see them make decisions that cause conflict later on ………..when they may say ‘I didn’t realise that when I made that decision, it would lead to that, and that and so on…………and I wish back then that I hadn’t started down that path’ General Practitioner 2; You have to keep trying until you find something that works for that individual, and it may be something different for the husband than for the wife, but I see that as my role in helping them interpret what is essentially a foreign language, that’s how I see it………and it is… really. Genetic Counsellor 2; Establishing that rapport is probably an important aspect of developing that trust ……….I mean …..It’s probably a very important aspect, I guess, why should they believe you? Clinical Geneticist; When I get the shared care booklet back from (X) hospital, I add my cell phone number and you’d be amazed the number of girls these days who give you a call at 2am in the morning because they are lying there and the baby’s kicking them to death but they still don’t understand what the bloody test meant…….or they e-mail you because they’ve read something on the web. General Practitioner 1;

You don’t tell women those things… because you don’t want them to worry. Obstetrician. While many contrapuntal voices were present in the narratives of participants, the

five dominant voices perhaps provide some insight into the source of ethical tension

present in the prenatal screening debate. Interestingly both groups were significantly

motivated by care, whether care for a potential child or care for a patient. However,

even with the supposedly common goal of care at the core, many tensions are

Page 108: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

108

present throughout the narratives arising from the clearly differing expectations, or

culturally endorsed expectations of how such care should be actualised.

Additionally, the strong presence of the ‘awakened voice’, which often replaced the

voice of capitulation suggests that for the mothers in whom this voice was present,

after the misunderstandings of their initial compliance or capitulation were exposed,

they did for the most part regain a sense of personal control and agency in pursing a

pathway that better reflected their own moral frameworks. However, for some this

came at the potentially avoidable cost of great emotional distress, anxiety and

alienation as will be discussed in Chapter Eight.

Contrapuntal voices – A window on individual moral frameworks?

While the presence of contrapuntal voices is acknowledged by many researchers

adopting this method of analysis (Balan, 2005; Gilligan et al., 2003; McLean-Taylor

et al., 1995; Raider-Roth, 2005), the underlying meaning or ethical import of the

contrapuntal voice has not yet been made explicit. Yet, contrapuntal voices are

morally significant from a phenomenological perspective in terms of what they

reveal about multiple layers of embeddedness and subjectivity, about the competing

strong evaluations, and the pluralities of goods that form and inform individual

moral horizons (Taylor, 1989). While consideration of what constitutes a ‘good’ or

‘harm’ may be a matter of disagreement, consideration of the contrapuntal voices

illuminate this subjective characterisation held by the particular individual.

Contrapuntal voices suggest the presence of a range of strong evaluations (ibid),

highlighting that individuals (who are embedded within communal moral

frameworks) do not embrace one singular ‘hypergood’ per se, but rather that

individual and community moral horizons are forged through the unique fusion and

interweaving of multiple goods. Contrapuntal voices therefore open a window on the

inner self dialogue, revealing the tensions between these strong evaluations, often

negotiating a course not between good and bad or right and wrong, but the more

ethically challenging pathway between competing goods (ibid). Contrapuntal voices

reveal something of how we position ourselves in relation to the goods we hold in

esteem, uncovering the deeply subjective account of our embeddedness. The

Page 109: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

109

interconnectedness of the voice, the phenomenological account of ontology which

positions the self as embedded, interpretive and relational, and ethics are thus

revealed in these co-occurring contrapuntal voices. For some however, rather than

revealing a fusion of horizons as Taylor (ibid) suggests, these often competing

strands that run through the contrapuntal voices may represent the conflicting

embeddedness of a confusion of horizons (Isaacs, 2007, p.18).

Thus actively attending to the muddy complexity of the plurivocal, contrapuntal

voices draws specific attention to the ethical aspects of the broader social, political,

cultural, and technological contexts, exposing links to the wider narratives that

shape the ethical terrain of prenatal screening. Contrapuntal voices therefore reveal

that there can be no singular transcendental ethic or hypergood per se (such as the

elevation of rationality), rather, the ethical is characterised by a plurality of ‘goods’

located within the complex interweaving and overlapping of individually constituted

(and frequently professionally derived) moral frameworks. The need to open shared

moral spaces institutionally, to create a space of shared interlocution, is therefore an

ethical imperative as it is within these spaces that the pluralities of understandings of

what is ethically ‘good’ may be built and the best moral outcomes maybe negotiated

as part of an ongoing, dynamic and evolving moral conversation.

Step 4 - Summary

The fourth step in the listening guide calls for the listener/researcher to summarise

and interpret the stories in a way that ‘pulls together and synthesizes what has been

learned through the entire process’ (ibid, p.168) in relation to the research

questions. This complete process of analysis was undertaken for all nineteen

participants.

Using Terri’s example once more, in addition to the previous descriptions of her

experience, a final summary was written with regards to the multiple listenings to

the story and layers of analysis and included the further thoughts. The final summary

follows:

Page 110: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

110

Throughout the interview Terri consistently uses the phrase “I should”,

highlighting a nagging voice of self silencing, suggestive of feelings that she

was coaxed down this pathway against her better instincts, and she now feels

somehow culpable and complicit in the distressing experience she endured,

thus, because of her compliance in it – she feels it is unreasonable to criticise

others.

In terms of the research questions, Terri’s explanations of her decision to

accept the offer of prenatal screening illuminate many key issues relating to

the research questions. The routine nature of screening obscured ‘choice’ for

her, while social expectations of responsible behaviour, given her ‘advanced’

age, permeated her thinking. In terms of informed consent, she

acknowledges that in retrospect she was ill informed about the potential

negative consequences of undergoing a nuchal scan although she felt

informed at the time. She notes paradoxically, that her ‘informed consent’ to

reject her doctor’s advice on amnio was sought in writing, while her

‘informed consent’ to accept the nuchal scan was presumed and her

understandings never canvassed. This illuminates the defensive legal

orientation that informed consent protocols often address in clinical care that

may have been exacerbated by the poor communication between Terri and

her doctors. Educational opportunities prior to testing were limited and when

a problem was suspected, all of the information that Terri came to rely on to

consider her situation came from self directed learning outside the medical

team.

The ‘I poem’ illustrates Terri’s connectedness to her family, and situatedness

in a culture of medical intervention and expected socially responsible

behaviour. Terri’s story also highlights the poor educational opportunities

she encountered and provides suggestions of where she felt this process

could be positively transformed, which link Terri’s entire story to the wider

social structures, entrenched ideologies and dominant discourses under

consideration.

Page 111: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

111

Limitations and Challenges

Although the link between narrative, ethics, experience and embedded

understanding is widely viewed as philosophically coherent and methodologically

appropriate amongst humanities researchers (Bruner, 1991; Clandinin & Connelly,

2000; Connelly, 2005; Laverty, 2006; Mishler, 1986; Riessman, 1993; Riessman,

2004), numerous criticisms have been levelled at narrative research methodologies

including the following:

• The strongly particular nature of narrative undermines its generalisability.

• The small and statistically ‘invalid’ samples traditionally canvassed for in-

depth narrative research further undermines generalisability.

• As narrative accounts offered are subjective and intersubjective they may be

biased and not reproducible.

• Narratives do not conform to accepted notions of ‘validity’. The subjective

nature of ‘stories’ may give latitude to participants to embellish, lie or

misrepresent ‘the facts’(Hardwig, 1997, p.52).

• The ‘snapshot’ nature of the narrative means outcomes are not enduring.

Each of these concerns emanates from a particular and limited view of what the

desired characteristics of research should be, privileging generalisability, validity,

reproducibility and objectivity. These characteristics emanate from the language and

epistemological orientation towards ‘knowing’, based on the presumed neutrality of

‘facts’, within popularly held views of scientific methodologies which have become

highly esteemed (Chalmers, 1999). However Bruner (2004, p.94) notes,

‘although the language of science, cloaked in the rhetoric of objectivity,

makes every effort to conceal that view except when it is concerned with the

foundations of its field……… they betray the fact that the so-called data of

science are constructed observations that are designed with a point of view

in mind’.

Page 112: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

112

Rather than aiming for validity, generalisability or reliability in the scientific sense,

a more fitting aim for qualitative research (including narrative) is to seek

explanation, authenticity, adequacy and plausibility (Bruner, 1986, 1991, 2004;

Clandinin & Connelly, 2000; Connelly & Clandinin, 1990; Mishler, 1986;

Polkinghorne, 1988; Riessman, 1993; Riessman, 2004). In discussing the tensions

that exist between these ‘two modes of thought’, Bruner notes, ‘efforts to reduce one

mode to the other or to ignore one at the expense of the other inevitably fails to

capture the rich diversity of thought’ (Bruner, 1986, p.11). However ‘wakefulness’

and proactive consideration of these potential concerns is necessary in order to

consolidate our understandings (Clandinin & Connelly, 2000).

While steps are taken in the methodology to preserve the integrity of the

participants’ voices, by positioning the researcher as ‘listener’ rather then teller, by

having a predetermined ‘topic list’ to focus inquiry, by checking with participants if

they have been misrepresented and by being transparent and reflective about these

multiple influences, in reality there are no failsafe methodological ways to identify

and totally negate all potential biases. All one can do as a researcher is adhere to the

rigours of the methodology adopted, be cognisant of its potential limitations and not

make claims beyond the methods’ capacity to deliver.

Chapter Summary

This chapter explored the central importance of narrative as an ethically and

ontologically appropriate means of accessing the personal experiences of all

participants. As embedded experiential accounts, personal narratives necessarily

open a window on the wider social, cultural, historical and institutional forces that

shape the practice of prenatal screening. Furthermore, the strong resonance between

a narrative mode of inquiry and the phenomenological acknowledgement of the self

as dialogically constructed and narratively understood strongly complements the

philosophical orientation of this work.

The nineteen individual narratives garnered during in-depth interviews were

transcribed and analysed using Gilligan et al’s (2003) Listening Guide. The

Page 113: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

113

Listening Guide is a voice-centred relational method of narrative analysis which

draws on a series of three sequential ‘listenings’ to each account (Gilligan et al.,

2003). As simultaneous and sometimes conflicting stories can co-occur within the

same narrative text, the freedom to interpret each narrative multiple times preserves

the complexity and situatedness of each story told. Within the Listening Guide, each

listening focuses on a different aspect of the narrative.

• The first listening focused on ‘plot’ and the listener’s reflective response to

the interview.

• The second focused on the ‘I voice’, and sought to understand how the

interviewee regarded themselves by examining statements made in the first

person.

• The third listening searched for the counterpoint of the story put forward,

which Gilligan calls the ‘contrapuntal voice’. Analysis of the contrapuntal

voices suggested that these voices were ethically significant, opening a

window onto the inner dialogue, exposing the plurality of goods and

competing goods, the multiple layers of embeddedness and subjectivity that

shape individual moral horizons.

• The fourth and final stage of this guide was to compose a summary in which

all three ‘listenings’ were pulled together and summarised in relation to what

they revealed about responses to the research questions.

Through this process of analysis the plurivocal nature of narrative was preserved, as

the multiple co-existing themes, voices, perspectives and values frameworks were

uncovered and their relationship the research questions considered.

However, before exploring the voices of the participants more fully, a brief

overview of the screening tests commonly encountered will be given in the

following chapter.

Page 114: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

114

CHAPTER 4

PRENATAL SCREENING – THE TECHNICAL LENS

Introduction

In order to orient the individual experiences of the participants considered in this

study a brief description of the most prevalent prenatal tests commonly referred to

by the participants follows, accompanied by a short background of the social

contexts in which they have been developed and interpreted. A brief explanation of

the strengths and weaknesses of each will also be given.

The term ‘prenatal screening’ broadly applies to all technologies that attempt to

determine the physical and health status of a foetus before birth. Commonly, it refers

to technologies such as Nuchal Translucency Screening (NT), Ultrasound (U/S),

blood tests including Maternal Serum Alpha Feto Protein (MSAFP) and Pregnancy

Associated Plasma Protein (PAPP- A), Amniocentesis, Chorionic Villus Sampling

(CVS), and Pre-implantation Genetic Diagnosis (PGD). In this short discussion

attention will be focused upon the four most prevalent screens encountered by the

mothers and practitioners in this cohort, i.e. the blood tests MSAFP and PAPP-A,

Ultrasound, Nuchal Translucency, and Amniocentesis.

Blood Tests – Maternal Serum Screening

Commonly referred to as the ‘triple test’ or, more recently, ‘quadruple test’,

maternal serum testing measures concentrations of three or four biochemical and

hormonal levels in maternal serum31F

32 (Borgida, 2002; Wald, Huttly, & Hackshaw,

2003). In conjunction with the increasing statistically determined risk of fetal

anomalies associated with advanced maternal age, abnormal levels of these

32 These markers are alpha-feto-protein, unconjugated oestriol, human chorionic gonadotrophin and inhibin-A.

Page 115: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

115

biochemical markers have been associated with neural tube defects, placental

problems and some chromosomal or karyotypic irregularities (ibid). Although

abnormal levels may indicate increased risk, they are not conclusive proof of the

conditions mentioned above and further confirmatory testing, such as amniocentesis,

is required to establish a definite diagnosis. A number of false positives of between

4% and 10 % are associated with maternal serum screening (Harrison & Goldie,

2006; Jaques et al., 2007; Press & Browner, 1997; West & Bramwell, 2006). Due to

its applicability to large populations and relatively low cost, maternal serum blood

screening became widespread in the late 1990’s to early 2000’s and was regarded as

a better predictor of risk than maternal age alone (Borgida, 2002). In women under

thirty five, who are by definition in a lower risk category, the use of maternal serum

testing was credited with an increased detection of Down syndrome from 28.7% to

46.3%, (Carothers et al., 1999, p. 186) cementing its clinical relevance. However,

more recently, the increasing frequency of nuchal translucency screening, in

conjunction with the measure of the four blood biochemistry markers mentioned

earlier is more accurate and has a lower false positive rate of around 1% (Spencer &

Cowans, 2007). Thus the combined nuchal translucency and blood testing has

largely superseded use of maternal serum screening alone.

Ultrasound

From its first use in the detection of foetal anomalies in the 1960’s, ultrasound has

become an increasingly routine and widely embraced tool in obstetrics practice

(Oakley, 1996) with around 90% of women in developed countries receiving at least

one ultrasound during pregnancy (Levi, 1998; Whynes, 2002). It is a non-invasive,

inexpensive, visual imaging technique in which high frequency sound waves are

passed through the body. The sound waves are absorbed and reflected by different

tissues to varying degrees, producing a pattern of echoes which can be represented

in picture form (Marieb, 1992 ). Ultrasound use became increasingly widespread in

the 1980s as a means of assessing obstetric risk (i.e. gestational age, placental

position, twin pregnancy). However, it is now increasingly focused on foetal

diagnoses with respect to the revelation of physical or structural anomalies (Getz &

Kirkengen, 2003).

Page 116: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

116

Generally regarded as a benign procedure because of its non-invasive nature,

ultrasound is commonly offered to all pregnant women irrespective of their risk

status with The Royal Australian and New Zealand College of Obstetricians and

Gynaecologists (RANZCOG) recommending all pregnant women be offered at least

one ultrasound before 20 weeks. RANZCOG further advises that the proactive offer

of more invasive screens for Down syndrome or other fetal aneuploidy32F

33 be reserved

for ‘high risk’ mothers only33F

34. Conversely, the Australasian Society for Ultrasound

in Medicine more cautiously recommend that ‘ultrasound examination in pregnancy

should only be performed for a valid clinical indication’34F

35, suggesting that perhaps

not all women should be offered such a screen. As ultrasound is claimed to carry

little physical risk to the mother or baby it has been widely accepted by women who

articulate their primary motivation in accepting as ‘seeing the baby’ (Erikson, 2001;

Rapp, 2000; Richie, Boynton, & Bradbury, 2004; Whynes, 2002). The motivation to

accept ultrasound to ‘see the baby’ was reinforced by most women in this study,

whose typical comments in articulating why they chose an ultrasound are mirrored

in Anne’s explanation,

I wanted to see the baby, of course, that was a very exciting thing for me. I was interested in whether it was a boy or a girl. With my first child I saw his face, and I was just …. Well….[laughs] I fell in love with him then, he had the sweetest angel face I’d ever seen, and so I was very keen to see my others as well. Anne.

While most of the mothers saw no potential downside in agreeing to have an

ultrasound, some practitioners interpreted this practice through a different, more

cautious lens with one midwife commenting on this phenomenon wryly,

I think they are wooed [by technology]……it’s the first photo of the baby…their photo albums begin now with a scan picture…..quarter of the way through the book is the birth. Midwife 4.

33 The term ‘aneuploidy’ relates to the occurrence of one or more extra or missing chromosomes from the expected 23 pairs, or 46 chromosomes. See http://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/ghr/glossary/aneuploidy. 34 The Royal Australian and New Zealand College of Obstetricians and Gynaecologists. http://www.ranzcog.edu.au/publications/statements/C-obs4.pdf. (Retrieved 18th June,2007). High risk women in this definition include those with ‘advanced maternal age or previous affected pregnancy’. 35 See Australasian Society for Ultrasound in Medicine. http://www.asum.com.au/open/home.htm. Accessed 29th May, 2007.

Page 117: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

117

In reflecting further on women’s motivations in accepting ultrasound screening,

several practitioners made comments in line with those below:

Women hope that they’re having that scan to find out if it’s a boy or a girl ……and a lot of them find out. [E: Do you think there is a clash of motivation between practitioners and patients?] Well, yes I think so, because from a health professional’s point of view you don’t care whether it’s male or female……I think women go in blissfully ignorant…. or at least not fully informed of what the possible outcomes are. Midwife 3.

And from an Obstetrician,

I do think that the vast majority of people go into a pregnancy thinking everything is normal, that they come for an ultrasound with the view of getting a picture and being told the baby is normal and I don’t really think they honestly appreciate that what you (the practitioner) are really looking for is in fact abnormalities. Obstetrician.

As a tool that is believed to be innocuous, which is readily accessible in the comfort

of an obstetrician’s rooms, an increasing tendency to scan multiple times during a

pregnancy has been noted in the literature (Bellieni et al., 2005; Marinac-Dabic,

2002) a trend highlighted by Mary who explained, With my obstetrician he just did a scan on me every time I went to see him, to make sure that everything was OK, with the baby’s size and so on. [E: How many did you have with Ben?] With Ben………about 12 ………a fair few…………every time I saw the obstetrician I made him give me a scan………in hindsight I guess that was a bit over the top.

This pattern of escalating ultrasound use, typified by Mary’s experience, is

beginning to raise concern amidst some practitioners in light of the growing body of

evidence to suggest that the cumulative doses of radiation to which the developing

foetus is exposed have not been adequately assessed and may indeed be collectively

unhealthy or unsafe35F

36 (Buckley, 2005, pp. 99-102). While Buckley (ibid) cites

extensive research implicating ultrasound as a causal factor in low birth weight,

intrauterine growth retardation, left handedness in male infants and delayed speech

development, these claims remain contested to some degree (Newnham, Doherty,

Kendall, Zubrick, & al, 2004). The relative caution advised in the recent systematic

review conducted by Bricker et al (2000) however suggests that the debate on the

36 Buckley (2005) explores numerous research findings related to the physiological effects of ultrasound on the developing foetus in this short section.

Page 118: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

118

safety of ultrasound on the developing foetus is far from settled, as suggested in the

following quote,

‘Existing evidence suggests that the use of routine Doppler ultrasound in low

risk or unselected populations does not benefit either mother or baby, and

may be harmful. At present, Doppler ultrasound examination should be

reserved for use in high risk pregnancies’ (Bricker et al, 2000, p.152).

There appears to be growing unease amongst some practitioners about the excessive

use of prenatal screening in general, and ultrasound in particular, with Bellini et al

(2005, p.692) cautioning ‘we should never forget that it is inappropriate to perform

so many scans in a low risk pregnancy’, and Marinac-Dabic (2002, p.S21)

concluding,

‘Recent innovations in the use of Doppler flow studies, higher energy levels,

smaller transducers with a more focused beam and longer times of exposure

have created new areas of potential risk to the developing fetus………… until

long term effects can be evaluated across generations, caution should be

exercised when using this modality during pregnancy’.

However, the growing chorus of advice to exercise restraint in the use of ultrasound

or reject medically unnecessary exposure to ultrasound may not be universally

accepted, as Mary’s experience suggests.

Soft Markers

Until the 1990s only major structural abnormalities, such as anencephaly or

gastroschisis36F

37 were detectable on ultrasound (Getz & Kirkengen, 2003). However,

more recently, as imaging technology has improved, the enhanced visual clarity with

37 Anencephaly is a condition in which the upper part of the brain and its protective skull cap are missing and the lower part of the brain and the base of the skull are not properly formed. This condition is always fatal. (http://www.ninds.nih.gov/disorders/anencephaly/anencephaly.htm. Accessed 27thMay, 2007). Gastroschisis is an abdominal wall defect in which the anterior abdomen does not close properly allowing the intestines to protrude outside the foetus. (http://fetus.ucsfmedicalcenter.org/gastroschisis/)

Page 119: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

119

which a foetus can be examined during ultrasound has resulted in the ability to pick

up relatively minor and previously unseen physical ‘anomalies’ or features (Boyd,

Chamberlain & Hicks, 1998). The detection of these more subtle structural changes

have become of increasing interest because of their potential statistical association

with certain chromosomal abnormalities (Getz & Kirkengen, 2003). These subtle

changes, termed ‘soft markers’, are defined as:

‘structural changes detected at ultrasound scan which may be transient and

in themselves have little or no pathological significance, but are thought to

be more commonly found in foetuses with congenital abnormalities,

particularly karyotypic abnormalities’ (Bricker, Garcia, Henderson,

Mugford & Roberts, 2000, p.29).

Examples of soft markers include echogenic heart, seen as white dots within the

heart tissue indicating a structural abnormality, echogenic bowel, dilated renal

pelvis, choroid plexus cysts (CPC’s)37F

38 and shortening of the femur 38F

39 (Getz &

Kirkengen, 2003). In isolation, few of these individual markers raise concern,

however, when several markers are present in a foetus, the statistical likelihood of a

chromosomal anomaly increases and further invasive diagnostic testing is

commonly recommended.

While clinical use of ‘soft markers’ is commonplace, and the diagnostic discourse is

peppered with references to them (Boyd et al., 1998; Getz & Kirkengen, 2003;

Snijders, Noble, Souka & Nicolaides, 1998; Spencer, Spencer, Power, Dawson &

Nicolaides, 2003), their clinical relevance is complicated by their often transient

appearance. In most cases where a soft marker is identified, a healthy, normal child

is born (Boyd et al., 1998; Di Pietro et al., 2006; Getz & Kirkengen, 2003; Whittle,

1997). In a benchmark, six year longitudinal UK study that followed the outcomes

of over 33 000 pregnancies, Pat Boyd (1998) and her colleagues in Oxford reported

that 92% of foetuses identified as potentially abnormal due to the presence of ‘soft

markers’ seen on ultrasound were later confirmed to be normal at birth. Boyd et al’s

38 A recent 2006 study concluded that ‘CPC’s detected by prenatal ultrasound do not pose or reveal a threat to fetal development’ (Di Pietro, Costigan, Cristofalo, & Lu, 2006, p.622). 39 For a fuller explanation of various soft markers, a useful website maintained by National Health Service in the United Kingdom. (http://www.pi.nhs.uk/ultrasound/softmarkers/index_sm.htm. Accessed 18th June, 2007)

Page 120: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

120

(1998) study further noted a 12-fold increase in false positives when relying on ‘soft

markers’ alone with a corresponding increase in diagnosis of actual malformations

of only 4% (ibid., p. 1579). Two instances of a normal foetus being aborted in

response to a reported soft marker were confirmed, where the parents chose not to

pursue the additional diagnostic testing advised (ibid). Even in this extensive study,

only ‘55% of malformed foetuses and infants were correctly identified prenatally’

(ibid., p. 1578).

With high false positive rates, questionable predictive powers, and the potential to

place healthy foetuses at risk by unnecessary exposure to the risk of miscarriage

while undergoing amniocentesis or unwarranted termination, and the significant

impact on anxiety levels of parents (Kowalcek et al., 2002; Watson et al., 2003), the

reporting of ‘soft markers’, which by definition may be ‘transient and have little or

no pathological significance’ (Bricker, et al, 2000, p.29), remains controversial.

However, as long as practitioners feel it is ‘unrealistic and unethical not to report

anomalies that may ‘leap to the eye’ (Fitzgerald, 1999, p.805; Getz & Kirkengen,

2003, p.2046), their reporting is likely to continue.

The conviction that every anomaly must be disclosed, regardless of its predictive

power or veracity, means that the separate clinical aims of determining gestational

age, obstetric risk, revealing gross or subtle structural abnormalities in the foetus,

and assessing the risk of chromosomal defects (associated with soft markers), are

not selectively pursued in practice. The separate ethical considerations surrounding

each aim, therefore, also become obscured as women who consent to scan to ‘see the

baby’ may be confronted with the uninvited disclosure of screening information.

Obtaining valid informed consent in this scenario is clearly compromised by the

clash of motivation between practitioner and patient, coupled with the ill-defined

and exploratory nature of such open ended screening which makes the disclosure

and discussion of potential findings prior to consent fraught with difficulty.

However, it has been suggested if the purposes of screening and scanning were

segregated, that selective consent for women could be easily accommodated

(Dormandy, Fitzgerald & Baillie, 1999).

Page 121: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

121

Nuchal Translucency

Another important example of a soft marker that is becoming increasingly adopted

in clinical care is the measure of nuchal thickening or nuchal translucency (refer to

Figure. 1). It is defined as the ‘maximum thickness of subcutaneous translucency

between the skin and soft tissues overlying the cervical spine’ (Nicolaides, Azar,

Byrne, Mansur & Marks, 1992, p.867). In combination with other risk factors

determined from blood biochemistry39F

40 and maternal age, the measurement of the

nuchal fold is used to assign an overall, age-adjusted risk to each individual

pregnancy. Nuchal measurements must be taken at a specific time in the pregnancy,

between 11 weeks and 3 days, and 13 weeks and 6 days40F

41, as the results may be

skewed significantly by the gestational stage of the pregnancy.

Figure 1. Ultrasound picture of foetus showing increased nuchal thickening

(http://www.mater-imaging.com.au/images/nuchal2.jpg)

As a relatively new scan, nuchal translucency has been introduced largely under the

unquestioned and entrenched rubric of the existing and widely accepted routine of

the 18 week ultrasound, further blurring the exercising of choice as the separate

clinical aims of this test may not be clearly differentiated by some women. Pilnick

(2004, p.451) further notes that the choice to undergo nuchal screening is often

presented in terms of ‘old versus new screening practice, rather than a

straightforward choice between screening and not screening’, a mode of

40 PAPP-A (Pregnancy associated plasma protein) and the free beta subunit of hCG ( Human Chorionic Gonadotrophin) (Kuppermann & Norton, 2005) 41 http://www.ranzcog.edu.au/publications/statements/C-obs4.pdf. Accessed 18th June, 2007

Page 122: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

122

presentation that may portray an expectation of cooperation. One midwife in this

cohort expressed concern that nuchal translucency was referred to as ‘the 12 week

scan’, a descriptor that normalised participation and obscured its intention and

purpose,

You’d certainly hope they [GP’s] would be giving the appropriate information that it was a screening test for genetic abnormalities, particularly Down syndrome, but that it was …..only a screening test and that there would be consequences if it turned up a higher risk…………I don’t know that many of them even knew that. To them it was just ‘the 12 week scan’……Midwife 3.

Commenting on mothers’ understandings of ‘the 12 week scan’, this midwife further

observed,

Most people assume they will have a normal baby and for most people that 12 week scan is an opportunity to see their baby…. are they taking the 12 week scan the same way [as the 18 week ultrasound] without really, really understanding……. what we’re doing ? Midwife 3.

Even if the widely held position that there is no physical risk to mother or child from

ultrasound is ultimately proven to be true, although this assertion is questioned41F

42,

there are numerous additional risks or potential harms associated with the reporting

of the false positives linked to soft markers and nuchal screening including:

• Exposure of a normal foetus to the unnecessary risk of amniocentesis

which is reported to carry a procedural miscarriage rate of 1:200

(Alfirevic, 2003; Boyd et al., 1998; Egan & Borgida, 2002). Although

more recent analysis of miscarriage rates associated with amniocentesis

suggest a significantly lower miscarriage rate of 0.06% (Eddleman et al.,

2006), the individual clinical skill of the practitioner has already been

established as a significant variable determining miscarriage from this

procedure (Herman et al., 1999; Kornman et al., 1996). It seems likely,

therefore, that the invasive nature of amniocentesis is accompanied by

some increased risk of miscarriage to the pregnancy, even if this risk is

small.

• Psychological harm to the mother resulting from ‘considerable short

term anxiety’ and distress of a false positive result (Watson et al.,

42 See Bellieni et al., 2005; Bricker et al., 2000; Buckley, 2005; Neilson & Alfirevic, 2000 .

Page 123: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

123

2003, p. 569; Zamerowski, 1999). A significant body of research

exists noting the presence of anxiety or depressive reactions, in

mothers undergoing prenatal screening which are not necessarily

related to the invasiveness of screening or to the outcome of the test.

These potentially ongoing psychological harms are considered more

thoroughly in Chapter Eight.

• Finally, the risk of terminating a normal foetus based on the presence

of a soft marker which, contrary to medical advice, is not confirmed

by further testing as reported by Boyd et al (1998).

While ultrasound is a powerful diagnostic tool for particular physical anomalies, it is

not a diagnostic tool for genetic or chromosomal conditions. Within the cohort of

this study, the distinction between the clear diagnostic result from amniocentesis and

the preliminary and unverified nature of ultrasound or accompanying blood

biochemistry screening procedures was not well understood by mothers. Several

practitioners expressed deep unease that this fundamental differentiation between

screening and diagnosing, so critical to understanding the nature of prenatal testing,

seemed so poorly grasped and difficult to communicate as evidenced in the

following comments.

I would certainly say that a lot of people who have a nuchal translucency do not probably understand, particularly the younger women. I think women over 35 do understand it’s a screening test for Down syndrome, and a lot of them do ask for it, because they don’t want to have the other test but I don’t know that a lot of them really understand the difference between screening tests versus a diagnostic test. Obstetrician

The word ‘screening’ they really don’t understand that…..so when I break that down and explain that we can’t say yes or no, they are surprised……….so….. it never surprises me that some of the words that we take for granted in everyday use, are words that we think people will understand, but they don’t really understand what that truly means………Genetic Counsellor 2

Regardless of existing understanding about the certainty or veracity of the tests

undertaken or the results given, the revelation of ultrasound markers that may be

statistically linked to chromosomal anomalies inevitably leads to the offer to

undergo further, more invasive diagnostic testing such as amniocentesis to secure a

definitive result, if only for a limited number of conditions.

Page 124: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

124

Amniocentesis

On receiving a ‘high risk’ categorisation from nuchal translucency, blood serum

screen or ultrasound, the next step for women who want definitive diagnosis of

certain conditions (though not all) is to have an invasive amniocentesis during

which some amniotic fluid, which contains foetal cells, is removed from the

amniotic sac surrounding the foetus (Marieb, 1992). Foetal cells are cultured and

may be karyotyped to reveal particular chromosomal abnormalities, most commonly

trisomies 13, 18, 21 or other aneuploidies including Turner’s syndrome,

Klinefelter’s Syndrome, Edwards Syndrome or Patau Syndrome for example.

Routine amniocentesis does not look for specific genes or genetic disorders,

although if there is reason to suspect a particular familial genetic disorder such as

Cystic Fibrosis, Huntington’s Disease or Duchene’s Muscular Dystrophy for

example, more specialised testing may be undertaken. In a routine amniocentesis,

the overall structure and shape of the chromosomes may flag markers of other less

common genetic conditions42F

43. Importantly, however, normal chromosomal shape

and structure at the macro level does not guarantee the absence of a genetic disorder

at the micro level of nucleotide sequencing of individual genes. Since its first

introduction in the 1970’s, the list of conditions that may be diagnosed via

amniocentesis has grown, although it is by no means comprehensive. While the most

common genetic anomalies are looked for, numerous more rare conditions remain

undetected. Thus while amniocentesis gives a definitive diagnosis for the limited

number of specific conditions analysed, the list of potential conditions unable to be

prenatally diagnosed remains vast.

As this procedure is usually performed at 16-17 weeks, and comprehensive results

may take several weeks to complete, a limited time window exists between

diagnosis and possible termination before the medically desired43F

44 gestational limit

of termination at 20 weeks. In recent years, in an attempt to confirm earlier

diagnoses, amniocentesis has been performed at 9 to 14 weeks; however, an

43 See www.genetics.com.au.(Accessed 17th April, 2006) Sincere thanks to the genetic counsellors interviewed for providing access to this additional information. 44 Pregnancy termination is medically preferred before 20 weeks as the procedural risks to the mother increase with increasing gestation. Often the 20 week limit presumed is not legally set, and many states in Australia have varying interpretations of the legal permissibility and preferred gestational limits.

Page 125: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

125

increased miscarriage rate of up to 1:20 or 5% (Alfirevic, 2003) has been reported.

The application of amniocentesis later in the pregnancy, resulting in later

terminations, is considered to be a detraction as earlier diagnosis and termination is

believed to be less confronting or affronting to parents, a view echoed by one GP,

It’s appropriate [to discuss termination] when you review them at about 10 weeks….because at 10 weeks, you’re in a position where a termination is of less a medical or surgical insult than perhaps at 16 weeks …General Practitioner 1.

The view that early termination was less likely to create psychological harm

however was not supported by Neugebauer et al (1997) who concluded that the

likelihood of depression after termination ‘did not vary significantly by history of

prior reproductive loss or by maternal age, nor did risk vary by time of gestation or

attitude toward the pregnancy’ (Neugebauer, Kline, Shrout, Skodol, & al, 1997,

p.383), suggesting that the gestational stage of the pregnancy is not the dominant

causal factor when pregnancy loss results in feelings of emotional trauma.

An emerging issue that has not been widely researched to date is the intense

psychological distress experienced in the growing time gap between identifying a

potential problem by nuchal translucency at 11-12 weeks gestation and the

potentially five to six week wait before amniocentesis can be performed effectively

at 17-18 weeks gestation. This situation was experienced by Mary, one of the

mothers who participated in this study. She explains:

[E: So you had the nuchal at 12 weeks?] Mmmm….. [E: And when did you have the amnio?] I had the amnio at 17 ½ weeks……[pause] ……. [E: How were those 5 ½ weeks of waiting?] Harrowing... [sighs]…that would be the best way to describe it……….I was a basket case…I didn’t know what to do….who to talk to ….. It had only just been developed, it was only just out there…..and there was really no-one to talk to. My obstetrician seemed to think that there was going to be no problems based on the scans, whereas the ultrasound specialist said because of the blood work this is what is going to happen.….I had the amnio the week before Christmas, and they said they should have enough cells and could have the results in three days……….Christmas eve we get a phone call. “Well we’ve got some results for you, but you’ll have to wait a week before we get the rest” because they didn’t have enough cells. So we got the first lot of results on Christmas eve, and the next lot on New Years eve, we got the all clear that bubby was fine…………so instead of taking three days it took nearly three weeks for us to get results……… which was just a nightmare.

Page 126: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

126

[E: So… are you saying the whole process took around 8 weeks…. is that right?] Mmmm…[pause]…..… almost 8 weeks of not knowing……trauma really….. I was actually prescribed sleeping tablets…….and then he was perfect, absolutely nothing wrong with him……………yes. [E: How did you feel when you were finally told that everything was OK, the test results were fine?] I just felt like screaming…………at everyone………….just for the whole….I was really glad that everything was OK…..but I didn’t like the way it was done…….if that makes sense…… [E: What was it specifically that you didn’t like?] I just…… sort of………being sat down and being told, OK… your baby‘s probably going to have Downs, and probably won’t survive………Your baby has a 1:32 chance of making it to full term …..And it’s just not something you like to be told…. …..And then to be told ‘we can find out, but you have to wait another 4-5 weeks before we can do that’….[sighs] Mary

While the informing and consenting protocols surrounding these tests have tended to

focus primarily on the physical risks, the risk of psychological harm is keenly felt by

women and potentially extremely damaging. Paradoxically the clinical improvement

of the earlier 11 week nuchal scan may in fact be intensifying the possible

psychological harms by lengthening the time gap between raising the initial alarm

and performing the diagnostic amniocentesis, optimally at around 17 weeks

gestation. Psychological harm from prenatal screening is well documented, yet

appears to be rarely factored into clinical assessment of the efficacy of screening, or

cost benefit analyses. The fuller implications of these potentially ongoing

psychological harms of engaging in prenatal screening will be more thoroughly

considered in Chapter Eight.

The following section, Section B, consists of Chapters Five through to Eight. This

section explores each of the participants’ voices in the broader context and themes of

existing research understandings. Participant stories are woven through the ongoing

and evolving conversations between other mothers, practitioners, scholars and

researchers working in this field.

Page 127: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

127

SECTION B

VOICES IN CONTEXT: ILLUMINATING PRACTICE, IDENTIFYING

CONSTRAINTS

Introduction

‘Evaluations of women’s decision making with regard to PD [prenatal

diagnosis] – and women’s decisions are judged widely and are central to the

professional debates surrounding PD. In contrast women involved in PD as

participants are rarely involved in publicly judging and evaluating the

decision making of the other players in PD programmes: those whose

decisions frame women’s own options’ (Brookes, 2001, p. 3).

The first three chapters articulated some of the background context in which prenatal

screening occurs, and gave an account of the ethical orientation of this research. As

a consequence of the particular ontological stance flowing from the

phenomenological philosophical tradition embraced in Chapter Two, Chapter Three

explained why a narrative mode of inquiry complemented the research aims both

ethically and methodologically. Having garnered individual accounts from the

nineteen participants, and considered the emerging themes, plots and contrapuntal

voices through analysis using the Listening Guide, the next task of this research was

to situate these participant voices within the broader context and themes of existing

research understandings, to weave the participants’ stories through the ongoing and

evolving conversations between other mothers, practitioners, scholars and

researchers working in this field.

Historically, as Brookes (2001) remarks above, women’s stories have been

significantly excluded from socially endorsed views of how the ethical aspects of

prenatal screening, which are predominantly framed by others, are represented to

and received by women. Therefore, in the next four chapters, the mothers who

participated in this research share their personal encounters with prenatal screening.

Page 128: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

128

While this research exposes many of the constraining factors that deny women full

ethical decision making capacity with respect to prenatal screening, inevitably the

array of options made available are significantly constructed by the perceptions,

presumptions, prejudices and beliefs held by health care practitioners. As

practitioner perceptions are integral in shaping the ethical terrain encountered by

women, their perspectives must also be included in any comprehensive analysis that

seeks to illuminate and potentially transform the numerous constraining factors

women face. Significantly, the perceptions and possibilities of both groups are

defined by the further layers of embeddedness in the organisational cultures and

practices surrounding screening. As each individual stakeholder has unique and

particular insights into the processes of prenatal screening, either as provider or

recipient, the combined analysis of all nineteen stories, each of which individually

illuminates, supports, contradicts and/or challenges the others, allows a larger,

jointly constructed, and hermeneutically informed collective picture to emerge.

Building on the four dimensional ethical framework44F

45 outlined in Chapter Two

(Isaacs and Massey, 1994), the following four chapters could be considered as

attending to the hermeneutical and appreciative dimensions of the ethical, paying

particular heed to the reasons, justifications and explanations participants offer of

their experiences. As Isaacs (2003) notes, the decision to take an appreciative stance,

or dispositional interest, compels us to actively recognise another’s humanity,

dignity and unique presence. In doing so we are enabled in our ability to relate to

another’s complexity, particularity and unique humanity. In terms of this research, in

attending to the appreciative dimension, I sought to understand and approach each of

the nineteen stories within the broader personal, social, political, historical and

institutional contexts that gave shape and situational meaning to their account.

Thinking appreciatively was particularly important when responding to participants’

comments, many of which were initially challenging. In a practical research sense,

one example (of many encountered) of how an appreciative stance informs this

research analysis can be illustrated through the following story. Leanne, a 32 year

old mother of a young toddler, originally seemed flippant and abrupt in her

explanation of why she actively pursued amniocentesis screening. Even after her

45 Hermeneutical, Appreciative, Appraisive, and Transformative.

Page 129: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

129

doctor advised her that her extremely low risk of 1:3000 45F

46 of having a child with

Down syndrome46F

47 made amniocentesis an unnecessary medical risk, Leanne was

determined to pursue this testing regardless of the potential miscarriage risk related

to this procedure. She explained, The first time we tried, we conceived so I felt lucky in that I was fertile, I knew there were no problems ‘down there’ (laughs)…. so I felt well….. I haven’t got the strength of character to bring up a disabled child ….. We conceived first time, so I thought well……. [hesitates] I would have terminated if I knew it was Down syndrome. I knew we could conceive quickly…….. It was just because I knew that someone has to be ‘the one’ and I didn’t want to be. … [E: Are you saying that regardless of what the risk factor you were told you would still have had the amnio because…..you may have been ‘the one’?] Yes, in the first 10 minutes of my 9 week visit to the obstetrician I told her I would have it done. And she was like ……….she wasn’t going to put me off because she could see I was quite strong about it. Leanne

Later in the interview, referring to her faith in her fertility Leanne explained, But I’m really lucky………. I can be a bit picky. Leanne

Leanne’s approach to this decision as a rational matter of quickly dispensing of and

replacing one defective child with another, better child was disarming. However,

throughout the course of the interview, it became clear that Leanne’s determination

to have all available tests was primarily motivated by fear; fear of disability and fear

of losing control. Throughout the interview, she frequently referred to a fear of

disability and repeated her conviction that she didn’t have the strength to care for

such a child. She further explained that she had ‘bad luck’ and could not accept such

‘bad luck’ for her child. She constantly referred to her anxiety that she could be ‘the

one’47F

48 who had the disabled child. As a self described ‘control freak’, Leanne felt

compelled to embrace any tool which increased her sense of taking charge of the

unpredictability of the reproductive lottery. She explained,

Of course you still worry about loads of other things that you have no control over. At least this I had control over, everything else I had no control over, but that I had control and I’m a bit of a control freak so…….. one thing I could eliminate after all the things you worry

46 Determined from combined Nuchal Translucency and blood test. 47 While amniocentesis can diagnose a number of chromosomal anomalies, Leanne spoke solely in terms of Downs Syndrome and seemed uninterested or unaware of the many other conditions that could be diagnosed using this test. 48 Leanne made specific reference to not wanting to be ‘the one’ with the disabled child fifteen times throughout a 90 minute interview.

Page 130: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

130

about when you’re pregnant , did I drink too much in the beginning, could it be born with a funny heart, well at least I know he doesn’t have that…. he doesn’t have Downs. . Leanne

And later in the interview

If I’m going to bring up a child for the next 20 years I’ve got a small amount of control and choice what condition it’s got, so I just can utilise that [technology] and I would do so a second time even although I know what I could lose, I could lose a child, and this could be it, but I’d rather be sure that they didn’t have a severe disability …..I’d rather know. . Leanne

In appreciatively considering these comments as being shaped by underlying

anxieties, elements of Leanne’s story quickly spiralled outwards, illuminating the

broader social and situational considerations that drive women’s decision-making in

this context. The many influences that were underpinning her behavioural choices

and her capacity to exercise informed consent became clear when considering

Leanne’s position appreciatively and hermeneutically. The considerations identified

by Leanne included the perceived need to be reassured, strong personalisation of

‘generalised’ risk factors, faith in technology to deliver a healthy child, and socially

entrenched stereotypically negative attitudes to disability. Hence the wider social

and cultural roots of Leanne’s currently held position were illuminated through the

appreciative and hermeneutic consideration of her story. Similarly, I have sought to

contextualise and value the experiences of all participants, to disclose or seek out the

necessary layers of interpretation that give crucial contextual meaning to each

account. These voices in context provide a rich and in–depth source of

understanding of the lived reality of individual experiences, and thus form a

valuable basis for reflection and suggested practice reform.

Collectively the Chapters of Section B simultaneously attend to the first three areas

of research outlined in the introduction48F

49. These areas are:-

1. Autonomy and Informed Consent.

While Chapter Two discussed the philosophical foundations and some of

the theoretical limitations of autonomy and informed consent, Chapter 4 will

expand upon these understandings by incorporating the experiences and

beliefs of participants revealed through their individual accounts. Their

49 See Chapter One

Page 131: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

131

encounters and explanations are incorporated into, and considered in light of,

existing research and understandings.

2. Constraints on Consent.

Existing research, predominantly from the United Kingdom, United States of

America, Canada and Europe identifies many problematic issues inherent in

currently accepted biomedical practices and consent protocols of prenatal

screening. A range of barriers to informed consent including philosophical,

institutional, social and personal barriers significantly shape and limit

women and practitioners in their capacity to have the necessary ethical and

educational conversations prior to engaging in screening. These barriers will

be identified and explored in the following four chapters as indicated by the

research participants.

3. Local Experiences.

Through the voices of the nineteen participants, individual and local

experiences in relation to the numerous constraints identified above will be

considered and compared to the constraints identified elsewhere. Additional

constraining factors that emerge from the experiences of this cohort flag

blurred accountability for informing between practitioners for patient care

and education ; an underdeveloped evidence-based culture of medical

practice when monitoring prenatal screening outcomes in Queensland; and

consideration of how the legal status of termination in Queensland

contributes to the culture of privatisation, hiding and silencing.

Within the realm of prenatal screening the constraints that shape and mould how

choice is constructed and whether informed consent is supported may be loosely

categorised into four porous groups being,

• Philosophical constraints arising from the often thin and narrow

interpretations of the ethical as realised through the exercising of

personal autonomy, choice and informed consent. Further

compounding these issues, the atomistic connotations implicit in the

Page 132: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

132

dominant interpretations of the philosophical concept of autonomy

entrenches an individualistic view of the self which undermines the

deeply related and embedded nature of decision-making. As outlined

in Chapter Two, the danger in adopting an intellectual commitment to

externally imposed philosophical reason at the expense of

hermeneutically aware, collaborative negotiation may potentially

narrow the view of what is permissible as an ‘ethical’ issue. Finally,

by representing moral decision making as a detached and singular

event rather than an ongoing, evolving, embodied and embedded

process with far reaching relational consequences, the ethical

considerations that precede clinical intervention may have become

undermined.

• Institutional constraints include the routine nature of testing which

obscures voluntariness, hierarchical power dynamics within

institutional settings both inter-professionally and between

patient/carer, and overt and covert counselling. Additional

institutional constraints include poor educational opportunities for

practitioners and patients, blurred accountability amongst various

practitioner groups for informing, inequity of access to testing and

the ever present time constraints of production-driven models of

institutional care.

• Social constraints emanate from the realisation that the choices made

available to women are significantly delimited by societal and peer

expectations of ‘responsible pregnant behaviour’ (Lippman, 1991).

Trust in science to deliver a healthy child becomes enmeshed with

maternal and practitioner feelings of blame and responsibility if a

disabled child is undetected, as embracing technology may abrogate

blame. Poor understanding of disability, the predefining of certain

physical/intellectual conditions as unacceptable, and inadequate

social support for disabled persons further shape behaviour,

behaviour that is deeply influenced by the political, legal, historical

Page 133: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

133

and cultural contexts in which such practices evolve. These social

precursors to how screening is developed, presented and interpreted

remain under acknowledged in the dominant and decontextualised

account of ethics.

• Personal constraints include the socially constructed ‘need’ to be re-

assured, the ‘self evident’ need to screen to reduce the increased

levels anxiety that flow from the discourse of risk that surrounds

pregnancy, poor understanding of the probabilistic and statistical

language of risk, and a lack of familiarity with the medical

procedures, processes and terminologies that the mother may

encounter.

These multiple and potentially choice constraining considerations overlap and

interweave, mutually feeding each other in the complex web of constructive and

destructive interactions that ultimately direct individual perception, behaviour and

‘choice’. Additionally, the critical combinations that culminate in a woman

experiencing constrained agency or diminished choice occur differently for different

people. Consequently these constraining features cannot be rigidly considered as

linear or hierarchal. Rather, they are subjective, intersubjective and interplaying,

further invoking Gilligan et al’s (2003) notions of simultaneously co-occurring and

contrapuntal threads that may create a unique pattern of either resonance or

dissonance. However, if our aim is to understand and support ethical decision

making in antenatal care locally, we need firstly to understand the various sources

and potential consequences of these constraining factors, to articulate their role in

the shaping the actual practice encountered by pregnant women and their

practitioners, and to assess whether the constraints identified in overseas research

are echoed locally. Each of these four areas will be considered in more detail in the

following four chapters.

Page 134: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

134

CHAPTER 5

VOICES IN CONTEXT:

PHILOSOPHICAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction

The desire that a person should act voluntarily from a position of knowledge and

understanding, to give their voluntary ‘informed consent’ to any medical

intervention, and be supported in their capacity to exercise free will without

coercion, is widely valued in Western society (Manson & O’Neil, 2007). Since its

inception with respect to research participants outlined in the Nuremberg Code in

1947, and reinforced in subsequent versions of the Declaration of Helsinki, the

specific requirement that practitioners seek patient consent has extended to clinical

care. Over the past four decades seeking consent from patients prior to medical

treatment has become ingrained in health care practice49F

50 (Beauchamp & Childress,

2001). Regarded as preserving individual patient autonomy, reliance on informed

consent as a means of ensuring ethical probity in clinical practice has consequently

become ‘so well entrenched that [it’s] presence, indeed [it’s] necessity, and

justification are rarely questioned’ (Manson & O’Neil, 2007, p.2).

Yet despite the obvious value placed on informed consent, current approaches to

actualising it in practice, which significantly focus on attaining the minimal legal

requirement of information disclosure, are significantly failing to achieve the ethical

ideals of intentional, voluntary and understood (by patients) intervention. A growing

body of literature confirms that low levels of informed consent, from an ethical

perspective, persist across a range of medical practices, including prenatal screening

(Bottrell, Alpert, Fischbach, & Emanuel, 2000; Braddock, 2002; Braddock et al.,

1999; Wear, 1998), and the presumption that legally permissible informed consent

necessarily incorporates the moral aspects of decision making appears flawed.

50 Manson and O’Neil (2007, p. 5) argue that the extension of informed consent protocols to clinical medicine was unwarranted due to the different purposes and intentions of clinical and research medicine.

Page 135: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

135

In a health care climate where practitioners and patients commonly claim to value

and aspire to meet the ethical standard of understood, or informed consent, the

widespread failures observed suggest more fundamental and underlying causes.

Research further suggests that patients for the most part desire fuller understanding

of their medical care (Leithner et al, 2006) and practitioners for the most part are not

wilfully withholding such information. Therefore, exploring the contextual and

theoretical foundations and presumptions that underpin the ethical requirements of

informed consent may provide some insight and explanations for the weaknesses

observed, and thus better equip patients and practitioners in achieving the ethical

outcomes sought. This chapter will consider the philosophical origins of the

elevation of autonomy and its subsequent linking to informed consent in medical

care. The experiences of participants will be considered in relation to the broader

medical and philosophical discussion of autonomy and informed consent.

The Autonomous Self

The word autonomy is derived from the Greek words ‘autos’, meaning ‘self’ and

‘nomos’, meaning ‘governance’ or ‘rule’. Hence autonomy is understood as

describing the capacity for self governance, for making individual choices, and for

exercising free will. A further inherent characteristic of autonomy is that such self

governance should be free from the control and interference of others. Hence

Beauchamp and Childress (2001, p.58) propose that there are two essential

conditions of autonomy being (1) liberty or freedom from control, and (2) agency,

which they describe as the capacity for intentional action. Respecting a person’s

autonomy thus requires not only the acceptance that they are entitled to make

choices based on personal values and beliefs, but extends, in some instances, to the

actions of enabling and supporting such autonomous choice even if it seems at odds

with conventional rationality (Beauchamp & Childress, 2001, p.63).

Most writers begin their exploration of the concept of autonomy with the work of

Immanuel Kant who argued that respect for autonomy flows from ‘the recognition

that all persons have unconditional worth and the capacity to determine their own

moral destiny’ (Beauchamp and Childress, 2001, p.64; Manson & O’Neil, 2007,

Page 136: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

136

p.17; Faden and Beauchamp, 1994). However, Kant’s initial account of ‘autonomy

of the will’ is not the commonly accepted account of liberty, agency based on

understanding, that permeates bioethical discussions today (Beauchamp &

Childress, 2001, p.351). Rather Kant regarded autonomy as the capacity to act

rationally, within the requirements of the universally applicable categorical

imperative (ibid).

Our collective expectations of autonomy have however evolved and more

contemporary incarnations commonly present autonomy primarily as individual

independence. It is on these more individualistic understandings that the currently

prevalent informed consent procedures are premised. Manson and O’Neil (2007,

p.18-19) explain,

‘It is easy to see why those who see autonomy as a matter of individual

independence link it so closely to informed consent: informed consent

procedures protect individual choice, and with it individual independence,

hence individual autonomy. So if we can show that individual autonomy is a

fundamental value – better still the fundamental value – and that it can best

be protected and implemented by informed consent requirements, it may

prove possible to justify informed consent procedures as required if we are

to respect autonomy.

Thus the debate rages over whether autonomy is a matter of ‘mere sheer choice’

(Manson & O’Neil, 2007, p.19), or whether autonomy is a matter of choice within

the confines of rationality and culturally acceptable parameters. Clearly, both

conceptions have flaws, the sheer choice position demands that all choices

regardless of their potential for self harm or dehumanisation be supported, and

individual choice based on reason and rational thought begs the question of whose

conception of rationality is privileged ( Macintyre, 1984). Thus Manson and O’Neil

(2007, p.22) conclude that ‘all of this suggests that appeals to individual autonomy,

however conceived, are unlikely to provide convincing justifications for informed

consent procedures’.

Page 137: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

137

However, the belief that informed consent protocols formalise respect for autonomy

seems firmly embedded in a social and cultural sense and is, therefore, expected

clinically. From a theoretical perspective, the detached autonomous, individualistic

‘I’, who will rationally consider their accessible options and give an unencumbered

and reasoned response to the question ‘what ought I do’, is largely a product of the

ontologically flawed modernist conceptions of the self as discussed earlier in

Chapter Two. While this concept of the ‘autonomous self’ has colonised orthodox

bioethical discourse, as Isaacs (2007, p.3) noted earlier, ‘this self is not a human

self’, it does not reflect the lived reality of human ‘being’ or enhance understandings

of how deeply embedded decisions are interpreted and made. People do not ignore

personal sentiments in moral reasoning, nor are they detached from sentimental

consequences (Sherwin, 1992). They are intentionally partial to family and friends

and have mutual obligations of care, responsibility, trust and affection. Hence, while

an individual may consider themselves to be rational and independent to a degree,

they are unquestionably and primarily embedded and embodied beings with

particular roles and responsibilities that may present non-negotiable constraints on

their ability to act in a purely individualistic or rationally considered way. Although

these alternative ways of being are often represented as competitive or mutually

exclusive, as noted earlier (Friedman, 1997, p.45), autonomy has many coexisting

facets. Social relationships, contexts and practices are not separate from autonomy

or individuality. Rather, social context and interdependence are an integral part of

realising self governance. Autonomy and objectivity therefore need not be

positioned competitively against relationality and subjectivity as mutually exclusive

positions.

Other assumptions embedded within the narrowly defined biomedical application of

the principle of autonomy are:

a) That the person making the decision, and not the community to which they

belong, are the final arbiter of the integrity of the decision made.

b) That if a person is equipped with the relevant information, has the cognitive

capacity to decide, and the ability to resist coercion, that internal barriers to

Page 138: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

138

choice, such as the need to conform to expected societal norms, are deemed

to be absent (Oshana, 2001).

c) That real access to a variety of options actually exists, and can be readily

accessed (ibid).

d) That relationships with others are supportive, both psychologically and

socially, and there is no consequence of abandonment or retaliation if a

choice is made that others, upon whom the person may depend, oppose

(ibid).

In response to the first point, women may fulfil many roles within a community such

as mother, partner, or responsible citizen to name a few, and thus have competing

responsibilities (Bridle, 2002; Lippman, 1999a). The best outcome as a mother may

be in direct conflict with the best outcome perceived by society at large. For

example, the birth of a child with a disability may be rationally and objectively

viewed as an unwanted burden or financial drain on society that should be resisted

by a responsible citizen, or conversely, subjectively viewed as an event that elicits

great compassion, joy, support and love within the child’s family. These two

positions are irreconcilable, yet in deciding whether to embark on prenatal

screening, women must balance these opposing concerns.

Access to and awareness of the range of available options is another source of

contention, with the routine incorporation of screening obscuring the voluntary

nature of participation. Many women interviewed in previous studies did not

understand that refusal to screen was an option, resulting in a clinical norm where it

was harder to opt out than in. Women who sought the alternative of non-

participation reported feeling labelled as ‘difficult’ or ‘unco-operative’ (Press &

Browner, 1993, 1997; Santhalahti et al., 1998; Williams et al., 2002c). The

expectation of participation inherent within ‘routine’ practices threatens to erode the

validity of any consent given and calls into question the notion of ‘choice’, when no

workable alternative is offered (Lippman, 1999a). Deference to the language of

individual choice may ring hollow when alternative pathways are not explicitly

offered. Indeed, under these circumstances choice may become acquiescence to the

Page 139: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

139

least detrimental of several unappealing options, rather than the ethically sought

after, understood, and intentional action.

Narrowly defined and reductionist views of autonomy may further exclude the

broader contextual factors of moral decision making by firmly focussing attention

on aiding the physician ‘getting’ consent (Manson, 2007, p.301). Consequently, the

bioethical discourse that informs the development of institutional practice and

policy, and which directs and dominates debate, become practical questions

concerning the quantity of information that is required to be disclosed (Manson &

O’Neil, 2007, pp.28-49). Additionally, much energy is invested into the

development of contrived ways to ‘measure’ consent to provide affirmation or proof

to practitioners50F

51. The patient, while being the subject of consent, the person giving

the waiver, is conspicuously absent from these deliberations. Dodds (2002, p.213)

explains,

‘the narrow focus on consent as the sole locus of autonomy considerations in

medicine has worked to constrain debate about autonomy in health

care……Identifying autonomy with informed consent in health care makes it

easy to overlook other limitations….Identifying respect for autonomy with

informed consent presupposes that ethical concern should be directed to the

actions of the physician in obtaining consent (whether the physician gives

full and adequate information, whether the physician has unduly influenced

the decision of the patient, whether the physician explains the information

clearly, etc) and not to the decision making process of the patient . Finally

the focus on informed consent ignores the ways in which health care

practices influence the development and demise of the capacity for personal

autonomy’.

Autonomy, when understood as rationally considered, unencumbered, and

individual choice thus provides too shallow an account of selfhood to form a secure

basis of meaningful ethical deliberation in health care as it fails to specifically 51 One such example is the Multidimensional Measure of Informed Consent (MMIC), See Marteau, Dormandy, & Michie, 2001; Michie, Dormandy, & Marteau, 2002.

Page 140: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

140

acknowledge the consequence of individual actions on others, or the deeply

relational and embedded nature of decision making. Thus Manson and O’Neil

(2007, p.19) conclude,

‘Individual autonomy cannot be the sole principle of medical or research

ethics, and consent requirements that protect individual autonomy cannot be

the sole criterion of ethically acceptable action.’

Autonomous Voices

The embedded and relationally defined nature of human being with its

accompanying plurality of goods necessarily creates conflicting desires. As Charles

Taylor noted earlier, the difficulty in negotiating the ethical is often not in discerning

good from bad, but more challengingly, discerning goods from competing, mutually

exclusive goods (Taylor, 1989). As the ethical framework outlined in Chapter Two

suggests, people do not generally act purely out of individualistic ‘self’ interest, but

are deeply motivated by their competing desire to preserve relationships of value.

The reality of negotiating conflicting desires, of subjugating the self to protect

valued relationships emerged frequently through the stories of participants. In terms

of practical decision making, the question of ‘what ought “I” do’, as presented to

independent autonomous women, was inevitably enmeshed in the opinions and

expectations of significant others, taking into consideration what they thought ought

be done. For example, Mary, who at 29 years old and pregnant with her second child

was given a 1:32 risk of having a child with a chromosomal anomaly from a nuchal

translucency scan, explained her thoughts about what her choices really were given

her conflicting views on termination from those of her partner. She said

I thought about it [termination] every day…..every single day….I just thought this is ………I didn’t know what to do ….In myself I knew there was nothing wrong, and then I had to look at ‘well what if there is’? What do I do then?...In my mind it didn’t worry me whether the baby had something wrong…..but then I had to look at the whole family side of things as well…How we would all deal with that so it was horrible………horrible. Mary

Later Mary returned to this conflict,

Page 141: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

141

I had decided that I didn’t care whether there was something wrong... I couldn’t terminate…………My other half said…. well we need to weigh up the options and depending on what was wrong….. he said it’s not fair to the rest of us but……………we had completely different views and hadn’t really looked at the outcome because that would mean there would be something wrong and we didn’t want to do that. I know I didn’t……….And he said, you have to consider this………and I said, ‘I’m not……..I’m not giving up hope’, it was very hard……….a very, very hard time………..but yeah…….I wasn’t for terminating and he was…but he said, ‘Well I don’t want to think about that, I know my baby is fine’……………..he was a rock , and I was a mess, an absolute basket case………… but yes ………we were at completely different ends of that . Mary

Mary’s experience illustrates the stark realities of relationally constrained agency

that limited her preferred option. She had been placed in a position where she may

have been called upon to reconcile the irreconcilable, in which she ‘couldn’t’

terminate, but in which her partner had expressed the opinion that keeping any child

with a disability was ‘not fair to the rest of us’. The choice of Mary’s words in

expressing the grave moral distress she was experiencing demand comment. She

described her partner as rational and calm, ‘a rock’, while she identified herself as ‘a

mess, an absolute basket case’. The source of Mary’s intense moral distress was the

looming inability to reconcile the two competing goods before her, her strong

personal commitment to the planned and wanted baby growing inside her, and the

equal commitment to preserving harmony and stability in her relationship with her

equally loved life-partner, coupled with his expectations of her obligations to him

and to their existing child.

Similarly, Danielle touched on the relational nature of decision making, through

constant use of collective rather than individualistic language such as ‘us’, ‘our’ and

‘we’ when she explained,

We were facing the completely hideous decision of aborting this baby or even worse…………………or having a baby with Down syndrome and looking at the ramifications for that child and for our existing children………….for the rest of our lives……………….Danielle

Each of the mothers explained their decision-making process within the context of a

significant relationship with their partner and other children, illuminating the deeply

embedded nature of their decision making capacity, reinforcing Taylor’s (1989)

earlier point that our moral lives and ethical decision making are not shaped by one

‘good’, but rather a plurality of competing goods that must be carefully negotiated,

balanced and fused. Preserving individual autonomy in the context of sustaining

Page 142: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

142

important relationships is thus necessarily more complex than the simple exercising

of choice suggests as in a practical sense, realising one’s own autonomy is

profoundly influenced, constrained, or supported by the world of others in which

we are situated.

Practitioners, too, struggled with the reality that seemingly competent and

independent women were often impeded, or unwilling, to follow their clearly

expressed intentions, but appeared deeply and blatantly constrained to act in their

own best interests by the wishes of their partners. In discussing a recent case of a

couple who opted to terminate their child, prenatally diagnosed with a cleft palette51F

52,

Midwife 2 remarked,

They were diagnosed, and they had counselling, and they had genetic counselling, they were shown pictures of before and after surgery, ……….all sorts of things, but……it was a cultural problem as well as the baby having an anomaly……….it was just ludicrous really…….and the husband was the main problem…….the husband was the one that did not [emphasis] want an abnormal baby. So convincing him that this was just looks, nothing else ….. which could be easily repaired……….just wasn’t good enough for him, and the poor woman was just distraught about everything. It would be a frightful position to be in ………do you lose your baby on the grounds that your husband doesn’t like the idea of it? Midwife 2

In discussing pregnancy termination, Mackenzie (1995, p.42) offers some insightful

observations about the relationally constructed deliberations that inform decision

making:

‘The decision process focuses on questions of whether you are in a position

to care for it, both now when it is in the foetal stage and more importantly

when it is an independent being; how and whether it can be integrated into

your life and the lives of other, for example other children, whose lives will

also be significantly affected by your decision; whether you feel yourself

able or prepared to provide the physical and emotional care and nurturance

needed in order for both the foetus and the child to flourish. What emerges

from these discussions is that the assumption of moral responsibility in

52 Cleft palette may accompany a range of potential genetic abnormalities, and up to 300 syndromes. In 70% of cases however, the malformation is not syndromal, no other impairments are present and the malformation may be successfully rectified with surgery (Cobourne, 2004). The termination in this case was not performed by Queensland Health.

Page 143: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

143

pregnancy cannot be constructed just in terms of responsibility towards the

foetus, but has wider focus on the self, on relations with significant others,

and on a person’s other commitments and projects’.

Just as the decision to terminate cannot be constructed solely in terms of

responsibility to the foetus, similarly, it cannot be constructed solely in terms of

responsibility to one’s own personal individual desires. Arguably, when the child in

question has been a planned and wanted child who now carries an unplanned and

unwanted disability, the stakes for many become raised (Asch & Wasserman, 2005).

Detached, rational, and atomistic views of autonomy are, therefore, flawed as a

framework of meaningful decision-making in this context as they dismiss the

fundamentally relational nature of ethical decision making and the fact that each

autonomous act has repercussions beyond the immediate decision maker.

Informed Consent and Choice

As previously suggested, ‘informed consent’, through respecting patient autonomy,

is generally regarded as essential for good quality, ethically robust health care and is

regarded as a successful means of protecting patients from coercion, deception, the

withholding of relevant information, and the problematic paternalism of past

decades (Manson & O’Neil, 2007). When levels of patient understanding are high,

greater acceptance of both positive and negative outcomes in care have been noted,

an outcome which is beneficial for practitioners and patients alike (Braddock, 2002;

Grover, 2003; Marteau & Dormandy, 2001). Despite the obvious problems with

modern conceptions of autonomy, informed consent given freely and based on full

and accurate information and understanding is nonetheless desirable.

As a principle that can be turned into an administrative process, autonomy has

become, in the words of Canadian sociologist Arthur Frank, ‘bioethics’ biggest hit’

(Frank, 2005). Institutionally, deference to patient autonomy and informed consent

as defined by, and driven from within, the medical and legal communities have

come to serve a multitude of administrative and legal purposes. According to

Manson (2007, p.301), these purposes include:

Page 144: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

144

• Demonstrating ‘proof’ of ethical practice, as patient ‘rights’ have been

incorporated into verifiable administrative processes. In some interventions,

for example, there is an administrative requirement that consent forms are

signed, thus ethical legitimisation is conferred to existing medical practices.

• Providing a defensive legal document lending protection to medical

practitioners against potential legal recourse.

• Distancing medical care from the widely criticised paternalistic practices of

the past by positioning the decisional capacity as resting solely with the

patient.

While the institutional objectives and benefits of being seen to promote patient

choice seem relatively clear, realisation of the claimed benefits for women, such as

increased control over reproductive decisions and access to more choices in care,

remain unrealised for many. For many women and their partners, ‘choice’ inevitably

equates to the expedient acceptance of the most common route, a pathway that is

clearly paved for them long before they realize they are on it (Lippman, 1999a).

While the terms ‘choice’, ‘consent’, ‘informed consent’ and ‘autonomy’ are liberally

scattered through the medical and bioethics discourse with respect to pregnancy

care, in reality, a person’s ability to exercise such choice is restricted by multiple

social, institutional, and personal constraints. Embedded in time, culture, history,

relationships and prior understandings, each individual’s perception is significantly

coloured by the unique layering of these interpretive filters. Many ‘choices’ are

made under non–negotiable constraints, and are situated in entrenched institutional

cultures and practices of which the person themselves may not even be aware. The

question of choice may be more accurately framed as ‘choices made available’. The

danger that arises in adhering to narrowly defined concepts of agency and choice

with their limited orientation is that an overall ethical legitimisation of the

established health care routines has occurred while deeper concerns about inherent

injustices and failures within existing and unquestioned institutional structures have

remained largely unchallenged (Sherwin, 1992, 2001).

Page 145: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

145

Despite a wide body of social research flagging patient vulnerability and unequal

power dynamics as factors which heavily compromise autonomy and weaken the

capacity to freely exercise agency (Donchin, 2001; Jecker, Jonsen, & Pearlman,

1997; Sherwin, 2001), individual participation is persistently presented as evidence

of ethically sensitive care. As any intervention is taken as fully consensual, the

belief prevails that ‘no injury can be done where the subject is willing’ (Manson &

O’Neil, 2007, p.3). However, as previously suggested, participation or willingness

alone does not automatically demonstrate that such participation is informed, nor

does participation, informed or otherwise, automatically ensure ethical acceptability,

even if it meets the minimal legal standards.

Local experiences of informed consent protocols and their outcomes as experienced

and articulated by members of this cohort significantly mirrored the patterns

observed outside Australia in which women’s actual experiences and knowledge

suggested ill-informed compliance (Bernhardt et al., 1998; Harris, Connor, Bisits, &

Higginbotham, 2004; Kohut, 2002; Markens, Browner, & Press, 1999; Press &

Browner, 1997; Santhalahti, 1999; Santhalahti, Hemminki, Latikka, & Ryynanen,

1998; Stapleton, Kirkham, & Thomas, 2002; Williams, Alderson, & Farsides,

2002c). The stories related by participants similarly highlight the documented

practical struggles in achieving the seemingly elusive goal of informed consent.

Only one of the seven mothers interviewed, Elizabeth, expressed a firm

understanding of the tests on offer and a clear awareness that testing was optional

rather than obligatory. Additionally, she could confidently articulate each test’s

potential outcome and accuracy and communicate the personal and moral meaning

of testing as she interpreted it.

Openly assessing themselves as ill-informed, five of the remaining six mothers

actively described themselves as poorly educated, admitting weak understandings of

which conditions were to be screened for, showing confused interpretations of what

‘risk’ ratios actually meant, displaying inadequate comprehension of the limited

nature of the reassurance sought, and possessing poor knowledge of the proposed

treatments that may be offered. The exception to this observation was the common

awareness that termination would be offered as the ‘next step’ in the event of an

Page 146: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

146

anomaly being found. While the seventh mother, Leanne, actively pursued all

available screening, describing herself as educated and well-informed, many of her

explanations throughout the interview revealed confusion and misunderstandings of

the details of the testing undertaken. Although Leanne’s commitment to have all

available screening may have made the finer details of any interventions superfluous

as she had resolved to accept all forms of screening regardless, as Therese Marteau

and her colleagues note, active participation without adequate understanding may

still demonstrate a lack of informed consent (Dormandy, Hooper, Michie, &

Marteau, 2002a; Marteau & Dormandy, 2001; Marteau et al., 2001). Potential harms

arising from a false sense of reassurance in response to an amniocentesis that offers

secure, but limited, knowledge also warrants mention. The negative psychological

impact experienced by women who have misunderstood the limited nature of

reassurance from amniocentesis and subsequently given birth to a child with a

disability has been found to be more severe and long lasting than for women who

have had no testing, but also birth a child with a disability (Watson et al., 2003).

Thus limited understanding may exacerbate the harms experienced even although

the screening was intentionally sought.

The following comments offered by mothers captured the range of their experiences. There was no reason given as to why the scanning ultrasound was done. I wanted to see the baby, of course, that was a very exciting thing for me. I was interested in whether it was a boy or a girl. With my first child I saw his face, and I was just …. Well….[laughs] I fell in love with him then, he had the sweetest angel face I’d ever seen, and so I was very keen to see my others as well. It only occurred to me as I was undergoing the ultrasound that they were making measurements of different parts of the child’s anatomy and physique and then I realised, I was thinking, well why are they doing this? I never talked to the radiologist, this is just me thinking, I thought they must be looking for things that were unusual or not right and only then it occurred to me that they were looking for abnormalities. Anne

Penny, a registered nurse expecting her first child, described her nuchal scan as such:

I think it really wasn’t presented as a ‘choice’, it’s just this is what you do…. And being my first pregnancy, I just thought well this is what you do…like every one has this scan and then another one and that’s the process in the medical world…….Penny [E: Did anyone discuss with you what the purpose of the scan was and what the potential outcomes may be?] No…they didn’t…………we were sitting there with the brochure, so I guess they would have assumed we would know something….but no actual discussion about what they were going to do, what they were looking for……through the ultrasound they would say stuff like, ‘we’re looking at the heart, or we’re looking at the brain’ and because I’m a nurse I

Page 147: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

147

would say, what are you measuring, and ask more medical oriented questions…………..which is when they mentioned the skin fold that would show Down syndrome or the heart that would also show Down syndrome………..through that they didn’t say particular disorders…I knew they would obviously check the brain to see if there was one ..[laughs]…that the heart is functioning... I would say we were moderately informed,…… yes…….., they’re looking for abnormalities…but should they actually find any then we were not informed about the process of what would happen next. Penny

Danielle, Mary and Terri relayed a typical tale in which their practitioner screened

first and explained later. Danielle explained, Basically it was just, go and do it and well talk about it later………Danielle

A similar experience was recounted by Mary,

It’s so….this is how it is….there’s the referral…off you go…..no questions…no ifs/buts/maybe………….I got no information about it the first time ….I just went.

On assessing whether she gave informed consent, Terri reflected,

Well, I thought I did [give informed consent] but it was only later when they came out with all these other things that I felt that there had been a communication breakdown. I thought I did at the time, but as I say in retrospect, I thought I was informed but I obviously wasn’t as informed as I should have been. I certainly wasn’t informed as to what the result would be and the fact that I would have to make choices after that based on what those tests came up with. Pregnancy, well it’s a vulnerable time, and this pregnancy was vulnerable for me, I’m sure there are lots of women in the same boat…. We really need to tread more lightly……… [Later in the interview]. I did ask questions and they were answered very directly, maybe I just didn’t ask the right questions? I certainly mustn’t have with regards to the tests that I had. Terri.

While Leanne was adamantly in favour of screening regardless of her medical need

or assessed risk level, her explanation illustrates another aspect of informed consent,

which occurs when patients demand interventions that are not medically indicated,

but are psychologically valued and desired. Leanne explained how she broached the

subject of screening with her obstetrician. In the first 10 minutes of my 9 week visit to the obstetrician I told her I would have it done. And she was like ……….she wasn’t going to put me off because she could see I was quite strong about it. There and then I told her (the obstetrician) in the first 10 minutes that I wanted to have an amniocentesis because my colleague at work has a Down syndrome child. ……..The obstetrician wasn’t necessarily keen for me to have it done…. she didn’t say in so many words….. but she was a very open-minded lady, but she could see that I wanted it so she accommodated me, we organised it and I said ‘thank you very much’. Leanne

Finally, Elizabeth was the only one of the mothers interviewed who had proactively

and independently educated herself to a high degree about the nature, efficacy, and

risks of the procedures on offer, and had actively decided, prior to having the first

Page 148: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

148

ultrasound, that she would not pursue further testing if indicated. In answer to the

question, ‘did you feel completely informed?’ Elizabeth replied,

Definitely. Definitely, it was mostly through self-education, but I don’t know whether if I hadn’t had that information they would have volunteered it. The bulk of our support and education came from outside the medical profession; maybe it’s my nature to research whatever I don’t know. We just wanted to find out what we needed to know. The conversation with doctors / midwives was more just clarification. Elizabeth

Collectively, the accounts offered by this cohort of mothers parallel observations

made outside of Australia previously outlined. If informed consent is defined by

adequate information disclosure, voluntary participation, and understanding of the

nature, risks, and implications of the proposed intervention, the comments offered

above suggest that informed consent was not established for six of the seven

mothers in this cohort.

From the practitioners’ perspective, the need to support ethically informed consent

in their patients was acknowledged as important; however, their comments

frequently gravitated towards descriptions of the numerous barriers to attaining the

idealised benchmarks set. While only one practitioner felt that women she saw were

generally well informed, more commonly, practitioners’ comments illustrated the

tensions of negotiating the fluid and complex ethical terrain they traversed with their

patients. These confounding factors included the realisation that informing was a

collaborative venture requiring active patient input, not simply a one-way delivering

of information. Additionally, practitioners acknowledged that the quantity and type

of information revealed could not be a standardised script, but required them to

refine and revise depending on the individual needs and learning capacity of the

particular patient. Issues of practitioner knowledge and preparedness to facilitate the

required knowledge sharing with patients were further recognised as a potentially

significant barrier to developing patient understanding52F

53. The critical time pressures

experienced in clinical care were mentioned as a factor that could lead to expediency

in fulfilling the administrative requirements of consent protocols, while possibly

jeopardising due attention to the moral intentions of the consenting process.

53 This aspect of practitioner training is discussed more thoroughly in Chapter 10.

Page 149: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

149

Awareness of the legal aspect of consent significantly permeated practitioners’

accounts, with one midwife wearily remarking,

I guess we’re at a stage with informed consent where you just have to do your best and write it down. Midwife 3

In assessing the levels of informedness in their patients, the following comments

highlighting the rarity of achieving informed consent in practice were offered by

practitioners. I think informed consent is intriguing and I don’t know that you could honestly ever say that there is true informed consent, because I still think in the end people hear what they want to hear and listen to what they want to listen to and I think we modify our consent discussions to include what we perceive the patient will understand…that’s certainly one of the issues, you tell the patient what you think they can understand, so you probably will tell an educated patient more than a lower educated patient. ……Obstetrician I think we get so busy and carried away with time, we just say “here, can you sign this” and yes, a lot of trust is put in us, and people hope we’ll do the right thing by them…. They sign it because they need it. They need the procedure done ….but they’re not at all confident that they are really safe…. I think safety is a huge issue with informed consent. Midwife 4 Exactly what does [informed consent] mean…………there is a problem I guess with informed consent, I do have a bit of a problem with informed consent, when talking one to one you’re getting what that person wants to give you and that will come across……….and in situations like that, if it’s a health professional giving the woman knowledge to make her own decision you don’t know that it’s the same from woman to woman…it’s different for different women…….it’s a bit of a minefield………you know…it’s huge really, isn’t it…………. Midwife 3 I think women go in blissfully ignorant…. or at least not fully informed of what the possible outcomes are…Midwife 2 There’s many a woman referred here who doesn’t know why she was referred………. because the referring hospital hasn’t told them anything………………or the GP hasn’t told them anything……….except ….we’ve found a little problem, we need a second opinion on the scan……………and then they come down and we say, yes your baby’s got spina bifida… and they didn’t know that was what was being looked for…..they had no idea…………Midwife 1 Often women who are well informed and well misinformed…..by a bit of web surfing……can be an interesting group of people to deal with because ultimately they may have read a load more than every other patient you deal with, you have to, once again, try and sort out what information they have received and put it in context….General Practitioner 1.

Collectively, these comments reinforce the difficulties observed elsewhere, and

outlined previously, that while women apparently actively participate in these

routine regimes, they commonly do so from a position of poor understanding.

Participation alone therefore should not be interpreted as representing ethically

Page 150: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

150

informed or robust intervention. These observations raise further questions of how

practitioners may be better equipped to respond to the learning and informational

needs of their patients. A fuller consideration of this aspect of the informing process

can be found in Chapter 9.

Concentration on Down syndrome as the condition of interest featured prominently

in mothers’ accounts as a justification for screening, a focus that provoked comment

from several practitioners. As an awareness of the numerous syndromes other than

Down syndrome that may be indicated by screening is a central piece of information

required to understand the strengths and limitations of testing, the exaggerated focus

on Down syndrome raised alarm for some practitioners. However, one midwife

interpreted some mothers’ preoccupation with Down syndrome as a demonstration

of good understanding saying, Most of them are quite well informed and they know it’s a screening for Down syndrome, and most will say I’m having the Down syndrome screening, so the women that I have encountered are usually quite well informed. Midwife 1

Other practitioners expressed discomfort that the concentrated attention paid to

Down syndrome ultimately created shallow and impoverished understandings which

persisted at the expense of developing more thorough knowledge about the range of

conditions and possible outcomes which potentially could contribute to false

reassurance. Because of that focus on Down syndrome you can lose sight of the myriad of other problems……… that pregnancies can have…..and I do sometimes, more than sometimes, quite often put Down syndrome into perspective and just remind people that this is just one condition …………and peoples’ understanding of what amnio or CVS result gives is just atrocious……Genetic Counsellor 2. I think they’re pretty uninformed, they think they’re only looking for Down syndrome, and when some other condition is picked up, like a heart defect but not Downs, or another condition, I think they don’t realise that’s a possibility….I don’t know what those providers tell them other than Down syndrome and it is targeted for Down syndrome but whether they say other anomalies could be identified at this time?……. Genetic Counsellor 1

None of the practitioners’ or mothers’ accounts, however, reflected any awareness of

the broader social and historical dynamics that determined Down syndrome to be so

universally unacceptable that such resources and energy should be directed at

preventing the birth of children with this condition. The predefining of certain

conditions as undesirable may influence how the offer to embrace the screening

Page 151: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

151

technology is received (Kenen, 1999). Institutionally endorsed facilitation of the

detection and removal of Down syndrome may suggest screening as an obvious and

rational route to take. Fuller consideration of how social attitudes to disability have

come to permeate screening protocols and parental expectations will be considered

in Chapter Seven which explores the social barriers to informed consent.

Just as Whynes (2002, p.7) concluded that the majority of women expressed

satisfaction with routine ultrasound, ‘accepting the procedure uncritically’, initially

most of the women in this cohort also accepted routine testing uncritically, similarly

accepting and interpreting current protocols at face value and believing that all

routine clinical procedures must necessarily be warranted and safe (ibid). Penny

describes her interpretation of this dynamic, I think there is a level of, if they don’t ask, they mustn’t really want to know….but at the time I didn’t really know what I needed to ask…does that make sense. Penny

However, the creation of a ‘don’t ask/don’t tell’ dynamic ultimately left many

women under equipped and inadequately prepared to negotiate the unforseen

outcomes.

Possibly reassured by their practitioner’s confidence like the women in Whynes’

(2002) study, most mothers in this cohort remained unaware that there might be

potential health risks with repeated ultrasounds53F

54 , that each procedure has an

accompanying false positive rate, that any reassurance may indeed be limited, or that

the list of complications and anomalies not detected by these interventions far

exceeds the list of those that are. Meanwhile, the apparent failure to provide

appropriate, balanced, and comprehensive information in clinical care allows these

seemingly entrenched misconceptions to be perpetuated. For most women, such

misconceptions and false expectations are never revealed, their scans are normal,

and they ultimately birth a healthy baby. However, for the remainder, those who

experience soft markers, elevated blood markers, increased age adjusted risks, or

recommendations of amniocentesis, the anxiety experienced is undoubtedly

compounded by their lack of informedness at the outset.

54 As discussed earlier – see Bellieni et al., 2005; Bricker et al., 2000; Buckley, 2005; Neilson & Alfirevic, 2000.

Page 152: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

152

Presumed Consent

A final note will be made about the presumption of consent in the medical context,

as this is often the basis upon which screening is undertaken. Clearly consent

doesn’t always require a signature on a form or a verbal agreement, and a

practitioner may reasonably presume that consent is given by the non- verbal actions

of their patient as this GP explained,

If you’re thinking just about routine blood tests, checking a person’s haemoglobin, you know it’s perfectly ordinary practice not to ask for specific consent, there’s an idea of implied consent, like someone rolling up their sleeve to get a vaccination, that’s an active action saying that they consent to the procedure, so, there are all sorts of situations like that where there’s no specific consent form, or even a verbal exchange, but that’s not to say consent isn’t given. General Practitioner 3.

Braddock et al (1999) noted earlier that the seriousness of the consequences of any

particular intervention demanded different rigour in informing for different

procedures. Commonly, the level of consent sought is linked to the level of

invasiveness of the procedure. The most common forms of prenatal screening are

ultrasound based and subsequently non-invasive, hence, less rigorous consent

protocols that undermine active patient participation have become normalised. The

practitioner comments below illustrate the pernicious nature of embracing the

presumption of consent as an acceptable benchmark which may fulfil the legal

requirements of consent, but which arguably falls short of the ethical standard

sought.

I think most doctors have the view that once an appointment is made and a woman has turned up and she lies down on that table then that’s consent………..once she is on the table and the doctor or sonographer explains what they’re looking for and what they’re doing……. I guess that’s taken as informed consent without signing a paper……Midwife 1 I think the medical profession might view informed consent as getting on the bed and saying you’ll have a needle or sitting and looking at a scan….we don’t get patients to sign consent forms for anything here as far as I’m aware…………I mean in the foetal medicine unit…..even for CVS and amnio…it’s something I’ve raised whether we should discuss consent forms…..and that type of thing… but the doctors feel that informed consent is them getting on the bed and laying there. [E: Do you disagree with that?] Maybe?..............I think when I have to sign a consent form it makes me consider exactly what I’m doing so, I guess coming from the genetics side of things we have a lot of consent forms we get people to sign when they have a gene test…so that people understand the implications, the risks and so on…….I find it unusual that they don’t. Genetic Counsellor 2

Page 153: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

153

This flawed, but critical, presumption that non-invasiveness negates the need for

rigorous consent has infiltrated practice, opening a logical space to regard consent as

somehow less important, and allowing practitioners to equate ‘non-invasive’ to

‘innocuous’. However, this premise negates the multiple potential harms including

the intense psychological harms, which persist regardless of the level of

invasiveness (Kowalcek et al., 2002; Leithner et al, 2004). Kowalcek et al (2002,

p.22) concluded that ‘before examination, the ultrasound group indicated the

highest, although not statistically, level of depressive reactions in spite of it being a

non-invasive test’. In the case of prenatal screening, where the outcome may lead to

the termination of a pregnancy, the ethical stakes are high and consenting protocols

must be rigorous regardless of the level of invasiveness. The potential to uncover

serious health problems with significant implications for parents should flag prenatal

screening in all its forms as an area of intervention requiring a more thorough,

explicit, and ethically secure approach to consenting patients. While we may accept,

as Beauchamp and Childress (2001, p.88) do, that because ‘actions are never fully

informed, voluntary or autonomous, it does not follow that they are never

adequately informed, voluntary or autonomous’, we ought remain vigilant to

institutional practices which erode and undermine the opportunity to examine the

moral implications of any medical intervention.

Chapter Summary

In summary, the experiences of the cohort of this study certainly demonstrate a

consistent failure to achieve the ethical safeguard of informed consent as articulated

in these particular accounts. While respect for autonomy through seeking a patient’s

informed consent may theoretically support freedom of decision making, it does not

automatically follow that a person has been made aware of, or is in a position to

actualise, their preferred option. The socially and institutionally embedded nature of

medical decision making dictates that such decision are always relationally

constructed and constrained. The strong legal bias that informs institutionally

developed consent protocols have focused attention too heavily on facilitating the

practitioner ‘getting’ consent, while inadequate attention has been given to

supporting the reflective understanding of the patient giving consent. Critical

Page 154: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

154

questions of who informs, what they inform, and for whose benefit the information

disclosed is chosen remain concealed under the dominant paradigm. Yet these

questions form the basis of a hermeneutically aware, ethically responsive, and

inclusive decision making. Thus, the dominant interpretation of autonomy and

informed consent must be expanded to embrace and accommodate the relationally

embedded dimensions of autonomy.

The next chapter will examine some of the particular institutional constraints that

impinge upon women’s and practitioners’ capacities to support informed consent in

clinical care.

Page 155: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

155

CHAPTER 6

VOICES IN CONTEXT:

INSTITUTIONAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction

Institutional factors constraining the realisation of informed consent in practice

include the routine nature of screening, overt and covert counselling, and barriers to

communication. Other factors include the pressures of limited time and resources, in

addition to the impact of existing legal frameworks on institutional policy and

practice. Each of these factors will be considered in relation to the wider body of

established research and the stories shared by participants locally.

Routine Testing and the ‘Normative’ Pathway

Previous studies have suggested that the reassuringly routine way in which

screening is presented to women implicitly presumes participation and, therefore,

may obscure the voluntary nature of the proposed test (Green, Hewison, Bekker,

Bryant, & Cuckle, 2004; Lippman, 1999a; Markens et al., 1999; Press & Browner,

1997; Santhalahti et al., 1998; Williams et al., 2002c). Press and Browner (1997)

further suggest that routinisation obfuscates the need for women to make a

deliberate decision and similarly blurs the practitioner’s obligation to intentionally

inform their patients (ibid). However, routinisation may be welcomed by some

women, allowing them to frame such decisions as simple formalities, and thus

bypass the ‘moral work’ (Williams et al., 2005, p.1987).

As understanding the optional and voluntary nature of any medical intervention is a

crucial precursor to informed consent, any routinisation which does not explicitly

alert patients to the alternative choice of ‘opting out’ inevitably compromises the

worth of the consent given. As Green and Stratham note, ‘acceptance of routines

because they are routine means pregnant women do not necessarily make an

informed decision’ (Green & Statham, 1996, p.143). The observation of under-

Page 156: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

156

informed compliance was evident in the experiences of five of the seven participants

in the mothers’ cohort of this study. For example, Terri, who unexpectedly fell

pregnant with her fourth child at the age of 38 remarked,

I guess because I was a bit older, there were questions asked and it was almost assumed that there were certain things I should do. I was asked quite a few times whether I wanted these tests done. I guess being older, I was 38, because I had gone over the 35 ‘hill’, over the hill [laughs], a lot of the doctors and nurses who saw me were saying “what sort of tests would you like - we need to be careful”…. I felt it was a case of I ‘should’ have the tests……. Definitely, it was promoted as everyone does it, especially if you’re over 35…

Terri further explained,

It was promoted as everyone does it, especially if you’re over 35 … Terri

Danielle, Anne and Penny relayed remarkably similar accounts of the events and

expectations that culminated in their screening experience. I just assumed that’s what you do…it’s routine……..I never imagined there would be anything……….I honestly thought it was just a routine exercise that you had [emphasis] to do……….the hospital said you had to do certain tests at certain times……..in my opinion I don’t think they give you the impression that it’s voluntary……..it’s expected, I don’t know that if you said no……I realise they couldn’t force you to do it…..but, yes, it’s expected………….mostly from the hospital….they have expectations that you do this after this and so on………..so I imagine that you didn’t really, as such, have a choice not to do it. Danielle No, I did not understand that it (ultrasound) was voluntary, when I was told that it was routine , I thought that that it wasn’t voluntary therefore I never questioned whether it was a voluntary thing or not. There was no reason given as to why the scanning ultrasound was done. …….She [GP] said it was a routine scan, she wrote me the form to take to the radiologist and there we are. Anne Basically, the obstetrician said that this was the standard process – it was just like – you have a 12 week ultrasound – here’s your request form and off you go. Yes, everybody does it; I assumed he just sent everybody…I think it really wasn’t presented as a ‘choice’, it’s just this is what you do…. And being my first pregnancy, I just thought well this is what you do…like every one has this scan and then another one and that’s the process in the medical world. Penny

These stories resonate with Santhalahti et al’s (1998) observation that when the

option to test is presented routinely with explicit expectations of compliance,

participation is interpreted as ‘self evident’(Santhalahti et al., 1998). Under such

circumstances it may be harder to ‘opt out’ of the accepted and expected routine

without appearing ‘difficult’ or ‘uncooperative’ (Press & Browner, 1997; Williams

et al., 2002c), as Terri further noted, It does make it harder to say no, because it means that you have to go out of your way to actually say ‘no, I don’t want it’. Terri

Page 157: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

157

Similarly, Penny encountered pressure from her doctors when attempting to ‘opt

out’ of the expected amniocentesis after her nuchal scan revealed a higher than usual

age adjusted risk. She explained,

So we’re sitting there looking at each other, thinking we’re not going to do anything about it and they’re sitting looking at us saying “Well, you really should have the amnio and that will tell you more definitively if there’s a problem” And it was like we really had to stand our ground, to say no….. We’ve already thought about this ….and we don’t want it… [E: Was that presented as a “you should” or was it more, “here is an option to consider”?] Oh, it was definitely a “you should”….it wasn’t an option....it was an expectation. They were booking an appointment for me the following week to have the amnio, and we were saying, but we don’t want one…….and it was difficult actually to sit there and keep saying “no, we’re telling you we don’t want it…..yes, we understand the risk, you’ve just told us the risk is this percentage”, but for us that wasn’t the point…. [E: How was your refusal accepted by your doctors?] Well, you could see that they thought we were not making the right decision, and that they were concerned for us – they were re-presenting the facts of the results, and re-presenting the low risk of amnio…. And we were like, yes we understand that, but were still not doing it…. Penny

While Penny resisted the palpable pressure to conform to the expected ‘next step’,

for others, such as Mary, the blatant expectations of her doctors, coupled with her

unwillingness or lack of confidence to question the gathering momentum for more

testing created a situation in which Mary later described herself as having been

‘railroaded’ into having an amniocentesis.

The main thing for me was not knowing, not knowing what the different outcomes of the tests were…………..and just being railroaded with it at the time…………… [E: Did you feel railroaded?] Yes……………..I think that’s the best way to describe it……….. [E: Who did you feel was railroading you?] The specialist who gave me the results…………he was very in your face…………..he was very good but very in your face with the results……………he said “shall I book you in for this…[amniocentesis]….its your option but ….if it was my wife I’d be making her do it”…………….OK! ..[sigh]. ….We went home and spoke to our obstetrician before we decided………but even information on that wasn’t readily available either which made it harder. Mary

As these mothers experienced, once such routines are entrenched, they become the

accepted benchmark of care, self-perpetuating, and often unreflectively endorsed.

The tacit social and medical presumptions and unequal power dynamics implicit

Page 158: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

158

within the institutional frameworks of medical care silently funnel women down the

predetermined normative pathway.

The routine inclusion of newer tests such as the nuchal translucency scan, under the

rubric of an older established antenatal routine of having an antenatal ultrasound has

further blurred the principles of consent and voluntary choice. While Whynes (2002,

p.11) positively notes that ‘… routinisation of use appears to have given rise to

routinisation of subject acceptance’, when women are conditioned to expect

particular interventions, the extension of accepted protocols such as ‘the 18 week

ultrasound’, to the more recent ‘12 week ultrasound’, further blurs intentional

consent as the starkly different clinical aims of each test may not be differentiated

by women (Kenen, 1996; Press & Browner, 1997). This was certainly the case for

Penny, who explained,

Basically, the obstetrician said that this was the standard process – it was just like – you have a 12 week ultrasound – here’s your request form and off you go. [E: Was it presented as something everybody does?] Yes, everybody does it; I assumed he just sent everybody, and you know I guess I just took his word for it…………, I had thought I would only have an 18 week scan , but ….that was obviously not the case. So, I booked the appointment, went to the hospital, and really didn’t know what I was there for so I thought… I better read a brochure, one that was floating about …. Penny

Practitioners too struggled with balancing the tensions between the need to devise

methodical, institution wide processes which ensured appropriate care at the

appropriate time, and the potential undermining effect such routinisation could have

on patients by eroding voluntariness and not providing time to build adequate

understanding. Most practitioners in this cohort articulated some tension between

balancing the logistical demands of seeing multiple patients in a busy clinical

environment with the time-consuming desire to respect voluntariness, support

education and honour informed consent in patients. Additional time pressures

resulting from the unstoppable biological trajectory of pregnancy create further

impetus to act before the medically preferred window to terminate before 20 weeks

passed. Recognising that methodical organisational processes can gather a

momentum of their own, engulfing and undermining the practicing of genuine

Page 159: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

159

‘choice’ for patients, the comments offered by this GP highlighted the potential

dangers and ‘choicelessness’ that routinisation potentially creates for women.

I think because of the structure of the Shared Care Program54F

55, they really have to have a set thing where there are predetermined tests at certain times so that the obstetricians who are ultimately in charge have all the information they want, so it’s very easy that we as doctors just slot in to that………….so that’s my fear ….that we present it as an obvious thing to want, that we medicalise the whole process. My other fear is that other GP’s out there doing shared care, who themselves have no ethical problem with termination; they will present it as a good idea. I think if it’s presented to us as GP’s and we are really told pretty much that we have to offer them to patients or we are not giving patients freedom of choice, but it’s presented in such a way that ‘of course you would want this test’, and we present it that way, then we don’t really give them a true choice. General Practitioner 2

These sentiments were further reinforced by a midwife, who reflected,

Because it’s offered to everyone, it’s just another step in the routine…so we just do it without really making sure we know what the implications are, we don’t ask all the questions,……… I wonder if that’s how it comes out…..so many people look at the 18 week morphology scan as an opportunity to get a picture of the baby and find out the baby’s sex…………which is of minor medical consequence…its not diagnostic……so its of such small consequence ……yet to many women that’s the big thing………are they taking the 12 week scan the same way without really, really understanding what we’re doing? Midwife 3

While practitioners generally agreed that routine presentation could undermine

voluntariness, some minimised the potentially powerful culmination of social

pressures to conform that routinisation created, holding on to the belief that the

exercising of individual choice was ultimately simple and unencumbered.

Responding to the question of whether routine presentation obscured voluntariness,

the following responses were offered,

Well it [routine testing] could obscure voluntariness …..I suppose that’s possible with anything……it’s offered to every woman but it’s up to them whether they take it or not, so long as they know what it means. …….Midwife 1

55 In Queensland, antenatal care is typically provided in one of three ways.

1. Shared care – in which the woman has most antenatal visits with her GP, returning to the tertiary hospital at 36 weeks for final antenatal visits and delivery.

2. Private obstetrician- after initial referral from a GP, all care, including delivery, is provided by the obstetrician of the woman’s choice.

3. Public care- in which all antenatal appointments take place in the antenatal clinic of a public hospital. In this mode of care, a woman may see multiple physicians during her pregnancy. This option is fully funded by the State and Federal governments.

The approximate distribution between these three modes of care are 35% private obstetrician, 35% shared care, and 29% solely public hospital care (Coory, Rosellli, & Carrol, 2007). There is another option of the Birth Centre in Brisbane. Although this option is flagged as the only publicly funded low intervention birthing service in Queensland, recent policy changes now require all women, regardless of risk status or age, to have ultrasound to assess their risk level prior to acceptance in this midwife-run service.

Page 160: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

160

Possibly, however…yes, I think it does. They don’t have to have any tests. Genetic Counsellor 1

Just as institutional logistics contribute to routinisation, patients’ demands and

expectations have also been found to contribute to shaping the dynamic of routine

screening with several studies confirming that women want such intervention

(Harris et al., 2004; Stephens, Montefalcon, & Lane, 2000; Whynes, 2002). In

conforming to the social norms of responsible pregnant behaviour, another GP cited

patient expectation as a real driving force in how such routine protocols evolve, I think there can tend to be a routinisation of things, whatever they are…….there’s also an expectation that certain tests are available would be offered and a number of people may think that if they weren’t offered, and then there would be something wrong. Of course what’s in their mind is that it’s a routine test, at that point, while there’s little doubt that whatever you say they will go and have it done, you could discuss why they’re having it done, that may have been explained or may not. General Practitioner 3 I don’t know who is driving it ……obviously consumers want it…..Genetic Counsellor 1

Such ‘consumer demand’ was evident in Leanne’s account, when she explained,

I told her I would have it done. And she was like ……….she wasn’t going to put me off because she could see I was quite strong about it. Leanne

Although Penny, Terri and Danielle passively conformed to the routine of screening

initially, when further diagnostic testing was indicated, they forcefully declined,

resisting clear directives from their various doctors to accept the next step in the

pathway, illustrating that indeed, mothers ‘don’t have to have any tests’. However,

their physicians’ reactions to their rejection, including paternalistic reactions of

rebuke and reproach, created distress and anger for these women which significantly

soured their ongoing relationship with their carers. While several practitioners of

this cohort defended their belief that no person ‘had to’ test, routinisation coupled

with admonishment for not complying may indeed create powerful pressure to

conform. As Stapleton and Kirkham (2002, p.639) have observed, institutional

structures and selective information can be massaged to encourage patients to make

the ‘right’ choice, rather than the ‘informed’ choice.

In assessing the impact of routinisation on voluntariness, comparable studies in the

Netherlands provide valuable insights into the effect such routinisation has on the

Page 161: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

161

uptake of prenatal testing. As a country which prohibits all routine screening that

may pose a psychological or physical health threat to the person being screened (van

den Berg et al., 2005), the routine offer of prenatal screening is prohibited by law in

Holland. Van den Berg et al (ibid, p.84) explain:

‘One of the categories of the population screening that requires ministerial

approval is screening for ‘serious disorders that can be neither treated nor

prevented’. Prenatal screening for congenital disorders comes under this

category, since the legislature considers termination of pregnancy as neither

treatment nor prevention (Health Council of the Netherlands: Committee on

Population Screening Act, 1996). Since there is no approval for this type of

screening in the Netherlands, it is forbidden to offer prenatal screening to

women unless they request it.’

Under the rubric of non-routine screening, uptake rates in the Netherlands have been

reported at 46% (ibid), under half that of the rates of up to 99% acceptance recorded

in situations where routinisation is entrenched (Spencer et al., 2003; Thornton,

Hewison, Lilford, & Vail, 1995). Such figures suggest that uptake may be largely

dependent on how a test is offered, and may not necessarily indicate intentional or

informed choice by the participant. Attempts to conflate high participation rates with

ethical acceptability such as those made by Whynes (2002) or Cuckle (2001, p.85)

who suggests that high uptake indicates ‘no conflict’ must therefore be challenged.

While routinisation is unproblematically accepted, advocates of routinisation such as

Whynes (2002, p.11) conclude ‘such a trade off between a large number of

reassured, negatively tested subjects against the small number of distressed

positively tested subjects is endemic to all screening programs and not only

scanning in pregnancy’. Interestingly, Whynes (ibid) notes that no participants

questioned the purpose or safety of ultrasound, presuming it to be safe, although

only one in ten women described themselves as ‘informed’. Perhaps as van den

Berg (2005), Kowalcek (2002) and Lippman (1991) postulate, the reassurance

women report may simply be relief from the stress generated by the test itself.

Page 162: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

162

While routinisation may contribute to inhibiting informed consent, some researchers

advocate for more tests to be offered routinely as a means of strengthening and

supporting informed consent (Dormandy et al., 2002a), with Levi (2002) further

cautioning that lack of routine access may restrict diagnosis of serious

malformations and thus deny access to the choice of a desired abortion (Levi, 2002).

These authors suggest that not routinely offering screening creates additional

practical barriers and therefore undermines the practical exercising of autonomy.

Dormandy et al (2002a) observed that double the number of women accepted

routine nuchal translucency scanning when offered as part of a battery of other

routine tests such as routine blood tests55F

56. They further concluded that women

undergoing screening on the same day visit had higher levels of knowledge56F

57 and

more positive attitudes than their ‘separate visit’ counterparts claiming,

‘conducting screening as a part of a routine visit, compared to screening

that requires a separate visit, seems to maximise informed choice to undergo

the test without impairing informed choice to decline’ (Dormandy, Hooper,

Michie, & Marteau, 2002b, p. 113 ).

These findings speak to the important impact that practical accessibility has on

influencing women’s behaviour, however, critical details of the difference in how

these tests were offered at each hospital or the impact of the non-standardised

information used are not disclosed in this paper. The further ethical distinction

between choice and informed choice are also not fully explored. Particular

contextual and institutional factors, such as the attitude of the nursing staff, the

perceived time pressures, potential bias in the information imparted, or different

ways of administering the tests, all of which have significant influence on the

outcomes, are also not fully divulged. Hence, the conclusions drawn in this paper

may not be as obvious as suggested and certainly require further exploration before

such claims can be confidently made.

56 Figures dropped from 41% acceptance to 21% when a separate visit was required to take up the offer of screening (Dormandy et al, 2001, p.109). 57 There are functional cognitive reasons explaining the apparently higher knowledge levels assessed immediately after information is given which do not necessarily indicate higher levels of understanding and these will be more fully considered in Chapter Nine.

Page 163: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

163

While reducing physical barriers may facilitate informed choice for some women,

for others routinisation potentially denies the opportunity to explore, assimilate, and

reflect upon the information given. Indeed, the offer to be tested immediately may

be experienced as coercive in that the perceived time pressure could be interpreted

as a strong recommendation to participate, creating a sense that women may ‘miss

out’ if they decline the offer here and now. This situation is described by one GP.

I think if they make a decision quickly they’ll tend to go for the test, so they’ll decide not to

miss out, they have it done and think about it later, but they don’t want to miss that

opportunity and regret that later…and then they’re on the treadmill. General Practitioner 2

While removing the ‘practical barriers’ may increase immediate uptake it may deny

a patient the opportunity to seek alternative information from different sources.

Within the scope of the studies completed (Dormandy et al., 2002a; Marteau,

Dormandy, & Michie, 2001; Michie et al., 2002; Michie, Dormandy, & Marteau,

2003) the reasons why women chose not to return for follow-up screening were not

pursued and attitudes after the initial consultation were not re-assessed. Perhaps as

Santhalahti et al (1998) suggest, the reason many women decline is not because they

have a philosophical objection or a practical barrier, but rather screening is not the

priority practitioners often assume it should be, a point re-iterated by Liamputtong

(2003, p.101) who observed, ‘women’s subjective perceptions may be divergent

from those of health care professionals’.

In conclusion, the benefits of routinisation are that administratively, routine

protocols ensure that medically valued tests are methodically carried out at the

clinically appropriate time. Additionally, for some women the practical barriers of

undergoing the test are removed by routinisation. However, these potential gains

appear to occur at the expense of a fundamental condition of informed consent

which is time to absorb and reflect upon the information given with time to develop

a sound understanding of the implications and outcomes of the processes consented

to. In the case of assessing the health of an unborn child with the potential view to

terminate a pregnancy, the potentially wide ranging ethical implications arguably

warrant fuller consideration than those afforded by routinisation. Without

accompanying ‘routine’ education to ensure that adequately informed decisions are

Page 164: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

164

reached, routinisation coupled with the expectation of compliance remains ethically

problematic.

Equally, however, while much of the research evidence suggests that many women

participate in a routine and inadequately informed way, this does not automatically

infer that they have been coerced or acted upon against their wishes. Nor does it

automatically follow that their autonomy has been violated as many competent

autonomous adults choose to defer to the medical ‘experts’ (Schneider 1996).

However, we can infer that without access to appropriate education, the outcome of

routinisation appears to have been a weakening of intentional and voluntary consent

for many women, as recognised by many practitioners in this cohort and evident in

the accounts of five of the seven mothers of this cohort.

Institutional Barriers to Education: Blurred Accountability for Informing

While the offer of screening is an established and accepted part of the antenatal

routine, the accompanying education required to inform patients about the purpose

and potential outcomes for this cohort of mothers often seemed ad hoc and chiefly

dependent on the personal commitment and knowledge levels of individual

practitioners. The technical aspects of testing are institutionally embedded, while the

preliminary educational aspects are left ostensibly to the discretion of individual

practitioners and largely dependent upon their own level of knowledge. All health

care professionals interviewed in this study articulated a strong commitment to the

ideals of informed consent supporting its aims and intentions, with many

demonstrating sound educational strategies such as providing individualised written

information or asking patients to paraphrase back their understandings to support

their decisions. However, a significant finding from this research is that confusion

and lack of accountability surrounding where, how, and who was responsible for

informing patients created a significant gap in the ‘informed’ consent processes.

Page 165: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

165

A consequence of the Shared Care57F

58 structure of antenatal care in Queensland is that

most women move between various health professionals for different parts of their

care. Typically, a woman will see a GP, an obstetrician, perhaps multiple midwives,

a sonographer and possibly a genetic counsellor if indicated. This

compartmentalised delivery of care creates a situation in which each practitioner

may reasonably presume that another practitioner has taken responsibility for

informing. This is evidenced by the following comments,

[E: Who is responsible for patient education?] The first contact person the patient sees for that pregnancy… Obstetrician. Basically if they are going through a private obstetrician, in my mind it’s up to them to talk to their obstetrician about that………so I might say…. you need to book with your obstetrician before 10 weeks to give you time to discuss it and decide ( about testing)….. General Practitioner 2. Probably the scanning department…..they could say, ‘well, you’ve presented here for a scan today, what do you think we are going to find or what do you hope we find?’…Midwife 2.

Well what sort of education……..we have our antenatal classes, but for prenatal screening….I don’t know that anyone is responsible…..I think we are relying on the GP’s to act ethically and responsibly and if they are going to order the test then they need to make sure they know what they are doing. Midwife 3.

They all see the genetic counsellor beforehand and if the result is out of range they will see her again…….but I think she sees everyone having a nuchal……yes………and this is where she tells them about false positives and false negatives……she does see everyone. Midwife 1.

The genetic counsellor referred to above subsequently explained that she did not in

fact see everyone. In a hospital in which all women regardless of risk status were

offered nuchal translucency screening, in which approximately 100 babies were born

each week, she was able to counsel only between 10 and 20 women. She explained It is quite disjointed…..there’s no set process……it does feel a bit haphazard… … [E: How many women do you counsel for Nuchal Translucency?] Very, very small……. In an average week I would see 10-15 women, 20 at most……….very, very small, very small. Everywhere has different processes and protocols………every GP has different processes and protocols too……..so that inequity depends on where you go as to what you’re offered…it’s clearly not a fair or just way to go…. but at the end of the day it’s up to GP’s, obstetrician, genetic counsellor, I guess whoever the patient presents to………I guess …antenatal clinic...but it is haphazard……mmmm………..for sure. Genetic Counsellor 2.

58 See footnote 55. p.159.

Page 166: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

166

For mothers trying to access the relevant knowledge, the lack of information

proactively offered proved to be a further barrier to the consent process as Mary

explained, Information on that wasn’t readily available [on amnio] either which made it harder. [E: Where did you find the information you wanted?] I rang the specialist and asked them to send it to me. [E: Are you saying it wasn’t offered…you had to request it?] No…. it wasn’t offered……..They sent me a two page list; there was spina bifida, all these different ones….. I’d never even heard of most of them…they said because you have this result it’s pretty likely you’re going to have one of these……….there was a two page list of them…Mary (birthed a healthy baby boy).

Mary’s experience highlighted further lapses in the communication and education

process, where disjointed information was divulged in a fragmented fashion by

various practitioners,

We got there for the scan and got given some paperwork that said they would scan the baby… on the day……The person who did the scan explained what they were looking for……they took a detailed history of how old, how many pregnancies and so on……………that happened 5 minutes before the scan………. [E: Was there any discussion about false positives, false negatives, and possible next step after a bad result?] No….no …nothing………………..they said we’re looking for a result of 1:60058F

59 if it’s over that you’re fine…………….if not we’ll look at other options……..and then they did it [E: What did you understand those other options to be?] Well she didn’t talk about that because she was just doing the ultrasound. Mary

Later describing herself as ‘not even remotely prepared’ Mary’s concluding remarks

reaffirm how her lack of knowledge contributed to the intense emotional anguish she

subsequently experienced.

I think a lot of people just aren’t aware of what can and can’t happen with these tests…..and I honestly think there needs to be a lot more information out there for the public…..well and truly……………..Information that can tell you,………OK, we do this test, this is what its for…… because I had no idea……………and there was no-one for me to talk to …… Who do you talk to ….there’s no 1300 number to ring………….what are my options? What do I do? I think that needs to be available……….I was a basket case………….I just sat in my

59 In the risk discourse of pregnancy, anecdotal stories of risk ‘slippage’ are common. Although elevated risk used to be considered as over 35 years old or above 1:350 from blood tests or Nuchal, frequently women report being categorised as ‘high’ risk at 31, as Danielle was, or with a Nuchal age adjusted risk of 1:500 as Terri was.

Page 167: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

167

room and cried…………….its not good feeling that way when you’re pregnant……….being on sedatives because you’re so worked up you can’t sleep with worry……………so yeah………Mary

Other mothers similarly described poor educational opportunities with their

practitioners and their turn to the internet to clarify and assuage their concerns.

Accordingly, most of the mothers in this cohort described themselves as ‘self

educated’ about the details of testing. While self education is not necessarily a bad

thing, the turn to the internet perhaps indicates a gap in communication with those

practitioners best placed to help or interpret the overwhelming and often

contradictory information available on the internet.

Communication – Commitments and Barriers

‘Strangers taking care of strangers can come to be as pathological a

factor in certain situations as sepsis’ (Wear, 1998, p.95).

As previously outlined in this thesis, dialogue and communication lie at the ethical

core of the intersubjective encounters between human beings. The ability of patients

and physicians to communicate effectively is therefore an essential element of

medical care, as it is through these dialogical encounters that mutual appreciation

and understanding may emerge. Consequently, barriers to effective communication

contribute significantly to the ethical failures observed both in the existing literature

and for individual members of this research cohort. Within organisational care,

power dynamics, organisational hierarchies, time pressures, financial pressures,

under resourcing, and inadequate support and training of staff, are recognised as

converging to undermine successful communication (Leithner et al., 2006; Stewart,

2001a; Stewart et al., 1999).

Research into communication patterns between health carers and patients

predominantly paints a bleak picture (Bub, 2004; Leithner et al., 2006; Leithner,

Fischer-Kern, Hilger, Loffler-Stastka, & Ponocny-Seilger, 2004). For example, in

Leithner et al’s (2006) study gauging pregnant women’s assessment of attitudes,

information, and communication styles of their physicians, only 22% felt ‘satisfied’

with physician attitudes, with a high 46% reporting strong dissatisfaction. Almost

Page 168: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

168

30% of respondents cited lack of time as a factor in the paucity of information

received leading Leithner et al (ibid) to conclude that women in their study generally

experienced a ‘striking lack of communication competence in nurses and physicians’

(Leithner et al., 2006, p.936).

Poor physician/patient communication was experienced by many mothers in this

cohort who noted a similar lack of information, emerging from a ‘don’t ask, don’t

tell’ dynamic of communication that left them ill prepared for sequelae of testing.

Penny summarised,

I think there is a level of, if they don’t ask, they mustn’t really want to know….but at the time I didn’t really know what I needed to ask…does that make sense… Penny

This experience was reiterated by Terri, who identified lack of time and poor

communication as significant factors in her negative experience, I did ask questions and they were answered very directly, maybe I just didn’t ask the right questions? I certainly mustn’t have with regards to the tests that I had, at the same time I did say that my cousin’s child had this, and I was concerned about that, so they sent me off for those tests. Now I would say there was a definite lapse in communication. I do think the communication issues are a bit of a problem there. It’s hard to say, I think it comes down to the speed of service, they are seeing so many women, and they don’t have the time. Terri

As Terri hints, her revelation that she harboured some concern may have prompted

her doctors to act in the way they did, highlighting the patient’s contribution to

shaping the quality and dynamics of the dialogues experienced (Post, Cegala, &

Miser, 2002). Patient input was frequently cited by practitioners as a significant

factor shaping how each consultation unfolded. The attitudes, openness, and

intellectual capacity of patients were frequently raised by practitioners when

explaining the poor communication patterns noted, as the Obstetrician explained, I think we modify our consent discussions to include what we perceive the patient will understand…that’s certainly one of the issues; you tell the patient what you think they can understand, so you probably will tell an educated patient more than a lower educated patient. Obstetrician

Although Mei-The et al (2000) were assessing communication patterns between

cancer patients and their doctors when they noted ‘patients had more influence on

what was and was not said in the consultation than might be expected’ (Mei-The,

Hak, Koeter, & van der Wal, 2000, p.1379), physicians in this cohort generally

Page 169: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

169

expressed that patient influence in poor communication was also prevalent in the

prenatal encounter. Mei-The et al (ibid, p.1381) concluded that

‘breaking the cycle of collusion between patient and doctor is not necessarily

a question of whether the patient has to be informed at all, which usually is

the case, but rather how doctors and patients deal with these facts in

practice. Awareness cannot be forced on the patient’.

Similarly, Post et al (2002) acknowledge the interdependent and dynamic nature of

communication, noting the active role that patients played in shaping the quality of

the informing process experienced. Several practitioners strongly rejected the

presumption that poor clinical communication stemmed solely from the practitioner

half of the communication dyad, acknowledging shared accountability with their

patients. Well, communication is a huge problem…a big problem……and this is where you wonder how much people actually do understand, have a full understanding…medical jargon…it’s always been a problem and I think it always will be…..I guess the thing is you need to ask them what they know and what they’ve understood……and they will say ‘yes, yes I know’, but then you ask them to paraphrase back what they’ve been told and they look at you blankly or they have it all mixed up…..or they really don t understand. Midwife 1 Girls go along to the doctor, first time they’ve ever met this guy, female, whatever, to find out they’re pregnant, no rapport, no nothing…………and yet, you’re supposed to believe whatever this person tells you ……………..and I might say from both sides of the fence…..I might tell you…..patients can lie as well as any other person…..or don’t tell you the whole truth or give you the whole picture…... Midwife 2. The problem is that they don’t understand the dynamics of testing …there’s the grey zone… there are the absolutes but there is a huge grey zone that may create more anxiety than anything else……that’s when I think they are not really aware enough….. Then again, their level of education affects that as well……..not everyone has the capacity to understand why something can or can’t show you something….Obstetrician

Further comments alluded to the difficulty some practitioners had in determining

what information was relevant. The desire to collude in protecting patients from

unnecessary anxiety, while still making sure all medically relevant tests were

performed, prompted the following comments:

I don’t know that it’s a breakdown [in communication] , its just that a lot of information is not given because it feels extraneous at the time, like it’s an extra burden, and with a very low chance of it happening why would you talk about all the potential possibilities…unless you’re dealing with the reality of what’s there…I think it’s just time, economics and

Page 170: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

170

emotional burden… why would you worry someone about something that’s highly unlikely. You do need to advise that there is a small risk that something unlikely could be found, but you wouldn’t go into detail about all the possibilities. It’s economics I think……… time and emotional burden. Genetic Counsellor 1 I think the barriers are a couple of things, as soon as a woman finds out they are pregnant, their level of anxiety is higher anyway, and they always do tend to worry about their baby. People are worried about exacerbating this anxiety by mentioning the possibility of an abnormality, so we don’t actually tell people, well, your risk of miscarriage in the first 8 weeks is 15%, between 12-20 weeks it this much and so on… the chance of stillbirth after 20 weeks is 1 % and so on ….. You don’t tell women those things……..and likewise mentioning anything about abnormalities, you don’t particularly mention to people that well…..5% of all babies can be born with something because you don’t want them to worry. So, that’s one of the barriers, not to worry the pregnant woman so much and so that effects how much you actually talk about, so you kind of order these tests and they know it’s kind of that they may be looking for a problem, but they are not truly informed about exactly what it is that is being looked for and how accurate it is and what we can and can’t pick up……so I think that’s one of the biggest problems…. Obstetrician.

While the motivations of these practitioners are clearly well intentioned, their

executive decision to exclude patients from a collaborative negotiation on what

information may be relevant occurred mostly without reflection, entrenching

Edwards, Elwyn, & Mulley (2002, p.827) observation that ‘information is

communicated only from the clinician to the patient, and that the acceptability is

communicated back’. However, Edwards et al (ibid) continue, proposing that a ‘two

way exchange about information and opinion is important if decisions are to reflect

the attitudes to risk of the people who will live with the outcomes’. This well-

established research suggests that the discernment of what knowledge is pertinent to

the patient is not uncovered, further entrenching the asymmetrical power dynamic, a

status quo that stifles authentic reflection and dialogue between patient and

practitioner, and which undermines patient-centred care. Practitioners of this cohort

further noted that information is often given in a time of crisis; hence, the ways in

which it is received and assimilated may be distorted by the emotional anguish of

the circumstances. I guess the big barrier [to effective communication] is that, it’s a crisis, you know it’s emotional turmoil and you’re trying to understand information when the rug has just been pulled out from you, and you know it’s important information, but ……… you’re emotionally not very well equipped to handle it at that stage. Having said that, it’s amazing how much people do understand and learn, and you know …..come to grips with what they need to know in a crisis. I guess I’ m conscious of the fact that ……often people are not …………. in the best position to absorb a lot of detail, or information, so I actually think it’s a mistake to try and burden them with resources and handouts and things like that. We shouldn’t have that expectation of them that they should take in a lot of new knowledge at that point in time. Clinical Geneticist

Page 171: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

171

Often the information comes as a shock so they can’t really deal with it - they don’t understand too much unless it’s a lethal condition and the baby, it’s just a matter of time before the baby will die, they tend to understand, like black and white. The subtleties are often lost. Genetic Counsellor 1

Illustrating the ability to focus and give attention as a critical precursor for learning

(Woods & Barrow, 1975)59F

60, Danielle described a scenario in which her emotional

distress, coupled with the distraction of her other children running around the room,

created a lack of attention that limited and distorted her understandings, resulting in

a poor educational outcome. I couldn’t have possibly understood the things she said to me….to the point where we would get home and [husband] would say, [the doctor] said this and I would have completely forgotten that ………..he was focussing on the facts and I was in a head spin…………..I mean she’s a good doctor, but I think she should have rung and said I don’t want to alarm you but…..I need to speak with you and your husband on your own ……because we brought the kids with us and so with the other two running around the room….that was a huge distraction…………..that I think perhaps…………they tread a fine line……..should they ring you up and make an appointment …..and start you worrying from that second?………..if she ever asked my opinion, I would suggest that if she dealt with couples in that circumstance again that she maybe do it differently. Danielle

While it is improbable that any person could ever be fully prepared for all

eventualities, as the sole purpose of prenatal screening is to uncover problems, it is

predictable that problems will be found in some cases. Therefore, this possibility

should be pre-figured in women’s minds prior to testing, to foster some awareness

that may lay the groundwork of preparedness for those who experience an

unwelcome result. The question of whether the poor preparedness for potentially

bad news intensifies the trauma experienced when the unwanted and unexpected

‘bad’ result does eventuate is not the focus of this study. However, given that robust

informed consent has been frequently associated with enhanced patient acceptance

of good and bad outcomes, more research is warranted in this area of antenatal care.

Overt and Covert Counselling

While the nature of patient/doctor, or patient/counsellor, interaction in prenatal

screening is often idealised as being non coercive, non-directive, and respectful of

the patient’s free choice (Anderson, 1999; Fineman & Walton, 2000; Williams,

Alderson, & Farsides, 2002b), the potential to exert influence in medical decision 60 Aspects of learning, including factors which impinge on attention, will be more fully discussed in Chapter 8.

Page 172: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

172

making is widely recognised by health professionals who acknowledge the

difficulties in maintaining a neutral, unbiased approach (Williams, Alderson, &

Farsides, 2002a, 2002d). For many women the mere offer of a test will be viewed as

a tacit recommendation (Press & Browner, 1997; Williams et al., 2002c), while the

presentation of a diagnosis predefined as undesirable (Kenen, 1999), and couched in

the negative language of burden and risk, may encode a subtle inference about the

(un)desirability of the child in question. Coupled with routinisation, clear directives

about expected behaviour are felt by women. Indeed, nearly 70% obstetricians

interviewed in Marteau’s 1994 study admitted to directively counselling couples to

terminate affected foetuses (Marteau, 1994 cited by Shakespeare, 1998, p.668)

reflecting deeply entrenched social and institutional biases, biases that Hubbard

(1988, p.232) suggests create a situation in which individual women implement

society’s prejudices ‘so to speak, by choice’.

The following practitioners’ comments elucidate some of the issues associated with

trying to dispense unbiased, value-neutral advice in a non-directive way. Walking

the fine line between providing the professional advice and expertise patients

sought, while remaining cognisant and respectful of the patient’s input and wishes

proved a difficult task for some.

I try very hard to be non-directive ….I do……..I think it’s possible… Genetic Counsellor 2. I guess it’s just how you present it ………….. …with older women………here we go again presenting subjective stuff…….for you at this stage you have a higher risk but it’s up to you to decide what ‘high’ risk means to you, what risk you are willing to take…….but according to the information we have here it is worth you having the test at your age because you are at increased risk.……Midwife 3 I think if its presented to us as GP’s and we are really told pretty much that we have to offer them to patients or we are not giving patients freedom of choice, but it’s presented in such a way that ‘of course you would want this test’, and we present it that way, then we don’t really give them a true choice. General Practitioner 2 Essentially it’s as non-directive as we can make it, we give people options of further testing and tell them the available information we have, what we can exclude with certain tests, then we give them the choice…….no-one is obliged to do anything……even if we have an abnormal result…..no-one is obliged to act upon that result if they don’t want to…however, directive counselling?......it depends who the patient talks to really, some people will push a lot more for things than others…….Obstetrician.

Page 173: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

173

However, in line with Schneider’s (1996) observations, physicians also recognised

that many patients did indeed seek overt direction, coming to them for interpretation

and elucidation of the overwhelming quantity of information that is accessible from

various sources, most notably the internet. The following practitioners explained,

I don’t think it’s hard at all, in one sense it’s easy to be non-directive, but it’s not a particularly good way to go in medical practice because it’s too much like a shopping mall model, and doctors should be in the business of, not coercing people, but offering some gentle direction on some cases, or at least endorsing what they feel is the best way to proceed in that patients best interest. …..most people would agree that it’s not that difficult, but people get into habits, and may not be aware that they are being directive. General Practitioner 3 It’s not lack of information that people have a problem with these days… With the internet, there is too much information, so it’s about sifting, interpreting and understanding which is the communication process that takes place in the clinical consultation. So….. Why do people keep coming with more information? …… it’s because they need assistance in understanding and interpreting, so I try not to give too much and expect them to take it all away and read it all and act upon it. Clinical Geneticist [Is non-directiveness a valuable aim?] No,…..no,….well…….I don’t think it is because I think the internet is non-directive counselling, …………and I think people come to us for information, but they also come to us for our professional advice…so while I don’t think that we should tell people what they should do…….and that’s what used to happen…..although in previous generation that’s what some people wanted too…but no…. I think people come more for advice….they do have to make their own decision but they do want an opinion from you. And I guess………..the other thing with non-directive counselling is…….to be totally non-directive you wouldn’t even bring up the fact that there was a test because that’s being directive in itself by offering it ……..we’ve already…...pre-empted it…. ….but I think to be totally non-directive you just end up giving people this whole lot of information and they’re just going to say, ‘well I don’t understand that’ ….because I think they can’t necessarily think through all that unless perhaps they know someone who has been through it. So, I don’t think that [non- directiveness] is what people want from us to be honest………General Practitioner 2

While advice may be sought by mothers, problems arose for some when they chose

to reject it, as Danielle did when she decided not to accept the offer of amniocentesis

after soft markers were identified on ultrasound.

Well the doctors at the hospital almost worded it like I was being a petulant mother, the way mothers talk to petulant children……well, that’s the decision you’ve made, and we respect your decision, but you know that’s a choice that you’ve made now and you have to live with that….it’s like we’ve given you this option and you’ve decided not to take it………so it was like I had to say “yes I HAVE decided not to take that option”……they didn’t actually say the words ‘its all your problem now sweetheart” , but that was the attitude. Danielle.

Page 174: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

174

As the mother of a child with Down syndrome, Elizabeth too encountered blatant

presumptions about what her expected course of action should be during her

subsequent pregnancy. She explains

I was 34 with Rebecca when I first went to the GP, and said I was pregnant again, I had Grace with me, and they had written a few notes down, and I said Grace had a heart defect and she was born with Down syndrome. He immediately started telling me I would be referred for a fetal cardiac scan, he said “I want this test, and we need to do a blood test”, and I said, ‘no I’m happy not to have that, they’re not that accurate and I don’t want it. I said to him, we knew about Grace before she was born, so that negates all that discussion, He basically just looked at me and said, ‘well I suppose you know what you are doing then’. Elizabeth

Having rejected the offer of a nuchal screen, Elizabeth was further confronted with

the persistent presumption of the sonographer, When I had the 12 week scan, the lady asked was I having a nuchal fold scan, we had Grace with us, and I said “no, I’m not interested”. But she went and had a look anyway and said, “It looks OK”. I was shocked, because I thought; you didn’t have my permission to do that. That’s not acceptable, but I decided not to make a scene. Elizabeth

For Penny and her husband, the directive and adversarial nature of their encounter,

and the pressure they sensed when deciding to decline the offer of further testing

caused distress and anger, They said ‘well, really you have to have an amnio’, and Stuart and I had talked about that previously and we had had a miscarriage three years earlier, and were told that our chances of falling pregnant again because of other issues between us were very low, so we said, even if there is a problem, we wouldn’t do anything about it…..So we’re sitting there looking at each other , thinking we’re not going to do anything about it and they’re sitting looking at us saying, “Well, you really should have the amnio and that will tell you more definitively if there’s a problem” . And it was like we really had to stand our ground, to say no….. We’ve already thought about this ….and we don’t want it… [Later in the interview]……….I think it just meant that for us we just tended to dig our heels in …..rather than be pressured…..it wasn’t that we had more questions, we just said no…..no discussion…no matter what you say….we didn’t need more education or information at that stage, we just said no…… we’re not doing it…. We both just really stuck by that original reaction…but we were more angry at the sonographer and doctor pressuring us…that we were somehow making the wrong decision and weren’t complying with what they thought the ‘right’ decision was…that made us more angry …..So we never really revisited whether we should have had the amnio………they did mention that they could put us in touch with a geneticist…..And when we refused to have the test they still offered us the opportunity to speak to a geneticist, so almost, it was like - they will convince you that you need to have an amnio, but in a very pleasant way…. They were saying well, you need to talk to a geneticist, and we said well, we’re not going to do anything, so what difference does it make? And we refused to do that as well. Penny

Like the women in Stapleton’s (2002) study, many of the mothers in this cohort

rarely asked questions in deference to their doctor’s superior knowledge and obvious

time constraints, while hierarchal power structures within the medical administration

Page 175: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

175

were found to influence the array of options presented (Anderson, 1999; Bernhardt

et al., 1998; Stapleton et al., 2002; Williams et al., 2002c). In investigating this

concern Bernhardt et al (1998) found that most women she surveyed (75%) felt ‘the

right amount’ of time had been devoted to dialogue concerning the purpose and

nature of testing (Bernhardt et al., 1998), although most conversations focused only

on the physical and administrative practicalities of the test. The possible outcome of

termination or descriptions of the disorders being screened for occurred in a

minority of cases while debate of any emotional, social or ethical aspects of

screening were neglected (Bernhardt et al., 1998; Press & Browner, 1993;

Santhalahti, 1999). The failure to regard these ‘non technical’ issues as worthy of

discussion may further undermine their relevance, sending a cue about their

perceived worth that may indirectly silence ethical discussion. This further

highlights the problem with a process in which the information that is deemed to be

ethically relevant is determined by others, often without consultation or regard for

individual patient values. However, it is important to note that practitioners too are

subject to overt directives, directives that shape the normative pathways that are

ultimately laid out for women. One general practitioner explained:

They held an information session for GP’s on a range of antenatal issues and obviously that was one, part of it was to do a big plug for the new screening….it was certainly presented with a great deal of excitement and ……you know , they were very pleased to have it (nuchal translucency) available and really, certainly from the fellow who had set it up ( at the hospital), he really expected that everyone would want the test and we needed to tell everyone that it was available. General Practitioner 2

In the face of these powerful professional expectations, which are often couched in

the language of legal obligation, acknowledging the overt and covert pressure on

practitioners to promote screening forms an important part of the dynamic observed.

Legal Frameworks: Practice and Policy Consequences

A further institutional consideration shaping technology use and directing ‘choice’

with regard to what testing is offered and why, is the legal framework under which

health care institutions operate. While there may be nothing legally contentious

about a woman giving her informed consent to have her foetus screened prenatally,

should she choose to undergo a termination in response to what those tests reveal,

Page 176: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

176

her actions, and those of her doctors’ fall under the Criminal Code in Queensland.

While termination of pregnancy is unlawful in most states of Australia, lawful

‘therapeutic’ termination can be procured on the grounds of threats to the physical or

psychological health of the mother60F

61. The presumption that a disability in the foetus

is automatically grounds for psychological distress in the mother is firmly

entrenched in clinical practice and in various state laws within Australia. However,

the nature or severity of any foetal anomaly rarely demands justification, and

termination is essentially freely available in all states including Queensland.

As there is no evidentiary requirement to substantiate any claim of psychological

distress, termination of a 20 week foetus with a cleft palate, or a 32 week foetus with

suspected achondroplasia 61F

62 (de Crispegny & Savulescu, 2004) is legally defensible

on the grounds that it creates emotional anguish in the mother. Through focusing on

the mental distress the presence of a disability may create in the mother, the law puts

women in the unenviable situation where they must build a legal case for

termination, based on their own mental fragility. The compounding affront of having

conceived a substandard child, followed by the necessity to build a legal case for

termination based on one’s own mental incapacity inhumanely places mothers at the

epicentre of this series of accumulating ‘failures’. This situation also places

practitioners in the unenviable position of procuring treatment in their patients’

interests while potentially placing themselves in breach of the law, a law which

increasingly is out of alignment with actual practice.

Further studies suggest that fear of potential litigation rather than genuine patient

need may be contributing to strong recommendations to screen given by many

doctors (Manson, 2007; Anderson, 1999; Press & Browner, 1997; Stapleton et al.,

2002; Williams et al., 2002b), and may represent a form of reassurance sought by

medical staff, mindful of avoiding possible lawsuits (Williams et al., 2002c) .

Indeed, the ‘legal grey area of malpractice for not offering tests’ has been identified

as a factor in the increasing numbers of women being offered the MSAFP blood test

in Canada (Press & Browner, 1997, p.980). With fear of litigation looming, a

61 Under Section 282 of the Criminal Code of Queensland. 62 This termination occurred in Melbourne, Victoria in 2000, and is discussed in an article by de Crispegny and Savulescu, 2004.

Page 177: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

177

mutually reinforcing bond of dependence between specialist and patient is fostered

which may effectively stifle full participation of the patient in moral decision

making.

In line with the claims made above, many practitioners in this cohort identified the

professional legal consequences of not testing as a motivating factor in the

increasing number of scans both devised and offered as evidenced by the following

comments, I feel….and I think probably the medical defence people would probably say the same; I am negligent if I don’t offer them the test. General Practitioner 2 [E: How much of the pressure to test is driven by the defensive legal position?] That’s 100%...yes…..yes….it is …it is….I think you’ll find more and more the defensive legal side weighs very heavily…..because if the doctor doesn’t offer, then they may be held accountable ………….many, many doctors are sued for that…for not offering…..there’s a lot of defensive medicine happening………..it’s sad to see that it’s gone down that path……….even the Caesar rate, they just jump in and do it at the drop of a hat …once upon a time they would give the woman the benefit of the doubt….it’s all defensive medicine now……….Midwife 1

Finally, this comment from an obstetrician identified wrongful birth lawsuits as the

issue at the heart of the medico-legal drive to screen.

Well, there’s two ways to look at that, there’s the medico-legal …..where…..pretty much…it only takes one or two lawsuits where people say they weren’t offered an amniocentesis when they should have been and they had a baby with Downs, and even although wrongful birth is something that you can’t really sue for, you can in fact sue for it in a way, so there’s definitely medico-legal pressure on GP’s and obstetricians to offer these things. Obstetrician

Perhaps, however, this is an overstated fear. The reality in Australia is that wrongful

life actions have been to date unsuccessful. However, the laws governing

discrimination, wrongful life, and termination, present conflicting messages about

disability, possibly fuelling the confusion and uncertainty practitioners feel.

Recently, two wrongful life claims were rejected in the High Court of Australia on

the grounds that there was no substantive evidence that life with a disability was

worse than the alternative of non-existence62F

63. Such rulings illustrate the paradoxical

nature of laws that reject wrongful life on the grounds that life with disability cannot

be proven to be worse than non-existence while supporting the terminations of

63 Harriton v Stephens. 2006 High Court of Australia 15; 9th May 2006; Waller v James; Waller v Hoolahan. 2006 High Court of Australia 16; 9th May 2006

Page 178: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

178

foetuses with (sometimes minor or no63F

64) disabilities, including the termination of a

32 week foetus with ‘suspected’ achondroplasia, as mentioned earlier (de Crispegny

& Savulescu, 2004).

A common theme of legal frameworks adopted in many Western countries is that

the foetus has no legal status. The trigger for recognising personal rights in law is

birth. If a foetus is never born it has no rights and cannot be discriminated against,

hence, the prevailing rights are those of the mother. Recent law reform in

Queensland relating to intentional harm of an unborn child adds a further layer of

complexity, conflict and possibly confusion for practitioners. Under this

legislation64F

65, if an assault on a woman prevents the live birth of a child she is

carrying, the perpetrator may receive life imprisonment for the intentional harm of

an unborn child. While these laws governing termination are legally consistent in

holding the foetus as a ‘non-person’ and preserving the individual rights of the

mother, there are real moral inconsistencies in recognising on the one hand that the

killing of an unborn child may constitute harm, while condoning on the other hand

the termination of a 32 week foetus on the grounds of maternal psychological

distress.

The continued placement of termination under the Criminal Code places emphasis

on cementing a defensive legal justification as opposed to one of exploring the

social, moral, and human consequences, without fear of prosecution. Often, the

secrecy that flows from such a defensive legal stance, coupled with privatisation and

individuation it promotes, inhibits open reflection as many of these decisions

become concealed from the public discourse. Practical consequences in policy and

care protocols are seen institutionally, a notable example being the failure to flag the

offer of termination on the Queensland Health Consent to Amniocentesis form65F

66. As

termination rates after an unwelcome diagnosis generally remain above 90% 66F

67, the

prospect of termination is not a remote possibility. However, in response to the

64 While termination remains illegal in most states, ‘over 95% of terminations before 15 weeks are for social reason in which the foetus is normal’ (Aldred et al., 2003, p.337). 65 Section 313 of the Criminal Code of Queensland. 66See http://www.health.qld.gov.au/informedconsent/ConsentForms/obgyn/O&G_01.pdf (Accessed 7th Februrary, 2008). 67 Carothers et al., 1999; J. Egan & A. Borgida, 2002; Erikson, 2001; Ford, 1999; Garne, 2001; Santhalahti, 1999 .

Page 179: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

179

question of why termination is not flagged as a potential sequel of amniocentesis

this GP explained. Well, that’s because it can’t………….because it’s still a felony…..it does in Victoria and Western Australia, the simple answer is that you can’t refer to something that is illegal, unfortunately we don’t have a Menhennit or Levine67F

68 ruling in this state which is the ability to avoid ………in absolute terms – prosecution….so the amniocentesis consent does draw attention to the fact that there is maternal and foetal risk… but I don’t think that that’s inappropriate……General Practitioner 1

Similarly, one genetic counsellor saw no ethical omission explaining,

I don’t think that it’s an omission because that should have been a prior discussion, as to why is someone having the amnio- it’s a risk procedure….and that the expectation is that should an adverse finding such as a chromosomal abnormality be found, it was for the couple to decide. I don’t think it’s sufficient to have an amnio to learn whether or not the baby has a condition so that you can prepare yourself with that information. E: So you don’t think it’s an omission not to flag termination as a possible outcome on that on the form? No……….. E: Do you think it’s appropriate to assume adequate discussion has taken place prior? Yes… I think it’s too late to have it on the form…it should be done before the decision to have the amnio……..what is the purpose of the amnio for you? E: Do you think for some women if that discussion hadn’t taken place, a written re-enforcement of the possibility of termination could be an extra safety net? No……because why would someone seek an amnio…or information….what was she going to do with that information?

While these practitioners were clearly comfortable with omitting the likelihood of an

offer of termination, another general practitioner felt less at ease:

[E: The Qld Health consent to amniocentesis form doesn’t mention termination as a possible outcome. Do you have any thoughts on that from an informed consent perspective?] I do actually…….I think that’s very bad because ….. the impression that I get is that most doctors that they then talk to, saying they have baby with Down syndrome, would just expect that that’s what they would want do …….we do this test, we get a result and this is how we treat it and make it go away……there’s seems to be unfortunately more and more of that expectation……..when I read the medical newspapers and even articles on pregnancy

68 Common law decisions that most impact in Australia are R v Davidson (1969) VR 667 by Menhenitt J (Supreme Court) and R v Wald (1971) 3, NSW DCR 25 by Levine J (District Court). These cases established that an abortion could be legally performed if the pregnancy would have a detrimental effect on the mother’s mental and physical well-being. The Menhenitt ruling established that both mental and physical health risks are grounds for a lawful termination. (See http://www.childrenbychoice.org.au/ndownloads/CbyCSubtoTaskforce.doc, p.10 – Accessed 5th October, 2007).

Page 180: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

180

screening I think that seems to be the general trend… I think particularly where termination is the expectation they will be hit with afterwards, they need to have that thought put in their heads beforehand that this will be brought up. I think a lot of people are just getting tests done without thinking it through to the next stage….to not bring up the possibility of termination is not good……..there’s a lot of things other than Down syndrome that get picked up though amniocentesis, I mean even the ultrasound that they do beforehand will often find babies that may not survive, so there’s lots of other things that can be picked up there……I think they need to have that in their mind before the test. General Practitioner 2.

Finally, as the law in Queensland, which regards termination as criminal, and the

practical access to termination, which is essentially unrestricted, are out of step, the

continuing positioning of termination under the Criminal Code has effectively acted

as a barrier to open information flow, creating a situation in which patients and

practitioners must quietly collude. If the purpose of placing termination under the

criminal code was to decrease the number of terminations, there is, as yet, no

evidence to suggest that current legislation in Queensland facilitates this outcome.

On the contrary, the two states in Australia, Western Australia and South Australia

that have removed termination from the criminal statutes report similar or

marginally lower termination rates than Australia generally68F

69 (Straton, Godman,

Gee, & Hu, 2006, p.15). When practice and the law operate out of synchronisation

with each other, further consequences such as lack of adequate data collection, under

resourcing of counselling services and incomplete consent protocols follow,

outcomes which will be further discussed in Chapter Nine.

Chapter Summary

Numerous institutional factors act to constrain the realisation of informed consent in

practice. These factors include the routinisation of screening which blurs the

voluntary nature of participation and may bypass the ethically critical informing

process. In this cohort some practitioners welcomed routinisation and were sceptical

about the extent to which this minimised or obfuscated voluntariness; yet, many

mothers were unaware of their option to opt out. However, the potentially fracturing

69 WA reports 18.2 terminations per 1000 pregnancies compared to 16.7 per 1000 in SA, and an overall estimated figure of 19.7 per 1000 pregnancies within Australia (Grayson, Hargreaves , & Sullivan, 2005, p.xv). Perhaps reflecting the disjoined and incomplete way that data is collected in Queensland, and the lack of mandatory reporting the estimated per capita figures are contradictory, reported as between 15.4 and 17.0 (Grayson et al., 2005, p.32) . The reality is, however, that as no mandatory reporting requirements exist, the numbers and reasons for termination in Queensland and other states remain impossible to quantify accurately (Pratt, Biggs, & Buckmaster, 2004).

Page 181: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

181

experience of diagnosing disability in a foetus with the potential view to terminate a

pregnancy evokes deep ethical questions. Ultimately these questions must warrant

fuller consideration than those afforded by under-informed and routine practice.

While the goal of non- directive counselling is professionally valued by many

practitioners, the presence of overt and covert counselling was strongly present in

the mother stories, reflecting a normative pathway of intervention, prefigured by the

presumption of participation. A potentially significant finding highlighted by the

accounts offered in this research, and possibly particular to Queensland, is the

blurred accountability for informing as a consequence of the variety of practitioners

that manage each pregnancy. Barriers to communication included practitioner desire

to shield patients from worrisome, but potentially remote, outcomes, while for

patients, their uncritical and unquestioning acceptance perhaps stifled the necessary

dialogue. Additional institutional pressures identified through the participant stories

were those of limited time, limited resources, and the ominous legal threat that

drives the practice of defensive medicine.

The following chapter will consider the social constraints to achieving informed

consent.

Page 182: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

182

CHAPTER 7

VOICES IN CONTEXT:

SOCIAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction

Social factors constraining the realisation of informed consent in practice include the

socially constructed, though often unrealised, expectations of enhanced choice,

societal reverence towards science and technology, feelings of blame and culpability

experienced by women and practitioners on the birth of a disabled child, the social

construction of disability as tragedy, and the acceptance of socially sanctioned cost

benefit analysis of screening that promotes the practice as financially responsible.

Each of these factors will be considered in more depth.

The Social Construction of Choice

The belief that prenatal screening automatically enhances reproductive choices by

providing improved knowledge about the foetus, thus enabling more informed

decision-making (Baird, 1999; Cuckle, 2001; Savulescu, 2005), seems actively

embraced by many parents and doctors alike as unproblematic, or even ‘responsible

pregnant behaviour’ (Lippman, 1991, p. 28). While such screening is predominantly

regarded as a technical or medical event, the background considerations directing

our ongoing communal commitment of resources, time, expertise, and funding into

supporting widespread screening programs are fundamentally driven by latent social

determinants. The questions of why the detection and potential elimination of

disability are culturally valued and endorsed are essentially social in nature.

Similarly, the type of prenatal screening practices developed and the increasing

frequency of their use equally reflect entrenched social values as much as they are

evidence of advancing technical capabilities. As it is these often veiled social

attitudes and norms that extensively dictate which choices come to be offered and

sanctioned, exposing these underlying presumptions is valuable in forming an

Page 183: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

183

ethical appreciation and response to the widespread acceptance and expansion of

prenatal screening regimes.

The high elective termination rates of 85%-98% for foetuses prenatally diagnosed

with some type of physical, chromosomal, or genetic anomaly reflect a strong trend

towards the abortion of affected foetuses (Carothers et al., 1999; Egan & Borgida,

2002; Erikson, 2001; Ford, 1999; Garne, 2001; Santhalahti, 1999), figures which

have been uncritically presented as strong evidence of choice enhancement (Cuckle,

2001). For parents who have been afforded the additional choice to avert the live

birth of a child with a disability, this appears to be the case. However, these same

figures sit uncomfortably with others who interpret them as evidence of narrowed

options and limited choices representing a lack of perceived alternatives in response

to a diagnosis predefined as undesirable (Kenen, 1999; Parens & Asch, 2000;

Shakespeare, 1998), as Regina Kenen notes,

‘Once a pregnant woman is presented with a category of conditions pre-

defined as a defect, the social context narrows her perceived options’

(Kenen, 1999, para 9).

Progress in the field of genetics has further stretched the boundaries and

expectations of ‘choice’, with some academics arguing that if we have the means to

gain genetic health information about our children, we have a ‘parental and moral

obligation’ to acquire it (Clarkeburn, 2000, p.1; Green 1997; Savulescu, 2001,

2005). However, once such knowledge is known, it cannot be unknown, perhaps

creating an impetus to act. Clarkeburn (ibid, p.2) clarifies her interpretation of this

parental obligation:

‘The duty to acquire information about the genetic constitution of the foetus

must be connected with the duty to act upon that information …… In the case

of untreatable and non-preventable genetic defects, the only possible

benefiting action is termination’

Broader (and perhaps more pertinent) questions of who determines the grey areas of

‘non-preventable’, or at what level the ‘untreatable’ becomes ‘unacceptable’ often

Page 184: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

184

remain curiously unarticulated in such accounts69F

70. These considerations are further

complicated by the considerable lack of agreement within the medical literature on

the definition of what constitutes a disability. Obesity, low intelligence, criminality,

predisposition to cancer or lack of athleticism (Duster, 2003; Rothblatt, 1997) are all

traits with a genetic component that could be considered debilitating by some, but

may not be considered reasonable grounds on which to terminate a foetus or reject

an embryo. The seemingly trivial example of non life threatening genetic dental

conditions cited by Aldred et al (2003) flags such an example. Attention to these

largely cosmetic and fixable conditions may seem like a misplaced vanity in light of

the more contentious eugenic implications of prenatal diagnosis, however, Aldred

(ibid) and his colleagues advocate open access to Pre-implantation Genetic

Diagnosis (PGD) for such conditions, which may cause intense psychological

suffering and social exclusion, concluding with the justification that ‘if a couple will

only have a finite number of children, it might be considered rational for that couple

to choose to have children who start life with the best genetic prospects’ (Aldred et

al., 2003, p.337).

While Aldred and his colleagues present the idea of ‘best genetic prospects’

unproblematically, as though there were some shared understanding of what this

means, adopting such malleable and manipulable definitions of disability further

obscures the criteria for use of prenatal diagnostic technologies, particularly in a

biomedical and social context in which individual choice is seen as valuable, and

medical consumerism can shape the wider community agenda. Not only can we

regulate when and how many children we have, we may now expect to control or

choose the type of child, an expectation endorsed by Leanne who explained,

If I’m going to bring up a child for the next 20 years I’ve got a small amount of control and choice what condition its got……so I just can utilise that [technology]…[later in the interview]…but that (Down syndrome) was one thing I could eliminate after all the things you worry about when you’re pregnant , did I drink too much in the beginning, could it be born with a funny heart…. well at least I know he doesn’t have that… he doesn’t have Downs. Leanne

70 Similar interpretations are offered by others such as Helga Kuhse, Peter Singer and Julian Savulescu – who likewise tackle the relativistic nature of assigning definitions of severe or unacceptable disabling conditions with remote, decontextualised or intellectual justifications.

Page 185: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

185

As demonstrated earlier, for many of the mothers in this cohort the choice to screen

was initially exercised as the unquestioning and trusting acceptance of the routine

pathway, reinforcing Lippmann’s description (1999) of a pathway clearly paved

long before many realize they are on it. While the notion of individual choice is

culturally valued, and the terms ‘choice’ and ‘autonomy’ are liberally scattered

through the medical discourse relating to prenatal screening (and other forms of

medical intervention), in reality, a person’s ability to exercise truly autonomous

choice is restricted, made for many under non – negotiable constraints. Situated in a

web of entrenched social and institutional cultures, frameworks, practices and

presumptions of which the person themselves may not even be aware, the exercising

of choice is more accurately one of choices from those choices made available, as

Anne describes,

From my experience I haven’t always been made aware of my choices. It makes me angry a bit because I wonder what other areas of the medical procedures, in terms of being pregnant and having a child are we not given a choice about where we actually do have choice. It raises a whole bunch of questions about other things we should have a choice about. Anne

A view further echoed by one GP who noted,

We’re putting them on an escalator, really we’re putting them on at the bottom and they have to follow it to the top…..I don’t believe its ‘voluntary’. We might say well, they don’t have to go on and have the amnio, then having that they don’t have to go on and have a termination, but once you’re there in that emotional response, you’re often in a position of no choice, because your alternative is to go through the whole pregnancy terrified, just terrified and I’ve seen people do that. General Practitioner 2

The largely predetermined nature of choice was further evidenced in Mary’s account

of testing for her third pregnancy after a traumatic and tumultuous experience of

false positive in her second pregnancy 12 months earlier. On being advised to have

another nuchal translucency and blood test, Mary expressed reservations to her

doctor. She relayed the conversation,

I said…‘Do I really have to?’…….because I’d seen the same obstetrician for all my (three) pregnancies he said “Well, we need to because of what happened last time….just to rule anything out” so I went with bated breath. [E: Did you feel that you had choice in that?] No …no……...not really………..no……… I felt like it was “You’ve got to go and do this”…Mary

Page 186: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

186

In spite of Mary’s ‘harrowing’ experience during her second pregnancy, she

maintained faith in screening and in her physician, her closing comments suggesting

that her perceived lack of choice was not the critical source of her distress. Rather it

was her lack of understanding about the potential outcomes and options that

compounded her distress and bewilderment.

Yes…[screening] definitely does [enhance choice]…………..but I think there needs to be more education about what can happen once you get the result back……………..because I had no idea……………and there was no-one for me to talk to …so yeah…..I did choose …I guess I had a choice with every test I had done….and because I trusted what I was told…I went ahead with it…..so yes and no…I had a choice not to but…….I didn’t at the same time. Mary

Considering the potential, risks of screening such as false positive results from

ultrasounds and blood tests, potential miscarriage from amniocentesis and CVS,

psychological distress (Goel et al., 1998; Kowalcek et al., 2002; Liamputtong &

Watson, 2002; Watson et al., 2003) and lack of decisive outcomes for many, the

reasons why women participate in prenatal testing in such high numbers are

complex and multifaceted. Certainly, routinisation and overt expectations to

conform partially explain the high uptake rates while the presumption of enhanced

reproductive choice may be a motivating factor for some women. However, as

pregnancy progresses naturally for around 97% of women (Baird, 1999; Ford, 1999)

resulting in the birth of a healthy baby with no complication or intervention, the

reality of enhanced choice to either terminate or gather additional knowledge prior

to the birth of a child applies only to the remaining 3%. Tom Shakespeare

comments (2005, p.221),

‘Approximately one in twelve adults is disabled. However, only about 1% or

2% of births are affected by disability: most people become disabled through

disease or accident in later life, particularly in old age. Disability is a

normal fact of life’.

This observation is further reinforced by Baird (1999, p.9) who claims that ‘most

neonatal disabilities result from ‘low birth weight, prematurity, viral or bacterial

infection, birth trauma or accident’ none of which can be predicted by prenatal

screening. However, rather than accepting the reality that disability is indeed a

Page 187: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

187

normal fact of life, our commitments are channelled into directing extensive

medical expertise and financial resources into identifying this 1%-3% with the

normative outcome of termination. This socially endorsed stance thus reflects, and

perpetuates, an interpretation of disability as so universally unacceptable and

undesirable that the extensive investment channelled into its ‘prevention’ is

unquestionably warranted.

One genetic counsellor explained that, while prenatal screening was not failsafe,

‘consumers’ 70F

71 definitely wanted ‘certainty and desirability…in their offspring’,

continuing to explain, ‘I think people want a healthy baby…because I personally

would’. On the other hand, the obstetrician saw prenatal screening as a simple

extension to tests that could be performed after birth noting,

There are lots of different reasons to chose to have those tests available….because those tests are just an expansion of tests that can be done after a child is born……..I think they offer people choices and they are there because people want those choices … so I don’t think its presence is a judgement statement, it’s simply a way of providing the options that some people want to have …. Obstetrician

The high elective termination rates observed suggests that many people expect, and

are entitled to have, the choice of termination. However, the critical difference, not

articulated in the discourse of choice that surrounds the prenatal testing

conversation, is that it remains unlawful to euthanize a child when diagnosis of a

disabling condition occurs after birth. Thus the imperative to detect any conditions

prior to birth, to prevent the ‘tragedy’ of disability, is created71F

72. Further research

reveals that the period immediately after receiving an unwelcome diagnosis is

frequently characterised by a sense of urgency and impetus to act which further

channels choice (Helm, Miranda, & Ched, 1998), while Shakespeare (1999, p. 30)

concludes in his critique of the rhetoric of choice that,

71 Some (not all) practitioners used business language, describing their patients as ‘clients’ or ‘consumers’. The production models of health care that such language portrays is not the specific focus of this research, however, it prefigures a relationship between the patient and health carer as one of contractual obligation, as opposed to a more appropriate one of covenant and care as advocated by Eric Mount (Mount, 1990). 72 Utilitarian thinkers such as Helga Kuhse, Peter Singer and others see no moral problem in euthanizing handicapped infants after birth, arguing that the trip down the birth canal is not morally significant, thus advocating that the choice to ‘terminate’ be extended into life (see Kuhse & Singer, 1985 for example).

Page 188: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

188

‘The evidence undermines this rhetoric of free choice………… in hundreds of

small ways the choice is unfree and the dice are loaded against the birth of

disabled children’.

Within these complex subjective and intersubjective webs of relationships and

perceptions, individual choice is rarely simple and may seem illusory and mocking

to some (Bridle, 2004, p.92).

Trust in the Medical System, Science and Technology

Leon Kass (2002, p.33) defines technology as follows,

‘Technology, in its full meaning, is the disposition rationally to order and

predict and control everything feasible in order to master fortune,

spontaneity, violence and wildness, and leave nothing to chance, all for

human benefit’.

When the goals of technology are considered in this light, to reject the promised

benefits to humankind could be interpreted as retrograde, illogical and

counterintuitive. Hence, a further consideration influencing ‘autonomous’ decision-

making is faith and trust in the medical system, science and technology, with

technology being identified as delivering solutions to problems while perpetuating

the myth of invulnerability (Frank, 1995, p.135). As such technology use in

pregnancy care has been viewed as a valuable tool, almost a form of insurance

towards producing a healthy child (Kenen, 1996). Lippmann goes further,

suggesting that once offered, technology is craved, and hence the ‘need’ to apply it

is securely constructed and ingrained (Lippman, 1991). To understand the context in

which these events occur we must examine the seductive power of science on which

medicine is based (Noble, 1999), and acknowledge its prestigious position in

Western society.

Science, Chris Newell writes, is paradoxically constructed as simultaneously ‘value

neutral yet inherently good’ (Newell, 2007, p.66), a stance which fulfils the

culturally revered pursuit of objective truth, while also providing the vehicle to

deliver on the promise ‘to purify the human species of its physical frailties’ (Noble,

Page 189: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

189

1999, p.172). Noble’s (ibid) commentary, positions science as a messianic, salvific,

quasi-religious force whose mission is to restore the human species ‘to its original

perfection’, and re-establish human dominion over the earth. In daily clinical terms,

however, the immediate embrace of technology is more expedient and practical

although arguably underpinned by hope in the visions of deliverance articulated by

Noble (ibid). The prized notion of an authoritative, unbiased, and objective solution

that is readily revealed by the application of a simple test is clearly very appealing as

it reduces the need to consider the more complex and unpredictable human

dimensions of a problem. Furthermore, by removing deliberations from the moral to

the technical domain, the questions that become admissible for consideration under

the scientific paradigm change, being shaped to reflect those for which technology

may provide an answer. Consequently medical care is increasingly driven by what

parameters technology can measure, although not necessarily what patients want to

know (Sherwin, 1992). Kass (2002, p.36) further explains,

‘Science becomes not the representation and demonstration of truth, but an

art: the art of finding the truth – or, rather, that portion of the truth that

lends itself to being artfully found’.

Lindemann-Nelson (2001, p.128) makes further reference to the technologically

defined ‘clinically correct story’ noting,

‘the clinically correct story is a narrative of passing because it first

represents the person as pathologically abnormal, then offers to repair the

pathology’.

While Hilde Lindemann–Nelson’s (ibid) comments above were made in relation to

the gender re-assignment of adult transsexuals, the ‘clinically correct story’ may

equally apply in the context of prenatal screening which represents certain foetuses

as ‘pathologically abnormal’ then offers to ‘repair’ nature’s mistake through

‘medically indicated’ termination. The authoritative standing and relevance of

technology is thus perpetuated.

Page 190: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

190

The scientific discourse of medicine has of necessity become expert and removed.

However, the consequence of this segregation has been that non-expert (patient)

contributions may have become undermined, leaving many women feeling

uncomfortable and underqualified to participate in such complex technical

deliberations. The scientific orientation of medicine, Sherwin (1992) argues, has

created a distance between itself and those it practices upon entrenching paternalistic

processes with their inherent reluctance to share power. How would an ‘unqualified’

woman who rejects (or even questions) culturally revered technologies be regarded

within a context where technology is presented as progressive, desirable and

infallible? In this context, questioning the substance of scientific expertise and

authority would simply not be an option for many. It is this potential for exclusion

that Lippmann (1999a) suggests has encouraged some women to adopt overtly

medicalised language to describe their own experiences noting, ‘women may sense

that the more they speak the biomedical story (e.g., quote risk figures; go for genetic

counselling), the more they will be recognized as rational, intelligent decision

makers’ (Lippman 1999a, p.270). This strategy was chosen by Elizabeth who

couched her refusal to screen in the medicalised language of risk factors,

inaccuracies and false positives, a language she felt engendered more respect from

practitioners,

The reaction of the medical staff is such that if they can tell you’ve read up and you know what you’re talking about, then they give you more respect and more consultation, rather than being spoken down to , I’m not saying I know all the medical terminology, but at least I get spoken to like an equal. But I feel that they should give me all my options, not make assumptions for me, and I have a brain, treat me as such, this is my child, I’m the expert in that. I find that using their language, they give you more respect. Elizabeth

This form of ‘narrative surrender’ as Art Frank (1995, pp.5-6) describes it, is one in

which the dominant story that trumps all others is the ‘medical narrative’. He

explains ‘the ill person72F

73 not only agrees to follow physical regimens that are

prescribed; she also agrees tacitly but with no less implication to tell her story in

medical terms’. Thus the authoritative cultural imperialism that scientific pursuits

hold becomes entrenched (Lindemann-Nelson, 2001). Where the biotechnology

revolution is presented as progressive, scientific and rational, to stand in question is

to be cast appositionally, as potentially retrogressive, biased, or irrational. Hence, a 73 Or in the case of prenatal screening, the mother of the potentially ill child.

Page 191: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

191

degree of moral censoriousness surrounds our commitment to the culturally revered

pursuit of science. The potential alienation women may feel on rejecting the

presumed benefits of such technological imperialism was summarised by Anne who

declined an offer of amniocentesis. She explains,

I felt misunderstood; I felt that they couldn’t understand why I didn’t want screening especially if there was a potential problem, almost as though I was being irresponsible. I felt that I wasn’t fitting in, that I was bucking the system………that I was almost, a tinge of being irresponsible in that, here we are, we (health care professionals) can prevent these nasty things happening to you as a parent, not considering the child, and we can make your life easier and if you let us, we can take care of this and you can lead a happy life and not have to concern yourself with a child with special needs. It was when I said I didn’t want an amniocentesis, and explained that I would have this child whether there was something wrong or not ……I felt like I wasn’t accepting their help, and they thought I needed their help … I felt they didn’t understand. Anne

Although medicalisation of pregnancy is not the focus of this particular study, this

topic featured strongly in the midwives’ reflections. Possibly demonstrating their

professional commitment to act as advocates for the women in their care, many

midwives held strong views on the unacceptable and increasing levels of

technological intervention in antenatal care.

They have to go to a professional, maybe a medical officer in order to ‘find out’ if they are pregnant, in order to diagnose that they are pregnant…it’s ludicrous…why don’t women know their own body well enough to say ‘I think I’m pregnant’ so from the very minute you know you’re pregnant, it’s medicalised…after that you have to have a scan to see if the baby is alright, or the gender of the baby……..woe betide if you bought white clothes! You’d have to know whether to have blue or pink….Midwife 4.

Women who spend a fortune using IVF to get pregnant are often so far the other way in engaging technology that they can’t think for themselves without asking what would the obstetrician do, or the gynaecologists do? Midwife 2 Well….. childbirth is highly medicalised now…..and I think too much so…….I think the natural enjoyment of pregnancy and childbirth has lost its spontaneity…………I think even the mothers who come in for a scan………they come back and say can I have a photo of my baby, I have to keep an album……………it seems to be the most important thing……..it seems they are almost reliant on technology to get through the pregnancy……..it’s almost like ……..this scan or this doctor will tell me exactly what’s happening………..this doctor is going to tell me exactly what’s going on. [E: in that sense, is technology the tool that delivers the perfect baby?] Unfortunately, some mothers think that’s so………….it’s definitely not……but I think…yes….more and more……Once upon a time there was the obstetrician and the mother, now you have the obstetrician and the subspecialty in maternal and foetal medicine…..where we have more and more doctors training in the abnormality side of pregnancy….and that seems to be the up and coming specialty these days………and so …..everything seems to be centred around scanning, Doppler’s, foetal growth and the most minor little thing becomes a major thing………..so the women wondering how much has the baby’s brain grown, is it’s brain still OK, it hasn’t put on that much weight so they go away

Page 192: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

192

and think about that, so women become conditioned to rely on that technology…. It seems to be………..seems to be…that every detail is a point to be managed…..Midwife 1

The power of medicine, and thus women’s dependency on it lies in the expert and

exclusive ability to interpret the elite and complex scientific world from the vantage

point of the ‘specialist’. Subsequently, many women, such as Anne, find that their

‘non-expert’ contribution is rejected and their confidence undermined, leaving many

feeling inadequate and underqualified to participate in such specialist deliberations.

Consequently, many women simply have to ‘trust’ that their practitioners are giving

good advice, a trust acknowledged by the obstetrician who noted: Most go in assuming everything we do has a purpose and they believe in that purpose ……and are very, very trusting. I mean you can go along and do any number of blood tests and very few people will question what you are doing. I think they express a general trust in the system to do the right thing by them….the problem is that they don’t understand the dynamics of testing. Obstetrician

Most women in this cohort, with the exception of Terri, trusted at least one of their

doctors. This was articulated by Mary, who spoke about her obstetrician with respect

and gratitude,

He’s the one who’ll make you get through this ….you have to trust their judgement at some stage….which is sometimes hard but I do trust him …he’s very good . All the others were …I don’t know…….just there doing a job….but he was the one who made everything real and put things in perspective. I didn’t listen to them… [other health professionals] …….I just went straight to the one person I knew I can trust…………I’d just ring him up and say I’ve been told this and he’s say “Oh that’s stupid, that’s crap don’t listen to that, I’ve got your results here you’re fine”. I went to the one person I knew I could trust and I had specialists bombarding me. I went straight to the one person I knew I could talk to and I knew I could trust………I was very lucky to have that. Mary

Interestingly, Mary did not reflect upon how the trauma of the false positive screen

that she needed to ‘get through’ had eventuated in the first place. During her

subsequent pregnancy just over 12 months later, Mary’s obstetrician revealed that

the previous false positive which resulted in 12 ultrasounds, an amniocentesis and

almost eight weeks of intense psychological turmoil was probably a consequence of

residual hormone levels from an earlier miscarriage, a potential explanation not

disclosed with the initial result.

Page 193: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

193

Most practitioners in this cohort were acutely aware of, and deeply humbled by, the

degree of trust placed in them by their patients, speaking respectfully about the

mantle of trust they carried.

They are looking for reputable sources of quality information that’s something they can trust, so there is need to have some sort of authority about what you speak …….. I guess that comes from being in the hospital, or position as a doctor, the fact that you’ve been referred to see this person by other specialists, so they think you must know what you’re talking about. That places you (as a specialist) in a position that provides legitimacy to what you tell them, but……. establishing that rapport is probably an important aspect of developing that trust ……….I mean …..It’s probably a very important aspect, I guess, why should they believe you? Clinical Geneticist

While trust in technology may be a motivating factor to embrace screening, lack of

trust can equally shape interpretation of results, as one genetic counsellor noted: I think they are more willing to trust it when it gives them good results…………..people who haven’t been very trustworthy of nuchal results are where the nuchal might be OK but the bloods are high, the result is a bit wishy washy…………they try to find excuses for why that results might be askew…………I’ve had morning sickness, and I’ve had some Panadol, they come up with all these different reasons why the test is wrong…….. When it’s a bad result…… Occasionally, there are cases where someone has entered the due date wrong for the bloods or maybe haven’t been thorough with the mum’s weight, and that can dramatically change the result………so when people get one result and we have to phone them with the new result………..they don’t trust us then. Genetic Counsellor 2

Demonstrating the scepticism referred to above, Penny did not trust the initial

nuchal translucency result she was given, a lack of trust that was justified when she

was later informed that poor calibration of the instrumentation used to analyse her

blood tests now meant she fell in the ‘normal’ range and there was actually no

increased cause for concern. She explains,

I was so concerned about making sure they understood about the 40 day cycle which could throw out the result, I made everyone write it down, and again at the post scan where they were saying our risk was so high, I was reiterating , have you made sure you note this long cycle was taken into account, I really didn’t trust that they had got it correct….and a couple of weeks later they rang and said……we’ve recalculated your result and it now falls in to the normal range…..and apparently the machine had not been calibrated correctly…. And I just thought, well thank goodness we didn’t go ahead and have an amnio……..at that time…. We felt pressured but we thought thank goodness we didn’t bow to that pressure…………Penny.

However, the dominant story is one of automatic trust in science, a socially

sanctioned trust in technology and medicine which significantly conditions the

acceptance of technological intervention as necessarily good.

Page 194: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

194

Responsibility and Culpability

While there may be different expectations of mothering in different social contexts,

a consistent theme is that women, more so than men, are responsible for their

children’s well being (Lindemann-Nelson, 2001, p.136; Rapp, 2000). In

commenting on mothering responsibilities during pregnancy Kathryn Pauly Morgan

(1998, p.94) remarks,

‘Women are increasingly targeted for surveillance - largely as

reproductively defined, instrumentally valuable ‘vessels’ or ‘vectors’. The

medical surveillance of pregnant women occurs not simply in the physician’s

offices but on the street, in restaurants, in public settings, and in the privacy

of familial settings when medicalised norms of ‘responsible pregnancy’ are

used judgmentally to evaluate and criticise the behaviour of pregnant women

particularly with respect to alcohol and tobacco use’.

Expectations of ‘responsible pregnant behaviour’ dictate that good mothers engage

in risk-lowering behaviours to ensure their child’s safety (Lippman, 1991, 1999a).

Such behaviours range from the innocuous abstaining from soft cheese, to the

potentially harmful forms of prenatal screening such as CVS or amniocentesis with

their attendant risk of miscarriage (ibid.). Press and Browner (1995, p.153) further

claim that women want to be seen to be behaving responsibly, hence,

‘adherence to routines of scientifically based prenatal care…is women’s

only culturally approved means of reassuring themselves and others that

they are doing “all that can be done” to ensure a healthy pregnancy’.

Markens et al’s comment that women accept screening because it is presented as

‘the medically and maternally responsible course of action’ (1999, p.362), further

recognises the societal pressures placed upon pregnant women to ensure the good

health of the next generation. More recent health trends have extended the medical

surveillance of pregnancy to ‘preconception’ and ‘internatal’ care (Lu et al., 2006),

care before and between pregnancies, further extending women’s status in medicine

as reproductive ‘vessels’ (Faden, Kass, & McGraw, 1996). The explosion of

Page 195: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

195

preconception advice and websites bears testimony to the intense level of interest,

control, and management of pregnancy73F

74, marking the expansion of the

medicalisation and regulation of the female body, an extension to the existing

intrusion and regulation that has been widely critiqued in the feminist literature.

Perceived pressure to do the socially ‘responsible’ thing loomed largely for

respondents in Helm et al’s (1998) study exploring women’s experiences in

responding to a prenatal diagnosis of Down syndrome. Feelings of immense

pressure from family and friends to terminate an affected foetus within the often-

restricted time frame between a diagnosis and the medically preferred gestational

limit for termination of 20 weeks were also noted. The perceived time pressure

limited opportunity for reflection, assimilation of information or understanding of

alternatives, all considerations that may undermine the exercising of informed

consent. As previously claimed, exercising ‘choice’ in these circumstances

incorporates more than a simple, rational decision but is clearly constrained by the

deeply related, embedded, and multifactorial contexts in which such interdependent

choices are made. Indeed, Wertz (1992, p.498) acknowledges social coercion as a

significant factor, saying ‘the problem of informal social coercion is real and must

be addressed along with problems of formal legal coercion’.

While none of the participants in this cohort raised ‘responsibility and blame’ as

significant areas of concern, researchers elsewhere have revealed that many women

identify themselves as advocates for their child’s health and therefore take

responsibility to act towards ensuring their child’s best interests (Lippman, 1999a).

As a consequence of this enduring sense of responsibility, women have often felt

culpable and blamed by society if their decision not to co-operate in prenatal

screening regimes has led to the ‘negative outcome’ of an undetected disabled child

(Marteau & Drake, 1995 , p. 1128). Hubbard (1988, p.232) further reiterates this

point saying,

74 A recent Google search of ‘preconception’ advice sites in Australia retuned over 55 000 hits, and over 1.3 million worldwide. Top of the Australian list is www.motherhood.com.au, which begins with the caption ‘Starting to work on Project Baby’.

Page 196: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

196

‘If a test is available and a pregnant woman doesn’t use it, or completes the

pregnancy although she has been told that her child will have a disability,

the child’s disability is no longer an act of fate. She is now responsible; it

has become her fault’.

However, mothers’ self-blame is only one of the many potential sources of pressure

to conform to screening regimes. In their 1995 study, Marteau and Drake elicited

responses from medical staff, pregnant women, and the general population to two

case vignettes about prenatal screening decisions. In one case, a mother rejected

prenatal screening and gave birth to a child with Down syndrome, while in the other,

no offer to screen was given and a child with Down syndrome was also born. In

assessing these fictitious cases, the respondents attributed more blame to the mother

who rejected screening, leading Marteau and Drake (1995) to conclude that the

perceived ‘preventability’ of the outcome produced higher attributions of blame to

the mother, both from medical staff and the general population.

Psychologists identify that attempts to make meaning in the face of unexpected bad

news or illness often lead to attributions of blame. If a person is deemed to be

experiencing something beyond their control, caused by external factors, research

suggests that they are more likely to be supported by medical staff and less

blamed74F

75. The attributions identified above by Marteau and Drake (1995) may

impact upon how medical staff relate to, and care for, patients if there is a perception

that patients are culpable in creating their own poor prognosis, or that they have

rejected the medically proposed ‘benefiting’ action. This is an important point when

considering the amount of support women may receive during the critical period

immediately following the diagnosis, or potential diagnosis, of a disabling condition

in their child. Danielle’s earlier assessment of her doctors attitude that ‘it’s all your

problem now sweetheart’, or Anne’s perception that she was being cast as

75 For fuller discussion and relevant psychology references see Marteau and Drake, 1995, p.1127. Attributions of blame also permeate medical discussion of more recent ethical controversies surrounding the refusal to treat patients who are smokers (Peters, Morgan, & Gluch, 2004) or the UK government recent decision to exclude obese women from access to publicly funded IVF programs (Lynch, 2007). While there are additional medical considerations when operating on smokers such as increased recovery time from surgery, and higher likelihood of complication, as Tonti –Fillipini (Tonti -Filippini, 2004) cautions, such action may be discriminatory as it may unfairly target marginalised groups in society such as the mentally ill, who are twice as likely to be smokers.

Page 197: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

197

‘irresponsible’ provide pertinent examples of the practitioner attributions of blame

that Marteau and Drake (1995) allude to.

In responding to others’ curiosity about whether blame could be apportioned,

Elizabeth, whose older daughter Grace has Down syndrome, talked about the

presumptions that others held when broaching the question of whether she ‘knew’

about Grace’s condition before birth. Lots of people ask us if we knew before Grace was born, and I just say ‘Yes’, because the next obvious comment is poor you, you’ve been saddled with this child and you didn’t know…….So being pregnant with Rebecca was interesting because some people assumed that we would want to know, it mustn’t happen again…. it makes me cross…. if I just say I knew, it shuts down the conversation. ……I remember a really good friend who was mortified that we would even consider having another child after Grace, I said to her what do you mean , and she said, ‘you know’, and I said ‘no…. why?’. Of course I knew exactly, but I wanted to make her say it. Elizabeth

Even though Elizabeth felt no blame, had been advised of her daughter’s probable

condition before birth, had firmly rejected the offer of confirmation through

amniocentesis, and vigorously defended her daughter’s worth, value and right to be

born, she was still confronted on a regular basis by others’ prejudices and

presumptions of what she ‘ought’ to have done, and the steps to prevent the travesty

of another disabled child being repeated in her subsequent pregnancy.

However, blame and responsibility did not rest with mothers alone. Blame was

keenly felt by practitioners who similarly expressed feelings of responsibility when

an undetected child was born, as Penny’s doctor did. Although Penny had been

offered amniocentesis and steadfastly refused due to concerns about the possibility

of miscarriage, her daughter was subsequently born with a rare genetic disorder, one

which would not have been detected by routine amniocentesis. Penny recounted the

conversation with her doctor following the diagnosis which conveyed his sense of

regret and accountability. Thinking about it, the obstetrician was very….apologetic…..when we went back for the 6 week check up…..he said, I’m sorry you’ve been in hospital for so long, waiting for these tests, if there is anything I can do….after we got the result back,…….. He must have rung….and he said “I’m very sorry that’s come back with ******Syndrome75F

76 ……….there was nothing through the pregnancy that would have indicated a problem”…….and it was like he had a sense of, he wished he had picked it up……………because now you’re stuck

76 As the syndrome that Penny’s daughter was diagnosed with after birth is a rare condition, revealing it would identify her within the Brisbane community. To preserve Penny and her daughter’s privacy it is inappropriate to disclose it.

Page 198: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

198

with that…… I don’t really know, he may have genuinely been sorry……. but because we are a little bit cynical, we were like; he’s just covering himself……Penny.

Finally, even when ostensibly there was no blame to be apportioned, the following

comment highlights that physicians keenly felt the brunt of the unpredictable and

inexplicable outcomes, outcomes that are an inevitable part of the human condition.

I think finding blame …..expecting the perfect baby and not getting it, the consequence of that is anger…… that they did all the right things, ate all the right foods , so someone must have done something wrong , I guess that’s an outcome of promoting the idea ….that if you do all the right things and have all the right tests, then you will get this outcome, it makes people less accepting that bad things happen, and sometimes they happen to nice people………..it doesn’t prepare people……..they can’t accept the outcome and they feel there has to be a reason for everything……General Practitioner 2

Poor Understanding of Disability

‘Disability tends to be associated with tragic loss, weakness, passivity,

dependency, helplessness, shame and global incompetence. In societies

where Western science and medicine are powerful culturally, and where

their promise to control nature is still widely believed, people with

disabilities are constant reminders of the failures of that promise, and of the

inability of science to protect everyone from illness, disability and death.

They are the ‘others’ that science would like to forget’ (Wendell, 1996 cited

by Pauly Morgan, 1998, p.94).

Prevention of the presumed pain, anxiety, stress, and suffering of the disabled and

their carers is often cited as a positive outcome of early termination of a foetus

carrying a disability (Anderson, 1999; Baird, 1999; Clarkeburn, 2000). As many

disabilities, especially genetically linked ones, cannot be cured, conventional

medical wisdom dictates that they must be prevented. As flagged before, Clarkeburn

(2000) goes further, claiming that the prevention of pain and suffering is not simply

an optional benefit of screening, but rather ‘prevent[ing] a child being born whose

life would be worse than non-existence’ is indeed ‘a parental and moral obligation’

(ibid., p. 401). While the argument that life is worse than death for the severely

disabled is disputed as a socially constructed interpretation, entrenched by the

portrayal of disability as an unrelenting tragedy (Asch & Wasserman, 2005; Parens

Page 199: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

199

& Asch, 2000; Reinders, 2000), it is nonetheless a message that many pregnant

women seem to have received (Lippman, 1991, p. 23). This message is further

entrenched by the visible and experienced lack of support in the community,

confirming the difficulties of living with disability (Williams et al., 2002c). Tom

Shakespeare (1999, p.29) further laments the pervasive influence of such attitudes

on the directions and implementation of research policy and practice saying,

‘An outdated attitude that impairment equals tragedy and that disabled lives

are not worth living permeates the clinical literature and informs the

research policy on genetics.’

In their critique of prenatal diagnosis, Parens and Asch (2000) expand upon the

themes above. They assert that not only is prenatal screening morally problematic

because if its role in entrenching discriminatory and prejudiced attitudes towards

people with disabilities, but additionally, it contributes to negative community

attitudes through the perpetuation of misinformation about the lived experience of

disability. They further claim that prenatal screening potentially undermines the

character of the parent-child relationship, making it contingent upon the quality of

the child, while also eroding communal acceptance and tolerance of diversity and

inclusion. Parens and Asch (1999) further contest the normative representations of

disability in which they claim the negative aspects of living with a disability are

unfairly accentuated. Hilde Lindemann–Nelson (2001, p.82) offers some insight into

the damage to identity that such biased representations may cause saying,

‘Just as we construct self-constituting stories around the aspects of our

selves and our lives we care most about, so others construct identity

constituting stories around aspects of our lives that they care most about.

Sometimes these stories centre on the same features that we care about too,

and sometimes they don’t. And sometimes these others interpret a feature of

out lives very differently from the way we interpret it, which is to say they

construct a different story, with different plots and from different points of

view around that feature’.

Page 200: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

200

Within this cohort of mothers, Leanne’s attitude was most heavily influenced by

negative perceptions of what life with a disabled child would entail. Based on her

knowledge of a work colleague, whose daughter had Down syndrome, Leanne

interpreted her colleague’s life as one of ongoing stress and hardship, directly

stemming from the disability in her child. She explained

Knowing my colleague and her family, she has a son 3 years older than her daughter now, to see how it has affected their life and knowing that little girl. [E: Do you perceive that as a negative experience?] Oh God No!! No! Not negative, realistic!...... If I hadn’t known her I wouldn’t have had it, but by knowing that one in a blue moon, by knowing that one, it’s not some textbook side paragraph, it’s….. She was the one, so by knowing that one, that was my decision made, I’m having it because I could also be that one, and if I was that one I knew what to do. Leanne.

However, when questioned about the particular hardships involved in raising a child

with a disability, Leanne’s answer revealed little detail, other than the assertion that

she lacked strength and character, and was not confident that she would get adequate

support from others to cope with the additional, though unspecified, burdens.

[E: If you were motivated by the experience of your colleague in parenting a child with a disability, what is it about your colleague’s experience and life with her child that makes it so undesirable to you, that you would take steps to prevent that?] I think we hadn’t tried for a baby for long, the first time we tried we conceived so I felt lucky in that I was fertile, I knew there were no problems ‘down there’ (laughs), so I felt well, I haven’t got the strength of character to bring up a disabled child and seeing what she has to do to bring her up and the support that she needs, I have no family here whatsoever, got no support, nothing just me and my husband. It’s hard enough to bring up a child with no disability, but with no-one to support us. …….So that, in conjunction with the knowledge that we haven’t been trying for a kid for two years, we conceived first time, so I thought well……. [ hesitates] I would have terminated if I knew it was Down syndrome. Leanne

Even though Leanne acknowledged her colleague’s acceptance and love of her

child, she firmly dismissed the idea that it would ever be acceptable for her to

mother a child with Down syndrome.

In the beginning [of the pregnancy] in the first few weeks I asked her what had happened to her and she was quite upfront and didn’t mind telling …..but I didn’t want to get into how she was feeling now, I just wanted to know the facts leading up to the birth… and she said how she was in shock and didn’t want the child and tried to run away….. But that was in her shock and now she has this daughter who had Downs and that’s how it is. I did tell her that I was having amnio, and she said, well what will you do if the baby does have Downs? Obviously she has the point of view that her daughter has Downs so she wouldn’t think about abortion, because that’s her daughter. I didn’t say it [that I would

Page 201: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

201

abort], when I could see where the conversation was going I changed the focus of the conversation, but she knew me she knew my attitudes, but, no, I didn’t spell it out in black and white, because we’re friends. I mean you don’t tell someone who has disabled child that you would have a test to make sure your unborn child doesn’t have what they got….. You’re not going to say that to a mother are you? ……..[later in the interview]……..We’re quite close knit at work, and she is very career minded and we all…. all of us tend to think she does a lot of unnecessary work to get out of the house….because it is so hard at home.….and we all tend to think that as well, basically because she can go out the house, and leave all the stresses.….. I’ve never asked her in so many terms [if she has difficulty coping with her daughter] but…. I would imagine………Leanne

The contradictory nature of Leanne’s account, explaining her relationship with her

colleague as ‘close’ while persistently evading, and making unsubstantiated

presumptions about the daily difficulties her friend encountered served to entrench

Leanne’s predetermined schema which equated life with a disability to unrelenting

hardship. Leanne’s determined unwillingness or inability to question her firmly held,

pre-existing belief that Down syndrome would never be acceptable in her family

was stubbornly disquieting, and it also contradicts claims made by some disability

rights advocates (Biesecker & Hamby, 2000; Ferguson, Gartner, & Lipsky, 2000;

Parens & Asch, 2000) who have noted that personal contact and knowledge of a

person with a disability often dispels many misunderstandings and has been

associated with decreased acceptance of termination following prenatal diagnosis.

As a visible and recognisable disability, Down syndrome was often singled out for

specific attention by mothers and practitioners, as evidenced in the following

reflections, I guess there’s a focus on Downs because it’s because it’s a survivable chromosomal condition, the others usually result in miscarriage or still birth, or a baby that survives a few hours or a few weeks, but no longer. So back in the days when they instituted screening, the other abnormalities weren’t considered a significant group to look for because they are going to die anyway and they wont cost us anything......people don’t talk about that as much either. Children with Down syndrome are present in our communities, they are visible and it’s got this kind of focus that people have because it is a baby with a visible problem that is incurable and has a definite feature about it…that’s recognisable…. I think that’s why....but if you look at the eugenics of it all, the reason it was actually created and why anyone even screens from a medical perspective it was because we were trying to reduce the live birth rate of Down syndrome because Down syndrome children costs us money. So there is the public perception of Down syndrome being one of the few recognisable, versus the medical profession which is actually all about money…..not everyone in the medical profession saw it like that …many saw it as allowing people to have the opportunity to make pregnancy choices and providing information, but really it started out as a money thing….Obstetrician.

Relaying the story of watching a young man with Down syndrome on the bus going

to work each morning, one genetic counsellor struggled to reconcile the apparently

Page 202: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

202

unthreatening normalcy of this young man’s life, to the starkly contrasting anxiety

and perceptions of danger, risk and undesirability held by many pregnant women

she counselled through the day. She explained: …it’s concerning that they’re all anxious about Down syndrome but they don’t actually know what it is……I think for a lot of people... it’s almost like anyone with a disability is under that label of Down syndrome…..any intellectual impairment…. it falls under that umbrella…….but the fear…………I don’t know………where that comes from………[later in the interview] .……..there are times when I sit back and think, this focus on Down syndrome just kills me…………I guess because when you put it in perspective its just one thing and there’s a whole spectrum of other things that could be wrong with a baby that may not be known until the baby develops. Maybe it’s autism, maybe it’s cerebral palsy, goodness knows what….. So that focus on Down syndrome is challenging for me……….there’s no doubt about that and I’ve talked about it with my supervisors and things……………particularly when I come to work on the bus and I see this 20 yr old guy with Down syndrome looking like he’s going off to work you know and I look at him and I think ………oh……what are we doing?............It feels really harsh and it’s so pointed….. that it’s at Down syndrome, and I don’t know how I reconcile that in my head………..Somehow I’ve done it …….up until now………. But I do find that really challenging…Genetic Counsellor 2.

She continued noting: Sometimes people really just shock me with their reaction …..usually you get the “oh no…..we couldn’t have a child with Down syndrome” lots of phrases you get used to hearing I guess, like “I don’t want to sound cruel but…….”, or “I just couldn’t bring someone like that into the world” …..Things that make you wonder where they come from …..And they’re not specific, for the vast majority, it’s not a specific experience that makes people think that way….. It’s just society…….. That makes people think that way……what’s in their family……….you know…. Genetic Counsellor 2

Fear of disability and abnormality lie at the core of the attitudes expressed.

Understanding how such schemata of normality emerge, Lindemann- Nelson (2001,

p.111) extrapolates from Marion Iris Young’s (1990, p.59) account of ‘cultural

imperialism’ to suggest how the dominant discourses of ‘normal’ have come to be

perpetuated and entrenched in our collective understandings. She explains,

‘The dominant group takes its own experiences, achievements and values to

be representative of human nature per se. To the extent that other groups

differ from it, then those groups must consist of defective human beings. It’s

often habitual and unconscious fears and aversions that drive people in the

dominant culture to identify subgroups as deviant rather than merely

different, but an element of moral censoriousness regarding people who do

not conform to the norms of the dominant group can also be present in the

identities that are constructed through cultural imperialism. In identifying

Page 203: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

203

those outside the dominant group as deficient or defective, the group affirms

its own sense of who it is’.

Thus deviance, not difference, demarcates and defines the social discourse of

disability, and the quest for normalcy in reproduction promotes the intense

surveillance of pregnancy even when the methods used are incomplete and

potentially harmful. The quest for normalcy was identified by several practitioners

as a significant factor shaping the behaviours adopted by physicians and parents

alike:

I guess….. We don’t really handle abnormality very well……our society is very geared towards normality…and I think that those things matter most. From a medical point of view we are trying to pick up the serious things first…..to make sure everything is OK……I don’t think there is any education in terms of what Down syndrome is though………I think we offer screening…… but when you in fact ask people do you know anything about Down syndrome, that’s actually the thing they are not well educated about ….. They don’t have much knowledge about what it is they think we’re screening for…..Obstetrician Normality is very important to us when we talk about reproducing a human being…. In birthing a baby, normality is very important…they need to have the correct numbers of toes and fingers and ears in the right position although that’s not as noticeable as the digits…. And yet…normality of the process of the event of birth is not hugely important. It’s the normality of the product and I think that has a huge meaning because it reflects on the genetic normality of the parents involved and their parents and the whole family really, so abnormality is to be avoided at all cost and abnormality is almost something to be ashamed of so technology is one way that we can, to use business terms ‘insure’ ourselves against that a little bit. Midwife 4

One GP felt that by offering more and more testing the medical profession had

colluded in generating and perpetuating the false expectations prenatal screening

potentially generated, expectations which ultimately could skew parental outlooks. I’d rather we changed the mindset of the couple, the medical profession are going along with this idea of the ‘perfect baby’ ….there are no perfect babies……I mean your child may be diagnosed with autism at 2 years old, that can be far more devastating than Down syndrome, I think…. far more devastating, certainly as devastating. One of the fears with Downs, apart from its prevalence, is the intellectual impairment, I think people fear that….if it’s something like Cystic Fibrosis, people deal with that better because there’s no intellectual impairment, although ultimately the child will die, but yes….. I think we’ve planted the idea that the more we offer screening and options for women not to have an imperfect baby, the more we reinforce the idea that they should expect a perfect baby………….and there’s no doubt that that’s behind the litigation of obstetricians for every CP [cerebral palsy] child that’s born. We’re adding to this expectation of a perfect baby and a perfect child and people are confronted with this all the way along. Then they get a child with autism or bad asthma, who’s in hospital three times a year, or ADHD, or just has a really difficult personality….I mean we’re all imperfect, there’s just different types of disability. I just think as a profession, doctors are buying into that, not only buying in but really pushing it…women may go through this process and have a baby that doesn’t have Down syndrome at the end ………have the normal baby…..well that’s great, but what if they strike other things done

Page 204: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

204

the track…… I think if someone had every test and everything was fine, then they went and found what a [comparatively] small problem is really; I think it can unhinge some people…..because they expected a perfect baby. General Practitioner 2

Yet negative assumptions of what it means to be disabled or abnormal are strongly

entrenched within the discursive language of screening (Clapton, 2004). Use of

potentially prejudiced language such as burden76F

77, risk, prevention, coping, or

adjusting to disability, all imbue a message of unremitting hardship (Clapton, 2003;

Reinders, 2000). Similarly, adopting the language of ‘medically’ indicated

intervention may further perpetuate the non-acceptance of disability while

positioning the ensuing discussion as one of technical or biological importance

while simultaneously silencing the social, personal, and ethical. Language, therefore,

has the potential to narrow and perhaps even trivialise the terms of deliberation, as

this GP suggested:

I guess that’s one of my dilemmas with the whole way it is presented, even when I read the medical stuff , I have seen it written, and I don’t recall if it was a journal article or letter to the editor, it is described as “preventing” Down syndrome………….. And it’s clearly not ‘preventing’ [exasperated laugh]… it’s clearly not ‘prevention’ at all. Its preventing a live birth of a baby with Down syndrome. It’s not prevention of Down syndrome at all and I think that’s strong terminology in medical circles, but if that term gets out into society at large, I guess inevitably it will do….you know, ‘I want a test to prevent Down syndrome’,…………I think their would be many doctors who would never correct that terminology…I think that’s shocking…….everybody that is ultimately faced with that decision after amnio……I don’t think any of them take it lightly, so it’s not as if it’s a flippant thing, ‘oh we’ll just get rid of the baby’…..it’s heart wrenching for all of them, so use of the word ‘prevention’ trivialises the child, it also trivialises the decision for them to and it’s just not true……it’s just not true. General Practitioner 2

Given that much of the pain, anxiety, and stress experienced by people with

disabilities and their carers stems directly from lack of social and governmental

support, not from the disability per se (Ferguson et al., 2000; Shakespeare, 2001),

many parents of children with disabilities feel it is unreasonable to judge quality of

life based on a social norm in which the disabled are under-resourced and

misrepresented. As this obstetrician predicted, if adequate societal support was

forthcoming, medicine could function very differently in regards to what practices

were endorsed with respect to disability.

77 The word ‘burden’ is defined as ‘something emotionally difficult to bear, a responsibility or duty, to weigh down or oppress’ (Microsoft, 1999).

Page 205: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

205

In an ideal world if everyone was guaranteed adequate respite, adequate care, free medical care, free support and a community that always stood by them, so that when they died they knew that their child would be looked after, we would have a very different way of approaching this. I think it is very much an example of a community that is fractured compared to how it used to be….we don’t have extended families; we cannot guarantee that a child’s brothers or sisters when they get older would not look after that person. There are no extended families to offer support and frankly, Australia’s support systems aren’t too bad but they’re not fantastic when it comes to respite care for people looking after kids with special needs, they are really pathetic so I think that aspect is the main reason why older women choose to have termination….They are frightened of being 80 and still looking after a 40 year old with Down syndrome and then worrying about what will happen when they die ….and they don’t want to put the burden onto their other children…..Obstetrician

However, as this genetic counsellor realised with some resignation, There are people who have the blinkers on and no matter what we say they just have that construct that was in their head…… a lot of people say…oh society is so cruel ….to people who are different……..and……….they tend to have, I think a lot of generalisations on how people with disabilities are and what type of life they might have, or lead, whether that’s far, far from the truth or not?...............Sometimes it probably is….and some may have views from a few decades ago in terms of the type of living environment for a person with a disability…I guess……..so I see my role as giving them a ‘now’ perspective I guess, on people with disabilities……..about education and living and work opportunities and that there is really good support from the government and private sector and…………… I try to do that to give some balance………… but it’s just me talking against their values…..wherever they’ve pulled that from …I’d be surprised if it ever really helped……but I feel it’s my place to at least try to make that comment. Genetic Counsellor 2

Further compounding negative social attitudes to disability is the increasing

discourse towards self-reliance (Reinders, 2000), entrenching feelings of failure and

fear experienced by some women on the birth of an imperfect child. Social policy

shift in recent years now lays the ‘burden of care’ squarely in the hands of

individuals and out of the hands of institutions. The option to access institutional

care, or respite care, for a severely impaired child is therefore becoming more

difficult to achieve. This stark reality confronting parents confirms the difficulties of

accommodating disability in a society that seems measured in its support. However,

the need to construct a meaningful role and place for people living with impairments

is crucial in changing the social prejudices observed, as James Lindemann- Nelson

suggests ‘the proper response to this concern may have little directly to do with

reproductive decision making and a great deal to do with how people with

disabilities are incorporated into social life’ (Lindemann-Nelson, 2001, p.12), a

view echoed by the clinical geneticist who observed,

I still think generally there is a lot of sympathy for people whose children do have health problems……..and there’s not yet anyone who’s making those decisions because they had no other options available to them. It’s a complex area because …….I always remember a couple whose child had Down syndrome……. Their view was that………as a community

Page 206: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

206

….they saw fewer and fewer opportunities for this person to have economic employment, because there aren’t as many unskilled jobs in the workforce as there was once. They just didn’t see that there was a way for an economic future for that individual, who was intellectually handicapped, so that’s a big challenge for the community…… to have productive and meaningful roles for people particularly the intellectually handicapped. Clinical Geneticist

The ‘Preventable’ Cost of Disability – Cost//Benefit Analysis

An additional form of social pressure to screen with a view to terminate is the

recurrent message that the health care costs incurred in caring for the disabled may

be prevented by utilising prenatal screening (Biggio, Morris, Owen, & Stringer,

2004; Caughey, 2005; Cuckle, 1995, 2001; Harris, 2004). Based on utilitarian

justifications of the moral imperative to conserve public funds, such discourse may

exert further pressure on pregnant women to view termination as a socially

responsible act. Indeed Williams et al. (2002, p.749) revealed that some respondents

in their 2002 study uncritically viewed screening as an ‘economic solution to the

problem of disability’. That government and health care institutions should embrace

policies that overtly sanctioned termination of foetuses with disabilities through the

provision of generous medical rebates seemed plausible to Leanne who explained,

When, I got the invoice for the amnio and the consultation, it was almost $500, Medicare gave me back almost all, except about $20, there was hardly any gap at all, so they gave back half the consultation and nearly all of the amnio, and I thought Medicare doesn’t normally give out that much, maybe you should find out the exact figures77F

78, because obviously the government doesn’t want a Down syndrome child in society, because they are expensive …..So of course they are going to give you most of the money back, because they don’t want them in society because they’re expensive. [E: Research shows that around 90% of babies with Down syndrome are aborted, do you have any thoughts about that?] Well, I’d say……. well on that 10% for not, but …… If I asked my colleague if she knew in advance would she terminate, I’m sure she would say of course not, because she wouldn’t give up the love of her child that she’s known for 7 years, but I’m sure she would have liked to have known…… but I was very surprised to get all that money back, and I thought, well the reason must be because they’re an expense to society, and that’s a message that the health care is sending…… but for me I would have had it anyway regardless of the cost. Leanne

While Leanne was fully in agreement with this perceived (though false) explanation

of government collusion, Danielle remained more circumspect,

78 The Medicare rebate for amniocentesis (Item number 16600) is 75% of the scheduled fee, which is no higher than the rebate for most other medical services. See http://www.health.gov.au/mbs/search.cfm?q=amniocentesis (Accessed 12th July,2006)

Page 207: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

207

I imagine it’s probably a push from the government, I mean we don’t have the funds that we need to support these children and adults……..and all the other mental health and other issues……if we could just weed a few of these out it would be helpful...…part of me thinks that it wouldn’t surprise me in the slightest to find the government had been strongly advising women to terminate………..I’m a bit sceptical really……I don’t have a lot of faith in those systems generally………Danielle

Shakespeare (1999, p.31) strongly cautions against the insidious validation of

prenatal screening regimes on the basis of an overall positive cost/benefit analysis78F

79 ,

claiming that such justifications overstate the true ‘cost’ of being disabled, while

understating the fundamental reality that the human condition is ultimately one of

frailty in which disability may become a feature of any person’s life. He explains,

‘Equally, there is a pernicious tendency to develop screening policies on the

grounds of cost-benefit models. These arguments balance the cost of

detecting and terminating affected pregnancies with the cost of supporting a

disabled person throughout their life. Particular policies are defended in

terms of a reduction to the welfare or medical bills of a nation. This rests on

highly dubious assumptions about the cost of being disabled. It replaces

human rights with economic rationality. It ignores the fact that anybody

could become impaired at any time due to accidents or disease, not just the

very small number of people who are born with impairment’.

Shakespeare’s concerns flag the potentially sinister and destructive consequences of

equating human life to reductionist economic argument and were also shared by the

Clinical Geneticist of this cohort of practitioners who noted:

Well [cost benefit calculation] - that’s the economic rationalist argument for prenatal diagnosis….. I mean there’s no doubt that to avoid the birth of a child with an intellectual or physical handicap, or long term condition would save the community and Medicare lots of dollars…. but it’s a very poor basis on which to value the worth of human life and reproductive choices. Clinical Geneticist

Despite the obvious reservations and flaws, cost-benefit analyses are regularly

invoked as a fiscal justification for extending screening programs. Indeed, a recent

79 Also referred to in the literature as cost effectiveness analysis (CEA) (Caughey, 2005), and cost utility (Harris, Washington, Nease, & Kuppermann, 2004).

Page 208: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

208

US study, which estimated the success of prenatal screening against the unsettling

criterion of ‘live births averted’ 79F

80 (Biggio et al., 2004, p.726) from a hypothetical

cohort concluded that,

‘in terms of overall cost to the medical care system, the most expensive

course of action was to offer no screening and incur the expense of caring

for infants born with trisomy 21. The majority of the cost benefit attained

with the sequential screen is derived from the reduction in the number of

trisomy 21 live births.’

Similarly, Harris (2004) and Kupperman (2005) conclude that testing is cost

effective at all ages, advocating that screening be routinely extended beyond the

traditionally ‘high risk’ over 35 year olds to include all asymptomatic women, as

clearly anyone may be ‘at risk’80F

81. In their theoretical model, Biggio et al (2004),

uncritically present the loss of 1.4 ‘euploid’81F

82, or normal chromosome foetuses, per

single Down syndrome child detected as the most ‘successful’ strategy, making no

comment on the collateral damage of the 1.4 normal foetuses lost. As the financial

‘benefit’ portion of cost/benefit equation is solely realised by not providing medical

treatment to a disabled person for the term of their life (Baird, 1999, Biggio, Morris,

Owen, & Stringer, 2004; Caughey, 2005; Cuckle, 1995, 2001; Harris, 2004), such

analyses only measure up when termination rates remain high. Cost benefit analyses,

therefore, perpetuate the institutionalisation of disability prejudice. The ethically

contentious and potentially eugenic nature of the presumption to terminate is not

explicitly confronted by any of these authors, while the unwanted fiscal

responsibility of caring for the disabled within the community further permeates the

discourse of pregnancy, bleeds into institutional policy and practice, and contributes

to hostile attitudes to people with disabilities (Parens & Asch, 2000). Furthermore,

the presumptions of cost-benefit analyses may position the social responsibility to

prevent the financial burden of caring for the disabled unfairly onto the shoulders of

individual pregnant women.

80 Note the language of risk – avert: to avoid something harmful. 81 Understandings of risk perception will be discussed more fully in Chapter 7. 82 Euploid: The normal number of chromosomes for a species. In humans, the euploid number of chromosomes is 46 with the notable exception of the unfertilized egg and sperm in which it is 23. http://www.medterms.com (Accessed 10th December, 2007)

Page 209: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

209

While Cuckle (2001) and Biggio et al (2004, p.726) acknowledge that economic

grounds may be eclipsed by social, ethical and political considerations, noting that

‘individual patient desires and values also merit consideration’, they maintain that

the fundamental decision ‘should be evaluated from the payer’s perspective’, the

‘payer’ being the health care provider. Against the cultural backdrop of economic

rationalism in health care, cited costs of $1220 per detection of Down syndrome

compared with an incremental lifetime cost of $228 400 to care for a child with a

trisomy (Harris, 2004, p.280) illustrates a stark mathematical reality, one which

fiscal logic dictates we endorse if economic rationalism is our ‘hypergood’. While

most cost-benefit analyses focus on the direct medical costs, ‘for ease of

measurement’, Macones and Odibo (2005, para 5) note that ‘it is widely accepted

that indirect and intangible medical costs often overwhelm direct medical costs’.

Indeed the ‘intangible’ costs of pain, suffering and grief (Macones & Odibo, 2005),

and the potential cost to women’s ongoing physical and psychological health and

wellbeing seem poorly factored into reductionist cost-benefit calculations (Tankard -

Reist, 2005, p.19). As a result, the reduced form of data deemed worthy of

consideration in such calculations presents an impoverished, distorted, and

incomplete measure.

Reflections on why certain procedures come to be funded at the expense of others

remain masked in the cost-benefit framework which essentially shapes the choices

on offer. As this obstetrician explained:

We will always focus on things we can test for, and the things we can’t test for or that aren’t realistic to test for, because they wont pick up enough to justify the cost, obviously those things will just be put down to the bottom, because you cant warn or make people anxious about something you can’t exclude……So obviously from my point of view a child with Cerebral Palsy that is severe, who needs 24 hour care is a lot more to embark upon than a child with Down syndrome,…… but we have no way of predicting that. I suppose the kind of things we try and avoid are poor outcomes from normal delivery, we’re trying to reduce prematurity, we’re trying to reduce adverse outcomes in late pregnancy anyway, we just can’t test for it though…and we can never really get rid of everything, so that’s why that’s been focussed from a different point of view. The things we can test for will always have a more visible impact on people. Obstetrician.

However, the question preceding such communal health care decisions, and one

raised by Alfirevic and Neilson (2004) is:

Page 210: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

210

‘What is the importance of establishing top quality Down syndrome

screening programs relative to other priorities in the maternity services-

notably tackling inequalities and ensuring that all women in labour have

enough midwives to meet their needs?’ (Alfirevic & Neilson, 2004, p.812)

The unease of acknowledging the concealed value judgments about persons with

disabilities that such practices imply and imbue was voiced by the Obstetrician who

noted: As soon as you start educating, you’re going to come up against groups of people, disabled rights groups or right to life groups who will say you are educating people to make judgement values about the worth of a life…and I think that is actually a problem. It’s why people don’t talk about it as openly…..some of it reflects individual judgement values about pregnancy choices and the value of a life. I think of it in a much wider scale than just education, it’s the fundamental issues that face society about once you start to talk about it you are admitting that you are placing values on certain levels of normality….and what is a variance of normal versus a true abnormality that kind of thing, people don’t want to face it so they avoid talking about it. Obstetrician

Whenever the subject of terminating disabled foetuses is raised, accusations of

eugenic intent inevitably follow. While many commentators invoke coercion as the

key differential in the ‘imposition’ of a eugenic agenda, as previously mentioned,

coercion of the more subtle, social forms addressed throughout this thesis may still

constitute coercion. Other social commentators such as Abby Lippmann (1991,

pp.24-25) remain unconvinced by what she sees as the insincere denial of the

eugenic intentions within saying,

‘though the word “eugenics” is scrupulously avoided in most biomedical

reports about prenatal diagnosis, except where it is strongly disclaimed as a

motive for intervention, this is disingenuous. Prenatal diagnosis presupposes

that certain fetal conditions are intrinsically not bearable’.

The current focus on cost/benefit analysis as a justification for detecting foetal

anomalies from a largely asymptomatic population may indeed represent an

emerging form of ‘fiscal eugenics’, discriminatory and eugenic outcomes driven by

the privileging of budgetary considerations above care provision within the

healthcare system. A 1926 quote from the American Eugenics Society states:

Page 211: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

211

‘Does eugenics mean less sympathy for the unfortunate? ... Eugenics does

not; it does mean fewer unfortunates with which to divide sympathy. This is

true kindness to both the victims and to society’ (American Eugenics Society

cited by Nelkin & Lindee, 1995, p. 31).

Rather than dividing sympathy, as the 1926 eugenicists did, we may be embarking

on a path to limit the number of disabled members entering our communities by

withholding or dividing financial resources. The social context and tacit

expectations may therefore act to exert a social pressure on women undergoing such

tests by creating a moral space where individuals ‘choose’ to implement society’s

prejudices (Hubbard, 1988).

Chapter Summary

Social constraints identified through the voices of participants and established

research show that the rhetoric of choice and the expectation that engaging in

prenatal screening will automatically enhance choice has significantly infiltrated our

collective psyche and seems generally and unproblematically accepted. However,

within the rhetoric, the reality appears to be that choice is deeply constrained and

funnelled towards the socially and institutionally endorsed ‘choices made available’.

Entrenched negative attitudes towards disability and the poor understanding and

under resourcing of people with disabilities create an atmosphere of fear, culpability,

and blame; an atmosphere in which choice is further delimited. When coupled with

faith that science can provide the much hoped for control over the unpredictability of

the human condition, a stance which Art Frank (1995, p.135) claims perpetuates the

myth of invulnerability, embracing technological intervention to ‘prevent’ disability

seems an obvious route to follow. In addition to the socially sanctioned and

scientifically revered aims of prenatal screening, the economic rationalist values that

increasingly permeate institutional health care dictate that the cost-benefit

justifications for pursuing and expanding screening regimes mutually reinforce the

scientific and social schema.

Page 212: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

212

The factors discussed in this chapter are by no means exhaustive. However,

collectively, they illuminate a dynamic of fear and blame overlaid with the promise

of control and power, a dynamic which entrenches prenatal intervention as the

morally, medically, and financially responsible course of action. While prenatal

screening potentially can facilitate enhanced choice for some, when presented

routinely and unproblematically in an institutional context which may systematically

undermines and impedes women’s opportunities to gain ethically adequate levels of

understanding, the underlying socially prejudiced beliefs that drive such intervention

remain unspoken.

The next chapter will consider the personal constraints that impact upon the

delivery, interpretations and acceptance of prenatal screening.

Page 213: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

213

CHAPTER 8

VOICES IN CONTEXT:

PERSONAL CONSTRAINTS

Introduction

In addition to the philosophical, institutional and social constraints previously

considered, many personal constraints also exist. The perceived need for

reassurance, individual perceptions of risk and the belief that the targeted type of

information revealed by screening may inject a degree of certainty or confidence

into the vulnerability and uncertainty of pregnancy, are commonly cited personal

factors which mould women’s behavioural choices. In combination with varying

personal capacitates for understanding the often unfamiliar medical routines and

terminologies, including risk interpretation, these personal constraints further delimit

how ‘choice’ and ‘consent’ may be interpreted and negotiated. It is to these personal

factors that we will now turn.

Reassurance and the ‘Desire to Know’

‘If knowledge is power, then ignorance is powerlessness’ (May, 1994, p.77)

‘Knowledge does not always empower; instead it may confuse and paralyze.

Parents may have to contend with perhaps the most unforeseen consequence

of it all; too much information, that is information they never realised the

testing might yield, and information they are not equipped to handle’

(Kolker & Burke, 1994, p.165).

The quest for ‘reassurance’ coupled with the ‘desire to know’ features significantly

in explanations women give of why they participate in prenatal screening

programmes (Harris et al., 2004; Lippman, 1991; Press & Browner, 1993, 1997;

Santhalahti, 1999; Santhalahti et al., 1998). As only 1% - 3% of pregnancies carry

some form of abnormality, not unexpectedly, many women experience the

Page 214: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

214

reassurance sought. Several studies claim that the virtues of prenatal screening

extend beyond that of mere reassurance claiming that screening is psychologically

rewarding, an experience that acts as a catalyst for positive behavioural changes

such as improving diet or stopping smoking, and one which facilitates increased

maternal attachment and foetal bonding (Ji et al., 2005; Lumley, 1990). However,

these positive outcomes are not universally accepted, with others, for example van

den Berg (2005), noting only 8% of respondents felt reassured. Scanholzer,

Gatzmann, Zimmerman and Buddeberg (2000) further argue that there is no

concrete evidence of any long term or lasting benefit to maternal attachment,

suggesting instead that the reassurance gleaned is simply a temporary artefact of

relieving the anxiety induced by the screen itself. Scanholzer et al (ibid) therefore

conclude that screening may not enhance the ability to cope with a negative

outcome, but may simply prolong the period of anxiety and stress following an

unwelcome result.

In the absence of any obvious or immediate harm, with no apparent reason to

decline, accepting screening with its promise of reassurance and presumption of

increased control may appear ‘self evident’(Santhalahti et al., 1998). This was the

case for most of the mothers in this cohort who seemed to believe that, as noted by

Whynes (2002), if a test is offered by a trusted practitioner, it must be safe.

Reinforcing observations by Marteau and Slack (1992), Calman (2002), and

Edwards (2003) have observed that positive health professionals’ attitudes are

pivotal in shaping and framing perceptions about screening. The following

practitioner comments similarly reflect positive personal and professional attitudes

towards screening:

I think it can become a very useful test to give early re-assurance, or otherwise for women……it’s the best screening tool that we’ve got. It doesn’t harm the baby; it harms the mother at times [laughs]………..it’s easy to do, its relatively cheap…………..if we can reduce the number of women going straight to amnio then that’s another benefit. Genetic Counsellor 2 I think the main thing if you’re looking at the patient’s point of view for requesting a prenatal screen is probably reassurance because there is a degree of fear and anxiety. Obstetrician

Women want to be reassured that their child doesn’t have that…….more than they actually think about what they’ll do if the test shows they do. General Practitioner 2

Page 215: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

215

I guess they do it for peace of mind to know the baby is OK and not to worry about it for the rest of the pregnancy, or getting prior knowledge of a problem to prepare themselves mentally. Midwife 1

The issue of reassurance for ‘certainty’ was raised by one Genetic Counsellor,

[E: Why do women accept prenatal screening?] Because they want certainty and desirability…in their offspring [E: Does prenatal screening give them certainty?] Some, but not full certainty……… [E: Do you think people understand what the uncertainties are?] No……………because they don’t understand that having a baby is a risky business………they don’t understand that 2-3% of the population will have a problem with their baby………..whether it be a learning disability or a turned foot……..some people are more concerned with intellectual disability and some with physical…..so, no I don’t think that people understand that they don’t start off with 100% chance of a healthy baby. I think people want a healthy baby………………..because I personally would. Genetic Counsellor 1

Another GP questioned the worth of exposing a mother and foetus to the potential

risks of screening if a woman did not intend to ‘act’82F

83 on the result saying,

I mean if someone says they are going to go ahead and have the baby anyway, it doesn’t necessarily abrogate the test, but………..it then raises the question that if you’re going to do an amnio and turn up a Downs, …given the fact that the amnio has a risk ……not only to the foetus, but also to the mother, why do the test?....... but if the person for social , religious or you know…..emotional reasons has already predetermined what they want to do with their body and their pregnancy, then ultimately you work around that constraint. General Practitioner 1.

While being prepared to accommodate the ‘constraint’ of individual patient’s moral

or emotional frameworks, this GP felt a valuable reason to pursue widespread

screening was to assist the practitioner. Prenatal screening may be relevant even if a woman is determined to continue with the pregnancy…..just purely to make the job of the obstetrician a bit less stressful…and indeed hopefully maximise the opportunity for a good outcome…even if the foetal outcome is not particularly good you don’t actually want to compromise the maternal outcomes as well……General Practitioner 1.

83 In most of the literature, the only acknowledged proactive action is termination, the decision to ‘not act’, i.e. to keep the child, is commonly presented in passive terms, although this too is an intentional action. See Coory (2007) for example.

Page 216: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

216

Positive endorsements from practitioners with their inherent suggestion that there

was something definitive and valuable to know were influential for Mary, who

explained, They sort of said ….well unless you want to go through this whole pregnancy not knowing, you’ve been given this test result this will put your mind at ease …if you want to not worry about it that’s fine but……Mary

Yet the selective list of anomalies routinely screened for includes only a small

fraction of the multitude of potential possibilities. Even then, conditions for which

treatment can be offered, other than selective termination, are relatively few (Baird,

1999; Press & Browner, 1997; West & Bramwell, 2006). Indeed, as previously

flagged, most neonatal disabilities result from ‘low birth weight, prematurity, viral

or bacterial infection, birth trauma or accident’ (Baird, 1999, p.9), none of which

can be predicted by prenatal screening. A welcome test result in reality offers

limited guarantees, and may even create an unrealistic or false sense of reassurance

when the result is negative (Marteau, Slack, Kidd, & Shaw, 1992). As observed by

this GP, the negative psychological sequelae that can flow from poor understanding

of the limited scope of screening may be equally distressing or harmful. I do think it’s very important [to make clear what these tests can’t tell you], people still think you can have a blood test for everything…………..people sometimes come in and say, ‘I want a check up, just test everything’ [laughs]……and they really think you can ‘test everything’….I shouldn’t laugh because we’re obviously not getting the message across……and there are people who think that antenatal screening tests everything. I think you really have to point that out because people will think when they have a baby at the end who may have a club foot…they get really upset…. because the ultrasound hasn’t picked it up……they have a lot of faith that the 18 week ultrasound will pick everything up…..I think that increases their risk of postnatal depression and just general emotional ability around having the baby……..it can effect their enjoyment of the baby, just because they’re not prepared…General Practitioner 2

Several midwives also verified that the common perception among the women was

one of over optimistic trust, captured in this comment:

A lot of women come with the expectation that if the nuchal is OK then everything will be perfect… Midwife 1

Amidst the mothers’ cohort there was a degree of confusion, some cynicism, and

even a sense of betrayal about the fragile worth of the much hoped for reassurance.

Danielle remarked:

Page 217: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

217

……….I mean I went through that complete stress for nothing and [my mother] still says to me look at that baby, look at that child and you went through all of that …..and it was all for nothing..............I tend to agree with her………I mean technology has a place…….its a reassurance for things so far…..but it’s limited reassurance…Danielle

Illustrating the observations made elsewhere that the sensation of reassurance may

simply be relief from the anxiety generated by the tests themselves (Harris et al.,

2004; Kowalcek et al., 2002; Liamputtong & Watson, 2002; Schanholzer,

Gatzmann, Zimmermann, & Buddeberg, 2000; van den Berg et al., 2005), Mary

explained: Before the test we had never even discussed it hadn’t even entered our minds……………it didn’t occur to us that we could be in this group where something could be wrong……..and hadn’t even crossed my mind……(after the amniocentesis)….I guess it’s mind easing to get a good result but I wouldn’t say it was iron caste, it meant to me that I didn’t have to worry about the next few weeks if there was something really wrong………….with my obstetrician he just did a scan on me every time I went to see him to make sure that everything was OK, with the baby’s size and so on. Mary

Undoubtedly Mary sensed some reassurance from the ‘good’ amniocentesis result,

however, the anxiety raised by the prior ‘bad’, false positive result clearly lingered

resulting in 12 anxiety reducing ultrasounds, to ‘make sure everything was [still?]

OK’ 83F

84. The attitude that false positives were ‘good mistakes’ was raised by Danielle, Their attitude (to the false positive) was like ‘well that’s good news isn’t it! That’s all worked out alright then” and I was like, well yes it’s great news, but it’s a shame I had to go through it! I don’t tend to question that sort of thing…..I mean perhaps it would have been even better news if we hadn’t done the ultrasound in the first place and not gone through that horrific time………….yeah………….my GP ………….the doctors at the hospital, once they suspected it was a false positive, they just went………..they didn’t want to talk about it ……it had nothing to do with their current thing for that week. Danielle

While Mary’s response to her heightened anxiety was to embrace extensive

surveillance of her pregnancy, like some of the women in Heyman et al’s 2006 study

Terri’s ‘high risk’ status spurred her to ‘disengage’ from her health care providers,

to seek her own reassurances through self-directed education.

I definitely wasn’t prepared for other problems being flagged, and I really wasn’t interested in finding that out. I had just come to the realisation that none of these tests, and this was never pointed out to me, that none of these tests could help me with the thing I was concerned about (Noonan’s Syndrome). That was never pointed out to me. They told me the tests would tell us about the Down syndrome, neural tube defects would be covered, none of which was what my cousin’s child had, but they didn’t point that out to me – I did my own research, I found that out. I just got on the internet; it took 15 minutes, it’s amazing what

84 The potential harms of excessive ultrasound use in pregnancy are not yet clear, and research continues. However, professional bodies advocate caution and counsel against excessive use. See Section B Introduction.

Page 218: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

218

you can find there……... I thought I've done this for nothing……. I was quite anxious about the whole thing. Terri.

Notably, Leanne articulated a strong sense of reassurance and control, while

acknowledging that other potential unforseen negative outcomes were possible.

Given her consistent focus and fears directed towards Down syndrome, perhaps this

one specific piece of information, that her child definitely did not have Down

syndrome, was sufficient reassurance. I felt reassured in that… [amnio was negative for Down syndrome], but of course there’s loads of other things that can go wrong as well, besides Down syndrome, at least I knew that was one thing that I could tick off, I was reassured in that , but of course you still worry about loads of other things that you have no control over. At least this I had control over, everything else had no control over, but that I had control and I’m a bit of a control freak so……..Leanne

Although Leanne could indeed exhibit control and agency in choosing to diagnose

or terminate a pregnancy if her child had Down syndrome, in the face of the

multitude of uncertainties that exist, her sense of control was perhaps overstated.

Lippmann (1991, p.25) claims that the selective nature of the reassurance gleaned

from screening is too restricted, simplistic and reductionist to be of any tangible

consequence, continuing, ‘at best, reassurance is an acquired, not inherent,

characteristic of prenatal diagnosis. Even if testing provides “reassurance”, it is of

a particular and limited kind’. Far from delivering clarity, most forms of prenatal

screening offer ‘an opportunity to move from complete uncertainty to quantified

uncertainty (West & Bramwell, 2006, p.66). While this may seem a more attractive

prospect than ‘unquantified uncertainty’, the paradox of this testing dynamic is that

asymptomatic women, like the mothers in this cohort, must first have their attention

selectively drawn to a particular, though incomplete, list of undesired outcomes,

increasing anxiety levels, which engaging in testing may then selectively relieve

(Harris et al., 2004; Kowalcek et al., 2002; Liamputtong & Watson, 2002; van den

Berg et al., 2005). In a scenario reminiscent of Lindemann-Nelson’s (2001, p. 126)

earlier description of the ‘clinically correct story’, screening protocols

simultaneously create anxiety in women by decreeing them to be ‘at risk’, then offer

a technologically mediated, culturally sanctioned and socially visible way to gain

reassurance and lower their ‘risk’.

Page 219: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

219

The frequently cited script of providing reassurance through giving ‘time to prepare’

for a child with special needs is often floated as a further positive outcome of

screening as this midwife explained:

I guess they do it for peace of mind to know the baby is OK and not to worry about it for the rest of the pregnancy, or getting prior knowledge of a problem to prepare themselves mentally. Midwife 1

Yet in light of the elective termination rates, commonly above 90%84F

85, the

presentation of screening as a preparatory tool seems exaggerated, while the

expectation that anyone could possibly ever be prepared enough was gently rejected

by the Down syndrome support volunteer, who explained:

People think they can gather knowledge and be prepared, but I don’t think you can ever really be prepared for everything in life. Not knowing myself gave me the chance to enjoy the pregnancy, look forward to meeting my baby, and when the baby was born we were instantly suspicious that something wasn’t right, but there she was and we were offered appropriate support and we moved through the reactions that parents go through, grieving, but I think for women to be put through that when they are most vulnerable and pregnant is just so unfair. Down Syndrome Support Group Volunteer

The particular type of reassurance sought or provided however is rarely specific.

Rather, women seek a broad, general sense of comfort that the pregnancy is

progressing normally (Lippman, 1991; Santhalahti, 1999). The reassurance that a

disabled person will be supported in the community is rarely offered, rather, the

reassurance offered is that a defective child will be identified and the frightening

outcome of parenting a disabled child will be averted (Bridle, 2004).

In spite of these critiques, the perceived ‘need’ for reassurance persists; a need

which Lippmann (1991) argues is constructed and perpetuated by technology use

itself. When coupled with the widely expressed conviction that knowledge is benign

and not harmful of itself, a powerful motivation to engage in screening is formed

(G. Anderson, 1999; Press & Browner, 1993; Santhalahti, 1999). Yet the

commonplace belief that all knowledge is valuable or empowering rather than

potentially paralysing or confusing is clearly challenged by Kolker & Burke (1994)

as already quoted above. Similarly, Regina Kenen challenges, ‘if a “gift” of

knowledge offers no cure, is it valuable?’ (Kenen, 1999, p.1545). Indeed,

85 Carothers et al., 1999; Egan & Borgida, 2002; Erikson, 2001; Ford, 1999; Garne, 2001; Santhalahti, 1999.

Page 220: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

220

knowledge does not always empower. For Terri , Mary, and Danielle their, perhaps

naïve, expectation that the knowledge gleaned from their initial scan might be

meaningful, instead invoked intense anxiety as they entered the unforseen ‘grey

area’ of imperfect, incomplete, and unable to be completed knowledge which

created intense distress and bewilderment. While one GP felt women were acutely

aware of the medical reason for screening, which is to find abnormality, the common

approach of framing an offer to screen in terms of “making sure things are ‘OK’”

instantly raises a suspicion in women that ‘things’ may not be ‘OK’. Thus women

are conditioned to accept the limited reassurance on offer.

I think women are aware that the reason the test is being done is to make sure that everything is alright. Now, that’s one way of looking at it, you’ve described it as a more positive search for abnormalities. I don’t think they are diametrically opposed; they are two sides of the same coin, but I don’t think women regard it as just an opportunity to see the baby, they know there is a medical purpose. General Practitioner 3.

The primary purpose of prenatal screening is undoubtedly to detect and to ‘prevent’

disability. Hence, any subsidiary benefits such as gaining reassurance, promoting

bonding, or reducing anxiety are all ancillary and surplus to the fundamental task.

They are not guaranteed outcomes of testing; hence, to suggest that screening is for

these purposes is misleading.

Efforts to determine whether prenatal screening predictions have been correct

through foetal autopsy are limited. Data gathered in the UK observed that despite

increasing termination rates, foetal autopsies rates which could verify prenatal

diagnosis and thus provide valuable reassurance and professional verification are

falling (Boyd, 2004). Boyd (ibid) further claims that only 30 – 60 % of terminated

foetuses undergo autopsy to confirm diagnosis, while a recent French study of 300

foetal autopsies, found autopsy examination changed the prenatal hypothesis in 20%

of cases and confirmed the original hypothesis in 39% of cases85F

86 (Laussel-Riera et

al., 2000). Other studies correlating prenatal diagnosis with autopsy findings report

a healthier, though still variable 60% - 90% confirmation (Ramalho, Matias,

Brandao, & Montenegro, 2006, p.1087; Johns, Al-Salti, Cox and Kilby, 2004;

Brodlie, Laing, Keeling & McKenzie,2002; Tennstedt, Chaoui, Bollman, Korner, &

Dietel, 1998). 86 The remaining 41% required minor changes in diagnosis that were not medically significant.

Page 221: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

221

As flagged earlier, Queensland has unique and particular problems in establishing

such an evidence base such as the fragmented health care delivery and the legal

constraints that diminish transparency. With termination remaining under the

Criminal Code, collection of foetal autopsy data as a result of termination is

disjointed, sparse, and very limited prior to 20 weeks when most terminations for

foetal anomalies occur. This data, which may provide some communal reassurance

that the outcomes of prenatal screening are indeed based on accurate predictions,

would be of significant value in assessing and shaping future practice and ought to

be more vigorously pursued.

While most studies considering the psychological impacts of prenatal screening

focus on the outcomes for women (Harris et al., 2004; Kowalcek et al., 2002;

Leithner et al., 2004; Watson et al., 2003; Zamerowski, 1999), practitioners too have

a vested interest in reassuring themselves. As flagged earlier, fear of potential

litigation against medical staff rather than genuine patient need may be contributing

to strong recommendations to participate given by many doctors (Anderson, 1999;

Press & Browner, 1997; Stapleton et al., 2002; Williams et al., 2002b), representing

a different form of reassurance, one sought by medical staff, mindful of avoiding

possible lawsuits (Williams et al., 2002c) . Indeed, as mentioned previously, the

‘legal grey area of malpractice for not offering tests’ (italics added) has been

identified as a factor in the increasing numbers of women being offered the MSAFP

blood test in one province of Canada (Press & Browner, 1997, p.980). Hence, a

mutually reinforcing bond of anxiety and trust between specialist and patient is

formed which entrenches the normative and routinised pathway of the offer and the

acceptance of prenatal screening for reassurance.

Finally, if women and practitioners perceive the need for reassurance, the question

of why women feel ‘at risk’ must be asked. As one genetic counsellor remarked

earlier, pregnancy is a “risky business”, but who is at risk, can we know the extent to

which they at risk and can risk status change? The next section of this chapter will

examine the discourse of risk that has infiltrated our daily language and perceptions,

and significantly altered our views of pregnancy and antenatal care.

Page 222: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

222

‘Risk’ in the Context of Antenatal Care

Risk assessments increasingly permeate various aspects of our daily lives, choices,

and perceptions, including those choices relating to health care generally and

antenatal care specifically (Helen, 2002; Olin Lauritzen & Sachs, 2001). Indeed, on

reviewing the incidence of the term ‘risk’ over a 24 year period in medical journals,

Skolbekken (1995) concluded that we are indeed in the midst of a ‘risk epidemic’

which is both prevalent and contagious. Drawing on the work of Armstrong (1995)

and de Swann (1990), Olin-Lauritzen and Sachs (2001, p.499) track the 20th century

emergence of ‘surveillance medicine’, from which the ‘not yet patient’ category of

illness emerged. In positioning the previously healthy person as a ‘patient in

waiting’, attention has increasingly turned to identifying and quantifying the various

risk factors that may forecast the likelihood of illness occurring. These forecasts

inherently promise prediction and thus control. Consequently, the previously distinct

categories of ‘healthy’ or ‘unhealthy’ have become blurred and we are increasingly

invited to regard ourselves and others, not as ‘well’, but rather ‘potentially unwell’

and thus in need of scrutiny and surveillance86F

87,87F

88. The ‘dragnet’ effect, which pre-

emptively regards everyone as potentially under threat, has significantly seeped into

the discourse and protocols of antenatal care as described below,

‘Intended to benefit everyone equally, the dragnet treats all pregnancies as

potentially pathological and needy, drawing pregnant women into anxious

dependence on expert medical risk management’ (Alderson, Williams, &

Farsides, 2004, p.75).

Not surprisingly, the negative language of risk, anomaly and defect that now

intrudes into pregnancy care has created considerable anxiety in women (Anderson,

1999; Lippman, 1991). Even use of the word ‘risk’, which means ‘the possibility of

suffering, harm or loss’ 88F

89, conveys a strong message of impending crisis. Thus

‘risk’ is not a neutral concept, but one that contains ideological messages which

87 Abby Lippmann (1991, 1999) further argues that surging interest in genetics will simply exacerbate this established trend, leading to what she describes as ‘geneticisation’. 88 This view is also claimed to be instrumental in the rise of ‘worried well’. See for example Bates, (2007) and McCredie, (2007). 89 Microsoft, 1999.

Page 223: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

223

have become ingrained into the contextual and narrative features of the information

given to women, features which immediately raise concern and doubt.

When the negative language of risk is contrasted against the positive expectations

of improved prognosis, promises of better medical management, and maximised

outcomes for mother and child, involvement in screening appears an obvious route

to follow (Lippman, 1991). Conventionally, mothers over 35 years old89F

90 have been

targeted automatically as ‘high risk’, an arbitrary cut off point determined as the

point at which the numerical risk of miscarriage through amniocentesis is equivalent

to the population based statistical chance of having a child with Down syndrome.

However, with the more recent advent and routinisation of the non-invasive nuchal

translucency scan, coupled with the knowledge that most children with disabilities

are born to ‘low’ risk mothers’ younger than 35 years of age, there is a rising chorus

amidst practitioners to lower the bar and encourage all women to undergo predictive

screening, as all are theoretically at some risk (Harris et al., 2004; Kuppermann,

Goldberg, Nease, & Washington, 1999; Kuppermann & Norton, 2005). The

motivation to intensify and expand screening protocols has been embraced in some

quarters of Queensland Health, with all women attending the major tertiary

maternity hospital in Brisbane now being offered nuchal translucency. Increasingly

younger women are being routinely invited to consider their risk status, an invitation

which encourages compliance with ‘risk lowering behaviours’, such as accepting

more testing (Lippmann, 1991, 1999).

Heightened risk awareness with its attendant promise of control is simultaneously

threatening and relieving. Skolbekken (1995) argues that a troubling consequence of

increased surveillance and quantification of risk in health care is that our collective

expectations about the where the locus of control in managing these risks lies has

been fundamentally distorted. He explains:

90 Anecdotally, there seems to be a downward pressure on the age at which a woman is categorised ‘high risk’. Classified by RANZCOG as above 38 years old, accepted clinical practice now defines women over 35 years old as high risk, although some women report younger categorisation, such as Danielle. This potential trend was also recorded by Tankard-Reist, (2005).

Page 224: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

224

‘The risk acceptance that is internalised in a fatalistic attitude to these

matters is being replaced by an ideology whose primary goal is to gain

control over life and death, where the identification of, and the struggle to

reduce/eliminate risk factors have become activities of considerable

importance and prestige within the health profession.’ (Skolbekken, 1995,

p297).

The misplaced trust in our capacity to control nature referred to above by

Skolbekken (ibid) was picked up by one midwife and a general practitioner who

explained:

People don’t accept that it’s just nature……………the fact that nature does some amazing things is all well and good ………… but nature should not make anything wrong with a baby…but…. not only do we want perfect babies, we want perfect birth, and therefore, we want a perfect child. Midwife 2 I think we’ve planted the idea that the more we offer screening and options for women not to have an imperfect baby, the more we reinforce the idea that they should expect a perfect baby………….and there’s no doubt that that’s behind the litigation of obstetricians for every CP child that’s born . We’re adding to this expectation of a perfect baby and a perfect child and people are confronted with this all the way along. Then they get a child with autism or bad asthma, who’s in hospital three times a year, or ADHD, or just has a really difficult personality….I mean we’re all imperfect, there’s just different types of disability. I just think as a profession, doctors are buying into that, not only buying in but really pushing it…women may go through this process and have a baby that doesn’t have Down syndrome at the end ………have the normal baby…..well that’s great, but what if they strike other things done the track………… but I think if someone had every test and everything was fine, then they went and found, what is really a [comparatively] small problem, I think it can unhinge some people…..because they expected a perfect baby……………so that’s one of my concerns about presenting it as routine, of course you’ll have these tests because they’ll produce a perfect baby. General Practitioner 2

Leanne shared the belief that doing ‘all the right things’ within her control afforded

her some power over the health outcomes of her baby,

I think in the back of my mind I knew it was alright. I was going to classes, yoga and stuff…. I knew the baby didn’t have Downs, I knew I wouldn’t have a natural childbirth, I knew I’d have an emergency Caesar, I knew I’d be drugged up, I had a sixth sense, I knew the baby was fine, but then again it was just a control thing. I just wanted to be as reassured because someone has to be the one. And I didn’t want to be. I did all the right things in my pregnancy. Eating properly, going to classes, yoga, aqua stuff and all that. Leanne

Realistically, as expressed by the two practitioners above, much of health care lies

beyond our control. Certainly there are instances where the ability to control risk

factors may contribute to preventative medicine with its protective benefits in some

Page 225: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

225

realms, such as coronary care, for example, where ‘high risk’ individual behaviours

such as smoking or diet are identified as impacting on the likelihood of disease. In

that case a person has some influence or choice over whether they continue to smoke

or to adopt a healthy diet, to proactively lower their risk in light of the clearly

documented health risks. However, even that well established population based

probabilistic link will not tell a particular individual what their personal risk is in the

multifactorial matrix of chance.

Additionally, in prenatal screening, the ‘risk’ of abnormality in a foetus is assessed

through prenatal screening after conception, when the genetic mould, and thus health

trajectory, of the child is largely established and unchangeable. While there are other

statistical risk factors in pregnancy associated with the mother such as increased age

(though evidence on paternal age90F

91 is scant and conspicuously absent from such

calculations), diet, substance abuse, folic acid intake, or exposure to teratogenic

substances, for women, the most commonly cited risk of having a child with a

disability is that of age, something over which a woman has no control by the time

they are pregnant. Hence, for these women, the only way to moderate or quantify

their individual risk status, for what it is worth, is by engaging in the pre-approved

screening provided. Age was cited as a factor by several mothers. Terri, who

described herself as ‘over the hill’ at 38 years old explained,

I guess because I was a bit older, there were questions asked and it was almost assumed that there were certain things I should do. I was asked quite a few times whether I wanted these tests done. I guess being older, I was 38, because I had gone over the 35 ‘hill’, over the hill [laughs], a lot of the doctors and nurses who saw me were saying ‘what sort of tests would you like - we need to be careful.’ Terri

Danielle whose ‘advanced maternal age’ of 31 was given as a risk factor described:

He started saying things like because of my age…..I was over 30 [Danielle was 31], that was another indicator of high risk...…I just didn’t expect that there would be anything wrong…..I had two previous uneventful pregnancies and it wasn’t as though I was 38 or 39………….I was relatively young……..to be having my third child……….I never felt that I should feel at risk……………..Danielle

91 Yang et al, (2007, p.696) conclude that ‘advanced paternal age was associated with increased risks of heart defects, tracheo-oesophageal fistulaoesophageal atresia, other musculoskeletal/integumental anomalies, Down's syndrome and other chromosomal anomalies.’

Page 226: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

226

Finally Mary, who at 29 had not considered the possibility of finding herself in the

‘high risk’ category recalled: Before the test we had never even discussed it hadn’t even entered our minds……………it didn’t occur to us that we could be in this group where something could be wrong……..and hadn’t even crossed my mind………Mary

One General Practitioner, who was also an ‘older’ mother, discussed her feelings of

being subject to the heightened presumptions of risk for the over 35 year olds. Even

armed with her considerable medical knowledge, she made the telling remark,

There’s so much more press about it out there now, and particularly, I can tell you as a mother who had gone through two pregnancies as a mother over 37 for one of them, there’s a lot said about it and it almost………………It almost feels like it’s inevitable if your older. I was 38, almost 39 with [daughter]; it almost feels inevitable that you’ll have a baby with Down syndrome from all the stuff you hear. General Practitioner 2

However, these risk factors referred to throughout these conversations, presented

unproblematically as numbers and ratios are determined on abstracted, population

based statistical analysis which have little predictive impact or relevance for the

individual person per se, a point articulated by West and Bramwell (2006, p.62):

‘If we accept the premise that identification of these foetal anomalies is

desirable, then screening can be seen to have benefits at a population level.

However, this is not the same as having benefit for individual mothers and

families’.

Yet, there is an abundance of research suggesting that this preferred mode of

communicating risk in health care is not well understood by either patients or

practitioners (Heyman et al., 2006), and its presumed relevance to the individual

may be grossly overvalued. It is to the problematics of ‘probabilisation’ in the risk

discourse of health care that we will now turn.

Probability and Risk Perception

Prenatal screening results are typically communicated in terms of population based

statistical probabilities and ratios, presented as ‘risk factors’ using a statistical

language which presumes an ‘abstract mathematical universe’ (West & Bramwell,

Page 227: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

227

2006, p.65). However, the quantification of risk factors requires first that we define

‘normal’ in advance, as Olin-Lauritzen and Sachs (2001, p.513) explain:

‘A system of figures and values forms a pattern of normality for the body. If

you can decide in advance what is normal and expected then you can

normalise, and through that, also exert power’.

In defining normality, the boundaries and limits of abnormality are also defined.

Hence, population-based norms are set against which individuals may be similarly

measured and compared in a self perpetuating system which flows logically from the

premise of surveillance medicine (Heyman et al., 2006; Olin Lauritzen & Sachs,

2001, p.513). The social construction of risk is intimately bound to the preferred and

available tools of mathematical and statistical modelling, the same tools which then

probabilise and pathologise individual patients. Consequently, risks that cannot be

quantified in the culturally sanctioned way remain unspoken (West & Bramwell,

2006), resulting in selective exposure only to those risks that can be measured

(Liamputtong, Halliday, Warren, Watson, & Bell, 2003). Hence, the risk concerns

raised apply to a limited smorgasbord of potentialities.

As risk factors are based on broad population data, their significance when

extrapolated to the individual is unclear as Olin Lauritzen and Sachs (2001, p.498)

explain:

‘as risk is calculated on an aggregate level and belongs to the world of

probability, transformation of risk appraisals to the level of the individual

and the understanding of one’s own health is, of necessity, difficult’.

While clinicians routinely and unproblematically present the concept of risk as a

population-based number, Getz (2003, p. 2052) points out, ‘to the individual

pregnant woman, the population base is one, and a risk of one in one hundred

means she can be the one’. The crucial piece of information that no risk factor can

ever determine, and a theme that reverberated strongly through the accounts offered

Page 228: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

228

by this cohort of mothers, is whether ‘I’ am, indeed, that one. As Shelford candidly

notes in reflecting on her own experience with cancer:

‘The information that I want is not that 1 in 10 patients will benefit, but

whether I am that one. As that information is unavailable, the evidence

seems to be meaningless to me as an individual, while obviously being

helpful on a population basis to determine best practice’ (Shelford, 2003,

p.757).

Within the mothers’ cohort Leanne’s narrative strongly centred on the theme of

being ‘the one’. Although her age adjusted risk from nuchal translucency was a low

1:1500, the prospect that she could be ‘the one’ extensively shaped her attitudes and

choices with respect to the screening she pursued. Highlighting the individual focus

of such risk factors, the problematic number for Leanne was not the 1500, but rather

the 1. Shelford (2003, p.757) continues her challenge of risk directed medicine

suggesting that statistical modelling has eroded the quality of the particular patient

care, further musing ‘whether we haven’t all been bamboozled in to believing that

statistics and evidence are really relevant in our care of the individual

patient’(ibid). Perhaps, as West and Bramwell (2006, p.64) suggest, people more

realistically approach such decisions on a 50-50 basis, in that they either do, or do

not, have the condition in question, challenging the presumption that people act

rationally upon the mathematical constructs before them. Calman (2002, p.161) also

questions the role of probability in decision making, noting that if rationality based,

quantified, probabilistic risk factors played any role in shaping behaviour, 25% of

the United Kingdom’s population would not continue to smoke. Clearly, rationality,

ratios, and statistics alone do not fully dictate individual risk perception.

The probabilistic language of screening is largely foreign to patients, and there is

strong evidence to suggest that practitioners, too, struggle with the clinical meaning

of these abstract statistical concepts as applied to individual patient care, often

displaying poor understanding of probability and commonly overestimating risk

(Ghosh, 2004). Furthermore, the inherently ‘elastic’ quality and language of risk

makes the task of communication complex and fraught as individuals may interpret

Page 229: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

229

identical numbers in different ways (Edwards, Elwyn, Unigwe, & Hood, 2003).

Confusion about risk and varying perceptions were certainly evident amongst this

group of mothers:

When they said the risk was what it was, we weren’t particularly perturbed….we went, oh well, 1:74 that’s not so bad…… and then they told us what the ‘normal’ risk was, and we thought OK, it is a little bit of a concern……..Penny

Similarly Terri explained, I had a 1:500 chance of having a baby with Down syndrome….It was presented as high risk; definitely, they said “it’s a high risk”. I had 3 separate doctors ring me from XX hospital, I believe they were registrars, I had never spoken to any of them before, and they all said that to me………Terri

Although the population-based statistical risk of having a child with Down

syndrome at Terri’s age of 38 years old is 1:190 91F

92, and Terri’s relative risk had

significantly decreased to 1:500, she was still categorised as high risk, and felt a

sense of urgency, pressure, anxiety and pending doom. Surprised to find herself in a

high risk category, Terri continued:

In the past I had never considered it. I think because all the medical professional people were saying you need to this and that, it was really brought to the fore…… I would never even have thought of that……Terri

The complexities of conveying these statistical nuances, which are selectively

interpreted, make the task of risk communication fraught with difficulty. Yet as

Helen (2002, p.126) suggest, the risk discourse in pregnancy may invite practitioners

to distance themselves to the ‘technical’ realm only, unfairly placing the whole

ethical burden on the mother. The following practitioner comments convey the

difficulties of risk communication,

[E: Do you think women have a good understanding of risk?] No, no… no…..Not at all. …………..particularly if we find a risk that we consider to be high……………Midwife 2

An objective view of risk is difficult for any person to perceive and it is in fact the subjective view that matters and guides patient choice – is it high risk for them? ….. Obviously with any scan, any variance of normal will make a person anxious, absolutely and I certainly think that it’s the variants of normal that are actually normal that create the greatest anxiety. ….I think it depends on the degree of the abnormality as to the amount of anxiety that gets created…but it is certainly I think, it is almost certainly a shock to a person to find any abnormality, instead of the other way around which would be more realistic. Obstetrician

92 http://www.wolfson.qmul.ac.uk/epm/screening/calcrisk.shtml. Accessed 14th Feb, 2006.

Page 230: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

230

Probably what the risk means is a bit confusing, because what they know, why they’re having the scan, the risk 1:60 or 1:900 can mean different things to different people….we’ve had women who have had a risk of 1:600 who say, oh my goodness that’s very high I want to have an amniocentesis……….and others with a risk of 1:12 saying, well I have an 11:12 chance of being OK……..so, it vastly depends on how that woman perceives that risk. Midwife 1

While the following genetic counsellor adopted sound educational strategies in

conveying risk, her observation that shock may affect capacity to understand, and

her acknowledgement that this unfamiliar, and, for some, difficult information may

take several visits and considerable time to sink in, further reinforces that routine

and immediate screening is ethically and educationally inappropriate.

Risk is the perspective of what someone perceives as high risk or low risk …. We use numbers and words……..such as there’s a 1:200 chance that this pregnancy will discontinue because of CVS or amnio, the miscarriage risk – how do you perceive that, is it high or low?......so there’s 199 chances in 200 that there won’t be a problem…we look at both sides of it…….so we put it as a population risk, this risk, how do they feel, etc, we use numbers and words and ask them to express how they perceive the risk….is it a high number or low number for them……[but]….they are usually so anxious and frightened, shocked so their understanding is probably pretty low….. I think they need to have graphics or visual imagery as well as words and I think they need to think about it over a few days and they need to have their partner with them and they may need to hear it a couple of times…. Genetic Counsellor 1

The other genetic counsellor remarked:

I think it’s really hard to prepare people because that grey area will be different for different people….a lot of the time…….there’s no doubt it creates a lot of anxiety ….there are a few examples in my head where someone got a result of 1:250 which isn’t low officially, it’s just within the high risk category….it may actually not be a terrible risk when you break down the nitty gritty of the figures……….and it depends what risk they’ve had before…there are some people who will look at that and feel massive anxiety…………but because the risk of the next option is roughly equivalent, that’s a very difficult decision and for some people they can hardly make that decision…it’s so hard ….its too hard …………..and I don’t know if you can ever really prepare people for that……Genetic Counsellor 2.

Liamputtong et al’s (2003) study exploring why women rejected screening revealed

that the subjective perceptions of risk held by women often differed from those held

by health care professionals. Women weighted the risk of anxiety more heavily than

their practitioners did (ibid, p.101). Conflicting representations of what constitutes a

‘risk’ further complicated interpretation of risk for mothers and practitioners. For

example, the risk for a woman over thirty five years old of having a child with

Page 231: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

231

Down syndrome is 1 in 38092F

93 , presented by practitioners as ‘high risk’. However,

the risk of miscarriage while undergoing amniocentesis to diagnose this condition is

1 in 200 (Alfirevic, 2003), a numerically higher risk, but one that is presented as a

‘low risk’ procedure. For women trying to grapple with these concepts, the

malleable and selective interpretations of ‘risk’, often coupled with poor scientific or

health literacy in general (Kendig, 2006), may present a barrier to forming secure

understandings.

Risk interpretation is further influenced by how undesirable the particular outcome

is perceived, with expectations of future burden varying widely (Edwards et al.,

2003). Thus, perceptions of what life with a disability entails lie at the heart of risk

perception. Some women on receiving a diagnosis of Down syndrome in their child

felt relieved that this was a condition compatible with life, in which their child could

lead a relatively meaningful, though supported life (Bridle, 2004). Others, such as

the couple described earlier by one midwife, on receiving a diagnosis of cleft palate

which may be viewed as a more minor disability, and one of the few ‘fixable’

conditions detected with no intellectual impairment, elect termination. Clearly

differing interpretations of social desirability influence how such risk factors are

constructed.

Lack of scientific or mathematical literacy was raised by several practitioners as a

contributory factor in the low levels of risk understandings displayed. In addition to

the poor knowledge of the critical clinical difference between ‘screening’ and

‘diagnosing’, a lack of familiarity with medical terminologies, and a fragile grasp of

the statistical concept and language of risk, also came into play as the following

practitioners explain:

Even those words….. ‘nuchal translucency’ is not something that’s been around for a long time, there’s not a lot of knowledge, and it’s not something their mothers can tell them about, because they didn’t have it. Amongst their peers, if they know anyone who’s recently been pregnant, they might find information about what is involved. Clinical Geneticist Often the information comes as a shock so they can’t really deal with it - they don’t understand too much unless it’s a lethal condition and the baby, it’s just a matter of time

93 http://www.wolfson.qmul.ac.uk/epm/screening/calcrisk.shtml

Page 232: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

232

before the baby will die, they tend to understand, like black and white. The subtleties are often lost. Genetic Counsellor 1 [Risk] ….it’s certainly not something that everyone understands …not at all……without really sitting down with them , I think it may get brushed over and assumed that a person had …….but it is hard, ….if it’s high you might throw in the risk of miscarriage and there’s just figures flying at them…it’s not easy. Genetic Counsellor 2

While the vocabulary used by the following GP in explaining risk was perhaps

intentionally chosen to convey an expert level of clinical competency to an

interested researcher, if such language was used in a clinical consultation, this too

could become a potentially alienating and isolating barrier for the uninitiated. I would, in broad terms, discuss the validity matrices that are used, the combination of both imaging and serology being used to form a matrix. I would discuss the fact that these are predictive in nature but not conclusive… General Practitioner 1

Confusion about risk was apparent in Leanne’s account, although, perhaps, she paid

scant attention to the details knowing she would pursue all available testing

regardless: After the 12 week scan the odds came back at 1:1200 or 1:1500. The obstetrician was like well, why do you want to have it done and I said it’s because of my colleague; she was ‘that one’. Then she said OK if that’s what you want we’ll have it done. I think it was 1:1500; the odds went up [after amniocentesis] to 1:3000. [E: So before amniocentesis they were lower?] Yes [E: What were they before?] 1:1500….. Then they went up to 1:3000 [E: So they were 1:1500, then they went to 1:3000] Yes [E: So that is actually a lower risk, the risk went down?] Yes [surprised]… I suppose it is …..But then….. I knew that someone has to be ‘the one’ ……and I didn’t want to be. Leanne

Later in the interview Leanne described herself as ‘a statistics person’, I’m more a statistics person so once I had the numbers, once I knew the averages ….yeah………I’m a statistics person….. Which when you think about that now you could ask why wasn’t I happy with the 1:3000? But the argument is…… I know ‘the one’.

Page 233: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

233

In conclusion, presenting risk as a reductionist, probabilistic, and purely numerical

decision is ultimately inappropriate, because as Olin-Lauritzen and Sachs (2001)

note, while the concept of risk is linear, bodies are complex and multifactorial, never

linear. Linear concepts, such as statistical risk, are therefore an inappropriate

platform from which to assess individual health threat as they fail to capture the

subjective notions of desirability that frame risk perception. As population based

measures, the relevance of retrospectively calculated, statistical risk ratios to the

individual is challenged by West and Bramwell (2006, p.61) who conclude that:

‘The implications may be that probabilistic screening information does not

provide useable information and, therefore, does not promote informed

choice. Tests may also fail to offer reassurance, or offer false reassurance’.

While the relevance of such data at a population level is clearly important in terms

of resource planning and predicting community health trends, their significance to

the individual seems overstated, although currently the presumed social benefits

have eclipsed and taken precedence over the individual (Heyman et al., 2006,

p.2370). Additionally, probability is such a poorly understood, poorly conveyed, and

reductionist concept that its persistent incorporation into health communication is

puzzling (ibid). Yet, the commonly proffered concept of risk as a function of logic

and mathematics continues to dominate medical conversation, rather than being one

part of multiple relevant considerations. The strong intuitive and emotional

components that play a substantial guiding role in risk assessment are frequently

overlooked (Slovic, Finucane, Peters, & MacGregor, 2004). However, if we desire

to manage risk effectively, the rationalist view needs to be tempered and softened

(ibid). Runciman (2002, p.113) explains:

‘This is the problem that faces anyone who tries to rationalise and re-order

our responses to risk: the quality of the danger always counts for more than

the quantity. We can know all the figures in the world, have them neatly set

out for us on easy–to–read labels, but everything will still depend on the

ways in which we choose to imagine disaster to strike’.

Page 234: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

234

Thus there is a need to inject some ‘proportionality’ into the risk messages conveyed

which ‘underscore[s] the ethical importance to balance the level of fear against the

level of risk’ (Solomon, 2005, p.44).

Anxiety and the Psychological Impact of Risk

‘Risk’ has become a central and inescapable concept in prenatal screening, and once

the spectre of risk is raised, anxiety almost inevitably follows. The personalisation of

risk (‘am I the one?’), superimposed onto the tension between security, insecurity,

reassurance, distress, and the opposing possibilities of vulnerability and control that

screening invokes may create a heightened perception of looming crisis. For many

women it is claimed this tension triggers compliance with testing regimes (Getz &

Kirkengen, 2003; Lippman, 1999a, 1999b). However, as an unquantifiable

emotional response, the anxiety experienced by women is rarely considered

admissible in the logical risk calculations favoured. The consenting process

predominantly focuses on procedural or technical information relating to potential

physical harms (Bernhardt et al., 1998), while the equally ethically relevant

psychological harms of unwarranted anxiety, increased vulnerability, and emotional

wounding, seem commonly overlooked.

That prenatal screening could potentially prompt anxiety in women seems a

predictable outcome, yet, the prospective immediate or ongoing psychological

consequences have received relatively little attention (Kowalcek et al., 2002) and the

limited research that does exist paints a contradictory picture. A number of studies

report generally positive effects ranging from little, no, or reduced anxiety (Kaiser

et al., 2002; Kleinveld et al., 2006; Whynes, 2002), while others note depressive

reactions ranging from short term and mild, to ongoing and extensive anxiety (Goel

et al., 1998; Kowalcek et al., 2002; Watson et al., 2003). Leithner et al (2006,

p.244) make the further observation that the level of anxiety experienced by women

is frequently underestimated by clinical staff.

Of those citing positive effects or no ‘significant’ lasting distress, Kleinveld et al

(2006, p.360) suggests that anxiety is not inevitably a bad thing, but rather an

Page 235: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

235

appropriate and necessary psychological response to an actual threat, and thus

anxiety illustrates an appropriate level of engagement in the process. Whynes (2002)

further reports uncritical and unproblematic acceptance of screening regimes,

restating the potential soothing effect that the reassurance of ‘good’ results from

prenatal screening provides and defending screening as a positive bonding

opportunity for mother and child. As background levels of anxiety may be

heightened during pregnancy, some of the authors above present screening primarily

as a positive opportunity to reduce existing anxiety. However, as previously

discussed, any reassurance gleaned may be simply an artefact of screening. It is

certainly not a guaranteed outcome; hence, justification on these grounds alone is

misleading.

Conversely, others have observed that the psychological responses of different

women to the various forms of prenatal screening commonly include ‘considerable

short term anxiety’ (Watson et al., 2003) , acute distress akin to a ‘major depressive

episode’ (Leithner et al., 2006), ‘a depressive reaction’ (Kowalcek et al., 2002), and

‘serious psychological harm’ (Goel et al., 1998). While West and Bramwell (2006,

p.62) were referring specifically to maternal serum screening when they concluded

that ‘information generated by the serum screening test is not information most

people can understand, use to make decisions, or that can alleviate their anxiety’, as

discussed earlier, the commitment to convey risk of all kinds in narrow probabilistic

terms pervades the discourse of all screening, thus, this comment may equally apply

more widely than just the serum screen. While short term anxiety passes for some

(Watson et al., 2003), other studies note a consequential anxiety that may last well

beyond the immediate period of testing with Hall et al (2000) observing negative

psychological effects from a false negative result continuing for up to six years.

Of the mothers in this cohort, a broad spectrum of anxiety levels and responses

were represented. Some, like Penny, disengaged from the risk discourse to alleviate

their anxiety: I think we just fobbed it off to be honest, I don’t remember wondering or pondering if this would be a child with some abnormality…for the rest of the pregnancy…in saying that though [daughter] didn’t move much, so at night I would sit and poke my stomach and say “are you OK in there”, just to get her to wriggle…I don’t think I was thinking about the result…. that had passed……….Penny

Page 236: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

236

Elizabeth proactively rejected screening from the outset and never personalised the

risk predictions. She explained, I had said, no I didn’t want it because I didn’t want a pregnancy that for the next 20 or so weeks where I was told I could be high risk and it turns out to be nothing. She [the physician] was supportive of that, she said, OK, you’ve done your reading. Elizabeth

However, for others, the stress and worry described was still evident and raw up to

two years after the event as Mary describes,

After the high risk result from nuchal translucency was given]…I was a basket case…I didn’t know what to do….who to talk to ….. It had only just been developed, it was only just out there…..and there was really no-one to talk to. [E: Did those doubts still linger after the amnio result was clear?] Yes….they still lingered, but not as heavily…..the doubt didn’t go until he was born. Mary

Contrasting this experience with her first pregnancy four years earlier, Mary

explained how her perceptions of doubt and risk had irrevocably changed,

With [my eldest] it was just, I was pregnant, it was great…………I had the usual scan at 18 weeks, but with the second, it was harder because I had miscarried at 10 weeks with the previous pregnancy, those first 10 weeks were the hardest, and then 2 weeks later they said……..It could be a Downs baby……..we’ll just wait another 5 weeks to find out………..so that was one of the worst pregnancies that I could have endured, in my mind………….The first 12 weeks with my third were sort of “Holy Crap” I’m pregnant again and I’m an idiot……..for me it was “Oh no …I have to go through all this again….all the stress”……I loved that first pregnancy a hell of a lot more……….because there was no stress and no worry……………everything was good………..you’d have an appointment every few weeks, everything was fine and we moved on………there was no doubt…Mary.

Terri became caught in limbo between rejecting further testing on the grounds that it

was ‘too risky’, while still harbouring grave reservations and concerns about the

health and future of her child, describing herself as ‘almost depressed’,

It was very hard for a while, I couldn’t put it out of my mind, but once I got to the end, I was at a stage, like most women , I just wanted it to be over, so there was a period of months where, almost 3 months where I think I was almost depressed….. After I did have him, I was looking at him through the crib, I was in a wheelchair, I was looking from an unusual angle and the crib had distorted his face, and I just thought, “Has no-one else noticed that?” It wasn’t until an hour later when they brought him round that I could see he wasn’t Down syndrome, but yes…………..for an hour I thought …yes…………..in the past I had never considered it. I think because all the medical professional people were saying you need to this and that, it was really brought to the fore……Terri

Similarly, Danielle rejected the risk of further testing, and spent the remainder of her

pregnancy in emotional turmoil, I spent the next 6 months basically not entirely sure………..and even when she was born ….I had seen a lot of babies with syndromes………….I knew when she came out she didn’t look like a syndrome baby………but I still had to check with the paediatrician………it

Page 237: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

237

wasn’t until then that I realised how much it had been worrying me for the last 6 months………………..even although we told ourselves it was probably fine, I was still quite worried………….that was pretty hard…..Danielle

While not all women experience anxiety, and of the seven mothers in this cohort,

Leanne’s proactive pursuit of screening left her positively reassured, Danielle’s

description of the impact of this experience warrants inclusion as it captures her

deep emotional wounding and fracturing experienced after being told of the soft

markers on her child’s ultrasound scan. Danielle further revealed that ‘even now’,

two years after her daughter’s birth, the doubt lingers.

Because ………..the complete sadness of it………..it was like mourning………having a grieving period for a baby that was inside you …….growing…… but you didn’t ………….[sighs]…………I guess just that loss of control and loss of hope that you have……………..for 18 weeks it had been a joyful period………and then suddenly it’s put to a screeching halt it was just……………it was just horrendous………….I wouldn’t wish it on anybody…………….no sleep……….I couldn’t concentrate, couldn’t focus…on anything……it was really terrible…………I was just………just ………yeah……………it completely shuts you down…………you have no control over it………………..for us ….we were facing the completely hideous decision of aborting this baby or even worse…………………or having a baby with Down syndrome and looking at the ramifications for that child and for our existing children………….for the rest of our lives……………….or just wait till she was born and deal with it then…………Even now I look at her sometimes and I think I wonder if there’s a lag over problem………not that she’s developmentally delayed in any way………but that’s still in the back of your mind…………….I don’t worry about it, its just a niggle that’s there…………it was just hideous………….horrible, horrible , horrible………..[sighs]…

[E: Can you talk about the joyfulness of your pregnancy?] [pause]……...it…….disappeared,……..just…….disappeared,…………completely disappeared…………………………….I wouldn’t say it never returned……but from then on it was certainly tinged with …………..not sadness…………but fear and uncertainty…………that in my mind……………..my husband says that when we left that surgery, the impression was that the obstetrician had said it was 100% sure everything was fine, but in my mind, I left that surgery with him saying unless you do amnio I can’t be 100%, but I’m pretty sure……….like 98%....................and for me that 2 % was like………phew……….should I do the amnio………but I wasn’t going to do it……..yeah……………………it was still a joy to be having the baby……….it was an event that we had joyful anticipation for…………but certainly it was from then on it was tinged with worry and fear………that something was wrong. I was a lot less blasé, any differences I would be very concerned about….Danielle

Perhaps surprisingly, Kowalcek et al (2002) concluded that the depth of stress

experienced was not related to the invasiveness of the procedure, and that indeed,

those undergoing a non-invasive ultrasound had higher depression levels than those

undergoing invasive amniocentesis or CVS. Leithner et al (2006, p.245) similarly

Page 238: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

238

noted that regardless of the invasiveness of the test, or the confirmed presence of a

fetal anomaly, all women suffered ‘acute distress’,

‘we found that all women in our sample experienced acute distress, not only

those with proven fetal malformations, genetic disorders or intrauterine fetal

death, but also those referred with the diagnosis of a sonographic sign.

Given the fact that ultrasound is not associated with a painful experience or

the possibility of fetal damage, we assume that the perceived stress derives

from the fear of an adverse diagnosis and its consequences’.

As the tacit and unconscious possibility of anomaly becomes an intrusive and

stressful probability, the unspoken fears come to the foreground creating the

depressive moods observed in women prior to undergoing prenatal testing

(Kowalcek et al., 2002).

Given the multitude of factors that determine risk interpretation, prediction of how

different women respond to ‘risk’ is highly fluid and thus notoriously difficult to pin

down. Risk perception, and the subsequent anxiety that flows from it, is contingent

upon each individual’s unique life experience, and thus varies with time, culture,

history and the contextual realities of each woman’s life (Rapp, 2000). Perceptions

are subjective, moulded by the particular context at a particular point in time, and

particular previous experience as Anne remarked:

I think another part of that was that in my experience, I had had a child with an abnormality, so realising how real that can be, if you have never experienced that, you may think well that’s a world away, that doesn’t touch me, but when you’ve experienced it you realise that It can touch you, it can touch anyone, nobody is buffeted from that ……it’s a real part of life, a real part of having children. Anne

As noted previously by Liamputtong (2003, p.101), women’s perception of risk may

vary from their practitioners. Additionally, the risk perceptions of practitioners may

be significantly skewed working in a tertiary care hospital specialising in birth

anomalies in which the prevalence, immediacy, and likelihood of such an outcome

may become exaggerated. However, physicians must balance their professional and

legal obligation to inform about remote but potentially serious outcomes, while not

unduly causing needless anxiety or giving false reassurance. Perhaps, the final word

Page 239: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

239

on risk, anxiety, and harm belongs to Terri who recognised the vulnerability of her

situation, and implored that more gentle and considered approaches be taken with

women in this potentially susceptible place. Pregnancy, well it’s a vulnerable time, and this pregnancy was vulnerable for me, I’m sure there are lots of women in the same boat…. We really need to tread more lightly. Terri

Yet as Hoffmaster (2006, p.41) laments, ‘vulnerability doesn’t mean much to

morality because, in part it is missing from moral philosophy, yet it is our very

vulnerability that creates the need for morality’. Attending to the moral and ethical

dimensions of prenatal screening within a vulnerable population thus demands more

than calculating and dispensing numerical risk information (Helen, 2002; Olin

Lauritzen & Sachs, 2001).

Chapter Summary

The personal constraints impacting upon personal behaviour and capacity to exercise

informed choice include the need to be reassured, often articulated as the ‘desire to

know’. Such motivations reveal a presumption that there is something valuable to

know, that all knowledge is valuable, and that such knowledge can be readily

accessed through the culturally sanctioned practice of prenatal screening. Most of

the women and many of the practitioners of this cohort cited the desire for

reassurance as the most common motivating factor driving the increasing use of

prenatal screening. However, need to be reassured is prefigured by an existing

anxiety; a heightened level of risk awareness that Lippman (1991) argued was

largely created by the prospect of testing itself. The negative language of risk and

presumptions of anomaly that frame the offer to test may create, therefore, a self-

perpetuating dynamic of intervention.

Further evidence exists in the literature that statistical measures of probability and

individual risk in which such offers are framed are generally poorly understood by

patients, while the presumed relevance of population based figures to the individual

are overstated. While such statistical representations may be meaningful for

population-based health management, they do not assist the individual woman in

answering the critical question to her of whether she is that ‘one’. The inability to

Page 240: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

240

make meaning of these ratios and probabilities thus represents a personal constraint

to the giving of informed consent. The increased levels of anxiety expressed by

several members of the mothers’ cohort illustrate the harmful and ongoing

psychological impact of risk. These (largely avoidable) harms, many of which flow

from lack of understanding as a consequence of ill-informedness, or under-

informedness represent ethical harms, harms which may be minimised through

reflecting upon the shortcomings of currently accepted protocols and transforming

practice to support women’s ethical decision making.

The three chapters of the following section will explore potential areas of

transformation and highlight future areas of research.

Page 241: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

241

SECTION C

TRANSFORMING PRACTICE: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL

CHOICES

The fourth, and final, stage of this research explores the critical role of educational

experiences and the conditions of learning necessary in promoting the ethical

standard of informed consent, above the minimal legal requirement of information

disclosure. These will be considered in Chapter Nine. The development of context

appropriate, andragogically and ontologically sound responses to the learning

process emerge from an awareness of educational philosophy and practice. It is these

critical educational precursors which support the necessary knowledge development

required to give ‘informed’ consent where transformational possibilities lie.

Recognising the intertwined nature of individual agency within institutional

frameworks and norms, Chapter Ten continues the theme of transformation,

considering the joint transformation of institutions and the individuals who function

within them. Chapter Eleven provides a summary of the outcomes of this research

and makes some suggestions for future areas of inquiry.

Page 242: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

242

CHAPTER 9

PATIENT EDUCATION IN CLINICAL CARE

Introduction

The preceding Section highlighted that the poor levels of informed consent observed

in studies overseas were likewise apparent in the accounts of at least five, and

possibly six, of the seven mothers interviewed for this study. Additionally, the

observations made by practitioners further suggests that low levels of understanding

and informed consent are a common scenario for women undergoing prenatal

screening in their clinical care. Numerous philosophical, institutional, social, and

personal constraints were identified in this research in line with the research

outcomes noted elsewhere. Additional factors revealed which are specific to the

local context included the segmented service delivery models of care which create

blurred accountability for ‘informing’ amongst practitioners coupled with the

particular legal ramifications of termination in Queensland which hinder

transparency in practice and infiltrate policy. Ineffective data collection and analysis

further inhibit evidence-based reflections on protocols of care. Collectively, these

factors may exert a significant impact upon practitioner and patient capacity to

jointly achieve the necessary levels of reflective understanding prior to screening

required by ethically robust informed consent.

If the experiences of this cohort are typical, and this may be determined by further

research, there is potential scope for local improvement in how women and their

carers are supported in achieving the ethical standard and safeguard of informed

consent. While many of these factors are firmly embedded in the wider social,

technical, and cultural context of prenatal screening as explored in Section B,

collectively, the experiences of this cohort suggest a failure of educational processes

prior to testing. The lack of prior education expressed by the participants of this

study was also prevalent in the existing literature. Therefore, an area of potential

transformation may be that of strengthening clinical approaches to patient and

practitioner education.

Page 243: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

243

As previously suggested, the crucial ethical difference between consent and

‘informed’ consent is the incorporation of some form of education or learning

opportunity, with the transfer and construction of the appropriate knowledge and

understanding prior to accepting any medical intervention. ‘Informed consent’ is

thus ideally given from a position of understanding after careful reflection and

deliberation of the central facts relevant to each individual. Thus, the moral integrity

of informed consent in clinical care is inextricably linked to patient education.

Accordingly, a vital ethical requirement of the patient-health carer relationship is

one of a mutual teaching and learning partnership, in addition to the obvious

therapeutic partnership. However, current patient education protocols show little

awareness, and incorporation, of established learning theory or practice, and do not

explicitly acknowledge the ethical importance of patient education.

An important way to support informed consent would be, therefore, to incorporate

the critical insights and understandings offered by educational theory and

philosophy into the informed consent process in clinical care. With this fundamental

link between ethical practice and patient education in mind, it is helpful to explore

some foundational insights offered by educational theory, research, and practice

before discussing how these insights may be incorporated into clinical care. While

these insights will be applied in the context of prenatal screening, the ethical

importance of patient education is relevant across all forms of medical intervention.

Hence, the educational insights offered in this chapter may apply widely beyond the

narrow context considered here.

From Information to Understanding: the Bridge of Learning

‘Where is the wisdom we have lost in knowledge?

Where is the knowledge we have lost in information?’

(Elliot, 1962, p.107)

As the gaining of knowledge is crucial to becoming ‘informed’, a change in strategy

that acknowledges the ethical importance of patient education and incorporates a

transformative learning experience into current clinical practice regimes may

Page 244: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

244

provide a successful vector for change. The insightful observation by T.S. Elliot

(ibid) above suggests the need to move beyond the mere delivery of ‘information’,

to foster the ethically required knowledge, understanding and, perhaps, wisdom. In

recent decades educationalists have moved beyond stimulus-response, transmissive

or ‘mechanistic’ models of learning towards a more holistic, interactive, and

responsive model of ‘learner centred’ education. Knowles, Holton and Swanson

(1998, p.35) contend that this shift is not new, rather it reflects an approach to

learning as a ‘process of mental inquiry, not passive reception of transmitted

content’, anchored to a pre-modern view of education as practised by revered

teachers of ancient times such as Confucius, Jesus, Aristotle, Socrates and Plato

(ibid).

When applied to the human condition, Reese and Overton (1970) further claim that

the more appropriate holistic view recognises the interactive, interconnected,

evolving and ongoing nature of learning, a process which may not necessarily

progress in a sequential or ‘logical’ manner. This view is further echoed by Bruner

(1991, p.2), who notes,

‘Knowledge growth is not uni-linear or derivational in a logical sense;

mastery of one task does not assure mastery of other tasks that in a formal

sense are governed by the same principles. Knowledge and skill, rather, are

domain specific and, consequently, uneven in their accretion. Principles and

procedures acquired in one domain do not automatically transfer to other

domains’ (Bruner, 1991, p.2) .

Along such a circular, or spiralling, pathway learners revisit prior beliefs,

incorporate past presumptions, and intentionally filter in or out specific information,

often in conflict with the presumed rational importance that such information

represents to others (Bruner, 1991; Reese & Overton, 1970). In the context of

prenatal screening, the presumption that the presence of disability in a foetus is

critical information to be tenaciously pursued, or that the quantification and

disclosure of risk factors is universally meaningful, are clearly not shared by all

parents, as illustrated earlier. Some of the women in this study experienced intense

Page 245: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

245

pressure, incredulity, or disbelief from practitioners and peers when they expressed

an unwillingness to conform to the expected logical norm, or to accept the presumed

values of their practitioners. The consequence for them was often one of deep

alienation, anger and distress93F

94. A holistic educational orientation embraces the

reality of multiple interpretive and possibly contradictory, layers of embeddedness,

and therefore sits comfortably beside the phenomenological and feminist accounts of

ontology as articulated in Chapter Two. This more responsive educational

framework further resonates with the philosophical orientation of this work.

Furthermore, the holistic and embedded stance recognises that learning, like ethics,

is significantly a social rather than technical process, one which is socially,

culturally, and historically situated (Biggs & Telfer, 1987; Gage & Berliner, 1991;

Knowles, Holton, & Swanson, 2005; Mezirow, 1996).

In the educational literature, learning is widely accepted as a fluid, interconnected,

and multi-step process embedded in time and inextricably linked to previous

learning experiences and existing interpretive filters (Bruner, 1991; Gage &

Berliner, 1991; Knowles, 1990; Knowles et al., 2005; Mezirow, 1991, 1996). The

information-processing model (Figure.2) of learning provides a useful framework

for understanding the key components of learning. These are:-

• paying attention to stimulus or events

• filtering through existing interpretive perception filters

• committing to memory (deep learning), and finally ,

• retrieval of stored knowledge from long term memory

94 See Chapter seven for a fuller exploration of this point.

Page 246: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

246

Fig.2. Information Processing Model (Adapted from Gage & Berliner, 1991, p.281).

As illustrated in the Information Processing Model, learning is an ongoing process

of refinement and feedback, rather than an episodic event. The administrative event

approach to ‘consenting’ patients has been stridently criticised by Wear (1998), who

argues that the treatment of consent as a minimalist, administrative event rather than

an ongoing and dynamic relational process, has created a major obstacle to realising

the ethical intentions of informed consent. As Wear (1998, p.96) remarks,

‘No one-shot event can be expected to have much success in pursuing such

goals [of actual understanding]……. A process model can verify and

strengthen what an event model cannot’.

When the role of knowledge building or learning is recognised as intrinsic to

‘informed’ consent, it becomes apparent that informed consent must inevitably be

recognised as ongoing since the very nature of knowledge construction upon which

its ethical credentials rest are inseparably bound to an ongoing and dynamic

educational process linking past, present, and future knowledge. Furthermore, within

the context of prenatal screening ethical decisions are made over time as a person

undergoes changes in their emotional, physical, and knowledge status (Press &

Page 247: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

247

Browner, 1995; Woods & Barrow, 1975). Hence, there is a strong need to open

educationally reflective spaces within institutional frameworks that support ongoing

meaningful dialogue. Significantly, these educational spaces may also be regarded

as open moral spaces (Walker, 1993) where the values, beliefs, and judgements that

guide patient and practitioner behaviour may be subject to critical reflection.

Exploring Adult Learning

The acceptance of education as an embedded and holistic process linked to prior

learning has significantly replaced the outmoded transmissive, episodic, or

compartmentalised view of learning (Daloz, 1986; Gage & Berliner, 1991; Knowles

et al., 2005; Mezirow, 1996). Thus incorporating these critical educational insights

into clinical care could significantly support the realisation of informed consent. A

vital characteristic of patient learning in the context of antenatal care is that all the

participants (patients and practitioners) are adult learners. Much has been written in

the past few decades about the unique features of adult learning. While some

controversy remains as to whether adult learning is significantly different from child

learning, and many commonalities on the continuum of ‘learner centred’ education

are apparent, it is generally accepted that developmental differences, capacities, and

expectations between adults and children do exist (Knowles et al., 2005; O'Brien,

2004; Russell, 2006; Taylor, 1996). These differences would seem to call for

tailored educational strategies.

Perhaps the three most influential scholars writing in the field of adult education are

Malcolm Knowles (1970, 1984, 1989, 1990, 2005) who developed the Adult

Learning Theory drawing on the critical differentiation between andragogy (adult

education) and pedagogy (child education); Jack Mezirow (1991, 1996, 1997, 2000)

who developed the Transformational Learning Theory; and finally Paulo Freire

(1985, 1990, 1993) who proposed the Critical Social Theory which explores the

central role of education and critical reflection in social transformation.

Considering each of these in turn, for Paolo Freire, education is the key to

awakening the critical consciousness to effect social transformation through

Page 248: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

248

promoting equity and redressing the oppressive elements in society (Freire, 1985).

Thus the focus of Freire’s writing in adult education is informed by the desire to

effect broad societal reform within dominating hierarchical social structures. Such a

framework for understanding adult education thus lies beyond the immediate focus

of this research which is concerned with the clinical education of patients for the

purpose of giving informed consent. While Freire’s work is influential and

insightful, more fitting frameworks exist to respond to the immediate questions of

this project.

The Transformational Learning Theory of Mezirow (1991, 1996, 1997) rejects the

objectivist (detached) paradigm of learning (Mezirow, 1996, p.159) and proposes a

interpretist paradigm which recognises the embedded, social, cultural, and emotional

aspects of learning. Mezirow further differentiates between instrumental learning

(detached, rational) and communicative learning (looking for meaning),

acknowledging the importance of language and communication in providing an

explanation of how people make meaning of their experiences. The capacity to make

meaning, to reframe and successfully identify and challenge pre-existing

assumptions, lies at the heart of Mezirow’s (1991, 1996, 1997) transformational

framework. Within this framework it is claimed that appropriate education may

encourage each individual to become ‘a more autonomous thinker by learning to

negotiate his or her own values, meanings, and purposes rather than to uncritically

act on those of others’ (Mezirow, 1997, p.11), a goal in line with the aims of this

project. Mezirow further endorses a learner-centred model of education in which

teachers are seen as facilitators rather than authorities.

While Mezirow (1991) claims to have advanced the adult education debate beyond

the distinction of Knowles’s (1970) andragogy vs. pedagogy divide through

strengthening the place of critical reflection in the process of making meaning, the

foundational doctrines and ontological premises of both models are not markedly

different. Both acknowledge the embedded nature of meaning and interpretive

frameworks, both are based on building trust and relationship in a learning

partnership, both promote the establishment of common learning goals, both

acknowledge the influence of prior experiences on new learning, both accommodate

Page 249: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

249

the unique contextual features that shape each encounter, and both advocate the

creation of an environment that nurtures joint collaboration and mutual respect in the

learning process. However, the twelve key propositions Mezirow’s (1996, p.62)

‘emancipatory paradigm’ are not easily transferred into an accessible, practical

educational model within clinical care.

The features which Knowles (1990) claims are specifically characteristics of adult

learning, or andragogy, were substantially defined and developed in the 1970

publication, The Modern Practice of Adult Education (Knowles, 1970). In this work,

clear distinctions between the dominant, child focused ‘pedagogical’ frameworks of

learning and the adult oriented ‘andragogical’ stance were drawn, centred around six

key characteristics of adult learning, characteristics which capture the ontological

coherency and moral significance of education.

For the purposes of this research, we must acknowledge that clinicians in the context

of antenatal care are not seeking to promote Freire’s (1985) broad social reform, nor

are they seeking to transform inherent societal prejudices and inequities. While they

may be seeking to promote informed participation in health care decisions that are in

line with a patient’s individual values and moral frameworks – it is beyond their

brief to transform existing individual interpretive frameworks as proposed by

Mezirow (1996, 1997). Thus, considering the context of this research, Knowles’

Adult Learning model provides the most appropriate and accessible practical

framework for strengthening patient education and understanding in the clinic. For

these reasons, the framework proposed by Knowles will be adopted as a broad

template for educational reform throughout the remainder of this work.

Knowles (1970, 1990) and Knowles et al (2005) argue that pedagogical approaches

to teaching that emerge from consideration of how children learn, promote overly

didactic and transmissive strategies, condemning the learner to a position of

inferiority and submission. As the permissible sources of learning are those which

emanate from the ‘teacher’, pedagogical models limit the knowledge worthy of

pursuit to that which the ‘teacher’ deems as a relevant inclusion. The learning

experiences of the mothers of this cohort certainly reflected an authoritatively

Page 250: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

250

centred, didactic approach in which the ‘expert’ professional often selectively

transmitted the information which they judged to be important. This view was also

evident in several of the practitioners’ comments shared earlier. As noted previously,

exploration of what knowledge is privileged for discussion or inclusion within

clinical conversations remains largely unchallenged, and such a tacit and accepted

part of the background asymmetrical power dynamics that it often escapes

consideration (Sherwin, 1998). Knowles et al (2005) argue that this authoritative and

instructive approach has been alienating to most adult learners as it fails to resonate

with the developmental capacities and the expectations of equality that independent

adults have come to anticipate in other areas of their lives.

Knowles (1990) claims that a further source of alienation for adults under the

pedagogical model is that full responsibility for what is learned, how it is learned,

when it is learned, and on what criteria it will be judged as successful, are placed

firmly in the hands of the teacher. While this locus of control may be more tolerable

in childhood education - although increasingly child centred educational paradigms

are becoming the norm - the developmental stage of independent adulthood makes

these presumptions potentially isolating for adult learners. As the pedagogical model

potentially relegates the learner to a passive and submissive role, Knowles (ibid)

suggests that the inevitable power imbalance created is grossly inappropriate in

fostering the educational partnership sought between competent adults, a view also

proffered by Mezirow (1996). The key differences identified by Knowles et al

(2005, pp.64-69) between andragogy and pedagogy are defined across six

foundational areas that prefigure how learning is approached. They are:

• The need to know

• The learner’s self concept

• The role of experience

• Readiness to learn

• Orientation to learning

• Motivation to learn

Page 251: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

251

While Knowles’s work has been critiqued for its loose definition of ‘adulthood’ (a

poor definition that has hindered consistency in research), for the insistence on

describing andragogy as the intangible ‘art’ as well as the ‘science’ of helping adults

learn, and for the claimed lack of empirical evidence to support the assertion that

andragogy provides a superior approach to adult education (Brown, 2006; Rachal,

2002), similar criticisms may equally be levelled at the other dominant educational

frameworks. Meanwhile, the andragogical lens retains its appeal as Rachel (2002,

p.212) notes, ‘the significance of andragogy continues to engage us’, concluding

that ‘perhaps all adult educators would be sympathetic to the view that as much of

the spirit of andragogy should infuse adult learning situations’ (ibid, p.224). Hence

Knowles’s work may be seen as a ‘work in progress’, that is, an approach to adult

learning whose full parameters are still being defined. In its current form, however,

it provides a workable, though not canonical, framework for strengthening patient

education in the clinical context.

Characteristics of Adult Learning

Expanding upon these six criteria, ‘the need to know’ from a pedagogical stance is

determined by the teacher, the teacher decides when, what and how much the

student needs to know. However, from an andragogical perspective, adults must first

be convinced of the worth ‘to them’ of any proposed learning and feel personal

commitment and motivation to learn before they are willing to invest the required

mental energy. Hence, if adult learners are not convinced of the need of the

proposed learning, they are unlikely to engage in it. Several mothers in this cohort

disengaged from the process as their need to know was clearly out of step with what

their practitioners presumed they needed to know. These disagreements between

women and their practitioners about what knowledge was relevant was interpreted

by some practitioners as rejection, and by some mothers as alienating, resulting in

feelings of being misunderstood, as Anne remarked, I felt misunderstood; I felt that they couldn’t understand why I didn’t want screening especially if there was a potential problem, almost as though I was being irresponsible….. I felt that I wasn’t fitting in that, I was bucking the system………that I was almost, a tinge of being irresponsible in that, here we are, we can prevent these nasty things happening to you as a parent, not considering the child, and we can make your life easier and if you let us, we can take care of this and you can lead a happy life and not have to concern yourself with a child with special needs. I said I didn’t want an amniocentesis, and explained that I would have this child whether there was something wrong or not, ………….I felt like I wasn’t

Page 252: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

252

accepting their help, and they thought I needed their help and that I would want to make that decision based on knowledge of this unborn child, an yet I didn’t, and that I felt, they didn’t understand. Anne.

Thus the fundamental starting point for clinical education ought to be mutual

negotiation of what the learner needs to know.

The learner’s self concept may also differ between adults and children. Pedagogy

presumes dependency in the learner while andragogy acknowledges the

developmental stage of adulthood as one of self direction and independence in

which learners have matured to a point where they are significantly ‘self’ directed,

not ‘other’ directed. Thus, the motivation to learn must come from an intrinsic desire

or perceived need to become better informed. Consequently, the commonly adopted,

though educationally outmoded, transmissive, didactic educational teaching

strategies often adopted clinically fail to penetrate. Modes of adult education that

require dependency on ‘expert’ teachers may, therefore, cause disaffection, as adult

learners can ‘resent and resist situations in which they feel others are imposing

their wills’ (Knowles et al., 2005, p.65), as Anne’s experience demonstrated earlier.

The role of the learner’s experience in shaping attention levels, motivation to learn,

and knowledge development, are significant and central considerations in adult

learning. Adult learners have accumulated a vast reservoir of prior knowledge and

interpretive frameworks through their wide-ranging life experiences and such

experiences significantly shape their reading of the meaning and worth of current

and new information. The recognition in educational philosophy of prior experience

shaping current understanding strongly resonates with the hermeneutic dimension of

ethical engagement discussed in Chapter Two, acknowledging that our

interpretations are ‘always already’ constituted to some degree. The heightened

awareness and intentional inclusion of prior learning in andragogy contrasts with the

dominant pedagogical view in which prior experience in children is known to be

limited; a stance which legitimises and reinforces the privileging of teacher

experience above that of the learner.

Readiness to learn for the adult learner is triggered by the need to acquire some skill

or knowledge that is tied to real–life situations. An adult learner’s readiness to learn

Page 253: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

253

is thus linked to their social role and conditioning, thus the unique particularity and

context of an individual’s life has considerable effect on capacity to learn, further

resonating with and complementing the phenomenological framework adopted in

Chapter Two.

Finally, the differences in the orientation to learning and motivation to learn were

observed by Knowles (1990). Child learners, Knowles argued, are predominantly

motivated by external measures such as the desire for good grades, gaining teacher

approval, or avoiding disapproval, and equating learning to the logical mastery of

content or subject matter. Adult learners are more problem centred, embracing

learning as a means to solve actual and immediate problems in real life situations.

The adult orientation to learning is to seek new knowledge which will be practically

applied in the short term, with the most common motivating factors being to

increase one’s sense of coping and self esteem.

If differences exist, and it seems that there are psychological developmental reasons

why they would (Taylor, 1996), it follows that strategies and conditions for

successful learning will also differ between adults and children. Hence, certain

approaches to, and pre-conditions for, learning will be more successful for adults.

Therefore, if we hope to facilitate appropriate learning opportunities for patients in

the context of health care delivery as an ethical imperative integral to the giving of

informed consent, these further six conditions of learning defined again by Knowles

(2005, pp.93-94), ought be considered.

• Adult learners are motivated by the ‘need’ to learn, thus educational

opportunities must be responsive to the particular needs of each

individual.

• Learning builds upon and integrates existing experiences.

• The physical environment must be comfortable, free from distractions

and conducive to positive relational interaction between the

teacher/facilitator and learner. Additionally, the adult learner must

perceive a mutual trust and respect in a collaborative, cooperative

partnership.

Page 254: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

254

• The goals of learning are mutually defined and ultimately must be

perceived as the learner’s goals. Teachers can facilitate and support

learning but the core responsibility and motivation rests with the adult

learner.

• Adult learners must share active responsibility for what is learned.

Participation breeds a sense of commitment necessary to genuinely

pursue the goals of learning.

• Learning opportunities are designed in such a way that a sense of

progress and success is created. Additionally, adult learners retain some

control and negotiation over how progress and success are defined.

These principles and conditions have permeated adult education in many areas from

ongoing professional and industry skill development and training to university

course structures. However, their ethical importance in clinical care and relevance to

patient learning remain consistently overlooked. Explanations for the failure to

embrace adult learning principles in institutionalised medical care are exacerbated

by the proposition that as illness is a time of vulnerability and dependency, the

presumptions of independence or self direction a key doctrine in adult education,

may not apply (Goodwin-Johansson, 1988, p.12). Further explanations point to

inherent power dynamics within the social and institutional contexts of medical care

where a person in the ‘patient’ role is socially conditioned to submit to the

authoritative expertise of professional health carers and, thus, may not exert their

full autonomy. Some of these considerations are apparent in antenatal care, such as

increased background levels of anxiety and vulnerability (Goel et al., 1998;

Kowalcek et al., 2002; Watson et al., 2003) or the perceived power differentials that

may silence discussion (Bernhardt et al., 1998; Sherwin, 1992, 2001). A vital point

to stress, however, is that while pregnant women may experience heightened

anxiety, they are not ‘ill’ per se. They are generally well, competent, and physically

able. Furthermore, they are not subject to the type of long term institutional care and

control that Goodwin-Johansson (1988) suggests can undermine capacity to assert

an equal relationship with their physician, although a lack of ongoing or established

relationship may be equally disempowering. In the right environment, however, with

appropriate encouragement and acceptance from health professionals, the principles

Page 255: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

255

of adult learning are highly relevant and could be successfully applied in antenatal

care to support informed consent.

While the conditions presented above are presented as discrete, in reality they are

inseparably interwoven and interconnected. However, Knowles et al (2005) further

claim that the strength of the andragogical model is its flexibility to embrace one,

some, or all of these principles depending on the particular situation. They conclude

that ‘what this means in practice is that we educators now have the responsibility to

check out which assumptions are realistic in a given situation’ (Knowles, 1990,

p.64). In guiding the transformation of learning in the clinical context of antenatal

care many, if not all, of these principles are potentially relevant.

Conditions of Learning in the Clinical Context

‘… because real education as I had already discovered, meant things you

really wanted to know rather than things other people thought you should

know’ (Davies, 1994, p.140).

The quote above from Robert Davies captures the underlying ethos of adult learning

proposed and refined by Knowles (1980, 1989), which is that ‘real’ education for

adult learners focuses on the motivation and need in the ‘learner’ rather than on the

imposed goals of the ‘teacher’. In the clinical context of patient education, each of

these learning considerations above will now be explored more closely through the

voices and experiences of the participants of this study, in conjunction with the

insights offered from other researchers in the field. Their relevance to patient

learning in the context of preparing women to consider the social, ethical, and

medical implications of prenatal screening will also be incorporated in this

discussion.

• The ‘need’ to know

Adult learners are motivated by the ‘need’ to know. Thus educational opportunities

must be responsive to the particular needs of each individual. The need to know

Page 256: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

256

incorporates three distinct dimensions defined by Knowles et al (2005, p.184) as ‘the

need to know how learning will be conducted, what learning will occur, and why

learning is important’. When these three dimensions are incorporated into

formalised adult learning programs, higher levels of success are achieved (ibid).

Significantly, prior conversations negotiating these three areas provide a vital

opportunity to clarify joint expectations, to identify and address misconceptions, and

to reveal the objectives of the learner. Thus shared goals for learner and teacher, or

patient and practitioner, may be negotiated and progressed.

The accounts offered by several mothers in this cohort supported the view that the

particular types of information presumed to be ‘of value’ by society at large, or

privileged by routine screening protocols, were not universally shared by mothers,

many of whom did not see the ‘need’ for the specific information being offered. As

Terri remarked,

I definitely wasn’t prepared for other problems being flagged, and I really wasn’t interested in finding that out. Terri

Or Anne, It only occurred to me as I was undergoing the ultrasound that they were making measurements of different parts of the child’s anatomy and physique and then I realised, I was thinking , well why are they doing this?.... I thought they must be looking for things that were unusual or not right and only then it occurred to me that they were looking for abnormalities...... I thought to myself well what if they do find something that doesn’t measure up to their expectations? I felt they got the information they needed and off you go. Anne

Therefore, the need to clarify patient learning objectives is a critical preliminary

element of informed consent, as patient objectives often differ substantially from

those held by health care professionals. The potential clash of motivation, and the

subsequent misunderstandings experienced and acknowledged by participants in

this research, reinforce this point and are further supported in the literature,

particularly with respect to risk assessment and disclosure (Liamputtong et al., 2003;

Tankard - Reist, 2005). Bridson, Hammond, Leach, & Chester (2003, p.1159)

further note that the ‘focus on disclosure which has arisen from the need to tell

patients about risk has meant not enough attention is given to patients’ objectives’.

Consequently, they (ibid) argue, ‘taking the time to explore patients’ objectives not

only improves consent procedures but may avoid some interventions altogether’.

Page 257: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

257

The delivery of prenatal screening may indeed have been avoided by Terri, Anne,

Penny and Danielle had their objectives been more explicitly canvassed prior to

screening. As Danielle reflected after the birth of her daughter when it became clear

that the vague anomaly picked up during her prenatal screen result was a false

positive, ………..their attitude (to the false positive) was like ‘well that’s good news isn’t it! That’s all worked out alright then” and I was like, well yes it’s great news, but it’s a shame I had to go through it! I don’t tend to question that sort of thing…..I mean perhaps it would have been even better news if we hadn’t done the ultrasound in the first place and not gone through that horrific time………….yeah…. Danielle

Or Terri, who reflected,

They told me the tests would tell us about the Down syndrome, neural tube defects would be covered, none of which was what my cousin’s child had, but they didn’t point that out to me – I did my own research, I found that out. I just got on the internet; it took 15minutes, its amazing what you can find there. I thought I've done this for nothing. Terri

These four women were opposed to termination and were committed from the outset

not to ‘act’ upon an unwelcome result, further stating an unwillingness to place their

child at risk through amniocentesis. However, for some, their initial lack of insight

into the underlying clinical purpose of screening, which they interpreted as part of a

compulsory routine with the added bonus of ‘seeing the baby’, coupled with poor

prior understanding of the ambiguity of a ‘screening’ result versus a more rigorous

‘diagnostic’ result, was never revealed. The anxiety and trauma subsequently

experienced, particularly for those women with false positive results could have

been significantly ameliorated by a prior discussion to decide whether this

particular, incomplete knowledge was indeed genuinely valuable to them prior to

screening.

Once a need to know is jointly negotiated and established, patient willingness to pay

attention is heightened, creating one of the fundamental precursors to learning.

Learning is more effective when the learner pays attention to what is being

presented; hence, paying attention is the critical precondition to learning (Cowan,

1995; Gage & Berliner, 1991; Knowles et al., 2005). As our senses are constantly

exposed to various inputs and sensations, we subconsciously and perpetually filter

information to establish what is worthy of our attention. Thus a key factor in

Page 258: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

258

determining which stimuli catch our attention is the personal motivation to learn

which is significantly influenced by the perceived need to know. However, patient

and practitioner presumptions about what ought to be known may differ

significantly, and attention and foci may be overtly or covertly directed. The amount

of attention paid may reflect to a degree the way such new knowledge is presented

and by the significance clinical staff attach to it. For example, as previously flagged

(Bernhardt et al., 1998), in the busy clinical environment many health practitioners

fail to even mention the moral aspects of prenatal screening as worthy of discussion.

Such failure may imply a lack of importance and signal to the patient that attention

is not warranted. Conversely, when such effort and emphasis is placed on risk

assessment and disclosure, its importance may become unduly exaggerated. One

genetic counsellor described the common scenario where the shortage of time limits

pre-test discussion to the bare technicalities, leaving little space to address any social

or moral considerations.

Well…… in 15 minutes there’s not a lot of time …………….look it’s pretty much a technical discussion for good or bad………….it’s seen as very much an education of this is what it is…these are the type results it will give you… you can’t say yes or no, but if you want to know for sure, you’ll have to have this or this………..I can talk to you after the result and we’ll talk in more detail …is this something you want to have?......it very much is factual , yes, very rarely would it go off……..[to the ethical]. Genetic Counsellor 2

Similarly, when education preceding prenatal screening is glossed over or reduced to

the dispensing of a pamphlet or list of conditions, as was Mary’s experience, a subtle

cue about the value of such education as nonessential is sent. Consequently, in a

cultural norm where something is deemed unworthy of consideration, the amount of

attention paid may be lessened (Winch, 1998, p. 121), a situation that significantly

erodes patient learning and undermines informed consent.

Although the patients’ need to know is an important predictor of their engagement

in, and commitment to, the learning process, this does not suggest that clinicians

have no input or guidance in determining which clinically significant information

patients should be alerted to. Indeed, their professional knowledge and clinical

expertise provides a substantial and valuable contribution to the insights sought by

women. The critical determinant is that a patient-centred dialogue takes place in

which a mutual exchange of objectives is shared and jointly negotiated between

Page 259: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

259

practitioner and patient (Bridson, Hammond, Leach, & Chester, 2003). Sharing

power with patients in this way may be liberating for practitioners, as shared power

rightfully brings shared responsibility, lightening the perceived onus on practitioners

to present themselves as the authoritative source and arbiter of all relevant

knowledge (Elwyn, Edwards, & Kinnersley, 1999; Fisher, Dixon, & Honeyman,

2005).

• Integrating Existing Experience.

As acknowledged throughout this work, moral frameworks are complex, thus, when

individual women come to the process of learning they bring particular interpretive

paradigms, both morally and educationally about how decisions will be reached. In

the context of pregnancy the nature of learning and the nature of ethical decision

making will encapsulate a broad spectrum of values and prior experiences. As

previously illustrated Leanne’s prior knowledge and experience of her colleague’s

child with Down syndrome created a strong personalised sense of fear. Coupled with

her experience of conceiving very easily, she developed a firm commitment to

embrace all screening possibilities. Similarly, pre-existing faith-based convictions

shaped the attitudes and behaviour of some other mothers as Anne explained,

I believe that every child has intrinsic worth and I think that every child should be allowed to live. I said I didn’t want an amniocentesis, and explained that I would have this child whether there was something wrong or not. Anne

Or Terri,

I had the attitude that if God had intended me to have a child like that then... (so be it). Terri

Penny’s prior experience with a miscarriage and difficulties conceiving again

featured strongly in her decision to reject amniocentesis,

we had had a miscarriage three years earlier, and were told that our chances of falling pregnant again because of other issues between us were very low, so we said, even if there is a problem, we wouldn’t do anything about it. Penny.

Only one practitioner disclosed the influence of her personal faith in her assessments

of the normative routines of prenatal screening saying,

Page 260: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

260

I don’t mention that I’m a Christian, I don’t actually mention my ethical viewpoint and I find it very frustrating that any opinions that can be seen to be linked to religion are then discredited and I think that’s really frustrating. Even although people who approve of abortion also have an ethical stance, their ethical stance is that they’re OK with it…..they don’t see it as an issue…..but because it’s not based on a religious belief, it’s not presented as moralistic. I struggle with that, I really struggle. General Practitioner 2.

As flagged by the GP above, the stance to promote screening and termination as an

ethically unproblematic outcome equally reflects a pre-existing positional bias and

one which inevitably translates into presumptions of practice.

The above comments illuminate how the broad range of prior experiences of adult

learners such as faith convictions, previous reproductive history, or perceptions of

disability potentially impacts upon ethical decision making in numerous ways. They

further illuminate the uniqueness and unpredictable influence of individual

perspectives, a uniqueness that demands an individualised stance towards supporting

adult patients in their learning journey, but one which the often predetermined

educational habits within institutionalised health care do not accommodate

(Goodwin-Johansson, 1988). This inherited, traditional cultural toolkit of a

predetermined transmissive model of learning seems so entrenched and

unchallenged that perhaps as Bruner notes ‘its form is so ubiquitous that it is likely

to be overlooked, in much the same way as we suppose the fish will be the last to

discover water’(Bruner, 1991, p.4).

Knowles et al (2005, p.191) summarise the impact of previous understandings

noting that they

• are the source of a wide and divergent array of individual interpretations

and difference,

• may provide a diverse and rich learning resource,

• may bring inherent biases which may inhibit or support new learning,

• are inextricably linked to each person’s sense of self identity.

While such experiences may serve as a resource to draw upon, they also at times act

as a gatekeeper or obstacle to the learning experience (ibid, p.195). As ‘knowledge is

never point of view less’(Bruner, 1991, p.3), the very nature of both educational and

Page 261: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

261

ethical inquiry significantly rests upon incorporating pre-existing knowledge,

relationships, and values. As moral contexts are interpreted through a unique veil of

history, relationships, and commitments, consequently we are always interpreting;

always filtering and our interpretations are always linked to past experience and

understandings which lay the foundations for future interpretations. Hence, actively

seeking and interpreting prior knowledge is essential to making the necessary

connection to current considerations.

• The Importance of Prior Learning in Constructing New Knowledge From a technical cognitive perspective, educational philosophers and theorists have

long acknowledged that when new information is presented in a way that is

disconnected from prior understandings, the creation of meaning upon which

reflective understanding is built is severely stifled (Dewey, 1938; Knowles, 1990;

Woods & Barrow, 1975). Thus, the construction of meaning to unfamiliar ideas is

essentially mediated through the use of familiar terms (Woods & Barrow, 1975).

Eliciting existing beliefs is, therefore, a crucial first step in any educational process

as presenting content out of context from past experience, or in isolation from related

knowledge, hinders the necessary creation of links that create the reflective

understanding sought by the ethical standard of informed consent. Indeed, if these

links to existing knowledge are not made, shallow, surface understanding may result

(Gage & Berliner, 1991; Winch, 1998), compromising informed consent.

Educationalists acknowledge the clear need to establish current understanding before

expanding with new concepts, likening the process to giving directions to a person

who is lost. The fundamental question before giving directions would (and should)

be: ‘where are you now?’ Frequently, the answer to this question of where a

woman’s knowledge is now prior to embarking upon prenatal screening is neither

sought nor considered explicitly relevant by existing clinical education protocols.

This crucial ability to attach meaning to new information mediated through existing

knowledge was succinctly demonstrated by Petersen (1966 cited by Gage &

Berliner, 1991, p285). During his 1966 study into the mechanisms of short term and

working memory, respondents were asked to recite meaningless combinations of

three letters. When repeated immediately, 88% were successfully recalled. However,

Page 262: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

262

when rehearsal was prevented for a mere 18 seconds, the success rate dropped to

only 15%. Peterson hypothesised that, as the nonsensical letter combinations had no

meaning or familiar code, they were easily forgotten. Their lack of meaning

suggested that no associations to existing reference points could be formed to aid

retention. Likewise, for many women the terms associated with the prenatal

screening tests they are about to undergo are also unfamiliar, even nonsensical, a

reality acknowledged by the following practitioners who remarked,

I see that as my role in helping them interpret, what is essentially, a foreign language, that’s how I see it………and it is… really. Genetic Counsellor 2 Even those words….. ‘nuchal translucency’ is not something that’s been around for a long time, so measuring the thickness of the skin at the back of the neck between 10-12 weeks, there’s not a lot of knowledge, its not something their mothers can tell them about, because they didn’t have it. Clinical Geneticist

If no previous point of reference exists for terms such as nuchal translucency,

trisomies, and amniocentesis, the opportunity to learn is made harder as meaningful

links for new information to existing schema of understanding must be built. The

creation of these mental maps takes time to develop and in the current clinical

scenario time is frequently scarce. Indeed ‘lack of time’ is often invoked as an

explanation for poor patient/carer relationships, as inadequate communication

creates low levels of satisfaction (Belle-Brown, Stewart, & Ryan, 2003; Bub, 2004;

Duberstein, Meldrum, Fiscella, Shields, & Epstein, 2007).

In a recent recommendation that shows scarce understanding of the educational

process, as opposed to the regurgitation of information, researchers in the UK

(Dormandy et al., 2002a) have recently advocated for screening protocols in which

prenatal testing information is dispensed, an immediate response elicited, and testing

performed during the same hospital visit. This recommendation has been suggested

on the grounds of streamlining administrative processes and enhancing informed

consent by reducing practical barriers to testing. However, as highlighted above in

the simple research undertaken by Peterson, the depth of the knowledge and

reflective understanding on which this immediate stimulus/response type of

‘informed’ consent is elicited must be queried. While it may be administratively

appropriate to elicit an immediate response for simple interventions with low level

consequences, the complexity and gravity of the potential outcomes of prenatal

Page 263: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

263

screening demand a fuller educational commitment. Perhaps as Ken Bain (2004,

p.41) has described, the type of shallow learning created by the immediate

stimulus/response advocated above could be described as ‘bulimic’ in the sense that

a ‘learner’ is fed ‘facts’ which may be absorbed for a specific narrow task,

regurgitated in a limited context then purged to make way for the next onslaught of

data. The depth of reflective understanding such ‘education’ creates seems

questionable as an ethical foundation when preparing women embarking upon the

ethically complex practice of prenatal screening. While this mode of informing may

meet the legal obligation of the informer to give information, it fails in an ethical

sense to promote the critical understanding required for considered moral decision

making.

From a clinical education perspective, if we are to achieve the knowledge

development that is essential to empower women in making genuine and active

decisions that are coherent with their moral frameworks, we must build strategies

and opportunities that incorporate the selective filtering process to accommodate the

unique and highly individual positions held. As Goodwin–Johansson (1988) notes,

flexibility about the quantity and type of information sought is required. Time and

commitment to clarify and to explore the objectives of screening to the patient are

also critical. Responding to existing frameworks of interpretations is a further

critical precursor to successful learning; hence, individual negotiation of which

questions are to be answered must form an integral and foundational part of ethically

responsible patient education. It is acknowledged again, however, that the

requirement to ‘inform’ in the legal sense of informed consent, and the requirement

to ensure understanding in the ethical sense are two different standards of

engagement. Informing for legal purposes is judged upon the action of the informer,

while informing for understanding in the ethical sense focuses upon the needs and

comprehension of the learner. Any patient-centred care must hold the latter as its

benchmark.

Page 264: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

264

• The Physical Environment and Patient Practitioner Relationships

Knowles et al (2005) advocate that the physical learning environment should be

comfortable, free from noise and distractions, and conducive to positive relational

interaction between the teacher/facilitator and learner. Ideally, the adult learner

should perceive the educational relationship as one of mutual trust and respect in a

collaborative, cooperative partnership. However, in the clinical setting, the dominant

aim is primarily one of identifying medical problems and providing physical,

medical treatment. The fundamental purpose (rightly or wrongly) is not to promote

the learning required to become informed for the purpose of giving ethically robust

consent. Hence, a significant clash of purpose and culture may exist in this context.

As a place where the isolation and treatment of medical ‘problems’ is paramount, it

is perhaps understandable that the creation of a reflective learning space for patients

has taken on a lower priority. Furthermore, the practical ramifications of rejecting

the overly paternalistic models of the past, and of embracing patient-centred

collaborative partnerships are a comparatively recent shift in medical thinking.

Hence, the finer details of what this relatively new patient-centred dynamic looks

like clinically are still emerging and evolving (Cegala, Street, & Clinch, 2007;

Elwyn et al., 1999; Elwyn et al., 2003; Fisher et al., 2005).

‘Adult education is predicated upon creating free space for reflection and

discourse and a reduction of the power differential between educator and

learner……… Ideally (and this is characteristic of adult education), the

relationship of educator to learner is one of subject to subject, a peer

relationship, rather than one of subject to object, not uncommon in the

education of children’ (Mezirow, 1996, p.171).

When this clash of purpose between the moral obligation to educate and the need to

treat is combined with the urgent and often pressurised environment, tight

resourcing, time restrictions, and a perceived need for quick decisions, giving due

support to a learning process that nurtures the critical understanding necessary for

autonomous choices to be made becomes seriously compromised. However, with the

potential consequences of poor understanding and low levels of informed consent

Page 265: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

265

being ongoing psychological distress, anxiety and potential feelings of depression

(Stewart et al., 2000, p.804), a practical commitment to supporting the right

environment which facilitates and supports patients’ understanding seems overdue.

In terms of the physical barriers to learning, the context of busy clinics with their

inherent time pressures, stretched resources and overcommitted staff can present a

distracting environment, one in which attention is focused purely on the immediate

medical outcomes, while the educational and ethical outcomes take secondary

priority. Such time constraints, as Bruner (2004) further notes, have worrying

consequences inhibiting reflection and learning,

‘One of the great triumphs of learning is to get things organised in your

head in a way that permits you to know more than you ‘ought’ to. And this

takes reflection, brooding about what it is that you know. The enemy of

reflection is the breakneck pace…’ (Bruner, 2004, p.98).

For the participants of this study, several factors were raised as environmental

impediments to learning in the clinical environment, most notably that of limited

time as the following comments illustrate. From the mothers,

When I have to wait I get the impression that the staff are very busy, they have a lot of patients to see therefore it becomes a bit like a factory and unfortunately that’s just the nature of the situation…I think when you have been waiting to see a doctor and you finally have your chance, you often don’t ask questions because you know they are so busy. Anne. I do think the communication issues are a bit of a problem there. It’s hard to say, I think it comes down to the speed of service, they are seeing so many women, and they don’t have the time. Terri.

Terri further explained that the rushed process and physical environment denied her

‘time to think’, I think that each parent should get, on a piece of paper, so they can read, re-read, proof read, information about the tests, what are the risks, what could the outcomes be, what do they test for, what don’t they test for. People need to be able to go home with that, rather than be put on the spot to make an instant decision…. That’s what I felt was necessary. These people were saying to me, you need to make a decision, right now; they didn’t want to give me time to think. Terri

Or the Down syndrome support group volunteer who remarked,

Women often don’t even know there is support [after receiving a prenatal diagnosis]; maybe if women were shown the big picture and offered support they might choose to slow

Page 266: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

266

down, take their time and think about things. I think it’s done too quickly, women are very quickly rushed off to more tests, genetic counsellor, and usually termination, I think it’s done without enough time to sit and talk with partners and family, and I feel women suffer from the rush. Down syndrome Support Group Volunteer

From practitioners, the following revelations about the impact of time pressure

which may compromise the quality of clinical care were offered:

Inside this particular hospital, you know they don’t have an hour to talk with patients, in fact, they don’t even have 20 minutes to talk with a patient, they have 10 minutes. How do you develop a rapport in 10 minutes? How do you determine what this lady’s thoughts are and steer your thoughts in line with hers? You don’t………..I mean there are two opposing thoughts coming in and if your belief is we want this baby out of here in a timely manner in a way that’s convenient to us, let alone her…. then who cares?........Midwife 2. I think we get so busy and carried away with time, we just say “here, can you sign this” and yes, a lot of trust is put in us, and people hope we’ll do the right thing by them…. Midwife 4 If someone says at the end of [the initial appointment] ‘so tell me about screening’ I don’t want to give them a quick answer………..I will tend to have a set ‘spiel’ about that, so I wouldn’t rush that conversation …….so I might decide to just do it and run late………..or I may ask them to come back, it’s a big area and there’s a lot to consider….I wouldn’t just say ‘oh yes, there’s a few tests, here’s the form’ but I know there are GPs out there who would do that. General Practitioner 2 GP’s are a bit the same; they are running that day to day stuff – how much time do they really have to teach women everything – they really don’t………..they really rely on women to find out information and certainly a lot of it goes by word of mouth, absolutely and that’s where the myths perpetuate. Midwife 2

Lack of time and less than ideal relationships between patient and practitioner often

combine to create poor communication habits, which Braddock (2002, p.344)

describes as a ‘one way conversation, without meaningful participation by patients’.

Stewart et al (2003) further identify time and poor communication as contributors to

the souring of relationship that leads to the loss of important ‘teachable moments’.

Relationships between practitioners and patients and their influence on

communication were a further area of concern which drew comment from

participants, some positive, some negative. From the mothers:

Through the pregnancy…I wouldn’t say we were a team….but I felt that the obstetrician was on our side………..it was more of a partnership. [E: An equal partnership?] No……in that he was the doctor and we’re just the patient… I don’t think I would call that equal………….because he still gets to make the decisions….Penny Or Terri,

Page 267: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

267

[E: How would you describe your relationship with your doctors?]

What relationship? We’re talking about a public hospital here! Well, no, no definitely not open and communicative. He just told me what I needed to know, but, well, doctors are busy. Terri

Elizabeth relayed an example of what she considered to be poor communication

with an Obstetric Consultant at a large public hospital, describing the experience as

a ‘Farside moment’. The depths of the chasm of miscommunication lead Elizabeth

flippantly to dismiss this consultant’s professional ability.

The consultant at the hospital read through my notes and noticed I had seen a genetic counsellor, she asked why – and I explained that I had another child – in the pram beside me – who was born with trisomy 21. …“How do you know?” she asked me. You know it was like a ‘Farside’ moment, with an obstetric consultant who doesn’t believe me, how did I know my child had Down syndrome, and I just pointed to Grace, as if to say “hello!!”. I thought she’s obviously stupid. Elizabeth

Poor communication in the delivery of ‘bad’ news also drew comment from some

mothers, who noted

The way the paediatrician said, ‘I’ll give you a ring when the results come back” And he just rang one day, four months later and said ‘oh yes, that test result came back, yes it’s positive for XXX, if you want to speak to a geneticist, just ring me tomorrow and let me know”. And that was how he spoke to me…….and I was dumbfounded….standing there going uh!!. And because I was dumbfounded I couldn’t ask any questions… and ‘ring tomorrow’, what was that all about? That to me was a very inappropriate way. I thought it should have been, please come into the office; we’d like to discuss the results…. That should have been the minimum way of telling someone their child had a particular condition….Penny.

And Mary Well the way [the nuchal result] was presented to me was like being hit by a train………..there needs to be more discussion about what the options are……Mary

On the positive side, many mothers had strong pre-existing relationships,

predominantly with their GP’s, based on trust in their physician’s expertise.

Significantly though, this did not necessarily translate into the recommended

participation in a collaborative partnership or the mutual defining of goals with their

carers. Most communication problems encountered occurred between external

specialists with whom women had not developed a good therapeutic relationship.

Significant research efforts have been invested to assess and critique physician

obligations in clinical communication (Anderson, Tschann, Guillion, & Oppenberg,

1989; Hulsman, Ros, Winnburst, & Bensing, 1999; Hulsman, Visser, & Makoul,

Page 268: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

268

2005), however, comparatively little research has been directed towards the

influence of patient communication on the medical conversation (Cegala &

Lenzmeier Broz, 2003). While the communication experience is significantly guided

by the attitude and orientation of the physician, importantly the communication

dynamic is also appreciably co-created by the patient (Cegala et al., 2007). Hence,

patient behaviour, expectations, and level of participation can exert a positive

influence in directing how clinical conversations unfold. As Cegala, Street and

Clinch (ibid, p.177) observed:

‘when communicating with high participation patients, physicians provided

significantly more information overall, more information in response to

patients’ questions and volunteered more information than when interacting

with low participation patients’.

They further concluded that ‘high participation patients’ communication style

promotes better alignment of patients’ and physicians’ goals and agendas’, a critical

precondition of successful adult learning. The desire for increased patient

responsibility and participation was also voiced by several practitioners, illustrated

in the obstetrician’s comment:

I guess from the word go, and this applies to every aspect of medicine if people really understood what they were having the test for, why they’re getting things done , what we’re trying to really achieve, and understanding these are really optional things….if they questioned a bit more……and interacted. To some degree there has got to be some motivation to self educate by the patient, some recognition of the importance of their own health……but we can’t presume to be paternalistic about it either… Obstetrician

High participation may positively influence communication; however, barriers such

as feelings of intimidation when communicating with practitioners, perceived power

imbalances, or patient fears that being assertive may endanger the relationship have

been observed. These fears often translate into a difficulty with asking questions

(Godolphin, 2003; Godolphin, Towle, & McKendry, 2001; Towle & Godolphin,

1999; Towle, Godolphin, Manklow, & Wiesinger, 2003). However, as

communication patterns which encourage patient questions create stronger patient

involvement, lower levels of anxiety, fewer subsequent visits and referrals, and

strengthened educational outcomes, creating the right conditions to encourage active

Page 269: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

269

participation is highly desirable (Cegala, Gade, Lenzmeier Broz, & McClure, 2004;

Cegala & Lenzmeier Broz, 2003; Post et al., 2002; Stewart, 1995; Stewart et al.,

2000; Stewart et al., 2003; Weston, 2001). The alignment of goals and firm

commitment to supporting patient questioning and promoting participation is needed

as it is a vital predictor of successful adult learning and clinical education.

Finally, many of the practitioners interviewed displayed genuine commitments and

behaviours that would foster strong educational and therapeutic relationships, which

promoted participation and valued good communication. Although most stopped

short of advocating genuine sharing of the therapeutic goals, the following

comments provide encouragement that, amongst this cohort of practitioners, there is

an awareness of the importance of good learning outcomes for patients.

My personal opinion, and this is purely a personal opinion is that we have come a long way in understanding and communication with women and understanding how they are feeling, this pregnancy is the most important pregnancy ever because it’s their baby so …..In general I think there is a bit more understanding and respect. Midwife 3 Being able to spend some time with them, ask them appropriate open questions to ascertain their understandings of not only of the information that I’ve given verbally, but also the written information that I would have given too… You bring them back and talk to them again…..and that’s the luxury you have in general practice that hospital don’t have…the luxury in general practice in terms of prenatal screening is that if they walk out of the room and they are still not sure, you encourage them to come back and talk about it and make sure they know the door is open………General Practitioner 1 Although everyone is booked to a timeframe of half an hour…. some go over, but I think our doctors are very, very aware that they must ……….the woman can’t go home without a good understanding….there’s always that pressure, and sometimes it’s hard to know what the understandings are……you know……. Midwife 1 I try not to give too much information and expect them to take it all away and read it all and act upon it. It is routine, having said that, to do a post clinic letter, so that’s usually about 1-1 ½ pages of content, usually summarising the important content of what took place. [E: Is this so that they have something concrete to refer back to?] Yes, so that letter is primarily the way that that happens, its not there immediately from the consultation because there’s a time delay from dictation to transcription to sending it out, but….. it serves as a reminder. It’s not necessarily a bad thing that there is a delay before they get that letter because it helps to reinforce what was said at the time …. I really don’t know if people read those letters, certainly many do, many keep them, and many don’t…… So, once they’ve got it, it’s theirs to show other family members, give to other health professionals as they see fit…..the issue of privacy and consent is in their hands. Clinical Geneticist.

Page 270: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

270

• Mutually Defined Learning Goals and their Role in Fostering Shared

Responsibility and Commitment

Successful adult learning, Knowles et al (2005) claim, is enhanced when the goals of

learning are mutually defined by teacher and learner, and ultimately embraced as the

learner’s goals. Once a sense of ownership in the learner is established, an elevated

sense of responsibility and commitment to genuinely pursue these goals is formed.

Additional benefits are increased feelings of competence, further re-enforcing the

pursuit of learning as a positive experience. Again, the mutual clarification of goals

at this stage depends upon effective dialogue as supporting the ethical importance of

dialogue and narrative in collaboratively constructing a mutually respectful,

appreciative, and hermeneutically aware relationship.

Much attention has been focussed on poor patient knowledge as an obstacle to

informed consent and defining shared goals, and as mentioned above, several

programs have been devised to teach patients how to better interact with

practitioners and to improve their health literacy ( Marteau et al., 1992; Post et al.,

2002; Towle & Godolphin, 1999; Towle et al., 2003), all of which are important

predictors of effective learning. However, another major impediment to informed

consent and good educational outcomes for patients is that of poor practitioner

knowledge about the details and potential outcomes of screening. Several studies

have revealed that some medical staff may lack the presumed knowledge or skill

required (Sadler, 1997; Tyzack & Wallace, 2003), often omitting pertinent

information for patients about prenatal tests because they may lack it themselves.

Clinical staff have also been observed to misjudge how much information patients

need or want and are frequently driven by the fear that too much information will

create anxiety in their patients (Marteau et al., 1992, p.138), a view echoed by some

practitioners in this cohort:

A lot of information is not given because it feels extraneous at the time, like it’s an extra burden, and with a very low chance of it happening why would you talk about all the potential possibilities…unless you’re dealing with the reality of what’s there…I think its just time, economics and emotional burden… why would you worry someone about something that’s highly unlikely.… Genetic Counsellor 1

Page 271: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

271

People are worried about exacerbating this anxiety by mentioning the possibility of an abnormality, so we don’t actually tell people, well, your risk of miscarriage in the first 8 weeks is 15%, between 12-20 weeks it this much and so on… the chance of stillbirth after 20 weeks is 1 % and so on ….. You don’t tell women those things……..and likewise mentioning anything about abnormalities, you don’t particularly mention to people that well…..5% of all babies can be born with something because you don’t want them to worry. So, that’s one of the barriers, not to worry the pregnant woman so much and so that effects how much you actually talk about. Obstetrician

Poor practitioner knowledge may also contribute to an excessive enthusiasm to test

as lack of confidence may encourage the exercising of a disproportionate amount of

caution. Tyzack and Wallace (2003) observed that less than 10% of the practitioners

they surveyed about pre-test counselling for Down syndrome screening provided

accurate information on the characteristics of screening tests, concluding that the

majority were not sufficiently informed to provide optimum counselling to patients.

Noting the obvious link between practitioner knowledge and informed patients, they

made the recommendation that ‘ensuring that care providers are themselves well

informed is therefore fundamental to delivering a quality screening program’ (ibid,

p.220). Concerns about poor practitioner knowledge or proficiency, and the

inevitable impact upon the development of appropriate understanding in patients

was certainly raised as a factor by many practitioners in this cohort, as evidenced in

the following comments,

GP knowledge is often mediocre as to the specifics of the exam, so they will not usually explain things like false positives etc…..Obstetrician I think that one of the reasons why shared care is somewhat fraught is that many people are giving shared care that have no ability whatsoever to determine the lie of a foetus or presentation… I happen to know that there are not too many GP’s, in my opinion, well qualified and able in my opinion to comment about antenatal care…General Practitioner 1 Some of them [GP’s] didn’t know what [the 12 week scan] was, they really quite frankly didn’t know what they were looking at and therefore they were ordering the test, putting their name to it and not knowing really how to interpret results, what was going to come from it, even although the safety net of course was that anything abnormal detected here would be directly referred to tertiary care here and the GP was notified. Midwife 3 Some GP’s know this information really well, but it’s really variable in terms of that, and also how many doctors organise the blood tests as well……so….it’s very variable ….and it’s frustrating because it’s easy information for GP’s to give and I know that there have been many information sessions aimed at GPs on the whole screening issue, they should perhaps be passing on more knowledge that what sometimes we see. Genetic Counsellor 2

Page 272: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

272

The recent shift in Queensland Health to a ‘shared care’94F

95 model of antenatal care

may have contributed to under-equipped GP’s being given additional responsibility

for ordering specialised tests which they previously had no involvement with. One

hospital midwife explained:

I do see that GP’s are having a lot of assumptions made about their knowledge……..they are doctors, therefore they should know everything….without really, really giving them the good education they require…………this is something new that’s come in after a lot of these GP’s began practice ……and they have never ever had to deal with it…….I guess some skills wouldn’t be there in the same way as people who have been brought up , you know newer GP’s who have learned about this screening right from the beginning of medical school…… many GPs have never had to deal with it before, and even within nursing, you don’t put people into areas to do things that they don’t have the skills to do, I certainly wouldn’t want to be put in cardiology……..the assumption is made from the outset that they know it, they do it, they are GP’s, they just do it……………….the assumption is made I guess by the policy makers in the organisation…..[we] need to assess what sort of education is needed….how is it going….and pick up on any comments or complaints that come in. How do you reach the ones that you need to reach because there are a lot who do know? How do you find the ones who don’t know about it? There’s the cost factor too…..you can only send out so much stuff……and the time to prepare so much information…… it’s a difficult task…… Midwife 3

Hence, before mutually defined learning goals can be negotiated, practitioners must

also be supported and equipped to embrace their critical ethical role as facilitators of

patient education.

• Defining progress and success

The final consideration of adult learning suggested by Knowles et al (2005) is that

educational opportunities should be designed in such a way that a sense of progress

and success is created. While most of the insights offered by Knowles et al (ibid) in

this phase centre upon ‘evaluation’ measures of more formalised learning, in the

clinical context of preparing women to give informed consent to medical

interventions, the relevance of this final phase is not instantly obvious as, clearly,

there are no external assessments to ‘pass’ or skill criteria to fulfil. There are,

however, internal criteria of success to be met. If the purpose of the learning is to act

as an ethical safeguard, pre-arming and equipping women with the relevant

knowledge to make decisions in keeping with their individual moral frameworks,

some of the trauma and anxiety created by the common misunderstandings

recounted by the cohort of this study may have been averted. As high levels of

95 See footnote 55, p.159

Page 273: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

273

informed consent are associated with greater acceptance of both positive and

negative outcomes, success and progress in this context may be realised in better

coping mechanisms and psychological preparedness to step up to the events that

unfold.

The Shared Ethical Orientation of ‘Patient-Centred Medicine’ and Adult Learning

If we value informed consent as a safeguard to the ethical integrity of medical

interventions, we must seriously value the educational process through which

patients and practitioners become informed. The pre-conditions supporting adult

learning suggested by Knowles (1980) outlined above, raise the practical question of

how (or whether) this andragogical educational framework may be integrated into

clinical care. Many of the proposed conditions may appear antithetical to the

medical environment, such as genuine shared decision making, negotiating patient

objectives even when they stand in conflict to conventional medical wisdom, or

embracing a particularised, rather than generalised, view of unique individual

contexts and interpretive frameworks.

The emerging trend towards “Patient-Centred Medicine” may provide a fitting

platform for change. Patient-centred medicine positions the patient as an equal

partner in health care decisions and thus provides a workable foundation on which

to construct adult centred learning engagements. This approach is already gathering

considerable momentum and is increasingly associated with improved health

outcomes on many levels such as improved patient and practitioner satisfaction,

better health outcomes with fewer referrals, and a reduction in the number of

malpractice suits (Stewart et al., 2000; Stewart et al., 2003; Weston, 2001).

Closer examination reveals that the core values of patient-centred care of respect for

relationship and a firm commitment to incorporate the patient (learner) perspective

via genuine communication mirror the foundational elements of adult learner-

centred educational theory. The common feature of both is their shared ontological

orientation, which further resonates with the ontological insights of a

phenomenological approach to ethics as outlined in Chapter Two. Recognising the

Page 274: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

274

‘self’ as related, embedded, historicised, and dialogically and narratively

constructed, the patient-centred approach actively seeks to incorporate prior patient

knowledge, existing interpretive frameworks, and individual values and beliefs,

encouraging physicians to respond to the uniqueness of individual patients (Stewart

et al., 2000, p. 804). Hence, the growing influence of Patient-Centred Care in

medicine provides a cohesive framework that is ethically, educationally and

therapeutically appropriate in addressing the observed ethical shortcomings that

flow from the inadequate transmissive educational paradigm currently adopted. Like

the andragogical model, a core aspect of ‘patient-centred care’ is the need to find

‘common ground’, to establish shared goals, and to build secure relationships as a

basis for a constructive therapeutic partnership. While Stewart et al (2003) note that

establishing this relationship may be initially time consuming, once a working

relationship is formed the time spent on subsequent visits may be reduced as the

trust and confidence developed can expedite subsequent clinical decision making.

As the potential consequences of not developing secure clinical partnerships with

patients are insecurity, anxiety or depression that may lead to further intervention at

a later date (Stewart et al., 2000, p.804), the potential ethical, clinical, and financial

benefits that may flow are clear. Benefits of robust informed consent mentioned

earlier include higher levels of patient and physician satisfaction, fewer referrals,

and a decreased number of medical malpractice suits, suggesting that the potential

ethical benefits flowing from support and facilitation of patient learning as an

integral part of the informed consent process may produce very practical dividends.

Transforming Patient Learning in Clinical Care

A number of practical challenges flow from accepting the argument that ethical

practice, through informed consent, is inextricably linked to patient education. The

explanations offered by Knowles (1990) and Knowles et al (2005) into the

developmental requirements of adult learners provide valuable insights to support

the ethical imperative to educate patients in clinical care. Points for further

consideration include how such educational understandings may be incorporated

into practice given the existing time constraints. Given the identification from this

research of blurred accountability for informing, important consideration of who is

Page 275: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

275

accountable for patient education must be addressed; reflections on how

understanding can be assessed or whether patient learning should be routinely

assessed will also need to be answered. The importance of updating and supporting

practitioners’ technical knowledge in addition to raising their awareness of the

requirements of the frequently underestimated role of patient educator must also be

proactively addressed. Finding ways to encourage patients to improve their own

health literacy and become more participative in their clinical education forms

another critical part of the equation. All of these facets of developing more ethically

robust care warrant further attention once the link to patient education is accepted as

ethically crucial, rather than as an optional extra undertaken only by highly

motivated practitioners or patients.

Thus, the area of clinical practice is ripe with possibilities for further empirical

exploration of these issues. Protocols already exist for assessing levels of informed

consent (Braddock, 2002; Braddock et al., 1999; Braddock, Stephan, Levinson,

Jonsen, & Pearlman, 1997), for assessing communication styles, and for forging

more successful patient collaboration and participation (Cegala et al., 2004; Cegala

et al., 2007; Post et al., 2002). Therefore, the effects of adopting different

educational strategies into clinical regimes could be monitored and evaluated,

forming the foundation of evidence-based, time efficient, clinically effective

educational practice. Such ‘evidence-based’ research may then illuminate how

educationally sound frameworks may be implemented to support the ethical

outcomes of everyday practice.

We can predict that increased technological sophistication will require increasingly

complex understanding. We can also predict, based on past experience, that the

landscape of prenatal screening is moving inevitably and irrevocably towards more

medicalised, technology driven pregnancies. Given these predictions, it is clear that

existing protocols for educating and building understanding, which are already

inadequate, will become even more unsatisfactory. Therefore, actively embracing a

transformative educational response which elevates the importance of learning and

knowledge development in the context of prenatal screening is crucial to securing

robust ethical care within the institutional medical setting into the future.

Page 276: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

276

Chapter Summary

As previously flagged, the crucial ethical difference between consent and ‘informed’

consent is the incorporation of some form of education or learning opportunity, with

the transfer and construction of the appropriate knowledge and understanding prior

to accepting any medical intervention. “Informed consent” is, therefore, given from

a position of reflective understanding after careful consideration and deliberation of

the central facts relevant to each individual. Hence, the moral integrity of informed

consent in clinical care is inextricably linked to patient education.

The experiences of most mothers in this cohort illustrated that current institutional

approaches to patient education, when they exist at all, are often approached as an

episodic or finite event, considered for the express purpose of attaining a ‘one off’

agreement or consent. Practitioners presented a similar story, acknowledging the

problematic and often inadequate informed consent protocols. While many

practitioners illustrated sound educational strategies in their own practice, they

recognised that ethically appropriate levels of informing may not be the universal

norm.

In terms of strengthening education processes within clinical care, the work of

educationalist Malcolm Knowles (1970, 1990; Knowles et al 2005) may provide a

workable template for reform, through emphasising the different considerations and

requirements of successful adult education. Knowles (ibid) recognises that education

is an ongoing process firmly embedded in time, history, relationships, personal, and

institutional contexts and the prior understandings held by the learner. Approaching

informed consent as an administrative ‘event’ may create a fundamental tension in

how patient education is approached clinically, and may stifle the application of

appropriate educational strategies. Knowles’s educational model is founded on the

belief that the developmental capacities of adult learners demands developmentally

responsive educational strategies.

Page 277: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

277

While transmissive and compartmentalised ‘instrumentalist’ views of education

have significantly fallen from vogue among educators, being replaced by more

learner-centred strategies, the educational strategies in the health care setting as

described and experienced by many of participants of this cohort reflect

authoritative and transmissive modes of informing. For informed consent to be

supported clinically, these must be replaced with more adult learner centred

strategies that embrace and acknowledge the embedded, relational, dialogical, and

culturally and historically situated nature of learning, from an adult perspective for

patient and practitioner. The six pre-conditions that support effective adult learning

suggested by Knowles et al (2005) discussed earlier may provide a workable

template to increase awareness and foster such reform. While Knowles has been

critiqued for making the distinction between adult and other learners rather than

viewing all learners on a continuum, and many of Knowles (1970, 1984, 1898,

1990) observations equally apply to any learner centred mode of education, Knowles

et al’s (ibid) six key points provide a practical starting point and focus for reflection;

• Identify the need to learn.

• Integrate existing experiences.

• Mutually define learning goals.

• Build mutual trust and respect in a collaborative, cooperative partnership

with shared responsibility

• Allow the learner to control and negotiate how progress is defined.

• Provide a comfortable physical environment.

Learning for the purpose of consenting to clinical interventions must be recognised

as more complex than the habitual dispensing or disclosure of disconnected

information. Rather it should be viewed as an active and mutually enriching

partnership, nurtured in a supportive, relational environment that is anchored to prior

knowledge and existing moral frameworks. While some of the conditions above may

seem beyond our reach, in accepting the link of ethical practice to patient education,

we are obliged to challenge current models of resourcing and staffing and to contest

many of the overarching and unjust financial constraints imposed by the managerial

focus on business models of care delivery that limit our capacity to fulfil the

fundamental ethical obligation to educate. Although not explicitly recognised, the

Page 278: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

278

emerging clinical framework of ‘patient-centred medicine’ shares a strong

philosophical orientation both with the phenomenological account of ontology and

the andragogical educational framework proposed by Knowles. The shared

ontological basis of these three areas, the patient-centred model of care, the

phenomenological understanding of the ethical and the andragogical framework of

education collectively complement the ethical intentions of informed consent.

As the practice of prenatal screening is shaped by individual and organisational

factors, the ethical and educational transformation of practice will ultimately depend

upon the moral integrity and orientation of the institutions we construct, in addition

to the values, capacities and conduct of those individuals who function within them.

The following chapter will explore potential areas of transformation, premised on

the understanding that transformation must occur at both the individual and the

institutional levels simultaneously, as in reality, they are inseparably enmeshed with

each partially defining, enabling, and/or constraining the other.

Page 279: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

279

CHAPTER 10

TRANSFORMING PRACTICE

‘It's better to light a candle than to curse the darkness’

Eleanor Roosevelt.

‘We need to think less about doctrine and principles and the rules to govern

behaviour, more about education and institutions – and what sort of people

we produce’(Kass, 2002, p.73).

Introduction

The experiences of participants explored throughout this work illustrate that

voluntary, understood, and informed consent was not routinely achieved in practice

for this cohort of mothers. In line with observations made elsewhere, the commonly

experienced clinical conditions of prenatal screening created moral harm to some,

imposing avoidable distress, alienation, and anxiety. Furthermore, to mothers who

unconditionally valued their expected child, the negative attitudes towards children

with potential disabilities inherent within screening protocols caused deep affront.

As discussed in Chapter Eight some literature suggests that the potentially avoidable

anguish and suffering created were simultaneously generated and alleviated in the

self perpetuating dynamic of testing. While small increases in anxiety levels may be

beneficial, illustrating appropriate levels of engagement and attention (Kleinveld et

al., 2006; Stephenson, 2006), a deep and sometimes ongoing sense of distress was

articulated95F

96 by some women in this cohort. This distress has been observed and

described in other studies as akin to a ‘major depressive episode’ (Leithner et al.,

2004) or ‘serious psychological harm’(Goel et al., 1998). Cristofalo et al (2006)

have noted that the sense of loss and worry reported by some women can remain

long after testing ceases 96F

97. The long term impact of such psychological distress

96 Though not formally measured. 97 Almost 30% of women in Cristofalo et al’s 2006 study imagined future health implications for their child long after they had been ‘cleared’ following the revelation of benign CPC’s (Cristofalo, DiPietro, Costigan, Nelson, & Crino, 2006).

Page 280: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

280

remains under researched suggesting a need for additional research in this area (

Boyd et al., 1998, p.1581).

While practitioners in this cohort universally expressed that they valued informed

consent in their patients, most struggled with their sense that patients often remained

ill equipped or under informed about the purpose and potential outcomes of

screening. Blurred responsibility among practitioners for the provision of care and

education, mothers’ unquestioning compliance with misunderstood routines, and

poor basic knowledge of the tests and their value or relevance by practitioners and

mothers alike, were observed in this cohort. Additionally, the procedural pressures

of routine testing obfuscated ‘voluntariness’ and the promotion of the presumed

benefits of testing further collided to undermine some women’s capacity to give

their informed consent. For practitioners, these aspects similarly constrained their

capacity to adequately inform. Although this limited research makes no claim that

the experiences of individual participants are representative or generalisable to the

whole population, if the accounts offered and outlined throughout this work are

indeed typical, and this may be determined by extended research, the routine

everyday medical intervention of prenatal screening, as described and experienced

by the participants of this cohort, suggests a local practice in need of ethical

transformation.

Chapter Nine recognised the central role of education in transforming some of these

entrenched practices. It was suggested that, as the moral integrity of informed

consent rested upon the possession of reflective understanding prior to consenting,

patient education was ethically essential. It was also proposed that robust

andragogical approaches to adult learning (Knowles, 1970, 1990; Knowles et al.,

2005) provided a potentially workable template from which to facilitate such

education clinically. However, while appropriate education may be a critical factor

in the ethical deliberations of individuals, underlying systemic problems and

contextual biases of institutionalised medical practice tacitly remain. Therefore,

while supporting patient autonomy through education is a valuable and important

ethical aim that should be faithfully pursued, ultimately, all decisions are

contextually constrained, relationally embedded, and communally moderated in the

Page 281: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

281

framework of broader societal customs and structures of medical practice. Indeed, it

is often the tension between individual moral frameworks and communally endorsed

social and moral frameworks that ultimately contribute to the moral distress

experienced by individuals. These communal frameworks include the master

narratives of ‘good’ mothering (good mothers test), the discourse of tragedy

surrounding disability (to be avoided at all cost), the elevation of rationality as the

privileged ethical arbiter (it is irrational not to ‘prevent’ disability) and the socially

embraced perfectibility doctrine of technology (science both defines and delivers us

from the unacceptable).

We cannot compartmentalise and segregate educational strategies and outcomes

from the multiple layers of embeddedness in the social, philosophical, cultural,

personal, and institutional contexts of medical practice in which health care is

situated. As noted earlier, Toulmin (1990, p.201) remarks,

‘We may temporarily shelve the contexts of our problems, but, eventually,

their complete resolution obliges us to put these calculations back into their

larger human frame, with all its concrete features and complexities’.

Accordingly the ethical and educational transformation of practice will ultimately

depend jointly upon the moral integrity and orientation of the institutions we

construct, in addition to the values, capacities and conduct of those individuals who

function within them. These two potential areas of transformation, the institutional

and the individual, will be considered in more depth.

Transforming Institutions

The transformation of institutional structures within which prenatal care is situated

may be reformed in three key structural areas these being (1) the institutional

orientation and organisational infrastructure with respect to ethics; (2) the promotion

of institutional reform in areas of internal and external policy direction, including

overarching legal frameworks and production/business models of care; and finally

(3) by actively questioning the ideologically driven faith in science and technology

Page 282: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

282

that values and promotes technological intervention. Simultaneously addressing

these areas may lay the foundation for a responsive ethical environment in which

personal capacities of staff and patients may be built, and in which the practical

realisation and support of the ethical may be genuinely facilitated.

Transforming Institutional Approaches to Ethics

‘Medicine being simultaneously the scientific and humanistic study of man

(sic) cannot escape being based in an explicit or implicit philosophy of

human nature’(Pellegrino, 2003, p.10).

As Edmund Pellegrino notes above, an ‘explicit or implicit philosophy of human

nature’ inevitably prefigures how ethics is operationalised in medical care. The

transformative process thus necessarily begins with the ethical, as it is within the

framework of the philosophy of human nature that fundamental insights into the

nature of human being and becoming, which is the core of ethics, may be expressed

and understood. As any medical condition is firstly embedded within the human

condition, a robust and resonant framework of understanding this human condition

must ideally prefigure any ethical conversation in the applied clinical setting.

While the growing profile of bioethics in recent decades has arguably increased

awareness of ethical issues such as promoting patient autonomy, preserving

confidentiality, contesting paternalism and illuminating asymmetrical institutional

power dynamics, many practitioners appear to harbour a great unease about the

relevance of the dominant principlist or rationalist ethical frameworks commonly

encountered (Caplan, 1999; Hoffmaster, 1991; Kass, 2002; Komesaroff, 1995;

Pellegrino, 2003). In approaching ethics as a detached and theoretical discourse,

dominated by ‘assumptions, conventions and imperatives’ (Komesaroff, 1995, p.64),

the increasingly specialist bioethics discourse often seems removed from the

immediate, day to day concerns of medical care. The well catalogued response of

positioning ethical dialogue and deliberation within carefully demarcated

‘dilemmas’ has progressively limited ethical conversations within restricted and

increasingly predefined possibilities. Often, extreme examples of what May (1994)

describes as ‘headliner quandaries’ are elevated, while discussion about the ‘micro-

Page 283: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

283

ethical’ (Komesaroff, 1995) or underlying ‘moral sensibilities’ (Kass, 2002) of

everyday practice, injustices, and relationships becomes silenced. Consequently, the

critical questions of ethics have become largely epistemologically based, framed as

abstract intellectual puzzles to be solved in the rational and technical realm of

philosophical ‘experts’.

Perhaps, not surprisingly, the effectiveness of this popular approach in responding to

the particular, deeply contextualised and immediate concerns of practitioners and

patients alike is regarded by many clinicians as lacking, with the increasingly

specialist discourse of bioethics seeming disconnected from the immediate, day to

day concerns (Komesaroff, 1995). Thus the social, political, and cultural

determinants of which cases are deemed to be morally relevant for discussion under

this model remain tacitly unacknowledged. Instead of opening medical practice up

to ethical reflection and enquiry, the narrow frameworks prevalent in much

institutional bioethics have perhaps unwittingly been instrumental in closing down

the ethical analysis required.

Komesaroff (1995) further observes from his perspective as a physician that ethics

should not be regarded as a technical expert discussion, but rather ethics is ‘what

happens between every patient and every doctor everyday’ (ibid, p.68). Expanding

on this claim, clinical ethics may be equally regarded as what happens in every

human encounter in the health care setting everyday, be that nurse-patient, patient-

patient, physician-administrator, orderly-social worker, or family member-physician,

and so on. The philosophical orientation, language, and organisational structures to

support an accessible and embedded ethics of the everyday in the clinic must be

open to accommodate the unique experiences and context laden realities of all

stakeholders. Margaret Somerville further notes:

‘It’s not that reason, common sense, objective facts, and science are

unimportant to ethics – on the contrary. Rather the problem is that they are

assumed to be the only matter important to ethics’ (Somerville, 2006, p.2).

While overarching moral concepts or principles are not rejected, they are more

appropriately regarded as anchor points from which to direct and guide ethical

Page 284: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

284

conversations, conversations which rightfully begin and end with the deeply

contextualised relational encounters between staff, patients and the organisation

(Beauchamp, 1999; Pullman, 2005; Walker, 1993). This, inevitably, will consist of

more than the rational analysis of the ‘neutral’ facts97F

98.

Hoffmaster (2006, p.43) further contests the dominant philosophical account noting

that vulnerability and interdependence, rather than rationality and individuality, are

the defining characteristics of the human condition. Hence, any ethically relevant or

resonant foundation must embrace the ontological understandings inherent within

the hermeneutic phenomenological account of the self as embedded, relational,

dialogical, interpretive, historicised and, thus, unique. An orientation to ethics such

as that proposed in Chapter Two which embraces context, considers particularity,

and actively incorporates the role of prior experience into current interpretations thus

lays a more coherent and shared moral foundation of understanding, the ‘implicit

philosophy of human nature’ acknowledged earlier by Pellegrino (2003). The

foundational ontological understandings inherent within the hermeneutical

phenomenological gaze therefore offers a more resonant, robust, and consistent

ethical framework from which to sensitively negotiate patient and practitioner

vulnerability in medical care.

As discussed in Chapter Nine this ethical stance also forms a more realistic basis

from which to support andragogical approaches to education, while prefiguring a

more appropriate ethical base from which patient-centred medicine may be

practically supported. Affecting such a shift in ethical orientation, however,

demands changes to the organisational infrastructure which supports and signals

expectations of ethical behaviour to staff and patients. Critically, it also demands a

changed stance towards practitioner ethics education. These two potential areas of

transformation, organisational infrastructure and practitioner education will now be

more fully considered.

98 One such systematically inclusive ethical decision making tool is the ‘Ethical Matrix’, first outlined by Beauchamp and Childress in 1994. Kaiser and Forsberg (2001) provide a practical account of its use, as applied to a national project assessing future directions for the Norwegian fisheries.

Page 285: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

285

Transforming Practitioner Education

Chapter Two explored the dominant institutionally entrenched views of how ethics

‘ought’ to function in practice, suggesting that these views emanated from various

entrenched, tacitly accepted, and socially reinforced frameworks of medical practice.

For example, the accepted belief in the presence of an overarching moral order that

may be accessed through application of the right rules or laws, or the belief that all

knowledge is valuable, or that science is by definition neutral and objective, are

significantly, though for the most part unreflectively, incorporated into health

practitioner ethics education. Hence, an initial place to open these pre-existing

presumptions to challenge and possibly to transform is in undergraduate,

postgraduate and ongoing health care professional ethics education.

Much health care ethics education centres upon the reductionist, though popular

principlist98F

99 approach to ethical decision making in which the four principles of

Beauchamp and Childress (2001) are methodically applied to various problems or

dilemmas (Cowley, 2005; Liaschenko, Oguz, & Brunnquell, 2006). This approach

tends to promote a particular type of case for which a technical, principlist approach

provides a clear answer, affirming this prescriptive mode of decision making as

reliable and successful. While the ‘tragic case’ (Liaschenko et al., 2006) mode of

teaching ethics is culturally and institutionally appealing, fitting well with the

production of education en masse, it provides limited avenues to highlight the

underlying personal, institutional, social, and cultural determinants that shape the

everyday moral agenda for patients and practitioners alike and, perhaps unwittingly,

entrenches the view that ethical deliberation is best left to ‘experts’. Ultimately,

examination of why some cases rise to prominence while others linger silently

remains unexplored in these often superficial or sterile ethical debates (Caplan, 99 See Beauchamp and Childress (2001). While Beauchamp and Childress give a full and detailed account of each principle, they strongly caution against the use of principles as a canonical script and clearly claim there ought to be no hierarchy in their application. Rather they urge a comprehensive and holistic consideration of each principle within each context. Dilemmatic cases such as the 2005 Terry Schiavo, end of life case in America, the 2005 case of the Queensland woman who had two sets of premature quads within 2 years using Assisted Reproductive Technologies, and the 2006 case of ‘Ashley’, the ‘pillow angel’, a nine year old girl from Seattle, who suffers from static encephalopathy, whose parents requested and received growth inhibiting hormones and surgery to stunt her physical growth and enable them to care for her more easily are routinely framed as a competitive ethical dilemma between the autonomous right of the individual, positioned in conflict with another mutually exclusive principle, such as justice or non-maleficence.

Page 286: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

286

1999; Cowley, 2005; Hoffmaster, 1991; Walker, 1993). Liaschenko et al (2006,

p.672) further claim that taking the dilemmatic case approach to ethics education is

‘of limited value because it limits understandings of moral problems to dilemmas;

negates the moral agency of the student; encourages solutions that are merely

intellectual; and suggests that ethical encounters are a matter for experts’.

Another potential consequence of imparting reductionist models of ‘doing’ ethics

clinically is the increasing trend noted by van den Brink-Muinen et al. (2006.p.334)

for practitioners to regard their ethical obligations solely in terms of seeking consent

in minimalist legal terms from their patients, a trend accompanied by a decreasing

tendency to clarify the ethically critical levels of patient understanding. Indeed

Braddock et al (1997, p.343) reported that practitioners checked for patient

understanding in only 2% of consultations.

Komesaroff (1995, p.67) noted earlier that ‘the vast majority of clinical decisions

are taken in an ethical environment in the absence of any obvious dilemma’. Thus,

conditioning practitioners to understand the ethical within a limited dilemmatic

event framework ultimately impoverishes their human understandings and thus fails

to equip them for the ongoing process of guiding morally sensitive interactions with

possibly vulnerable ‘patient others’ that lies ahead. When ethical debate and

education focuses on extreme examples, an insidious consequence, Kass further

argues (2002, p.2), is that the morality of the commonplace – which is the heart of

the ethical - becomes marginalised,

‘The use of surrogate wombs or the definition of death or guidelines for

terminating life sustaining treatment captures most of the attention- not

surprisingly - but the morality of ordinary practice is largely ignored. Yet

every encounter is an ethical encounter, an occasion for the practice and

cultivation of virtue and respect, and between doctors and patients for the

exercise of responsibility and trust on both sides. How do physicians speak

to patients? Do they have reasonable expectations of their physicians? How

do we, individually and culturally, stand with respect to rearing children,

sharing intimacies, revering life, facing death? In the absence of attention to

Page 287: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

287

these more fundamental and pervasive moral postures and practices, is it

reasonable to expect that an ethics for the extreme cases will be sensibly

worked out even in theory, let alone be successful when ‘applied’ to

practice?’

Thus, there is a strong need for graduate, undergraduate and ongoing professional

ethics education to be ‘re-humanised’, and for ethics education to focus on preparing

practitioners with the necessary hermeneutical insights and sensitivities to enable

them to become responsive ethical interlocutors who might be attuned to the unique

everyday ‘moral sensibilities and affections or habits and customs of moral agents’

as Kass (2002, p.63) suggested earlier. Framing moral understanding in health care

practice as existing between embodied and embedded ‘doers’ in relationships that

are shaped by the dynamics and flow of power inherent in that setting, thus provides

a more meaningful and empowering ethical scaffolding. Ethical encounters are

rather understood and approached as deeply situated human encounters. While these

encounters are guided by the frameworks of values, principles and virtues

appropriate to the caring setting, attention to the contextual particularities and

recognition of the important role of identity and individual subjectivities become

permissible in seeking sensitive and practical outcomes. In essence, health care

ethics must be taught as a transformative, relational, and engaged endeavour. The

role of the practitioner is not one of ethical ‘expert’ or adjudicator; rather, the

practitioners’ moral obligation to themselves, their patients, their practice and their

organisation is to be and become an informed and sensitive interlocutor within the

multiple relationships that define the health care setting.

Instilling such an ethical stance begins with the key revelations that:

• The human condition is one of being and becoming.

• The human self is embedded in multiple contexts of history, culture,

language, relationships, biology, time and spiritual horizons. The unique

culmination of these layers shapes unique moral frameworks for patient and

practitioner alike and defines the multiple ‘goods’ we affirm.

Page 288: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

288

• The illness experience (or illness experience in one’s child flagged by

prenatal screening) can fracture these goods; hence illness, or the threat of

illness, is a time of multiple vulnerabilities.

• Vulnerability calls for a caring response from another, as Hoffmaster notes,

‘vulnerability marks the limits of individualism’ (Hoffmaster, 2006, p.43).

The burgeoning re-emergence of the ‘medical humanities’99F

100 within health care

ethics education provides some practical leadership in enhancing practitioners’

humanistic and ethical understandings of themselves and their patients. Similarly

grounded in a hermeneutical view of the ethical, the medical humanities invite

exploration of individual illness experiences through creative works such as

literature, poetry, music, biography and art. Thus, we are invited to consider the

unique experience of each person, as opposed to viewing the ethical response in

terms of ‘general principles and typical patients’ (Begley, 2003, p.127). Ultimately

however, the transformation of health practitioner education rests upon more than

the simple incorporation of humanities centred activities into the existing

frameworks (although this is a powerful strategy), but by also adopting the

principles of andragogical learning, encouraging practitioners to participate in and

define what they ‘need to know’, by incorporating their prior experiences as a

starting point for ongoing ethics education, and by enabling them to share

responsibility for their own learning as a personally transformative, dialogical and

reciprocal encounter.

The Ethical Role of Patient Educator

A fundamental, though perhaps under-acknowledged, ethical role that practitioners

play is one of patient educator. As illustrated in Chapter Nine, patient education is a

moral imperative; hence, practitioners must be equipped with a fuller appreciation of

the significance of this crucial role. In order to fulfil this role successfully, however,

practitioners must be prepared with firm understandings of educational philosophy

and learner-centred andragogical teaching strategies as these are most fitting in

100 See for example Begley, 2003; Biley & Champney- Smith, 2003; Collett & McLachan, 2006; Darbyshire, 1994; Grant, 2002; Gull, O'Flynn, & Hunter, 2002; Macduff & West, 2002; McKie & Gass, 2001; Milligan & Woodley, 2008; Pullman, Bethune, & Duke, 2005; Weisberg & Duffin, 1995.

Page 289: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

289

facilitating the levels of reflective understanding that patients require in order to give

their informed consent.

In addition to an ethical stance anchored in the lived and living human experience,

understandings of the ethical import of educational philosophy and a commitment to

patient-centred care, practitioners must also possess relevant technical skills and

medical knowledge. While limited research exists on practitioners’ knowledge base

in prenatal screening, the link between a practitioner’s knowledge and their

subsequent ability to appropriately educate, inform and prepare women for testing is

an obvious one. The research that does exist paints a disquieting picture of a practice

in need of attention, and of practitioners in need of support. Sadler’s 1997 survey

undertaken in the United Kingdom of health professionals’ knowledge of serum

screening for Down syndrome, for example, concluded that,

‘Women need accurate information to give informed consent to serum

screening. Most health professionals likely to be involved in antenatal care

in this district do not fully understand the test and are thus unlikely to

provide such information’ (Sadler, 1997, p.176).

Indeed only 14% of obstetricians in Sadler’s 1997 study (ibid) correctly answered

over half the survey questions. While General Practitioners were the most common

initial source of women’s information they scored ‘significantly less than other

groups’ (ibid, p.176). Similarly, Tyzack and Wallace (2003) noted that less than

15% of practitioners provided accurate information on the characteristics of

screening tests regarding Down syndrome, concluding that, ‘the majority of health

professionals in the present survey are not providing their patients with accurate

information about screening in an age-specific manner’(ibid, p.220). More recently

in the United Kingdom, Qureshi, Armstrong, & Modell’s 2006 survey of the GP’s

role in prenatal genetic counselling revealed that GPs displayed,

‘lack of confidence in providing basic prenatal genetic

advice………..indirectly demonstrating a lack of confidence in providing

Page 290: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

290

prenatal advice about the risk of Downs Syndrome’ (Qureshi, Armstrong, &

Modell, 2006, p.109).

Bramwell and Carter (2001, p.139) observed that, when understanding of genetic

anomalies or test accuracy was low, in lieu of providing accurate information on

which a patient could assess and give informed consent, some practitioners offered

information based purely on their own personal judgment of the value of the testing

under consideration. Such personal beliefs held by practitioners often reflected

overestimation of the efficacy and usefulness of screening (ibid).

Accounts offered by some practitioners, and previously discussed throughout this

research, identified similar knowledge gaps in GPs’, suggesting that GP’s may be ill

prepared for the specialised prenatal counselling role. This situation augurs poorly

for the future, as prenatal screening becomes progressively more focused on genetics

and becomes further embedded within an increasingly routinised framework of

antenatal care. As Qureshi et al (2006, p.109) reasonably predict, ‘in the near future,

[GP’s] will be exposed to increasing numbers of antenatal genetic screening tests’.

Given the apparent lack of preparedness or support that GP’s experience, coupled

with the growing complexity of specialised roles that they are expected to fulfil, the

ongoing education and support of practising GP’s remains an area of growing

concern, but also of potential reform. While educational outreach to practitioners is

vital, the problem of how to reach and support those most in need persists as it may

be difficult to engage practitioners in the ongoing education they need. One Midwife

explained, Many GPs have never had to deal with it before, and even within nursing, you don’t put people into areas to do things that they don’t have the skills to do. I certainly wouldn’t want to be put in cardiology……..The assumption is made from the outset that they know it, they do it, they are GP’s, they just do it……………….the assumption is made I guess by the policy makers in the organisation…..[we] need to assess what sort of education is needed….how is it going….and pick up on any comments or complaints that come in. How do you reach the ones that you need to reach because there are a lot who do know? How do you find the ones who don’t know about it? There’s the cost factor too…..you can only send out so much stuff……and the time to prepare so much information…… it’s a difficult task. Last year one of our education sessions was particularly focused on prenatal screening and we had experts from here and a lot of excellent information and that was great and it was well attended, for an education session, they get their continuing education points for it. It was well attended, so….. we had around 50 GP’s………..and there are in excess of 700 in the Brisbane North area alone [7%]. Those are the numbers that turn up to these things, and to a large extent, the ones who turn up are probably the ones who have the interest and have a lot of the knowledge anyway………so….. I do feel that there probably are gaps……….big gaps. Midwife 3

Page 291: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

291

Exploration of what such practitioner education would consist of, or how it could be

most effectively delivered, is not within the scope of this research. However, this

research certainly flags practitioners’ ethical and technical education as potential

areas of ongoing transformation that is likely to have significant impact upon ethical

outcomes for women who engage in prenatal screening.

Open Moral Spaces in Institutional Care

While ethical awareness and sensitivity in practitioners and institutions are sought

and valued by patients, practical considerations of how to nurture the qualities

desired, or how to implement the organisational infrastructure required to support

meaningful and accessible ways of approaching clinical ethics, are less apparent.

However, as individual moral behaviour and agency is significantly shaped by the

normative structures, policies, and organisational procedures, the organisational

ethics infrastructure created (or omitted) significantly influences all stakeholders in

achieving the ethically coherent outcomes desired (Barnett & Vaicys, 2000;

Silverman, 2000).

As positive ethical outcomes for patients have been shown to be significantly

influenced by organisational factors rather than by the professionalism of individual

practitioners alone (Renz & Eddy, 1996; Wildes, 1997 cited by Silverman, 2000),

the healthcare organisation , public or private, must be recognised as having an

active role in shaping the wider ethical climate in which its employees and patients

interact (Silverman, 2000). Suggesting that the hospital organisation is not simply a

neutral location in which independent actors fulfil their various individual roles and

responsibilities, Silverman (ibid, p.205) further claims that

‘ethical issues of the clinic are well beyond the control of the individuals

involved, as the delivery of patient care is situated in a web of organisational

patterns, relationships, structures and processes. Hence, rather than

individual professionalism, the moral dimensions of patient care need to be

conceptualised as being largely influenced by organisational dynamics’.

Page 292: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

292

Hence, institutions need to respond ethically at an organisational level as they have

the capacity to mediate and share ‘the same range of moral responsibilities and

obligations that have traditionally been implicit in the relationships between

physicians and patients’ (ibid, p.204). The type of institutionalised, normative

structures, policies, and procedures endorsed informs employees and patients about

the priorities and intentions of the organisation with respect to the resolution of

ethical issues (Barnett & Vaicys, 2000; Silverman, 2000). The ongoing

transformation of the ethical in health care, therefore, jointly depends upon the

moral integrity and orientation of institutions in conjunction with the values,

capacities, and conduct of those individuals who function within them100F

101.

Philosophically, the understandings of ontology inherent within the

phenomenological paradigm previously indicated in Chapter Two recognise all

stakeholders as embodied, embedded, interpretive, relational, and dialogical.

Margaret Urban Walker’s (2003, pp.59-70) ‘expressive-collaborative’ approach to

clinical ethics, as explored earlier in Chapter Two, suggests that forging a genuinely

collaborative ethical response in institutional care requires the creation of inclusive

and ‘open moral spaces’ where ‘actual dialogue replaces hypothetical methods and

fixed prior constraints on admissible concerns’ (Walker 2003, p.75). In other

words, Walker compels us to commit to entering each other’s narratives as a means

of enhancing our shared ethical understandings, having earlier described the process

of building an ethical response as ‘not a solution to a puzzle, but rather an outcome

of a negotiation’ (1993, p. 36). Again, the promotion of an expressive-collaborative

stance recognises that the ethical, like the educational, is an ongoing and evolving

process of negotiation towards an end point, rather than an isolated event.

While rational deliberation may form a critical part of how we ascribe order and

meaning, moral understanding is primarily realised within the possibilities and

limitations of the multiple layers of our embedded, embodied reality. As the ethical

is characterised in individual lives by a plurality of ‘goods’, located within the

101 A practical organisational framework to support the nurturing of ethical cultures in institutional health care based on educational support, practical consultation advice and policy reform is proposed by Milligan and Winch (2007).

Page 293: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

293

complex interweaving and overlapping of uniquely constructed (and sometimes

professionally moulded) moral frameworks, there is a need to open shared moral

spaces institutionally. The creation of a shared moral space of interlocution is an

ethical imperative as it is within these spaces that the pluralities of understandings of

what is ethically ‘good’ may be built and the best moral outcomes maybe negotiated

as part of a continuing and evolving moral conversation. Adopting this expressive-

collaborative view of institutionally embedded ethics facilitates the creation of

inclusive and open moral spaces, in which ethical conversations rightfully begin and

end with individual subjectivity rather than objectivity, in which particular

contextual and situated knowledge, rather than generalised and abstract meanings,

forms the basis of the organisational ethical discourse. Indeed, it is precisely these

shared moral spaces that invite individuals to open themselves to the ethical plight

and perspective of ‘the other’, thus widening the scope of ethically permissible

conversations and laying the foundations of a more inclusive framework for

operationalising ethics in the clinic.

The provision of such a space institutionally requires leadership, commitment, and

financial support. It further requires that the dominating production models of care

delivery, which have encouraged the adoption of reductionist understandings of

ethics, be challenged as when staff remain overcommitted and under resourced the

time or the place for critical ethical and educational conversations become incurably

undermined. Finally, however, Meyers (2007, p.35) cautions, ‘merely creating a

venue for everyone to speak cannot equalise the balance of power and produce

genuine consensus’. Rosemary Tong similarly counsels that where ‘all voices are

not heard, … the moral truth does not emerge’ (Tong, 2002, p. 420). Any physical

space must, therefore, be accompanied by the appropriate intellectual or

philosophical space in which the attitudinal stance advocated throughout this work

of embracing ethics as incorporating the appreciative, the hermeneutic the appraisive

and the transformative. Finally, it will be a space where ethics is explicitly

recognised as an ongoing conversation between informed, ethically sensitive and

hermeneutically aware interlocutors embedded in a web of dynamic relationships, an

expressive-collaborative space (Walker, 1993, 2003).

Page 294: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

294

Transforming Policy

Health care policy, whether imposed externally from government directives or

generated internally within particular institutions, significantly shapes the available

options, expectations, and resources with respect to how (or even if) the ethical is

supported in practice. As previously indicated the organisational policies governing

the internal resourcing of procedures, of setting acceptable standards of care, or of

signalling expectations about which outcomes are clinically or morally relevant,

significantly contribute to the ethical landscape inhabited by staff and patients

(Barnett & Vaicys, 2000; Silverman, 2000).

In Australia, for example, access to government funded Medicare rebates for a

particular procedure signals communal endorsement, politically sanctioning and

legitimising the worth of such intervention. As the clinical geneticist noted,

Legitimising it in many ways means giving it a Medicare item number and that really makes the difference in terms of availability or access and uptake because part of that is consideration of how much these things cost……if you’ve got to put some dollars on the table, you have to show some level of commitment to wanting that test, but if it’s free or bulk billed under a Medicare item number, then it can happen without really…..your direct assent, in a sense. So cost is an important factor in terms of what is routinely offered. Clinical Geneticist.

Similarly, the levels of resourcing, staffing and time allotted to particular

consultations further delimit clinicians’ scope of practice by forcing them to reduce

and prioritise which aspects of screening will be given preference within the limited

time fixed. As one genetic counsellor noted,

Well…… in 15 minutes there’s not a lot of time …………….look it’s pretty much a technical discussion for good or bad………….it’s seen as very much an education of this is what it is…these are the type results it will give you. Genetic Counsellor 2

Lack of time was cited by several practitioners as negatively influencing their

capacity to engage in meaningful moral dialogue with women, as illustrated in the

following comments. Particularly inside this particular hospital, you know they don’t have an hour to talk with patients, in fact, they don’t even have 20 minutes to talk with a patient, and they have 10 minutes. How do you develop a rapport in 10 minutes? How do you determine what this lady’s thoughts are and steer your thoughts in line with hers? You don’t. Midwife 1

Page 295: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

295

There’s not the time or effort to put into women who need instant information, even although they have known they are pregnant for some months and have quietly ignored it. Really, GP’s are a bit the same; they are running that day to day stuff – how much time do they really have to teach women everything – they really don’t. Midwife 2

However, not taking the time may ultimately be counterproductive as the

constructive therapeutic and educational partnership that supports the ethical aims of

practice is undermined and patient outcomes suffer (Say & Thomson, 2003).

Empirical research is clearly showing that time spent establishing good

communicative partnerships often results in lower patient anxiety, increased trust

and confidence, higher physician and patient satisfaction, decreased referrals, and

decreased number of medical malpractice suits (Bekker, Hewison, & Thornton,

2003; Levinson, Roter, Mullooly, & Frankel, 1997; Stewart, 1995; Stewart et al.,

2000). However, Braddock (2002, p.351) challenges the assumption that patient-

centred consultations take longer, making the point that ‘the key issue may not be the

amount, but rather, the quality of the dialogue’. Similarly Bub (2004) advocates for

the ‘need to listen better not longer’ (Bub, 2004, p.64) and Waitskin and Stoeckle

(1976, cited by Wear, 1998, p.54) observed that clinicians overestimated the time

required to achieve informed consent from their patients by a factor of nine times.

Most of the authors cited above acknowledge that initial consultations to establish a

rapport and strong therapeutic relationship may take longer; however, the ongoing

benefits recorded suggest efforts to educate practitioners promote better

communication patterns and pay very practical dividends.

Additional policy considerations include the discourse of cost–benefit models of

analyses which often accompany the introduction of prenatal screening programmes

and policies. These may be interpreted as legitimising or lending communal

endorsement to the underlying eugenic presumptions inherent within such

procedures and are therefore ethically contentious. Some professional codes of

practice, notably the Australian Society of Genetic Counsellors (ASGC, 2000,

p.4) 101F

102 reject financially focused justifications for widespread screening stating,

102 See www.hgsa.com.au/images/UserFiles/Attachments/ASGCCodeofEthics.pdf (Accessed 8th August 2007)

Page 296: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

296

‘when aiming to reduce the burden of genetic disease in the community,

genetics services should strive to ensure that economic and other

considerations are of secondary importance to the physical and

psychological needs of the individual’.

While this statement suggests that financial implications should be given secondary

consideration, as Lippman (1991) noted earlier, the very telos of the practice of

genetic counselling is directive, premised on the belief that certain conditions

(although which particular ones is open to debate and individual interpretation) are

inherently too burdensome to bear. The promotion of screening protocols emerges

from a professional practice significantly defined by a discourse of risk which

presupposes an ideal of perfection that can be aspired to.

While production models of care significantly undermine the relationship building

and rapport required to foster an appropriate therapeutic partnership and to enhance

patient learning, perhaps the most influential policy shaping institutional and

individual practitioner behaviour with respect to prenatal screening protocols (and

hence, indirectly shape women’s experience and access to such screening) is the law

governing termination of pregnancy. In Queensland, termination of pregnancy falls

under the Queensland Criminal Code 102F

103, although lawful ‘therapeutic’ termination

can be procured on the grounds of threats to the physical health of the mother103F

104. A

direct consequence of this position as discussed in Chapter Six is an erosion of

transparency which stifles the collection of important public health information

relating to the numbers and reasons for termination as a consequence of prenatal

screening. Adequately informed reflection and ownership of this widely accepted

intervention is subsequently severely inhibited.

The widely accepted (or perhaps even expected by some) practice of termination

following an unwelcome prenatal diagnosis is therefore arguably out of step with the

103 See Section 224, 225 and 226 of the Queensland Criminal Code which states, ‘Any person who, with intent to procure the miscarriage of a woman , whether she is or is not with child, unlawfully administers to her or caused her to take any poison or other noxious thing, or uses force of any kind, or uses other means whatever is guilty of a crime , and is liable to imprisonment for 14 years’ (Shanahan, Smith, Ryan, & Carter, 2005, p.438) 104 Under Section 282 of the Queensland Criminal Code. Many practitioners cite psychological health as a mitigating circumstance; however, this is not specifically articulated in the law.

Page 297: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

297

law in Queensland as it currently stands. The placement of termination under the

Criminal Code places the emphasis on cementing a defensive legal justification as

opposed to one of exploring the human consequences, without fear of prosecution.

Often, the privatisation and individuation that flows from such a defensive legal

stance inhibits open reflection as many of these decisions become concealed from

the public discourse. Practitioners, too, find themselves occupying contestable legal

ground with respect to such terminations under what are predominantly ‘unclear and

complex state abortion laws’ (de Crispegny & Savulescu, 2004, para 5; MacFarlane

& Reid, 2006, p. 155). With the Criminal Code in Queensland clearly stating that

any procedure is to be a ‘surgical operation’, its purpose reserved ‘for the

preservation of the mother’s life’ (Shanahan et al., 2005, p.506), the grounds of

termination to preserve the psychological wellbeing of the mother due to fetal

abnormality remain contestable in Queensland law. Additionally, the presumption

that a disability in one’s child may cause inevitable, unresolvable psychological

harm of the magnitude that would endanger the mother’s life seems yet another tacit

endorsement and reinforcement of the master narrative defining disability as

tragedy. This lack of clarity potentially places practitioners in a grey legal area, one

which promotes fear and encourages the concealment and silencing observed.

Figures collated from the 1998 law reform in Western Australia and termination

rates recorded in South Australia where termination has been more readily

accessible since 1970 reveal that decriminalisation of termination appears not to

have opened the floodgates on abortion in those states. As previously mentioned,

both of these states retain similar, or even slightly reduced, per capita rates of

terminations compared to the Australian average104F

105 (Chan & Sage, 2005; Grayson et

al., 2005; Straton et al., 2006, p.3). While the intention of current laws in

Queensland may be to acknowledge and enshrine the value of human life, the

figures of state based comparisons suggest that the law as it stands does not appear

to be curtailing the practice of termination in Queensland105F

106. In spite of the legal

obstacles, abortion is available, in effect, on demand for any reason in Queensland.

The ethical consequence of this is that women are denied open and transparent

105 See footnote 69, p.180. 106 Although, there are numerous geographical and demographic factors that contribute to these figures that are not analysed in the documents quoted.

Page 298: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

298

access to relevant counselling services while overall community understanding of

the reasons and drivers of termination cannot be meaningfully addressed in a public

health sense as the appropriate data which would significantly inform such public

debate is not collected. Perhaps, and paradoxically, law reform with respect to

termination in Queensland may form a critical plank in creating a more ethically

transparent culture in which the links between prenatal diagnosis and termination

may be openly considered and assessed.

Injecting consistency into data collection and analysis.

The need to collect ‘evidence’ about particular medical interventions is increasingly

regarded as essential to reflecting upon and refining ‘best practice’ in clinical care.

Such an evidence base is broadly claimed to enable doctors and patients to make the

best possible clinical decisions (Kerridge, Lowe, & Henry, 1998) and is generally

regarded as a superior approach to refining and assessing practice than the more

subjective methods of the past (Bastian, 1994; Hope, 1995). Indeed, Solomon

(2005) argues that collecting and analysing appropriate data can ‘stimulate

individual and institutional moral accountability’ (Solomon, 2005, p.43) by creating

an essential feedback loop which simultaneously motivates individual reflection

while ensuring institutional accountability. Solomon (ibid) further notes, ‘without

data to prove that the problem is local - ‘here in our own institution’- it is too easy

to dismiss the problems as not relevant to us’. Thus, there is a strong need for local

institutions to commit to the collection, analysis, and incorporation of local

‘evidence’ on outcomes into policy direction and evaluation. Comments from the

practitioners of this cohort suggest that a significant, and negative, consequence of

the legal framework of termination in Queensland has been that the collection of the

data necessary to assess current policy and inform future policy direction lacks

transparency and is not coherently tracked in practice.

In terms of prenatal screening, Dr Kypros Nicolaides, who is credited with

developing and validating nuchal translucency as a robust screening instrument, has

commented that, when making any new screening test routine, it is critical that the

results and accumulated data are subjected to ‘rigorous audit’ (Nicolaides, Heath, &

Page 299: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

299

Cicero, 2002, p.308). Currently in Queensland, although nuchal translucency is

becoming increasingly routinised, the recommended ‘rigorous audit’ appears not to

be methodically occurring. While the efficacy of nuchal translucency screening is

known to be highly operator dependent requiring significant specialised training

(Braithwaite et al., 1996; Nicolaides, Snijders, & Cuckle, 1998), critical

comparisons between the numerous public and private providers in Queensland on

false positives, false negatives, predictive values, and consequential terminations

across facilities are not routinely collected or assessed. Hence, the critical evidence

base for reflecting upon whether such outcomes sit comfortably with the expected

medical goals and communal moral values is lost, as is the ability to assess the

extent of avoidable psychological harm being experienced by women.

However, it is not only data on nuchal translucency that is missing. Collation of data

on the number of terminations carried out due to suspected birth anomalies

identified prenatally is also missing from the Queensland equation as these incidents

are not recorded prior to 20 weeks when most terminations occur. As the

obstetrician explained: The lack of data collection on products of conception, from both miscarriage and termination, results in the loss of valuable demographic information about actual incidences of birth defects. These are not compiled at all if a pregnancy ends before 20 weeks in Queensland. Confidentiality means that these stats can’t be gathered and there is no legal requirement. Obstetrician.

National Medicare data tracking such outcomes is also incomplete as there is no

mandatory requirement to report terminations (Pratt et al., 2004). Similarly, post

mortem results to corroborate suspected diagnoses appear not to be routinely

pursued in practice and, thus, are not assessed in any meaningful way that could

inform practice. Previously published research elsewhere has shown that prenatal

diagnosis is fully supported by autopsy findings in 60-80% of cases (Laussel-Riera

et al., 2000; Ramalho et al., 2006, p.1087; Tennstedt et al., 1998), leaving 20-40% in

doubt. Hence, this information, which could provide a critical check and balance on

practice and be incorporated into informed decision making, remains lost to women,

practitioners, and policy makers. As Ramalho et al (2006, pp.1087-8) conclude, the

systematic evaluation of all cases of elective termination is imperative in assessing

the adequacy and worth of prenatal diagnosis. The following comments illustrate the

extent and consequences of the problem locally.

Page 300: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

300

We have no record….because what happens for example is a woman with a soft marker picked up in a private scanning clinic goes down to the Royal, and they may offer a CVS or amnio, they go back to their region because the Royal is a tertiary centre and they never know whether that woman decided to continue with the pregnancy or not… That’s the problem across Australia I think…you can’t get reliable data, Queensland I think doesn’t [collect data on terminations]… there is a maternal morbidity and mortality registry and also, I don’t know whether all labs have to send in products of conception or abnormal chromosome results…I don’t think they do..… I think there should be… so we could for example… when we give figures like there’s a 1:85 chance that a woman of 40 yrs old will have a baby with Down syndrome, is it really that? We haven’t included in our population the terminations and products of conception lost so we can’t include those figures….. I think it’s definitely a necessity. Genetic Counsellor 1

There’s no collection of information about the area of prenatal testing, and so if in Queensland for example, termination of pregnancy. …I think if we’re not collecting this information, then you can’t inform the community about what’s actually happening, so we can’t make decisions about whether that is good or not so good if we’re not aware of the data. I do think we should have better collection of things like prenatal tests. For example, in Victoria, uptake and outcome and it’s a quality assurance in many ways…is … much better developed and I think it’s a mistake of Queensland not to have some way of collecting information on numbers of amnio’s, what happens as a consequence because then the community doesn’t know and can’t meaningfully influence whether that’s a good thing or not. Clinical Geneticist

These comments illustrate that valuable data in determining what aspects of prenatal

screening practice are indeed ‘relevant to us’, are not methodically collected in

Queensland. However, as the clinical geneticist noted, while the lack of government

commitment to provide the structural and financial resources to pursue such data

analysis and incorporate it into policy development remains, the barriers to securing

an evidence based practice will continue. However, developing such a register

would require financial commitment, a commitment that is currently not a funding

priority as the clinical geneticist noted,

It would have to happen like a registry, like a cervical registry, Pap smear registry that data gather…….. You could for instance have the data from the pathology laboratories that receive amniocentesis samples or CVS samples because they are specialised tests done in relatively few labs that could be a point of contact, they could be de-identified. The other problem is that we don’t really have a way of following up in the fragmented health care system, as to what happens after ………so, in other words, if many of these tests are performed in the private sector, the follow up imposes costs on private doctors who would have to be paid to extract the data…so, it’s probably a resources issue as much as anything else. How would that be useful well…. informing the community about these issues would be of benefit…at least people would know what was happening ……I think it would be enormously useful …. I guess one of the problems is the quality of obstetrics services in general, with a lack of doctors employed to develop policies etc, so, there’s not been the infrastructure to systematically implement a program of that sort. So that’s a resources issue….Clinical Geneticist.

Page 301: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

301

Importantly, however, the presence of reliable evidence does not automatically

ensure that better decisions will be made (Goldenberg, 2005; Kerridge et al., 1998;

Stewart, 2001b), and the claim that evidence based medicine inevitably offers an

improved method of decision making may be difficult to discern, particularly in the

local context where current practice is so inconsistent. Additionally, medical

decision making inevitably draws upon a broad range of ‘knowledges’, filtered

through various interpretative frameworks such as the values of science, personal

experience and biases, or economic and political considerations. Not surprisingly,

like all human beings, practitioners, too, adopt definitions of evidence that

‘reflects their own interests and bias’ (Stewart, 2001, p.287). Kerridge et al (1998,

p. 1151) further note:

‘It is not always clear how practitioners integrate these factors into a final

decision, but it seems unlikely that medicine can ever be entirely free of

value judgments’.

Hence, while the word ‘evidence’ may suggest an unfaltering and steadfast reality,

there can be no objective standard in terms of how such evidence is collected or

interpreted and the consequentialist view implied by the term ‘evidence’ ultimately

may not accommodate the ethical and medical realities of clinical decision making

(Stewart, 2001). Many important outcomes may never be sufficiently calculated or

defined, and crucially, without evidence is not without value. Accordingly, the types

of evidence privileged in seeking an evidence based approach inevitably stem from

sources of ‘authoritative knowledge’, entrenching a hierarchy in which quantitative

measurable outcomes are elevated at the expense of qualitative or subjective

knowledge (ibid). Goldenberg (2005, p.284) concludes:

‘Popular thinking holds, however, that if it is neutrality that is desired,

numbers are the pinnacle. In this age of the ascendancy of health outcomes

research, where statistical analysis dominates health policy decision making,

“evidence” is tantamount to measure not meaning’.

In the final analysis, however, ‘evidence’, complete with its limitations and selective

interpretations, can still contribute valuable insights to the wider considerations of

the outcomes of testing by clarifying which questions ought to be raised by

Page 302: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

302

providing relevant supporting information to identify the gaps in knowledge that

might incorporate ethical reflection into the evolving policy debate.

In practical terms in Queensland, in conjunction with law reform, important steps to

address the procedural gaps with respect to data management and analysis could

begin with the mandatory reporting of terminations, and the adopting of a central

database modelled on that operating in South Australia (Pratt et al., 2004).

However, termination constitutes only one aspect and there are many areas of

practice in need of more careful deliberation and reflection. Additional areas which

would yield meaningful data with direct impact on the practice and protocols of

routine prenatal screening include,

• Differential collection of data relating to the numbers of terminations as a

consequence of prenatal screening.

• Collection of data tracking the outcomes of amniocentesis and miscarriage

rates and comparison between particular practitioners/institutions with

clinically expected rates.106F

107

• Injecting some consistency into following the outcomes of particular patients

who move between facilities or between the public and private sectors.

• Instigating some longitudinal studies correlating nuchal translucency results

to the long term health outcomes of children. These are needed to refine the

ongoing validity and interpretation of nuchal results and will also contribute

to updating of professional standards and accreditation.

• Instigating a central register collecting data on genetic make-up of products

of conception from terminations and miscarriages for verification of prenatal

diagnosis.

This list is by no means comprehensive, and while comment on the reporting,

analysis, and efficacy of health statistics is not within the scope of this research, the

role of managing this data more effectively has been flagged by several practitioners

in this cohort as having the potential to positively contribute to a more robust,

107 While assessing individual practitioners remains a controversial and widely debated topic, and there may be clinical reasons why certain practitioners appear to have less favourable patient outcomes, this may be a way of identifying those professionals in need of support, and may provide an additional safeguard for patients.

Page 303: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

303

evidence based practice and policy formation. While much of this data is potentially

‘available’, it is not currently being extracted or analysed in ways that have a

meaningful impact on developing understanding of the underlying social

determinants of practice or being incorporated into refining more ethically

responsive and coherent medical protocols.

Transforming Faith in Technology: Challenging the Sacred Narratives of Science

‘Man (sic) is gifted with pity and other kindly feelings: he has also the power

of preventing many kinds of suffering. I conceive it well within his province

to replace Natural Selection by other processes that are more merciful and

not less effective’ (Sir Frances Galton, 1908, from The Galton Institute107F

108,

formerly the Eugenics Education Society).

The development, funding and access to prenatal screening and other reproductive

technologies occur in a political space shaped by existing societal values, beliefs and

prejudices. In our Western, (mostly) educated, individualistic society, the political

space is one in which the pursuit of science has come to hold a kind of powerful

cultural imperialism (Lindemann-Nelson,2001). Where the biotechnology revolution

is presented as progressive, scientific, and rational, to stand in question is to be cast

automatically, and appositionally, as backward, prejudiced, and illogical. Hence, the

culturally revered pursuit of science and our belief in the perfectibility doctrine it

promotes reinforces our ongoing commitment to scientific progress.

Cultural images of biotechnology as trustworthy and ‘self correcting’ (Nelkin, 1996)

further deflect any critique of the practices of science, while the agenda of the wider

public discourse, according to Duster (2003, p.xiii), is shaped by experts such as

geneticists, medical specialists, lawyers, and researchers on one hand and critics on

the other, portrayed as ‘nannies, naysayers, know-nothings and luddites who put

their heads in the sand and try to stop the machinery of progress’. When collective

scrutiny and accountability is placed into the private realm of individual hands (via

108 The Galton Institute ‘exists to promote the public understanding of human heredity and to facilitate informed debate about the ethical issues raised by advances in reproductive technology’. www.galtoninstitute.org.uk (Accessed 4th February, 2006).

Page 304: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

304

autonomy and choice), the technological agenda becomes an essentially self

regulating body, closed off to public inspection. Under these conditions, which

Margaret Urban Walker describes as ‘privatisation’ (Walker, 1998, p.172), the

subtly coercive dimensions of these practices can become hidden from public view,

closing avenues of public reflection and critique.

While the technological revolution of science promises perfection or restoration, in

the case of prenatal screening, at least, the capacity to treat has not kept pace with

the capacity to diagnose. Additionally, true ‘prevention’ remains mostly

undelivered, largely beyond the grasp of current screening technologies whose

focus is centred on detecting a disability after it already exists. Explanations offered

in scientific terms are often incomplete, and the selective information deemed

worthy of pursuing is predominantly driven by what existing technologies can

measure, rather than what individual parents may want to know. Indeed, this

selective ‘knowledge’ is often tenaciously pursued, even when parents express deep

scepticism or disinterest as to its alleged worth as Penny, Elizabeth, Terri and

Danielle experienced. With respect to prenatal screening, such knowledge is rarely

pursued with the intention of offering a practical cure, other than the offer of a

‘medically indicated’ or ‘therapeutic’ termination.

While conceding that human behaviour is vastly complex, reductionist accounts,

including reductionist genetic accounts, of these complexities, often removed from

the cultural and social interpretive frameworks that shape them are interpreted as

scientific fact. Exploring the socially embedded nature of science, Duster (2003)

notes that behavioural geneticists are not looking for genetic markers of corporate

crime, toe size, or even eye colour – rather, they focus on entrenching existing

culturally endorsed preferences and prejudices, focusing, for example, on research

into disability, mental illness, intellectual impairment, intelligence, or athleticism.

While many human characteristics have a genetic component, the genetic

knowledge we chose to pursue is largely framed by social and cultural

determinants, hence, the pursuit of genetic information is not simply a neutral

scientific pursuit.

Page 305: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

305

However, faith in technology to deliver the longed for healthy child persists and

misunderstandings about the limitations of technology to secure this outcome

continue to permeate the prenatal debate. As discussed earlier, some commentators

now claim that it is morally remiss of a parent not to enhance their child genetically,

claiming it is ‘rational to want the best possible child’ (Aldred et al., 2003, p.337;

Savulescu, 2005). While medicine has undoubtedly made great advances in many

areas, future claims of genetic redemption must be tempered with an awareness of

the culturally situated human context into which these revelations are made. We

must ask ourselves if the eradication of human suffering is really achievable, or if

the embodied human condition is inevitably one of unpredictability, vulnerability,

interdependence, and fragility, as opposed to one of domination of nature through

science, individual power and invincibility. Perhaps recognising some of the story-

like qualities of the technological imperative may be an important anchor point in

developing a more accountable and humane use of technology.

Finally, while embracing the ‘technological imperative’ may hold great promise for

the relief of pain and suffering, improved quality of life, and enhanced well being

for many, the challenge remains of ‘how do we support the humane and ethical use

of such technologies, in ways that do not further re-enforce discriminatory and

stigmatizing practices?’ Our capacity to confront and address this question will

shape the ethical tone of the future.

Transforming Individuals

As previously indicated, individual and institutional transformations must occur

simultaneously and in partnership as in reality they are inseparably interwoven, each

defining, enhancing or limiting the other. The suggested institutional

transformations included broadening and redefining clinical accounts of ethics,

creating open and accessible ethical spaces and stances within the organisational

infrastructure, re-humanising clinical ethics education for practitioners, supporting

practitioner technical education, embracing law reform, and challenging the sacred

narratives of technological progress as categorically progressive and good.

Page 306: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

306

The remainder of this chapter will forward some suggestions for the transformation

of individuals who access care, or who work within the healthcare system.

Individual transformation may be facilitated through a commitment to collaborative

shared decision making between clinician and patient via effective communication

for patients and physicians alike. Such education and communication must be

informed by adopting accessible and appropriate methods of patient education based

on portraying an accurate and balanced picture of the aims and potential outcomes of

screening, presented in terms that are accessible and in line with the level of health

literacy of the patient. Each of these considerations will now be discussed more

thoroughly.

Enhancing Patient Participation – Supporting Shared Decision Making within a

Framework of Patient-Centred Care

There is a growing awareness among practitioners, increasingly cemented in health

care policy and law reform108F

109, that patients should rightfully have a central role in

contributing to decisions concerning their own health care and that they, for the most

part, seem to welcome this extended role (Bub, 2004; Coulter & Magee, 2003;

Elwyn et al., 1999; Fisher et al., 2005; Godolphin et al., 2001; Little, Everitt,

Williamson, Warner, & al, 2001; Say & Thomson, 2003; Stewart et al., 2000;

Stewart et al., 2003; Towle & Godolphin, 1999; Weston, 2001; Weston & Belle-

Brown, 1989). The intentional acceptance of more ‘patient-centred’ care, of which

shared decision making (SDM) is a key feature, better supports patient autonomy

and is also regarded as a more appropriate and respectful basis from which to form

strong therapeutic partnerships. Patient-centred care ideally incorporates five key

characteristics. These are:

• Adopting a multidimensional understanding of illness as a social,

psychological and biomedical event.

• Seeking understanding of the ‘patient as person’, exploring the impact of

illness on each individual patient. This includes eliciting the patient’s

feelings, expectations and understandings. 109 Examples include more open access to medical records, freedom of information legislation and policy reform such as that in the UK discussed in Fisher 2005.

Page 307: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

307

• Sharing power and responsibility by fostering more egalitarian relationships

within the medical setting and negotiating common ground in partnership.

• Forming a therapeutic alliance based on mutual trust. The therapeutic

alliance must also be mindful of health promotion and risk reduction.

• Incorporating awareness of the ‘doctor as person’ and the impact that

personal qualities may have on developing ongoing partnerships and on how

medicine is practiced.

(Little et al., 2001, p.469; Mead, Bower, & Hann, 2002, p.285; Stewart et al.,

2003)

The key elements of sharing power and building mutual trust in the therapeutic

partnership has generated a rising tide of commentary in the literature reflecting the

cultural shift towards SDM109F

110. While the recent systematic review of SDM

undertaken by Makoul and Clayman (2006) concluded there was no singular

definition, or commonly understood features, of SDM, they describe it as an

intentional mode of patient/practitioner interaction defined by a partnership of

mutual respect, of equally valuing patient preferences, of discussing all options,

benefits and risks, of facilitating appropriate education, and of negotiation,

deliberation and seeking of mutual agreement on health care decisions (Makoul &

Clayman, 2006, p.304).

Adopting shared decision making within a patient-centred model of care appears to

have many positive health outcomes such as reducing excessive diagnostic testing

and ongoing referrals, lowering the incidence of malpractice suits, reducing anxiety,

increasing patient compliance with treatment regimes 110F

111, improving health literacy

of patients and generally improving the health status of individuals (Levinson et al.,

1997; Stewart, 1995; Stewart et al., 2000). Such positive outcomes Stewart (2000,

p.799) claims are directly attributable to patient perceptions of being included as a

110 Other permutations and incarnations of SDM include Godolphin and Towle’s (2001) Informed Shared Decision Making (ISDM) and Trevena and Barrat’s (2003) Integrated Decision Making (IDM). 111 Goodwin-Johansson (1988) and Raffle (2001) caution against structuring patient education in overly optimistic terms as a means of ensuring ‘compliance’ as this potentially undermines patient autonomy and creates falsely high expectations of treatment. Irrespective of whether a patient ultimately accepts the preferred medical recommendation, the aim of patient education is to genuinely support reflective understanding.

Page 308: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

308

full participant in the clinical encounter rather than as a mere passive recipient of

treatment.

While the potential benefits seem compelling, Braddock (1999) notes that Shared

Decision Making is rarely achieved in practice and others report uncertainty over

how to actualise SDM in clinical care (Little et al., 2001). Hence, despite a palpable

cultural drift in support of SDM, a wealth of research is still being generated

indicating that patients frequently feel they are currently not receiving as much

information as they need, that they are significantly dissatisfied with health

encounters, and that most would welcome a more active role in the decision making

process than they are currently afforded (Leithner et al., 2006, p. 937).

Even with practitioner and patient receptiveness to SDM, significant challenges and

barriers exist. While most practitioners welcome change and see partnership with

patients as positive and productive, Fisher et al (2005, p.531) have noted a residual

reluctance to ‘let go’, claiming that shared decision making may be interpreted by

some as ‘disturbing and undermining’ (ibid). Additionally, clinicians who are

primarily trained to deal with the physical dimensions of care may be poorly

equipped in their training to communicate effectively with patients as required by

the SDM process. Within the predominant disease-centred model of training

experienced by health practitioners, emotional and psychological issues may become

relegated to a residual role (Zecca, Gradi, Nilsson, Bellotti, & al, 2006, p.129).

Consequently, some authors claim that practitioners may lack an awareness of the

emotional impact of illness on a person’s life (Bub, 2004; Fisher et al., 2005; Mead

et al., 2002; Say & Thomson, 2003). However, it is precisely an awareness of the

emotional and psychological dimensions of care in practitioners that patients value

when assessing what characteristics make a ‘good’ physician (Di Blasi, Harkness,

Ernst, Georgiou, & Kleijnen, 2001; Duberstein et al., 2007; Laidlaw et al., 2007).

Further factors inhibiting the realisation of SDM include the presumption that it will

inevitably take extra time which practitioners don’t have111F

112; that limited educational

materials are available to scaffold or support patient involvement; that some

physicians are simply more comfortable retaining the traditional paternalistic way of

112 Although this claim is refuted. See Braddock, 2002; Bub, 2004; Stewart, 1995 and Wear, 1998 .

Page 309: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

309

relating; that low levels of communication competency are widely apparent in

patients and practitioners; and, finally, as discussed earlier, that some practitioners

simply lack the technical knowledge, and thus confidence, to invite too open a

relationship with their patients. Patients too may be reluctant to share what they

believe to be their less authoritative knowledge in a relationship often characterised

by a perceived imbalance of power (Say & Thomson, 2003).

The apparent ‘reluctance’ to participate may be masking a lack of confidence rather

than an active renunciation of decision making. While some patients do genuinely

express less desire to be actively involved in decision making (Coulter, Entwistle,

& Gilbert, 1999; Edwards & Elwyn, 2001; McKinstry, 2000; Schneider, 1996),

being patient-centred is not about wilfully imposing an additional decisional

burden on patients who are unwilling or unable to accept the invitation. Rather,

shared decision-making in a framework of patient-centred care actually means

‘taking into account the patient’s desire for information and for sharing decisions

and for responding appropriately’ (Stewart, 2001a, p.445). Inevitably, establishing

this foundational insight into the evolving therapeutic partnership will begin with a

dialogue between patient and practitioner. As Connelly (2005) notes, it will begin

with a ‘mindfulness’, an openness to help the patient tell their story and a

commitment to value this unique story when it is told.

‘Physicians must be able to help the patient tell the story that is most

important, meaningful and descriptive of the situation. If the patients’

narrative is not heard fully, the possibility of diagnostic and therapeutic

error increases, the likelihood of personal connections resulting from a

shared experience diminishes, empathic opportunities are missed and

patients may not feel understood or cared for’ ( Connelly, 2005, p.84).

Hence, the adoption of patient-centred care and the realisation of SDM in practice

will require effective communication skills from all parties in an educational

encounter based on accurate and balanced information in a receptive institutional

environment. It is to these two considerations, communication and patient education,

that we will now turn our attention.

Page 310: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

310

Enhancing Patient /Provider Communication

As narratively constructed beings, the ability to communicate and convey our

personal stories, to speak, to listen to, and to be heard by each other, lies at the heart

of human ethical engagement in the medical arena as elsewhere. As an entry portal

into the unique moral perceptions, understandings, and experiences of another

human being, effective communication forms the bedrock of the ethical encounter.

Chapters Two and Three outlined the ethical importance of narrative, noting that the

sharing of experiences through dialogue can improve common understandings,

uncovering the rich complexities of individual lives, and better informing our ethical

judgements. Narrative and dialogue, or communication are, therefore, pivotal in

shaping the ethical agenda and there is a strong need to foster constructive

communication competencies in all individuals within open moral spaces within

institutions.

In spite of the acknowledged association between good communication and

enhanced health outcomes for patients, the research journals are full of examples

lamenting the consistently poor state of health care communication (Bub, 2004;

Cristofalo et al., 2006; Leithner et al., 2004), failures that often translate into

alienation, crisis, physical harm and potentially moral harm. Physicians are

recognised as having a potentially powerful influence on promoting patient

involvement and opening strong communication channels. Generally, however, it

appears that behaviours that optimize patient participation, such as promoting active

partnership building and the use of supportive talk, are under used by practitioners

in practice (Street, Gordon, Ward, Krupat, & Kravitz, 2005). Consequently, much

attention has been focussed on improving the communication skills or competencies

of physicians. Competent communication by practitioners includes the development

of active listening skills, and is further characterised by personal and professional

qualities of empathy, non-judgement and self reflection and the ability to identify

and address the emotional concerns of the patient (Barry, Bradley, Britten,

Stevenson, & Barber, 2000; Laidlaw et al., 2007; Post et al., 2002).

Page 311: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

311

Importantly however, communication is a dialogue, requiring input from both

parties. As the patient is the crucial ‘other half of the whole’ in the communication

dyad, some researchers are increasingly turning their gaze to the patient’s role in

shaping medical communication (Cegala, 2006; Cegala et al., 2004; Cegala &

Lenzmeier Broz, 2003; Cegala et al., 2007; Post et al., 2002; Street et al., 2005). The

reason for this shift in emphasis is not to excuse poor communication in

practitioners or to relinquish physician responsibility but to understand and support

the positive and potent effect that high patient participation is observed to have on

the overall quality of health communication and subsequent health outcomes. In

their review of sixteen randomised control trials assessing the impact of teaching

patients to communicate on health outcomes, Post et al (2002, p.344) concluded that

there was a direct link between patient communication training and improved health

related outcomes.

High participating patients engender a different communication dynamic with their

practitioners described by Cegala et al (2007, p.124) as follows,

‘When interacting with high participation patients, physicians volunteer

more information about treatment–related topics such as risks and benefits,

treatment options, side effects and descriptions of what treatments entail

than when interacting with low–participation patients’.

Additionally, the greater feelings of control and equalizing of the perceived power

imbalance by high participating patients also benefits physicians as effective patient

communicators are less likely to use indirect, or non-verbal ‘hints’, in conveying

their concerns (Cegala et al., 2007; Post et al., 2002; Street et al., 2005). Indeed,

high participating patients are more likely to directly disclose their ‘full selves’

(Barry et al , 2000, p,1250) thus facilitating the physician’s capacity to actively

listen (Post et al., 2002). Accordingly, the transformation of health care

communication depends upon several factors including the particular context, the

particular communication skills of the individuals involved, access to training

programs which develop communication competencies in patients and providers,

and an awareness of the ethical significance of effective communication.

Page 312: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

312

Communicating What? Promoting Accurate and Balanced Information

Underlying decisions regarding what information is to be communicated, by and to

whom, for what purpose, and to whose detriment or benefit, significantly prefigure

and shape the tone of any evolving conversation. With respect to prenatal testing, an

area of medical intervention heavily laden with socially, culturally, and technically

laden expectations and prejudices, the subject of what information is deemed

permissible is substantially pre-filtered through the existing biases inherent within

the normative pathway. However, patients cannot build informed reflective

understanding unless they are supported with appropriate, full, and balanced

information including a detailed description of any condition and the likely

outcomes with or without the proposed intervention. The need for even-handed,

accurate, and comprehensive information to support individuals faced with morally

confronting decisions is therefore essential (Irwig, McCaffery, Salkleld, & Bossuyt,

2006).

Commonly, however, research indicates that educational materials aimed at assisting

patients in giving informed consent frequently omit topics of relevance to patients,

overestimates the usefulness and benefits of intervention, and often contains

inaccurate, misleading, or incomplete information (Bramwell & Carter, 2001;

Burkell & Campbell, 2005; Coulter, 1998, 2002; Coulter et al., 1999; Lawson, 2006;

Williams et al., 2002d). While Coulter’s (1999) review was targeted specifically at

ten specific health conditions, which did not include prenatal screening, her

conclusion of a widespread failure to provide accurate and balance information of

relevance to patients was entrenched across many fields of medical care. She

concluded:

‘Current information materials for patients omit relevant data, fail to give a

balanced view of the effectiveness of different treatments and ignore

uncertainties……… the most common fault [of educational material] was to

give an overoptimistic view, emphasising the benefits and glossing over the

risks and side effects’ (ibid, p.318-9).

Page 313: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

313

While uncertainty is an inherent feature of clinical practice, and indeed of life,

because it may contribute to patient anxiety, regret, or dissatisfaction, physicians

may suppress or deny uncertainty in order to maintain patient confidence (Katz,

1984 cited by Gordon, Joos, & Byrne, 2000, p.60). Gordon et al (2000, p.63) further

note that, as medical education emphasises the importance of ‘unambiguous fact,

solvable problems and correct answers’, physicians may have a pre-existing

discomfort with uncertainty and their inability to control it. Indeed, Braddock et al

(1997, p.323) noted only 5% of consultations in their study explicitly mentioned

uncertainty. Uncertainty and risk are nonetheless defining features of prenatal

screening and honest disclosure of this inherent ambiguity must be foundational in

promoting the adequate understanding desired in recipients of screening. However,

Williams et al (2002d) found in their analysis of educational materials pertaining to

prenatal screening that,

‘the implicit certainty and precision frequently contained in leaflets and

statements of practitioners at our research sites illustrate how tentative

ambiguous concepts can be repackaged into authoritative medical

certainties’ (Williams et al., 2002d, p.236).

Stapleton et al (2002, p.641) likewise concluded that educational leaflets in

maternity care primarily promoted the perpetuation of existing normative pathways

which favoured technological intervention, noting that ‘the framing of information

in favour of particular options, ensured compliance with the “right” choice’. The

consequence of this encounter for women, Stapleton et al (2002, p.639) conclude,

was ‘informed compliance rather than informed consent’, an outcome that

disrespects patient agency and inhibits capacity to be a full participant in shared

medical decision making.

A further example of selective framing in the prenatal debate is the observed

obscuring of the link between screening and termination (Santhalahti, 1999;

Santhalahti et al., 1998; Suter, 2002,p.257-8). While it is the case that most couples

are never faced with termination as a consequence of screening, for the small

Page 314: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

314

percentage that do Suter (2002, p.258) asserts that ‘providers should be direct about

this option and its emotional costs’. The potential consequence of providing

incomplete, falsely ‘unambiguous’, or overly optimistic information, in Raffle’s

(2001) opinion is that ‘by giving information that only emphasises the positive

aspects of screening the autonomy of individuals is ignored’ (ibid, p.92). Raffle

(ibid, p.97) proposes that ‘it is inappropriate to continue to use information about

screening purely for encouraging high uptake’, particularly if high uptake is then to

be summonsed as evidence of ethical probity and lack of decisional conflict as some

researchers have suggested (Cuckle, 1995; Whynes, 2002).

The presumption that patients may be alarmed by too candid a picture or that they

should be sheltered from the unsettling truth is firmly rejected by Say & Thomson

(2003) and Coulter (1999) who found that rather than being troubled by the presence

of uncertainty or potentially bad news, participants expressed a definite preference

for information that is ‘balanced and indicates a careful and honest assessment of

the pro’s and cons of treatment’ (ibid, p.319). Similarly, the frank disclosure of

uncertainty is essential in promoting realistic expectations of care and of building

trust in the therapeutic relationship (Gordon et al., 2000; Say & Thomson, 2003).

Just as overly optimistic views about the benefits of screening may be painted, so,

too, an excessively pessimistic picture of the difficulties of disability may direct

choice towards a particular outcome. As previously discussed in Chapter Seven,

negative or misguided stereotypes about living with disability may inform parental

deliberation about the value of prenatal screening, while the normative pathway

tacitly entrenches a eugenic values position (Bridle, 2004; Lippman, 1991;

Shakespeare, 1998). Lawson (2006, p.56) further claims that the dominant negative

stereotypes of Down syndrome in particular are directly linked to the higher

numbers of selective terminations for this condition than for other conditions.

Abramsky, Hall, Levitan, & Marteau, (2001, p.466) likewise observed in their

recent study exploring the information given to parents after the diagnosis of a sex

chromosome abnormality that ‘ although there were some examples of excellent

counselling, there were other examples of grossly inadequate or frankly misleading

information being given’. Thus, any full and balanced disclosure of information

about potential outcomes of prenatal screening should ideally incorporate social

Page 315: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

315

education about the experience of disability (Parens & Asch, 2000). When given a

‘risk’ from ultrasound, nuchal or serum screening, women need balanced and

accurate information about what life with a disability is like (Shakespeare, 2001), as

Parens and Asch (2000, p.34) suggest,

‘As more and more disabilities can be detected prenatally, perhaps all that is

possible at this first, earliest juncture is for prospective parents to receive

accurate information about the purposes of screening and brief but balanced

information about the disabilities being tested for’.

This social information about life with a disability is as critical in interpreting the

meaning of testing as any genetic or clinical information (Shakespeare, 1999, p.31).

Thus, the purpose of communication and informing is not simply to ‘get’ informed

consent, but to empower the patient to make decisions consistent with their own

values framework and intentions for their own future (McMillan & Gillett, 2002).

Inevitably this will mean that some patients ultimately reject the medically preferred

option and physicians will increasingly need to learn to trust patients with such

decisions (Fisher et al., 2005).

Page 316: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

316

Supporting Patient Learning in the Clinical Environment

‘All one can ever do for a learner en route to he or she forming a view of his

or her own is to aid and abet him or her own voyage’ (Bruner, 2004, p.90).

Supporting patient learning in the clinical environment is an ethical imperative, thus

the remainder of this chapter will explore some practical steps that may be taken to

‘aid and abet’, and hopefully equip and empower, patients for active participation in

their own health care decisions. While the vast range of limitations to ensuring full

understanding discussed throughout this work may never be completely negated,

some basic and achievable improvements could be made in terms of patient

education beginning with the quality and relevance of health information.

The purpose of consumer health information should be to empower patients by

reinforcing and extending their knowledge and enhancing their understanding.

However, as flagged previously, it seems that much material falls significantly short

of this expectation (Bramwell & Carter, 2001; Burkell & Campbell, 2005; Coulter,

1998, 2002; Coulter et al., 1999; Lawson, 2006; Stapleton et al., 2002; Williams et

al., 2002d), thus more relevant and accessible educational materials are needed.

Research suggests that practitioners and patients value written health information

(McVea, Venugopal, Crabtree, & Aita, 2000), but the use of educational handouts

alone has enjoyed limited success (Braddock et al., 1999; Godolphin et al., 2001;

O'Cathain, Thomas, Walters, Nicholl, & Kirkham, 2002). Sole reliance on written

material without supporting discussion has been associated with poor educational

outcomes (Godolphin et al., 2001), while Braddock’s (1999) study on informed

consent which included the use of supplementary written material revealed that only

9% of patient - doctor interactions met the criteria for informed decision making.

Additionally, the efficacy of health information leaflets largely depends on the

knowledge of the physician distributing them, and is significantly determined by

how they are circulated (McVea et al., 2000). In practices with a large central

stockpile, leaflets were found to have limited effect, whereas, in practices where

individual practitioners maintained their own selected range, these were more likely

Page 317: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

317

to be distributed appropriately. Furthermore, patients were more likely to read

material specifically recommended by a doctor as the explicit attention drawn

increased the perceived legitimacy of the information (ibid).

A fundamental characteristic of any patient information ought to be that it is

‘readable’(Hochhauser, 2003), yet health education information is frequently written

at a level beyond the health literacy capacities of the general population (Coulter,

1998; Coulter et al., 1999; Hochhauser, 2003; Kendig, 2006). Often, the legal

orientation of written health material and the desire to protect against litigation or

authorise treatment, infects and corrupts the educational intention of genuinely

informing. Consequently, many health documents, particularly informed consent

forms, adopt an inaccessible legal parlance that may be alienating to patients, written

at a reading level that may exceed most patients’ health literacy capacity (Bottrell et

al., 2000; Hochhauser, 2003; Kendig, 2006). If written educational leaflets to

contribute to successful learning they must be readable and contain accurate and

balanced information. As patients are also known to respond more positively to

specific and tailored information, often disregarding generic information, the non-

specific nature of much educational health literature demands that they be

accompanied by a dialogue with a practitioner to provide necessary individualised

interpretation as generic messages may be disregarded as not relevant to particular

individuals (McVea et al., 2000).

In addition to purely written material, the use of visual representations in the form of

decision aids has been found to have a powerful impact on improving patient

understanding. Decision aids are described by Bekker, Hewison, & Thornton, (2003,

p.323) as ‘interventions that help individuals focus on a deliberative choice between

two or more treatment options’. Typically, a decision aid includes a visual

representation of the options, highlighting the risks, benefits, and likely

consequences and an invitation for an open discussion of each person’s individual

attitudes and values with respect to their decision112F

113. Commenting on a systematic

113 Examples include written texts, flow charts, pictorial representations, interactive computer programs with varying capacity to personalise the information given. The Ottawa Personal Decision Guide website provides numerous examples. http://decisionaid.ohri.ca/decguide.html. Accessed 7th August,2007.

Page 318: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

318

review of seventeen trials assessing the efficacy of decision aids, O’Connor et al

(1999, p731) concluded,

‘Decision aids improve knowledge, reduce decisional conflict, and stimulate

patients to be more active in decision making without increasing their

anxiety. Decision aids have little effect on satisfaction and a variable effect

on decisions.’

Thus, the use of decision aids, such as visual flow charts, or pictorial representations

of risk during clinical discussions, have been consistently found to improve

understanding, promote decision making and stimulate patient participation

(O'Connor et al., 1999). The underlying cognitive explanation for the observed

improvements, Bekker et al (2003) suggest, is that cognitive strategies are better

supported by decision aids primarily because they assist patients to think about

potential areas of conflict and seek meaningful, personalised feedback. Such

immediate, interactive, and responsive feedback is recognised by cognitive theorists

as essential in the educational cycle because misconceptions may be exposed and

crucial patient understandings may be immediately assessed and strengthened (Gage

& Berliner, 1991; Woods & Barrow, 1975). As patients are encouraged to articulate

and justify their reasoning in an immediate exchange with their practitioner, more

stable decisions are reached and misunderstandings can be more easily identified

and instantly remedied in an ongoing conversation. Consultations using decision

aids may take longer, but with immediate feedback, the degree of post choice

conflict was found to be lower and higher levels of understanding were reached

(O'Connor et al., 1999). As patient and practitioner ability to interpret the complex

probabilities that accompany prenatal screening is recognised as being problematic

(Edwards & Elwyn, 2001; Edwards, Elwyn, & Mulley, 2002; Edwards et al., 2003;

Ghosh, 2004), decision aids may be useful in providing different and

complementary visual learning strategies to support the critical understandings of

uncertainty that lie at the heart of screening technologies.

Page 319: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

319

Within this cohort of practitioners, each of the two genetic counsellors and the

clinical geneticist actively and successfully incorporated numerous positive learning

strategies into their sessions with patients, including the use of decision aids.

I think they need to have graphics or visual imagery as well as words and I think they need to think about it over a few days and they need to have their partner with them and they may need to hear it a couple of times….and they need to know what it means in terms of the general functioning of the baby and also discuss the dynamics of having a child with a disability in the family unit etc. We have tools like chromosome pictures, and so on and I don’t think a lot of other people would have those resources; I can explain the numbers and arrangements and so on. Genetic Counsellor 1

I often use a picture to show the fluid behind the neck, that will be measured, for results, I like to use graphs, people really connect quickly, but it’s different for everyone, so you have to keep trying until you find something that works for that individual, and it may be something different for the husband than for the wife, but I see that as my role in helping them interpret, what is essentially a foreign language, that’s how I see it. Genetic Counsellor 2 I see the time they spend with me as a one-to-one communication process, I guess I would routinely use pen and paper to draw things like autosomal dominant, autosomal recessive, pictures of chromosomes, not usually customised so it’s their chromosomes, but to give them an idea of what it is that we’re talking about when we say ‘chromosomes’. So, they would be commonly used in consultations, visual aids, but I guess explaining simple concepts like numerical chromosomal abnormalities or structural re-arrangements where pictures are very helpful. Clinical Geneticist

The clinical geneticist also adopted several effective teaching strategies, including

the ‘teach back’ (Kendig, 2006, p.330) in which patients are asked to ‘teach back’

to their health carer . He explains,

When they start asking questions or implications, that you can see that they understood the genetics of the thing – in the context of couples it often is couples that you see, one asks a question and the other one can answer it for them, so I can say, yes that’s right………… that’s the best way, when they start to generate hypotheses based on their own understandings of what this means, and what it could mean, then you know that they have understood it. Another……… way that you can check that is, if the spouse isn’t there, is to ask, what are you going to tell your spouse about what we said ……….so , they have to put it in their own words and that can be a very good feel, as to how articulate they are about understanding what has taken place. Usually, in more passive ways as well, because it is somewhat threatening to repeat ‘what the teacher just said’ so to speak………. it can be a bit of a challenge, but by saying does that make sense to you, or do you understand what I mean………..or, you look like you’ve understood this – is that correct? You can pick up on those are non-verbal cues as to whether they get it or not. [Do you ever experience patients who just don’t get it?]. Oh yes ……..yes… [Laughs] there are…….. Well, I think the most important thing is to say …….well, lots of people don’t get this …don’t feel bad that you don’t understand …… lots of people don’t really understand this…….. So they don’t need to know what Mendel worked out……Clinical Geneticist.

Page 320: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

320

Similarly one of the GP’s described the adoption of educationally insightful

practices: I’m also keen to make sure that for instance you only give them one or two little take home sound bites each visit…..it’s ….as much as practically possible……..it’s good to get their partner or support person in because, as you know, most patients remember about 25% of what you tell them. The first thing is you talk to them as clearly as you can, secondly get the partner in, so he can pick up the bits she misses, the third thing is you do is write them little notes, and draw diagrams, and I tend to hand write them, I don’t like the proforma things, because it tends to stick more in their brain, they know it’s just for them not every Jane Doe that walks through the door. Particularly for women who are up to speed on their IT, I encourage them to , if they come across something when they are web surfing to send me the (URL) address and I’ll have a look and say this is rubbish, or it’s good……General Practitioner 1

While some of the practitioners of this cohort displayed positive and sound

educational practice, in prenatal screening the majority of education and counselling,

if it happens at all, is undertaken by professionals who have limited knowledge of

genetics and consequently may have difficulty conveying the associated

uncertainties and risks (Qureshi et al., 2006; Sadler, 1997; Tyzack & Wallace,

2003). Indeed, of the mothers in the cohort who did not glean sufficient

understanding during consultation with their medical practitioners, many resorted to

the internet as an educational tool. Accessing information through the internet was a

strategy that most women seemed comfortable with, but which drew mixed response

from practitioners as the following comments illustrate.

The bulk of our support and education came from outside the medical profession, maybe it’s my nature to research whatever I don’t know, we just wanted to find out what we needed to know. The conversation with doctors / midwives was more just clarification. Elizabeth I got home I got on the internet and just typed it in and tried to find out as much as I could... I spoke to my mother who is a nurse………………………….they were the two main areas I went to. Danielle

There are those women on the other hand who will do internet searches and find everything under the sun and in fact scare themselves silly……..out of their wits with too much information. …if there is such a thing. Midwife 2 Often women who are well informed and well misinformed………..by a bit of web surfing……can be an interesting group of people to deal with because ultimately they may have read a load more than every other patient you deal with, you have to, once again, try and sort out what information they have received and put it in context. General Practitioner 1

There is considerable scope, therefore, to improve and support the development of

appropriate decision aids, based on accurate and balanced information which is

Page 321: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

321

responsive to patient and practitioner needs for use in routine daily clinical

encounters.

Chapter Summary

The ethical and educational transformation of practice ultimately depend jointly

upon the moral integrity and orientation of the institutions we construct in addition

to the values, capacities, and conduct of those individuals who function within them.

Transformation must therefore be supported at the individual and the institutional

levels simultaneously as, in reality, they are inextricably linked, each impacting

upon the other.

Institutionally, the philosophical orientation towards ethics must be re-humanised

and re-contextualised if it is to be relevant and responsive to the everyday, micro-

ethical, and immediate ethical dimensions of practice that practitioners and patients

desire. Institutionally, this may be supported through the ethics education of health

professionals, in addition to ensuring ongoing technical education within

institutionally legitimised and structured open, inclusive moral spaces. Policy reform

in response to the damaging production models of health care which place onerous

time and resource constraints on practitioners (and thus patients), also require further

consideration as does the role of legislation on undermining transparency in the

practice of termination within Queensland. Finally, institutionally entrenched

acceptance of the perfectibility doctrine of science and a mostly unquestioning belief

in technological progress as irrefutably good (although not transparently monitored),

remains an area of practice demanding further critique and consciousness raising.

Individually, patients may be supported to be full moral participants in their health

care decisions by adopting a patient-centred model of care which promotes the

realisation of genuinely shared decision making between patient and practitioner. As

authentically shared decision making is associated with reduced interventions,

reduced referrals, fewer malpractice suits, and improved health literacy and health

status of individuals, this mode of relating in the clinical encounter better supports

the ethical aims of achieving informed consent based on genuine reflective

Page 322: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

322

understanding. However, in order to achieve this, patients and practitioners may

need support in developing the necessary communication competencies. While

communication education may target at all stakeholders, patient communication

training has been found to be more effective, as ‘high participating’ patients

significantly influence and improve the quality and effectiveness of health care

dialogue. Much available health literature aimed at supporting patients omits topics

of relevance to patients, overestimates the usefulness and benefits of intervention,

and contains inaccurate, misleading, biased or incomplete information. Thus there is

a clear need to develop comprehensible, accurate and balanced literature, written in

language that is accessible and easily understood by the general population that

might complement patient understanding and invite the ethically essential

conversations between practitioner and patient to occur.

In a framework of patient-centred care with a commitment to shared decision

making, the ethical imperative of patient learning may be supported by strategies

such as the use of relevant decision aids which enable immediate feedback and allow

the patient to personalise the medical concepts by pursuing existing patient

knowledge to forge appropriate cognitive links; by actively eliciting patient

motivation which is a key predictor of learning; and by clarifying what knowledge

is morally, socially, and educationally important. In adopting these insights into how

practice may be transformed, the currently observed breakdown of informed consent

may be redressed.

The following and final chapter will recap the purpose of the research, summarise

the research findings, and consider the implications of this research for the direction

of future inquiry.

Page 323: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

323

CHAPTER 11

CONCLUSIONS

‘Everything will depend finally, not just on the possibility of choice, but what

is chosen’ (Kass, 2002, p.9).

This final chapter will recap the purpose of this research, review the findings in

relation to the questions posed at the outset, reinforce the significant contributions

made by this research, and highlight potential areas of ongoing research and

analysis.

Purpose of the Thesis

As outlined in Chapter One, this thesis had four broad aims. The first aim was to

clarify the nature and significance of respect for autonomy as exercised clinically

through the seeking of informed consent within biomedical practice.

The second aim was to examine the existing research emerging predominantly from

the United States, Canada, the United Kingdom and Europe which outlined

problematic issues associated with prenatal screening protocols that identified

barriers to achieving the ethically desired standards of informed consent in practice.

These barriers to ethical care included numerous philosophical, institutional, social

and personal constraints that undermined women’s capacity to give reflectively

considered and informed consent to the prenatal screening interventions on offer.

The third area of research sought to answer the question of whether similar problems

to those identified abroad were experienced by participants from a local cohort

within particular practice settings in Queensland. As limited research of this nature

has been undertaken locally, this research sought to explore the individual

experiences of a cohort of nineteen stakeholders comprising seven mothers, eleven

health practitioners and one disability support volunteer who were invited to share

their personal narratives outlining their experiences of prenatal screening. Their

Page 324: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

324

individual experiences were compared to and contrasted with accounts contained in

existing published literature with the following questions providing the focal points

of the research.

• Are the indicators of informed consent as voluntary, understood

and intentional participation as defined within the bioethics

literature met in practice?

• What individual and institutional constraints impinge upon a

person’s capacity to exercise autonomy and give ethically

reflective and informed consent in the clinical context?

• If informed consent is critically linked to gaining appropriate

levels of reflective understanding, what educational opportunities

are accessible to promote understanding prior to consenting in the

antenatal arena?

The fourth area of investigation examined the potential contribution of incorporating

the insights offered in educational philosophy and the principles of adult learning.

As becoming ‘informed’ to consent is primarily a mastery of understanding through

the process of learning, it was suggested that a practical educational framework may

provide a valuable contribution to addressing and potentially transforming the gaps

in current informed consent protocols. An approach grounded in educational

philosophy more appropriately regards learning as an embedded, relational process

rather than an event in which information is merely transferred from one place to

another.

The key findings arising from each of these four areas of research will be

summarised in light of what they reveal about the initial questions posed.

Contributions of this Research

The first aim was to clarify the nature and significance of respect for autonomy, as

exercised through ‘informed consent’ in the context of the routine clinical practice

of prenatal screening. Chapter Two considered the philosophical roots of the

elevation of autonomy and critiqued the emergence of overtly individualistic,

Page 325: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

325

detached, and rationalist views of the self present within dominant analytical modes

of ethical inquiry (Kass, 2002; Taylor, 1989; Toulmin, 1990; Walker, 1993, 1998). It

was proposed that the dominant, rationally considered and principled approach to

clinical ethics provided an inappropriate ontological foundation from which to

appreciatively understand the particular and multiple layers of embeddedness that

inform individual moral frameworks. It was further suggested that individual moral

frameworks are characterised not solely by rationally considered action as presumed

by the dominant modes, but by a plurality of often competing goods, of which

rationality is only one of many equal and other considerations. While this

ontological foundation is well established within the phenomenological

philosophical tradition, it is not widely reflected in the dominant institutional ethical

protocols which often adopt administratively or legally reductionist approaches to

the ethical. When this phenomenological orientation is adopted, the ethical

importance of narrative as a fundamental tool of social inquiry is further reinforced.

The experiences of the participants reinforced the need to realign medical practice

with a more resonant ontological foundation as basis for inclusive and

hermeneutically aware ethical deliberation. The narratives of the participants

substantially supported the view that individual moral deliberations and the making

of moral meaning begin, not with rationality and reason, but within the embedded

contexts of significant relationships, interpreted through a veil of personal histories,

cultures and beliefs. Once this phenomenological orientation was adopted, Chapter

Three outlined why a narrative mode of inquiry was the most ethically coherent

methodology to open a shared moral space of interlocution, providing an invitation

and entry portal into the unique world of individual moral decision making.

The second and third aims of the research involved comparison of the experiences of

the local cohort of mothers and practitioners with the experiences and insights

offered in existing published literature. These two aspects of the research will

therefore be considered together. Chapters Five, Six, Seven and Eight sought to

identify the potential barriers to achieving informed consent in practice. The primary

observation of this research confirmed that five and possibly six of the seven

mothers interviewed considered themselves ill-informed, and concluded that their

Page 326: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

326

participation in screening was the result of compliance with the institutionalised and

routine normative pathway. Practitioners, too, struggled with their realisation that

informed consent seemed so difficult to achieve within the multiple time and

resource constraints of institutionalised care. These observations significantly mirror

the experiences recounted in overseas research.

A distinctive feature of this research is the incorporation of the mothers’ experiences

and the practitioners’ experiences. Commonly adopted approaches to researching

ethical issues have often privileged professional perspectives, or, been concerned

with giving “voice” to an excluded group. The purpose of combining these

perspectives was not simply to describe local practice more thoroughly. Rather

consideration of these ‘competing’ discourses was an intentional attempt to move

beyond the often adversarial nature of ethical conversations in health care, to explore

how different perspectives can interact with each other in a meaningful way to better

inform and direct practical and informed transformation. As mentioned at the start of

this work, each participant came to this project in a spirit of trust and collaboration

with the honest intention of contributing to better understandings, to guide more

ethically responsive practices for the future. The inclusive stance adopted throughout

this work therefore challenges us to acknowledge that these so called distinct groups

are not so separate after all. Mothers are health carers, health carers are parents, and

all are bound by the social, cultural, and institutional structures in which they must

attend to their particular roles and responsibilities.

In addition to the philosophical constraints identified earlier, additional barriers to

supporting informed consent were considered in three areas of institutional, social

and personal constraints. Institutionally, participants identified the routine nature of

screening, communication barriers, overt and covert counselling, the minimalist

legal orientation of policy frameworks, and blurred accountability for informing as

significant factors that undermined the ethical. The issue of blurred accountability

may be specific to the Queensland context in which each woman may see several

practitioners in her pregnancy, and in which each practitioner may reasonably

presume another has undertaken the ethically required discussion of the purpose,

limitations, and potential outcomes of testing. However, the consequence of this

Page 327: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

327

blurred accountability for some mothers in this cohort was a complete lack of

opportunity to question and extend their understandings.

Social constraints identified by participants, and reflected in existing literature,

included the lack of acknowledgement of the socially constructed and largely

predetermined nature of choice which promotes those choices that are culturally

valued while less valued choices are often not explicitly articulated. Social

constraints also included trust in science and technology as automatically choice

enhancing and necessarily good, fear of blame, feelings of social responsibility to

prevent disability informed by poor understandings of disability, and the culturally

sanctioned economic justifications of cost benefit analysis.

Personal constraints that undermined women’s full participation in the decision

making process included their heightened need to be reassured. Paradoxically, the

feelings of reassurance gleaned were mostly accompanied by a lack of awareness of

the limitations of testing and an overstated belief in the minimal reassurance given.

Heightened risk awareness which is possibly brought on by the prospect of

screening itself, poor understandings of the mathematical concepts of probability

and chance, and a tendency to over personalise the generalised abstract population

based risk numbers, created further barriers to full ethical consideration. The final

personally constraining factor that promoted ill-informed compliance with routine

screening regimes was the perceived need to alleviate the anxiety and fear that the

prospect of screening had created.

The experiences of this cohort flag the following as areas of further research and

potential reform,

• Within this cohort of mothers, and practitioners, and within the existing

literature, routine screening is recognised as potentially obscuring the voluntary

nature of screening and thus inhibiting opportunities to explore and become

informed prior to intervention. Screening must therefore be clearly presented as

an option rather than a routine expectation.

• The ultimate link between prenatal testing and selective termination must be

more explicitly made at the start of the process. This may provide some women

Page 328: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

328

with the opportunity to assess whether the potential information that may be

revealed is ultimately of value to them.

• The limitations of screening, including the inability to provide definitive

answers, must be made more explicit to reduce false reassurance.

• The negative language of burden, risk, and defect that permeates the discourse of

screening may negatively impact on how such information is interpreted; more

considered language choice may promote open discussion.

• Pregnancy may be a time of vulnerability for some women and the real prospect

of psychological harm that can accompany prenatal screening must be seriously

considered as a negative aspect of the screening process. Ways to minimise the

observed psychological harms must be sought.

• The ethical nature of the prenatal intervention and its consequences must be

made more explicit. Selective termination on the basis of fetal abnormality raises

ethical questions that point beyond the immediate individual making the decision

to other significant, yet influential, social prejudices.

• The potential dangers of women receiving no opportunity for discussion and

education as a consequence of the blurred accountability for informing observed

between practitioners must be acknowledged and addressed.

A significant contribution made by this research is in the fourth and final area of

investigation which examined the potential contribution of incorporating an

educationally grounded response to the ethical failures observed. The incorporation

of well established principles of educational philosophy and adult learning into

clinical regimes was explored as a potential basis for positive ethical transformation

of clinical practice. This aspect of potential transformation, explored in Chapter

Nine, rejected the bioethical focus on information disclosure as educationally

superficial and thus ethically inadequate. The view of information as somehow

separate from the interpretive frameworks in which it is applied that is inherent

within the disclosure approach to ensuring informed consent was rejected in favour

of the embedded, relational, and interpretive framework for understanding the

cognitive processes.

Page 329: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

329

When considered from the multidisciplinary standpoint adopted, the shared

ontological basis of the phenomenological account of the ethical, the andragogical

framework of education, and the patient-centred model of medical care can provide

a coherent and complementary platform from which the ethical intentions of

informed consent can be practically supported. The same principles of learning and

adult education may be similarly applied to practitioner education in preparing them

for the ethically important role as patient educator as discussed in Chapter Ten.

An incidental contribution of this research was the extension of the Listening Guide

methodology with respect to articulating and understanding the ontological

importance and moral significance of contrapuntal voices. The ethical significance

of contrapuntal voices as opening a window on the plurality of goods that defines

individual moral frameworks has not been explicitly considered in published

references to the Listening Guide.

Directions for Future Research

The stories offered by participants locally in this cohort strongly mirrored the

observations reported in the research carried out abroad. However, the small sample

size and limited scope of this research suggest that further empirical research ought

be undertaken on a larger scale to establish the extent to which the challenges

identified in this cohort are apparent within institutional practices across Queensland

and even perhaps, given the lack of Australian research generally, across all

Australian states and territories.

Chapter Ten outlined several potential areas of further research to achieve the

required institutional and individual transformation that underpins practice reform.

From an educational perspective, the following areas of future research may be

pursued.

• The development of educational outreach programs to equip and support

practitioners in their ethical role as patient educators as outlined in Chapter

Ten.

Page 330: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

330

• The development and assessment of appropriate decision aids in conjunction

with patients’ focus groups to promote engaged, reflective understanding

prior to consenting.

• Assessment of whether increased levels of understanding and informedness

improves patient acceptance and preparedness for potentially unwelcome

results.

• Identification of the impact of blurred accountability for informing and its

consequences on women’s levels of understanding.

• The institutionally endorsed professional role for clinical ethicists is in its

infancy in Australia. The potential contribution to policy development and

educational opportunities for staff and patients that clinical ethicists make in

practice settings overseas, notably in Canada and the USA, flag this

institutional role as valuable one in providing appropriate support to work

through some of the organisational and educational issues identified in this

research. Thus, assessment of the potential organisational role for clinical

ethicists, to support those who must make these difficult moral decisions

requires further consideration in the local context.

Other aspects of screening practice that suggest further research included,

• Consideration of whether the increased time gap of 5-6 weeks between an

unfavourable nuchal translucency result and confirmation through

amniocentesis prolongs the psychological trauma of testing. The potential

long term effects of any anxiety and the development of support mechanisms

requires further exploration.

• The need to undertake adequate data collection and analysis was raised in

Chapter Ten as a means of promoting ‘institutional moral accountability’

(Solomon, 2005, p.43). Forms of data analysis could include

Comparison of outcomes between facilities

Retrospective comparison of predicted anomalies with actual

outcomes to confirm predictive accuracy

Confirmation of diagnosis from fetal autopsy where

appropriate.

Page 331: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

331

Summary

Recent history of antenatal care shows how quickly new technologies become

routinised and are embraced before their clinical or societal relevance is clear

(Markens et al., 1999). As this trend continues with the incorporation of genetic

testing, the predicted need to increasingly defer to biomedical authority (Press &

Browner, 1997) may further compromise patient autonomy and the capacity to reach

the ethical standard of ‘educated’ informed consent. It is, therefore, imperative to

respond to the insights offered by mothers and practitioners locally and to develop

procedures which can accommodate existing and emerging technologies without

eroding patient rights, practitioner obligations, or the ethical conduct of care.

When such deeply entrenched social, personal, and institutional constraints

discussed above are excluded from the ethical discourse of screening, the language

of autonomy and choice may seem ‘illusory and mocking’ for some (Bridle, 2004)

as the capacity to exercise autonomy is, in reality, compromised. Realistically, for

many the choice to undergo prenatal screening is the last in a long line of essentially

non-choices, socially entrenched and predetermined, to funnel parents down a

particular normative pathway, laid out long before they even conceived their child.

The powerful culmination of the law, the cultural imperialism of science and

technology, and the master narrative of individualism, merge to shape the political

landscape in which prenatal screening is practiced. While educational and

organisational reform may provide a more receptive environment in which all

stakeholder perspectives may be sought and valued, a fuller ethical response calls for

the reshaping of the political space by contesting these dominant discourses.

However, practical steps can be taken educationally to promote informed consent.

Basing patient education on existing patient knowledge, building of appropriate

cognitive links, ascertaining patient motivation which is a key predictor of learning,

and eliciting what knowledge is morally, socially, and educationally important to the

patient can promote the reflective understandings required of ethically informed

consent. It is the loss of these educational insights in the current transmissive modes

Page 332: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

332

of education that has been a major factor in the breakdown of informed consent as

an ethical safeguard (Braddock, 2002).

Extending Charles Taylor’s (1989, p.92) claim that ‘the central notion here is that

articulation can bring us closer to the good as a moral source, can give it power’,

this work has sought not only to articulate, but to appreciate and understand the

multiple interweaving factors that shape the sociologically complex practice of

prenatal screening. Taylor (1989 cited by Abbey, 2000, pp.41-42) describes

articulation as ‘bringing into the light of awareness that which is unspoken but

presupposed’. Once the underlying moral values have been articulated, Taylor (ibid)

argues that the complexity of the moral life and the diverse range of goods to which

individual persons adhere can be better appreciated and attempts to simplify or

reduce moral understandings may be resisted. Furthermore, if respect for others,

based on the indisputable acceptance of their ‘inalienable preciousness’ (Gaita,

1999, p.4) is recognised as a source of moral good, and if the culturally sanctioned

means supporting this good is through respect for another’s autonomy safeguarded

by ensuring their opportunity to exercise their educated and understood informed

consent, then the numerous barriers to ethically robust and considered prenatal

interventions identified in this research, and elsewhere, require that they not only be

articulated, but also be transformed.

Page 333: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

333

References

Abbey, R. (2004). Charles Taylor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Abramsky, L., Hall, S., Levitan, J., & Marteau, T. M. (2001). What parents are told

after prenatal diagnosis of a sex chromosome abnormality: interview and questionnaire study? British Medical Journal, 322(7284), 463-466.

Alderson, P., Williams, C., & Farsides, B. (2004). Practitioners views about equity within prenatal screening services. Sociology, 38, 61-80.

Aldred, M. J., Savarirayan, R., & Savulescu, J. (2003). It's only teeth - are there limits to genetic testing? Clinical Genetics, 63(5), 333-339.

Alfirevic, Z. (2003). Early amniocentesis versus trans abdominal chorionic villus sampling for prenatal diagnosis. The Cochrane Library.

Alfirevic, Z., & Neilson, J. (2004). Antenatal screening for Down's syndrome. BMJ, 329, 811-812.

Anderson, G. (1999). Non-directiveness in prenatal genetics: Patients read between the lines. Nursing Ethics, 6(2), 126-136.

Anderson, T. E., Tschann, J. M., Guillion, D. S., & Oppenberg, A. A. (1989). Physician communication style and malpractice claims. A complex relationship. Western Journal of Medicine, 150, 356-360.

Andrews, M. (2000). Lines of narrative: Psychosocial perspectives. London: Routledge.

Asch, A., & Wasserman, D. (2005). Where is the sin in synecdoche? Prenatal testing and the parent-child relationship. In D. Wasserman, J. Bickenbach & R. Wachbroit (Eds.), Quality of life and human difference. Genetic testing, health care and disability. New York: Cambridge University Press.

ASGC. (2000). Australian Society of Genetic Counsellors: Code of Ethics. Retrieved 14th December, 2006, from 1Hhttp://hgsa.com.au/images/UserFiles/Attachments/ASGCCodeofEthics.pdf

Bain, K. (2004). What the best college teachers do. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.

Baird, P. (1999). Prenatal screening and the reduction of birth defects in populations. Community Genetics, 2(1).

Balan, B. N. (2005). Multiple voices and methods: Listening to women who are in workplace transition. International Journal of Qualitative Methods, 4(2), 1-21.

Barnett, T., & Vaicys, C. (2000). The moderating effect of individuals' perceptions of ethical work climate on ethical judgments and behavioural intentions. Journal of Business Ethics, 27(4), 351-362.

Barry, C., Bradley, C. P., Britten, N., Stevenson, F. A., & Barber, N. (2000). Patients' unvoiced agendas in general practice consultations: qualitative study. British Medical Journal, 320, 1246-1250.

Bastian, H. (1994). The power of sharing knowledge. Consumer participation in the Cochrane Collaboration. Oxford, UK.: Cochrane Centre.

Bates, J. (2007). Worried well. Nursing Standard, 21(38), 27. Beauchamp, T. (1999). The 'four principles' approach. In J. Lindeman - Nelson

(Ed.), Meaning and medicine: A reader in the philosophy of health care (pp. 147-155). New York: Routledge.

Page 334: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

334

Beauchamp, T., & Childress, J. (2001). Principles of biomedical ethics (5th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

Begley, A. (2003). Creative approaches to ethics: prose, poetry and dialogue. In V. Tschudin (Ed.), Approaches to ethics: Nursing beyond boundaries. London: Elsevier Science.

Bekker, H. L., Hewison, J., & Thornton, J. G. (2003). Understanding why decision aids work: Linking process with outcome. Patient Education and Counselling, 50, 323 - 329.

Bell, S. E. (1988). Becoming a political woman: The reconstruction and interpretation of experience through stories. In A. D. Todd & S. Fisher (Eds.), Gender and discourse. The power of talk (pp. 97-123). Norwood, NJ.: Ablex.

Belle-Brown, J., Stewart, M., & Ryan, B. L. (2003). Outcomes of patient provider interaction. In T. L. Thompson, A. M. Dorsey, K. I. Miller & R. Parrot (Eds.), Handbook of health communication. (pp. 141-161). Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.

Bellieni, C. V., Buonocore, G., Bagnoli, F., Cordelli, D. M., Gasparre, O., Calonaci, F., et al. (2005). Is an excessive number of prenatal echographies a risk for fetal growth? Early Human Development, 81, 689-693.

Bernhardt, B., Geller, G., Doksum, T., Larson, S., Roter, D., & Holtzman, N. (1998). Prenatal genetic testing: Content of discussions between obstetric providers and pregnant women. Obstetrics & Gynaecology, 91(5), 648-655.

Biesecker, B. B., & Hamby, L. (2000). What Difference the Disability Community Arguments Should Make for the Delivery of Prenatal Genetic Information. In E. Parens & A. Asch (Eds.), Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights (pp. 340-357). Washington: Georgetown University Press.

Biggio, J. R., Morris, C., Owen, J., & Stringer, J. (2004). An outcomes analysis of five prenatal screening strategies for trisomy 21 in women younger than 35 years. American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 190, 721-729.

Biggs, J., & Telfer, R. (1987). The process of learning (2nd Ed.). Sydney: Prentice - Hall.

Biley, F. C., & Champney- Smith, J. (2003). "Attempting to say something without saying it..." writing haiku in health care education. Journal of medical Ethics; Medical Humanities, 29, 39-42.

Bottrell, M., Alpert, H., Fischbach, R., & Emanuel, L. (2000). Hospital informed consent for procedure forms. Archives of Surgery. 135(1), 26.

Boyd, E. (2004). Autopsy after termination of pregnancy for foetal anomaly: Retrospective cohort study. British Medical Journal, 328.

Boyd, P. A., Chamberlain, P., & Hicks, N. R. (1998). 6-year Experience of prenatal diagnosis in an unselected population in Oxford. The Lancet, 352(9140), 1577-1581.

Braddock, C. H. (2002). Factors that predict better informed consent. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 13(4), 344.

Braddock, C. H., Edwards, K. A., Hasenberg, N. M., Laidley, T. L., & Levinson, W. (1999). Informed decision making in outpatient practice. Time to get back to basics. JAMA, 282(24), 2313 - 2320.

Braddock, C. H., Stephan, D. F., Levinson, W., Jonsen, A., & Pearlman, R. A. (1997). How do doctors and patients discuss routine clinical decisions? Journal of General Internal Medicine, 12(6), 339.

Page 335: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

335

Braithwaite, J. M., Kadir, R. A., Pepera, T. A., Morris, R. W., Thompson, P. J., & Economides, D. L. (1996). Nuchal translucency measurement: training of potential examiners. Ultrasound in Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 8(3), 192-195.

Bramwell, R., & Carter, D. (2001). An exploration of midwives and obstetricians knowledge of genetic screening in pregnancy and their perception of appropriate counselling. Midwifery, 17, 133-141.

Bricker, L., Garcia, J., Henderson, J., Mugford, M., & Roberts, J. (2000). Ultrasound screening in pregnancy; A systematic review of clinical effectiveness, cost effectiveness and women's views. Health Technology Assessments. 4(16).

Bridle, L. (2001). Confronting the distortions: Mothers of children with Down Syndrome and prenatal testing. Down Syndrome Association of Queensland (Aug 2001), 19-23.

Bridle, L. (2002). Prenatal diagnosis, choice and the moral character of parenthood. Paper presented at the What Does it Mean to be Human in the 21st Century? Wesley Hospital, Brisbane, QLD.

Bridle, L. (2004). Stories of choice: Mothers of children with Down Syndrome and the ethics of prenatal screening. Unpublished PhD, University of Queensland, Brisbane, Australia.

Bridson, J., Hammond, C., Leach, A., & Chester, M. R. (2003). Making consent patient-centred. British Medical Journal, 327(7424), 1159.

Brodlie, M., Laing, I., Keeling, J., & McKenzie, K. J. (2002). Ten years of neonatal autopsies in tertiary referral centre: retrospective study. British Medical Journal, 324, 761.

Brody, H. (2002). "My story is broken can you help me fix it?" Medical ethics and the joint construction of narrative. In K. W. M. Fulford, D. L. Dickenson & T. H. Murray (Eds.), Healthcare ethics and human values: An introductory text with readings and case studies. Malden, Massachusetts. Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

Brookes, A. (2001). Women's voices: Prenatal diagnosis and care for the disabled. Health Care Analysis, 9(2), 133-150.

Brown, K. (2006). Leadership for social justice and equity: Evaluating a transformative framework and andragogy. Educational Administration Quarterly, 42(5), 700-745.

Brown, L. M., & Gilligan, C. (1991). Listening for voice in narratives of relationship. In M. B. Tappan & M. J. Packer (Eds.), Narrative and storytelling: Implications for understanding moral development. New directions for child development. San Francisco: Jossey-Boss.

Brown, L. M., Tappan, M. B., Gilligan, C., Miller, B. A., & Argyris, D. E. (1989). Reading for the self and moral voice: A method for interpreting narratives of real life moral conflict and choice. In M. J. Packer & R. B. Addison (Eds.), Entering the circle: Hermeneutic investigation in psychology. Albany, N.Y: State University of New York Press.

Browner, C. H., & Press, N. (1996). The production of authoritative knowledge in American prenatal care. Medical Anthropology Quarterly, 10(2), 141-156.

Bruner, J. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Bruner, J. (1991). The narrative construction of reality. Critical Inquiry, 18(1), 1-21.

Page 336: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

336

Bruner, J. (2004). Narratives in science. In E. Scanlon, P. Murphy, J. Thomas & E. Whitelegg (Eds.), Reconsidering Science Learning (pp. 90-98). London: The Open University.

Bryman, A. (2004). Social research methods (2nd Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bub, B. (2004). The Patient's lament: hidden key to effective communication: How to recognise and transform. British Medical Journal, 30, 63-69.

Buckley, S. (2005). Gentle birth, gentle mothering. Brisbane: One Moon Press. Burkell, J., & Campbell, G. D. (2005). "What does this mean?" How Web-based

consumer health information fails to support information seeking in the pursuit of informed consent for screening test decisions. Journal of the Medical Library Association, 93(3), 363.

Calman, K. C. (2002). Communication of risk: choice, consent and trust. The Lancet, 360(9327), 166.

Caplan, A. (1982). Mechanics on duty: The limitations of a technical definition of moral expertise for work in Applied Ethics. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 8, 1-18.

Caplan, A. (1999). Moral experts and moral expertise. Clinical Ethics: Theory and Practice, 59-87.

Caplan, A. (1999). "What is immoral about eugenics?" British Medical Journal 319: 1284.

Carothers, A. D., Boyd, E., Lowther, G., Ellis, P. M., Couzin, D. A., Faed, M. J. W., et al. (1999). Trends in prenatal diagnosis of Down syndrome and other autosomal trisomies in Scotland 1990 to 1994, with associated cytogenic and epidemiological findings. Genetic Epidemiology, 16, 179-190.

Cassell, E. (1991). Recognising suffering. Hastings Centre Report, May - June, 24 - 31.

Caughey, A. B. (2005). Cost-effectiveness analysis of prenatal diagnosis: methodological issues and concerns. Gynecologic and Obstetric Investigation [NLM - MEDLINE], 60(1), 11.

Cegala, D. J. (2006). Emerging Trends and Future Directions in Patient Communication Skills Training. Health Communication, 20(2), 123.

Cegala, D. J., Gade, C., Lenzmeier Broz, S., & McClure, L. (2004). Physicians' and Patients' Perceptions of Patients' Communication Competence in a Primary Care Medical Interview. Health Communication, 16(3), 289.

Cegala, D. J., & Lenzmeier Broz, S. (2003). Provider and patient communication skills training. In T. L. Thompson, A. M. Dorsey, K. I. Miller & R. Parrot (Eds.), Handbook of health communication. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc.

Cegala, D. J., Street, R. L., & Clinch, C. R. (2007). The impact of patient participation on physicians' information provision during a primary care medical interview. Health Communication, 21(2), 177.

Chalmers, A. F. (1999). What is this thing called science? Brisbane: University of Queensland Press.

Chan, A., & Sage, L. C. (2005). Estimating Australia's abortion rates 1985-2003. Medical Journal of Australia, 182(9), 447-452.

Clandinin, J., & Connelly, M. (2000). Narrative inquiry: Experience and story in qualitative research. San Francisco: Jossey Bass Publishers.

Clapton, J. (2003). Tragedy and catastrophe: contentious discourses of ethics and disability. Journal of Intellectual Disability Research, 47, 540-547.

Page 337: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

337

Clapton, J. (2004). Burden, bioethics and disability. Queensland University of Technology, Applied Ethics Seminar. 8th October. 2004.

Clarkeburn, H. (2000). Parental duties and untreatable genetic conditions. Journal of Medical Ethics, 26(5), 400.

Cobourne, M. T. (2004). The complex genetics of cleft lip and palate. European Journal of Orthodontics [NLM - MEDLINE], 26(1), 7.

Collett, T. J., & McLachan, J. C. (2006). Evaluating a poetry workshop in medical education. Journal of medical Ethics; Medical Humanities, 32, 59-64.

Connelly, J. (2005). Narrative possibilities. Using mindfulness in clinical practice. Biology and Medicine, 48(1), 84-94.

Connelly, M., & Clandinin, J. D. (1990). Stories of experience and narrative inquiry. Educational Researcher, 19(5), 2-14.

Coory, M., Rosellli, T., & Carrol, H. J. (2007). Antenatal care implications of population based trends in Down syndrome birth rates by rurality and antenatal care provider, Queensland, 1990-2004. Medical Journal of Australia, 186(5), 230-234.

Coulter, A. (1998). Evidence based patient information. British Medical Journal, 317, 225-226.

Coulter, A. (2002). What do patients want from high quality general practice and how do we involve them in improvement? British Journal of General Practice, 52 Suppl (S22-26).

Coulter, A., Entwistle, V., & Gilbert, D. (1999). Sharing decisions with patients: Is the information good enough? BMJ, 318, 318 -322.

Coulter, A., & Magee, H. (2003). The European patient of the future. Maidenhead: Open University Press.

Cowan, N. (1995). Attention and memory: An integrated framework. New York: Oxford University Press.

Cowley, C. (2005). The dangers of medical ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 31, 739-742.

Cristofalo, E. A., DiPietro, J. A., Costigan, K. A., Nelson, P., & Crino, J. (2006). Women's response to fetal choroid plexus cysts detected by prenatal ultrasound. Journal of Perinatology, 26(4), 215.

Cuckle, H. (1995). Cost effectiveness of antenatal screening for Cystic Fibrosis. BMJ, 311, 1460.

Cuckle, H. (2001). Extending antenatal screening in the UK to include common monogenic disorders. Community Genetics, 4(2).

Daloz, L. A. (1986). Effective teaching and mentoring: Realising the transformational power of adult learning experiences. San Francisco: Jossey-Boss.

Darbyshire, P. (1994). Understanding caring through arts and humanities: a medical/nursing humanities approach to promoting alternative experiences of thinking and learning. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 19, 856-863.

Davies, R. (1994). The cunning man. London: Penguin Books. de Crispegny, L. J., & Savulescu, J. (2004). Abortion: Time to clarify Australia's

confusing laws. Medical Journal of Australia, 181(4), 201-203. Dewey, J. (1938). Experience and education. New York: The Macmillan Company. Di Blasi, Z., Harkness, E., Ernst, E., Georgiou, A., & Kleijnen, J. (2001). Influence

of context effects on health outcomes: A systematic review. The Lancet, 357, 757- 762.

Page 338: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

338

Di Pietro, J. A., Costigan, K. A., Cristofalo, E. A., & Lu, Y. (2006). Choroid plexus cysts do not affect fetal neurodevelopment. Journal of Perinatology, 26(10), 622-627.

Dodds, S. (2000). Choice and control in feminist bioethics. In C. Mackenzie & N. Stoljar (Eds.), Relational Autonomy (pp. 213-235). New York: Oxford University Press.

Donchin, A. (2001). Understanding Autonomy Relationally: Toward a Reconfiguration of Bioethical Principles. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 26(4), 365- 386.

Dormandy, E., Fitzgerald, T., & Baillie, C. (1999). Antenatal screening. British Medical Journal, 318(7186), 805.

Dormandy, E., Hooper, R., Michie, S., & Marteau, T. (2002a). Informed choice to undergo prenatal screening: A comparison of two hospitals conducting testing either as part of a routine visit or requiring a separate visit. Journal of Medical Screening, 9, 109-114.

Doucet, A. (2006). Do men mother? Fathering, care and domestic responsibility. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Duberstein, P., Meldrum, S., Fiscella, K., Shields, C. G., & Epstein, R. M. (2007). Influences on patients' ratings of physicians: Physicians demographics and personality. Patient Education and Counselling, 65(2), 270-274.

Duster, T. (2003). Backdoor to eugenics. New York: Routledge. Dworkin, G. (1988). The theory and practice of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press. Dworkin, G. (2003). Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Hastings Center Report,

33(2), 42-44. Eddleman, K., Malone, F., Sullivan, L., Dukes, K., Berkowitz, R., Kharbutli, Y., et

al. (2006). Pregnancy loss after mid trimester amniocentesis. Obstetrics & Gynaecology, 108, 1067-1072.

Edwards, A., & Elwyn, G. (2001). Understanding risk and lessons for clinical risk communication about treatment preferences. Qual Health Care, 10 (Suppl), i9-13.

Edwards, A., Elwyn, G., & Mulley, A. I. (2002). Explaining risks: Turning numerical data into meaningful pictures. British Medical Journal, 321, 827-830.

Edwards, A., Elwyn, G., Unigwe, S., & Hood, K. (2003). Effects of communicating individual risks in screening programmes: Cochrane systematic review. (Cover story). BMJ: British Medical Journal, 327(7417), 703-707.

Egan, J., & Borgida, A. (2002). Screening for Down syndrome. Obstetrics & Gynaecology, 27(2), 22-30.

Egan, J. F. X., & Borgida, A. F. (2002). Screening for Down Syndrome. Obstetrics & Gynaecology [on-line via Proquest], 27(2), 22-30. [on-line].

Elliot, T. S. (1962). Choruses from 'The Rock' (1934). In Collected Poems 1909 - 1962. Faber & Faber.

Elwyn, G., Edwards, A., & Kinnersley, P. (1999). Shared decision making in primary care: the neglected second half of the consultation. British Journal of General Practice, 49, 477-482.

Elwyn, G., Edwards, A., Wensing, M., Hood, K., Atwell, C., & Grol, R. (2003). Shared decision making: developing the OPTION scale for measuring patient involvement. Quality & Safety in Health Care, 12(2), 93-99.

Page 339: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

339

Erikson, S. L. (2001). Post-diagnostic abortion in Germany: reproduction gone awry, again? Social Science & Medicine.

Errante, A. (2000). But sometimes you're not part of the story. Educational Researcher, 29(2), 16-27.

Faden, R., Kass, N., & McGraw, D. (1996). Women as vessels and vectors: Lessons from the HIV epidemic. In H. Wolfe (Ed.), Feminism and bioethics: Beyond reproduction. New York: Oxford University Press.

Ferguson, P., Gartner, A., & Lipsky, D. (2000). The experience of disability in families: A synthesis of research and narratives. In E. Parens & A. Asch (Eds.), Prenatal Testing and Disability (pp. 72-94). Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press.

Fineman, R. M., & Walton, M. T. (2000). Should genetic health care providers attempt to influence reproductive outcome using directive counselling techniques? A public health prospective. Women & Health, 30(3), 39-47.

Fisher, B., Dixon, A., & Honeyman, A. (2005). Informed patients, reformed clinicians. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine [NLM - MEDLINE], 98(12), 530.

Fitzgerald, T. (1999). Antenatal Screening: women are being given incomplete information. British Medical Journal, 318, 805.

Ford, N. (1999). Ethical aspects of prenatal screening and diagnosis. In Conference Proceedings "Scientific, Medical, Ethical and Legal Aspects of Prenatal Screening and Diagnosis" 17thSept 1999. Edited by Norman Ford. Caroline Chisolm Centre for Health Ethics.

Frank, A. (1995). The wounded storyteller: Body, illness and ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Frank, A. W. (2005). Reinventing Bioethics for New Medical Dilemmas: Narratives and Principles in the 21st Century. Public lecture 26th July, 2005. Queensland University of Technology.

Freire, P. (1985). The politics of education. New York: Seabury Press. Friedman, M. (1997). Autonomy and social relationships. Rethinking the feminist

critique. In D. T. Meyers (Ed.), Feminists rethink the self. Oxford: Westview Press.

Gage, N., & Berliner, D. (1991). Educational psychology. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.

Gaita, R. (1999). A common humanity: thinking about truth love and justice. Melbourne: Text Publishing.

Garne, E. (2001). Different policies on prenatal ultrasound screening programmes and induced abortions explain regional variations in infant mortality with congenital malformations. Fetal Diagnosis and Therapy, 16(3).

Getz, L., & Kirkengen, A. L. (2003). Ultrasound screening in pregnancy: advancing technology, soft markers for fetal chromosomal aberrations, and unacknowledged ethical dilemmas. Social Science & Medicine, 56(10), 2045-2057.

Ghosh, A. K. (2004). Do medical students and physicians understand probability? Quarterly Journal of Medicine, 97, 53-56.

Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women's development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Gilligan, C. (1996). The centrality of relationships in human development: A puzzle, some evidence and a theory. In G. G. Noam & K. W. Fisher (Eds.),

Page 340: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

340

Development and vulnerability in close relationships. Mahwah, NJ.: Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc.

Gilligan, C., Spencer, R., Weinberg, K., & Bertsch, T. (2003). On the listening guide: A voice centred relational method. In P. Camic (Ed.), Qualitative Research in Psychology. Expanding Perspectives in Methodology and Design. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.

Gillott , J. (2001). Screening for disability: a eugenic pursuit? Journal of Medical Ethics [NLM - MEDLINE], 27 Suppl 2, II21.

Glesne. (1999). Becoming qualitative researchers: An introduction. Ontario: Longman.

Godolphin, W. (2003). The role of risk communication in shared decision making. British Medical Journal, 327(7417), 692-693.

Godolphin, W., Towle, A., & McKendry, R. (2001). Challenges in family practice related to informed and shared decision - making: A survey of preceptors of medical students. JAMC, 165(4), 434 - 438.

Goel, V., Glazier, R., Summers, A., & Holzapfel, S. (1998). Psychological outcomes following maternal serum screening: a cohort study. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 159(6).

Goldenberg, M. (2005). Evidence based ethics? On evidence-based practice and the 'empirical turn' from normative bioethics. BMC Medical Ethics, 6, 11.

Goodwin-Johansson, C. (1988). Educating the Adult Patient. Lifelong Learning, 11(7), 10.

Goodyear, M. D. E., Krleza-Jeric, K., & Lemmens, T. (2007). The Declaration of Helsinki. BMJ, 335(7621), 624-625.

Gordon, G. H., Joos, S. K., & Byrne, J. (2000). Physician expressions of uncertainty during patient encounters. Patient Education and Counselling, 40, 59-65.

Grant, V. J. (2002). Making room for medical humanities. Journal of Medical Ethics; Medical Humanities, 28, 45-48.

Grayson, N., Hargreaves , J., & Sullivan, E. A. (2005). Use of routinely collected national data sets for reporting on induced abortion in Australia. Sydney: AIWH National Perinatal Statistics Unit.

Green, J. M., Hewison, J., Bekker, H. L., Bryant, L. D., & Cuckle, H. S. (2004). Psychosocial aspects of genetic screening of pregnant women and newborns: a systematic review. Health Technology Assessment, 8(33), 1-+.

Green , R. M. (1997). Parental autonomy and the obligation not to harm ones child genetically. Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, 25, 8.

Green , R. M., & Statham, H. (1996). Psychosocial aspects of prenatal screening and diagnosis. In T. M. Marteau & M. Richards (Eds.), The trouble helix: Social and psychological implications of the new genetics (pp. 140-163). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Grover, S. (2003). The psychological dimension of informed consent: Dissonance process in genetic testing. Journal of Genetic Counselling, 12(5), 389-403.

Gull, S. E., O'Flynn, R. O., & Hunter, J. Y. L. (2002). Creative writing workshops for medical education: Learning from a pilot study with hospital staff. Journal of medical Ethics; Medical Humanities, 28, 102-104.

Hall, S., Bobrow, M., & Marteau, T. M. (2000). The psychological consequences for parents of receiving false negative results on prenatal screening for Down syndrome. Journal of Medical Genetics, 37, A13-A13.

Page 341: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

341

Hardwig, J. (1997). Autobiography, biography and narrative ethics. In J. Lindeman - Nelson (Ed.), Stories and their limits: Narrative approaches to bioethics. New York: Routledge.

Harris, G., Connor, L., Bisits, A., & Higginbotham, N. (2004). "Seeing the baby": pleasures and dilemmas of ultrasound technologies for primiparous Australian women. Medical Anthropology Quarterly [NLM - MEDLINE], 18(1), 23.

Harris, R. A. (2004). Cost utility of prenatal diagnosis and the risk-based threshold. The Lancet, 363(9405), 276.

Harris, R. A., Washington, A. E., Nease, R. F. J., & Kuppermann, M. (2004). Cost utility of prenatal diagnosis and the risk-based threshold. Lancet [NLM - MEDLINE], 363(9405), 276.

Harrison, G., & Goldie, D. (2006). Second-trimester Down's syndrome serum screening: double, triple or quadruple marker testing? Annals of Clinical Biochemistry, 43, 67.

Helen, I. (2002). Risk and anxiety: polyvalence of ethics in high-tech antenatal care. Critical Public Health, 12(2), 119-137.

Helm, D., Miranda, S., & Ched, N. A. (1998). Prenatal diagnosis of Down's Syndrome: mothers reflections on supports needed from diagnosis to birth. Mental Retardation, 36(1), 55-61.

Herman, A., Maymon, R., Dreazen, E., Zohav, E., Segal, O., Segal, S., et al. (1999). Utilization of the Nuchal Translucency Image-Scoring Method during Training of New Examiners. Fetal Diagnosis and Therapy, 14(4), 234.

Hesse - Biber, N. S., & Leavy, P. (2006). The practice of qualitative research. London: Sage Publications.

Heyman, B., Hundt, G., Sandall, J., Spencer, K., Williams, C., Grellier, R., et al. (2006). On being at higher risk: A qualitative study of prenatal screening for chromosomal anomalies. Social Science & Medicine, 62(10), 2360.

Hochhauser, M. (2003). Is it ethical to give out unreadable information? Managed Care Quarterly, 11(2), 33-36.

Hoffmaster, B. (1991). The theory and practice of applied ethics. Dialogue, 30, 213 - 234.

Hoffmaster, B. (2006). What Does Vulnerability Mean? The Hastings Center Report, 36(2), 38.

Hope, T. (1995). Evidence-based medicine and ethics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 21, 259-260.

Hubbard, R. (1988). Eugenics: New tools, old ideas. In (pp. 225-235). New York: Haworth Press.

Hubbard, R. (2001). "Prenatal testing and disability rights, by Eric Parens and Adrienne Asch, eds." Socialism and Democracy 15(2): 164.

Hulsman, R. L., Ros, W. J., Winnburst, J. A., & Bensing, J. M. (1999). Teaching clinically experienced physicians communication skills. A review of evaluation studies. Medical Education, 33, 665-668.

Hulsman, R. L., Visser, A., & Makoul, G. (2005). Addressing some of the key questions about communication in healthcare. Patient Education and Counselling, 58(3), 221-224.

Irwig, L., McCaffery, K., Salkleld, G., & Bossuyt, P. (2006). Informed choice for screening: implications for evaluation. British Medical Journal, 332, 1148-1150.

Page 342: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

342

Isaacs, P. (1998). Social practices, medicine and the nature of medical ethics. Paper presented at the Society for Health and Human Values Spring regional Meeting, Youngston, Ohio, Youngston State University.

Isaacs, P. (2001). Ways of seeing in applied ethics: Reassessing the philosophical paradigm. Paper presented at the Applied Ethics: Challenges and Explorations, Carseldine Campus, QUT, Brisbane.

Isaacs, P. (2003). Doing ethics - An action based approach. Paper presented at the Peninsula Behavioural Health Conference, Gatlinburg, Tennessee.

Isaacs, P. (2007). Ontology, narrative and ethical engagement. Paper presented at the 'Confessions: Confounding Narrative and Research', Queensland University of Technology, Brisbane.

Isaacs, P., & Massey, D. (1994). Mapping the applied ethics agenda. Paper presented at the Third Annual Meeting of the Association for Practical and Professional Ethics, Cleveland, Ohio.

Jackson, E. (2000). Abortion, autonomy and prenatal diagnosis. Social & Legal Studies, 9(4), 467-494.

Jaques, A. M., Halliday, J. L., Francis, I., Bonacquisto, Forbes, R., Cronin, A., et al. (2007). Follow up and evaluation of the Victorian first-trimester combined screening programme for Down syndrome and trisomy 18. BJOG, 114(7), 812.

Jecker, N., Jonsen, A., & Pearlman, R. A. (1997). Bioethics. An introduction to history methods and practice. Boston: Jones and Bartlett Publishers.

Ji, E., Pretorius, D. H., Newton, R., Uyan, K., Hull, A. D., Hollenbach, K., et al. (2005). Effects of ultrasound on maternal -fetal bonding: a comparison of two and three dimensional imaging. Ultrasound in Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 25(5), 473-477.

Johns, N., Al-Salti, W., Cox, P., & Kilby, M.D. (2004). A comparative study of prenatal ultrasound findings and post-mortem examination in a tertiary referral centre. Prenatal Diagnosis, 24(5), 339-346.

Jonsen, A. (1998). The birth of bioethics. In (pp. 282-321). New York: Oxford University Press.

Kaiser, A., Ferris, L., Pastuszak, A., Llewellyn-Thomas, H., Johnson, J.-A., Conacher, S., et al. (2002). The effects of prenatal group genetic counselling on knowledge, anxiety and decisional conflict: issues for nuchal translucency screening. Journal of Obstetrics & Gynaecology, 22(3), 246-255.

Kaiser, M., & Forsberg, E. (2001). Assessing Fisheries - Using an Ethical Matrix in a Participatory Process. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 14(2), 191.

Kass, L. R. (2002). Life, liberty and the defense of dignity. The challenge for bioethics. San Francisco: Encounter Books.

Katz - Rothman, B. (1986). The tentative pregnancy : How amniocentesis changes the experience of motherhood.: W. W. Norton & Company.

Kendig, S. (2006). Word Power. The Effect of Literacy on Health Outcomes. AWHONN Lifelines, 10(4), 327-331.

Kenen, R. (1996). The 'at-risk' health status and technology: A diagnostic invitation and the 'gift' of knowing. Social Science & Medicine, 42(11), 1545-1553.

Kenen, R. (1999). Disability rights and prenatal genetic testing. Network News, 24(2), 3.

Kerridge, I., Lowe, M., & Henry, D. (1998). Ethics and evidence based medicine. British Medical Journal, 316(7138), 1151.

Page 343: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

343

Kersten, J. M. (2007). Emotions in employee-supervisor workplace relationships: The lived experience of women professionals. Unpublished 3255585, University of St. Thomas (Minnesota), United States -- Minnesota.

Kleinman, A. (1988). The illness narratives. Suffering, healing and the human condition: Basic Books, Inc.

Kleinveld, J. H., Timmermans, D. R. M., de Smit, D. J., Ader, H. J., van der Wal, G., & ten Kate, L. P. (2006). Does prenatal screening influence anxiety levels of pregnant women? A longitudinal randomised controlled trial. Prenatal Diagnosis, 26, 354-361.

Knowles, M. (1970). The modern practice of adult education: Andragogy versus pedagogy. New York: Association Press.

Knowles, M. (1984). Andragogy in action. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass,. Knowles, M. (1989). The making of an adult educator -An autobiographical

journey. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Knowles, M. (1990). The adult learner: A neglected species. Houston, TX.: Gulf

Publishing Company. Knowles, M., Holton, E. F., & Swanson, R. A. (1998). The adult learner: The

definitive classic in adult education and human resource development (5th ed.). Houston, TX: Gulf Publishing Company.

Knowles, M., Holton, E. F., & Swanson, R. A. (2005). The adult learner : The definitive classic in adult education and human resource development. Burlington: Elsevier.

Kohut, R. J. (2002). Women's knowledge of prenatal ultrasound and informed choice. Journal of Genetic Counselling, 11(4), 265-276.

Kolker, A., & Burke, B. M. (1994). Prenatal testing: A sociological perspective. Westport, CT.: Bergin and Garvey.

Komesaroff, P. (1995). From bioethics to microethics: Ethical debate and clinical medicine. In P. Komesaroff (Ed.), Troubled bodies. Critical perspectives on postmodernism, medical ethics and the body: Melbourne University Press.

Kornman, L. H., Morssink, L. P., Beekhuis, J. R., De Wolf, B. T. H. M., Heringa, M. P., & Mantingh, A. (1996). Nuchal translucency cannot be used as a screening test for chromosomal abnormalities in the first trimester of a pregnancy in a routine ultrasound practice. Prenatal Diagnosis, 16(9), 797-805.

Kowalcek, A., Muhlhoff, A., Bachmann, S., & Gembruch, U. (2002). Depressive reactions and stress related to prenatal medicine procedures. Ultrasound Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 19, 18-23.

Kuhse, H., & Singer, P. (1985). Should the baby live? :The problem of handicapped infants. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kuppermann, M., Goldberg, J. D., Nease, R. F. J., & Washington, A. E. (1999). Who should be offered prenatal diagnosis? The 35-year-old question. American Journal of Public Health [NLM - MEDLINE], 89(2), 160.

Kuppermann, M., & Norton, M. E. (2005). Prenatal testing guidelines: Time for a new approach? Gynaelogic and Obstetric Investigation, 60, 6-10.

Labov, W. (1972). The transformation of experience in narrative syntax. In W. Labov (Ed.), Language in the inner city: Studies in the black English vernacular (pp. 354-396). Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

Laidlaw, T. S., Kaufman, D. K., Sargent, J., MacLeod, H., Blake, K., & Simpson, D. (2007). What makes a physician an exemplary communicator with patients? Patient Education and Counselling, 68, 153-160.

Page 344: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

344

Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh : the embodied mind and its challenge to Western thought. New York: Basic Books.

Laussel-Riera, A., Devisme, L., Manouvrier- Hanu, S., Puech, F., Robert, Y., & Gosselin, B. (2000). Value of feto pathological examination in medical abortions: comparison of prenatal diagnosis and autopsy results of 300 foetuses. Ann Pathol, 20, 549-557.

Laverty, J. (2006). Investigating the experiences of grandparent childcarers: Reflections on using narrative inquiry. Retrieved 18th October, 2006, from 2Hwww.uws.edu.au/download.php?file_id=7424&filename=Judy_Laverty.pdf&mimetype=application/pdf

Lawson, K. L. (2006). Expectations of the parenting experience and willingness to consider selective termination for Down Syndrome. Journal of Reproductive and Infant Psychology, 24(1), 43.

Leithner, K., Assem-Hilger, E., Fischer-Kern, M., Loffler-Stastka, H., Thien, R., & Ponocny-Seilger, E. (2006). Prenatal care: the patient's perspective. A qualitative study. Prenatal Diagnosis, 26, 931-937.

Leithner, K., Fischer-Kern, M., Hilger, E., Loffler-Stastka, H., & Ponocny-Seilger, E. (2004). Affective state of women following a prenatal diagnosis: predictors of negative psychological outcome. Ultrasound Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 23, 240-246.

Levi, S. (1998). Routine ultrasound screening of congenital anomalies: An overview of the European experience. Annals of the New York Academy of Science, 18(847), 86-98.

Levi, S. (2002). Ultrasound in prenatal diagnosis: polemics around routine ultrasound screening for second trimester foetal malformations. Prenatal Diagnosis, 22, 285-295.

Levinson, W., Roter, D. L., Mullooly, J. P., & Frankel, R. M. (1997). Physician -patient communication : The relationship with malpractice claims among primary care physicians and surgeons. JAMA, 277, 553-559.

Lewthwaite, B. J. (1999). Listening to the voices: A qualitative study to examine the attitudes of women related to the routine use of ultrasonography in pregnancy. The University of Manitoba (Canada), Canada.

Liamputtong, P., Halliday, J. L., Warren, R., Watson, L. F., & Bell, R. J. (2003). Why do women decline prenatal screening and diagnosis? Australian women's perspective. Women and Health, 37(2), 89-108.

Liamputtong, P., & Watson, L. (2002). The voices and concerns about prenatal testing of Cambodian, Lao and Vietnamese women in Australia. Midwifery, 18, 304-313.

Liaschenko, J., Oguz, N. Y., & Brunnquell, D. (2006). Critique of the "tragic case" method in ethics education. Journal of Medical Ethics, 32(11), 672-677.

Lindeman - Nelson, J. (2003). Hippocrates' maze. Ethical explorations of the medical labyrinth. New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc.

Lindemann-Nelson, H. (2001). Damaged identities: Narrative repair: Cornell University Press.

Lippman, A. (1991). Prenatal genetic testing and screening: Constructing needs and reinforcing inequities. American Journal of Law and Medicine, 27(1&2), 15.

Lippman, A. (1999a). Choice as a risk to women's health. Health , Risk and Society, 1(3), 281-291.

Lippman, A. (1999b). Prenatal diagnosis [letter]. American Journal of Public Health [NLM - MEDLINE], 89(10), 1592.

Page 345: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

345

Lippman, A. (2003). Eugenics and public health. American Journal of Public Health [NLM - MEDLINE], 93(1), 11.

Little, P., Everitt, H., Williamson, I., Warner, G., & al, e. (2001). Preferences of patients for patient-centred approach to consultation in primary care: Observational study. British Medical Journal, 322(7284), 468.

Lu, M. C., Kotelchuck, M., Culhane, J. F., C., H., Klerman, L. V., & Thorp, J. M. J. (2006). Preconception Care Between Pregnancies: The Content of Internatal Care. Maternal and Child Health Journal, 10, 107.

Lumley, J. (1990). Through a glass darkly: ultrasound and prenatal bonding. Birth (Berkeley, California), 17(4), 214-217.

Lynch, E. (2007). Why size matters. Nursing Standard [NLM - MEDLINE], 21(18), 22.

Macduff, C., & West, B. (2002). Developing the use of poetry within healthcare culture. British Journal of Nursing, 11(5), 335-341.

MacFarlane, P. J. M., & Reid, S. J. (2006). Queensland Health Law Handbook (16th ed.): Qld Department of Health.

MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue : a study in moral theory: University of Notre Dame Press.

Mackenzie, C. (1995). Abortion and embodiment. In P. Komesaroff (Ed.), Troubled bodies (pp. 38-61). Melbourne: Melbourne University Press.

Macones, G., & Odibo, A. (2005). First Trimester Screening: Economic Implications. Seminars in Perinatology. Prenatal Screening: Incorporating the First Trimester Screening, 29(4), 263-266.

Makoul, G., & Clayman, M. L. (2006). An integrative model of shared decision making in medical encounters. Patient Education and Counseling, 60(3), 301-312.

Manson, N. C. (2007). Consent and informed consent. In R. E. Ashcroft, H. Dawson, H. Draper & J. R. McMillan (Eds.), Principles of Health Care Ethics (2nd ed.): John Wiley & Sons Ltd.

Manson, N. C., & O'Neill, O. (2007). Rethinking informed consent in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Marieb, E. (1992). Human anatomy and physiology (2nd ed.): The Benjamin Cummings Publishing Company.

Marinac-Dabic, D. (2002). The safety of prenatal ultrasound exposure in human studies. Epidemiology, 13(3 Suppl), S19-22.

Markens, S., Browner, C., & Press, N. (1999). 'Because of the risks': how US pregnant women account for refusing prenatal screening. Social Science & Medicine, 49(3), 359-369.

Marteau, T., & Dormandy, E. (2001). Facilitating informed choice in prenatal testing: How well are we doing? American Journal of Medical Genetics, 106(3), 185-190.

Marteau, T., Dormandy, E., & Michie, S. (2001). A measure of informed choice. In Health Expectations (pp. 99-108): Blackwell Science Ltd.

Marteau, T., & Drake, H. (1995). Attributions for disability: The influence of genetic screening. Social Science & Medicine, 40(8), 1127-1132.

Marteau, T. M., Dormandy, E. R., & Michie, S. (2001). Informed choice and prenatal screening: Comparison of same day vs. return visit testing. American Journal of Human Genetics, 69(4), 426-426.

Page 346: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

346

Marteau, T. M., Slack, J., Kidd, J., & Shaw, R. W. (1992). Presenting a routine screening test in antenatal care - Practice observed. Public Health, 106(2), 131-141.

Mauthner, N. (1998). 'It's a cry for help': A relational perspective on post-natal depression. Feminism and Psychology, 8(3), 325-355.

Mauthner, N., & Doucet, A. (1998). Reflections on a Voice-Centred Relational Method: Analysing maternal and domestic voices. In Feminist dilemmas in qualitative research: Public knowledge and private lives (pp. 119-146.). London: Sage Publications.

May, W. (1994). The virtues in a professional setting. In K. W. M. Fulford, G. R. Gillett & J. M. Soskice (Eds.), Medicine and Moral Reasoning (pp. 75 - 90). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press,.

McCredie, J. (2007). Worried well driving GPs to distraction. Australian Doctor, 1. McKie, A., & Gass, J. P. (2001). Understanding mental health through reading

selected literature sources: an evaluation. Nurse Education Today, 21(3), 201-208.

McKinstry, B. (2000). Do patients wish to be involved in decision making in the consultation? A cross sectional survey with video vignettes. British Medical Journal, 321(7265), 867.

McLean-Taylor, J., Gilligan, C., & Sullivan, A. M. (1995). Between voice and silence. Women and girls, race and relationship. Cambridge, MASS: Harvard University Press.

McMillan, J., & Gillett, G. (2002). Consent as empowerment: The role of post-modern and narrative ethics. In K. W. M. Fulford, D. L. Dickenson & T. H. Murray (Eds.), Healthcare ethics and human values: An introductory text with readings and case studies. Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

McVea, K. L. S. P., Venugopal, M., Crabtree, B. F., & Aita, V. (2000). The organisation and distribution of patient education materials in family medicine practices. The Journal of Family Practice, 49(4), 319-326.

Mead, N., Bower, P., & Hann, M. (2002). The impact of general practitioners' patient-centeredness on patients' post-consultation satisfaction and enablement. Social Science & Medicine, 55(2), 283-299.

Mei-The, A., Hak, T., Koeter, G., & van der Wal, G. (2000). Collusion in doctor-patient communication about imminent death: an ethnographic study. British Medical Journal, 321, 1376-1381.

Meyers, C. (2007). Clinical ethics consultants and conflict of interest structurally intertwined. The Hastings Center Report(March- April), 32-40.

Mezirow, J. (1991). Transformative dimensions of adult learning. San Francisco: Jossey- Boss.

Mezirow, J. (1996). Contemporary paradigms of learning. Adult Education Quarterly, 46(3), 158-172.

Mezirow, J. (1997). Transformative learning: Theory to practice. New Directions for Adult and Continuing Education(74), 5-12.

Michie, S., Dormandy, E., & Marteau, T. (2002). The multi-dimensional measure of informed choice: A validation study. Patient Education and Counseling, 48, 87-91.

Michie, S., Dormandy, E., & Marteau, T. (2003). Informed choice: understanding knowledge in the context of screening uptake. Patient Education and Counseling, 50, 247-253.

Page 347: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

347

Microsoft. (1999). Encarta Encyclopaedia Miller, W., & Crabtree, B. F. (2004). Depth interviewing. In S. Nagy Hesse - Biber

& P. Leavy (Eds.), Approaches to qualitative research: A reader on theory and practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Milligan, E. (2004). Ethical practice in prenatal screening: Can informed consent deliver? Unpublished Honours, Queensland University of Technology, Brisbane.

Milligan, E., & Winch, S. (2007). Embedding ethics in institutional care. The role of PACES in nurturing an inclusive moral space. Paper presented at the Health, Bioethics and the Law: Inclusions and Exclusions. The Australasian Bioethics Association and The Australian and New Zealand Institute of Health, Law and Ethics Joint Conference 2007, International House, University of Melbourne.

Milligan, E., & Woodley, E. (2008). Creative expressive encounters in health ethics

education: Teaching ethics as relational engagement. Teaching and Learning in Medicine, In Press.

Minichiello, V., Aroni, R., Timewell, E., & Alexander, L. (1995). In-depth interviewing (2nd ed.). Melbourne: Longman.

Minister, K. (1991). A feminist frame for interviews. In S. B. Gluck & D. Patai (Eds.), Women's words: The feminist practice of oral history (pp. 36-39). New York: Routledge.

Mishler, E. G. (1986). Research interviewing: Context and narrative. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Mitchell, K., Kerridge, I., & Lovat, T. (1996). Bioethics and clinical ethics for health care professionals (2nd ed.). Wentworth Falls: Social Science Press.

Mount, E. (1990). Professional ethics in context: institutions, images, and empathy. Louisville, Ky: Knox Press.

Nedelsky, J. (1989). Recovering autonomy: Sources, thoughts and possibilities. Yale Journal of Law and Feminism, 1(1), 7-36.

Neilson, J., & Alfirevic, Z. (2000). Doppler ultrasound in pregnancy: Cochrane review. Cochrane Library(Issue 2).

Nelkin, D. (1996). An uneasy relationship: The tensions between medicine and the media. The Lancet, 347(9015), 1600-1604.

Nelkin, D., & Lindee, M. S. (1995). The DNA Mystique: The Gene as a Cultural Icon: W.H. Freeman & Co.

Neugebauer, R., Kline, J., Shrout, P., Skodol, A., & al, e. (1997). Major depressive disorder in the 6 months after miscarriage. JAMA, 277(5), 383.

Neuman, W. L. (2000). Social research methods: Qualitative and quantitative approaches. (4th ed.): Allyn and Bacon.

Newell, C. (2003). Embracing life: Ethical challenges in disability and biotechnology. Interaction, 16(2), 25-33.

Newell, C. (2007). Narrating normalcy: Disability, medicine and ethics. Journal on Developmental Disability, 13(2).

Newnham, J. P., Doherty, D. A., Kendall, G. E., Zubrick, S. R., & al, e. (2004). Effects of repeated prenatal ultrasound examinations on childhood outcome up to 8 years of age: follow-up of a randomised controlled trial. The Lancet, 364(9450), 2038.

Page 348: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

348

Nicolaides, K. H., Azar, G., Byrne, D., Mansur, C., & Marks, K. (1992). Fetal nuchal translucency: ultrasound screening for chromosomal defects in first trimester of pregnancy. British Medical Journal, 304, 867-889.

Nicolaides, K. H., Heath, V., & Cicero, S. (2002). Increased fetal nuchal translucency at 11-14 weeks. Prenatal Diagnosis, 22, 308-315.

Nicolaides, K. H., Snijders, R. J., & Cuckle, H. (1998). Correct estimation of parameters of ultrasound nuchal translucency screening. Prenatal Diagnosis, 18, 519-523.

Noble, D. (1999). The religion of technology. New York: Penguin. Oakley, A. (1996). The history of ultrasonography in obstetrics. Birth, 13(1), 8-13. O'Brien, G. (2004). What are the Principles of Adult Learning? Retrieved 12th

August, 2007, from 3Hhttp://www.southernhealth.org.au/cpme/articles/adult_learning.htm

O'Cathain, A., Thomas, K., Walters, S. J., Nicholl, J., & Kirkham, M. (2002). Women's perceptions of informed choice in maternity care. Midwifery, 18(2), 136-144.

O'Connor, A., Rostom, A., Fiset, V., Tetroe, J., Entwhistle, V., Llewellyn-Thomas, H., et al. (1999). Decision aids for patients facing health treatment or screening decisions: systematic review. British Medical Journal, 319, 731-734.

Olin Lauritzen, S., & Sachs, L. (2001). Normality, risk and the future: implicit communication of threat in health surveillance. Sociology of Health & Illness, 23(4), 497-516.

Oshana, M. A. L. (2001). The autonomy bogeyman. Journal of Value Inquiry, 35(2), 209.

Parens, E., & Asch, A. (2000). The disability rights critique of prenatal genetic testing. The Hastings Center Report, 29(5), S1.

Parker, M., Forbes, K. L., & Findlay, I. (2002). Eugenics or empowered choice? Community issues arising from prenatal testing. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 42(1), 10-14.

Pauly Morgan, K. (1998). Contested bodies, contested knowledges: Women, health and the politics of medicalisation. In S. Sherwin (Ed.), The politics of women’s health: Exploring agency and autonomy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Pellegrino, E. D. (2003). From medical ethics to a moral philosophy of the professions. In J. K. Walter & E. P. Klein (Eds.), The story of bioethics. Washington: Georgetown University Press.

Peters, M. J., Morgan, L. C., & Gluch, L. (2004). Smoking cessation and elective surgery: the cleanest cut. Medical Journal of Australia, 180(7), 317.

Pilnick, A. (2004). 'It's just one of the best tests that we've got a the moment': the presentation of nuchal translucency screening for fetal abnormality in pregnancy. Discourse and Society, 15(4), 451-465.

Polkinghorne, D. E. (1988). Narrative Knowing and the Human Sciences. Albany: State University of New York Press.

Post, D. M., Cegala, D. J., & Miser, W. F. (2002). The other half of the whole: Teaching patients to communicate with physicians. Family Medicine, 34(5), 344-352.

Pratt, A., Biggs, A., & Buckmaster, L. (2004). How many abortions are there in Australia? A discussion of abortion statistics, their limitations, and options

Page 349: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

349

for improved statistical collection: Parliament of Australia. Social Policy Section. Research Brief no. 9 2004–05.

Press, N., & Browner, C. (1993). 'Collective fictions': Similarities in reasons for accepting maternal alpha-fetoprotein screening among women of diverse ethnic social class backgrounds. Fetal Diagnosis and Therapy, 8(suppl), 97-106.

Press, N., & Browner, C. (1995). Risk, autonomy and responsibility: Informed consent for prenatal testing. The Hastings Center Report, 25(3).

Press, N., & Browner, C. (1997). Why women say yes to prenatal diagnosis. Social Science & Medicine, 45(7), 979-989.

Priest, S. (1998). Merleau-Ponty. London: Routledge. Pullman, D. (2005). Ethics first aid: Reframing the role of 'principlism' in clinical

ethics education and practice. Journal of Clinical Ethics, 16(3), 223-229. Pullman, D., Bethune, C., & Duke, P. (2005). Narrative means to humanistic ends.

Teaching and Learning in Medicine, 17(3), 279-284. Qureshi, N., Armstrong, S., & Modell, B. (2006). GPs' opinions of their role in

prenatal genetic services: a cross-sectional survey. Family Practice, 23(1), 106.

Rachal, J. R. (2002). Andragogy's detectives: A critique of the present and a proposal for the future. Adult Education Quarterly, 52(3), 210-227.

Raffle, A. E. (2001). Information about screening - is it to achieve high uptake or to ensure informed choice? Health Expectations, 4(2), 92-98.

Raider-Roth, M. B. (2005). Trusting what you know: Negotiating the relational context of classroom life. Teachers College Record, 107(4), 587-628.

Ramalho, C., Matias, A., Brandao, O., & Montenegro, N. (2006). Critical evaluation of elective termination of pregnancy in a tertiary foetal medicine centre during 43 months: correlation of prenatal diagnosis findings and post-mortem examination. Prenatal Diagnosis, 26, 1084-1088.

Rapp, R. (2000). Testing the woman, testing the fetus. The social impact of amniocentesis in America. New York: Routledge.

Reese, H. W., & Overton, W. E. (1970). Models of development and theories of development. In L. R. Gottlet & P. B. Baltes (Eds.), Life span development psychology (pp. 115-133). New York: Academic Press.

Reinders, H. (2000). The future of the disabled in liberal society: An ethical analysis. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

Renz, D. O., & Eddy, W. B. (1996). Organisations, ethics and health care: Building an ethics infrastructure for a new era. Bioethics Forum, 12, 29-39.

Richie, K., Boynton, J., & Bradbury, I. (2004). Routine ultrasound scanning before 24 weeks of pregnancy. Health Technology Assessment Report 5. NHS Quality Improvement Scotland: Glasgow.

Riessman, C. (1993). Narrative analysis. Newbury Park, California: Sage Publications, Inc.

Riessman, C. (2002). Narrative analysis. In A. M. Huberman & M. B. Miles (Eds.), The qualitative researchers companion (pp. 217-274). Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

Riessman, C. (2004). Narrative analysis. In M. S. Lewis-Beck, A. Bryman & T. Futing Liao (Eds.), Encyclopaedia of Social Science Research Methods. London UK and Newbury Park CA: Sage Publications.

Rothblatt, M. (1997). Unzipped genes: Taking charge of baby making in the new millennium. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Page 350: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

350

Runciman, D. (2002). Do we really want to know the odds? In K. W. M. Fulford, D. L. Dickenson & T. H. Murray (Eds.), Health Care Ethics and Human Values: An introductory text with readings and case studies. (pp. 111-113). Oxford.: Blackwell Publishers Inc.

Russell, S. S. (2006). An overview of adult-learning processes. Urologic Nursing [NLM - MEDLINE], 26(5), 349.

Sadler, M. (1997). Serum screening for Downs Syndrome: how much do health professionals know? British Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology., 104, 176-179.

Sandman, L. (2004). On the autonomy turf. Assessing the value of autonomy to patients. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy,, 7, 261-268.

Santhalahti, P. (1999). Participation in prenatal screening and intentions concerning selective termination in Finnish maternity care. Fetal Diagnosis and Therapy, 14(2), 71-79.

Santhalahti, P., Hemminki, E., Latikka, A., & Ryynanen, M. (1998). Women's decision making in prenatal screening. Social Science & Medicine, 46(8), 1067-1076.

Savulescu, J. (2001). Procreative beneficence: why we should select the best children. Bioethics [H.W. Wilson - SSA], 15(5/6), 413.

Savulescu, J. (2005). New breeds of humans: the moral obligation to enhance. Reproductive Biomedicine Online, 10(Supplement 1), 36-39.

Say, R., & Thomson, R. (2003). The importance of patient preferences in treatment decisions - challenges for doctors. British Medical Journal, 327(4), 542.

Schanholzer, S. M., Gatzmann, L., Zimmermann, R., & Buddeberg, C. (2000). Psychological aspects of ultrasound examinations during pregnancy. Gynakologisch-Geburtshilfliche Rundschau, 40(3-4), 119-124.

Schneider, C. E. (1996). The practice of autonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Shakespeare, T. (1998). Choices and rights: Eugenics, genetics and disability equality. Disability and Society, 13(5), 665.

Shakespeare, T. (1999). Manifesto for genetic justice. Social Alternatives, 18(1), 29. Shakespeare, T. (2001). The Danger of Disability Prejudice. Retrieved 1st

September 2001, from 4Hwww.genecrc.org.site/hi/hi3z.html Shakespeare, T. (2005). The social context of individual choice. In D. Wasserman, J.

Bickenbach & R. Wachbroit (Eds.), Quality of life and human difference. Genetic testing, health care and disability. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Shanahan, M. J., Smith, P. E., Ryan, S., & Carter, R. F. (2005). Carter's Criminal Law of Queensland. Australia: Lexis Nexis Butterworths.

Shelford, G. (2003). Risk, statistics and the individual. British Medical Journal, 327(7417).

Sherwin, S. (1992). No longer patient. Feminist ethics and health care. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Sherwin, S. (1998). The politics of women's health: exploring agency and autonomy. The Feminist Health Care Ethics Research Network. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Sherwin, S. (2001). Diagnosis difference: The moral authority of medicine. Hypatia, 16(3), 172.

Page 351: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

351

Silverman, H. J. (2000). Organisational ethics in health care organisations: Proactively managing the ethical climate to ensure organisational integrity. HEC Forum, 12(3), 202-215.

Skolbekken, J. (1995). The risk epidemic in medical journals. Social Science & Medicine, 40(3), 291-305.

Slovic, P., Finucane, M. L., Peters, E., & MacGregor, D. G. (2004). Risk as analysis and risk as feelings: Some thoughts about affect, reason, risk and rationality. Risk Analysis, 24(2), 311- 322.

Snijders, R., Noble, P., Souka, A., & Nicolaides, K. H. (1998). UK multi-centre project on assessment of risk of trisomy 21 by maternal age and foetal nuchal translucency thickness at 10-14 weeks gestation. The Lancet, 352(9125), 343-346.

Solomon, M. Z. (2005). Realising bioethics goals in practice: Ten ways 'is' can help 'ought'. The Hastings Center Report(4), 40-47.

Somerville, M. (2006). The ethical imagination: Imagining an ethics for the future. Carlton: Melbourne University Press.

Sparkes, A. C., & Smith, B. (2005). When narratives matter: Men, sport, and spinal cord injury. Journal of medical Ethics; Medical Humanities, 31, 81-88.

Spencer, K., & Cowans, N. J. (2007). ADAM12 as a marker of trisomy 18 in the first and second trimester of pregnancy. Journal of Maternal - Fetal & Neonatal Medicine, 20(9), 645.

Spencer, K., Spencer, C., Power, M., Dawson, C., & Nicolaides, K. H. (2003). Screening for chromosomal abnormalities in the first trimester using ultrasound and maternal serum biochemistry in a one stop clinic: A review of three years prospective experience. British Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology., 110(3), 281-286.

Spencer, R. A. (2002). Hanging out and growing strong: A qualitative study of relationships with adults that foster resilience in adolescence. Unpublished 3055888, Harvard University, United States -- Massachusetts.

Stapleton, H., Kirkham, M., & Thomas, G. (2002). Qualitative study of evidence based leaflets in maternity care. British Medical Journal, 324(7338), 639-643.

Stephens, M. B., Montefalcon, R., & Lane, D. A. (2000). The Maternal Perspective on Prenatal Ultrasound. Journal of Family Practice

Journal of Family Practice J1 - Journal of Family Practice, 49(7), 601-604. Stephenson, P. (2006). Before the teaching begins: managing patient anxiety prior to

providing education. Clinical Journal of Oncology Nursing, 10(2), 241-245. Stewart, M. (1995). Effective physician- patient communication and health

outcomes: A review. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 152, 1423-1433.

Stewart, M. (2001a). Towards a global definition of patient-centred care. British Medical Journal, 322, 444-446.

Stewart, M. (2001b). Whose evidence counts? An exploration of health professionals' perceptions of evidence-based practice, focusing on the maternity services. Midwifery, 17, 279-288.

Stewart, M., Belle- Brown, J., Boon, H., Galajda, J., Meredith, L., & Sangster, M. (1999). Evidence on patient- doctor communication. Cancer Prevention and Control, 3(1), 25-30.

Page 352: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

352

Stewart, M., Belle- Brown, J., Donner, A., McWinney, I., Oates, J., Weston, W., et al. (2000). The impact of patient - centred care on outcomes. The Journal of Family Practice, 49(9), 796 - 804.

Stewart, M., Belle- Brown, J., Weston, W., McWhinney, I., McWilliam, C., & Freeman, T. (2003). Patient - centred medicine: Transforming the clinical method. (2nd ed.). Oxon.: Radcliffe Medical Press.

Straton, J., Godman, K., Gee, V., & Hu, Q. (2006). Induced abortions in Western Australia, 1999-2005. Report of the WA Abortion Notification System. Perth: Department of Health.

Street, R. L., Gordon, H. S., Ward, M. M., Krupat, E., & Kravitz, R. L. (2005). Patient Participation in Medical Consultations: Why Some Patients are More Involved Than Others. Medical Care, 43(10), 960.

Strickland, L. (1994). Autobiographical interviewing and narrative analysis: An approach to psychosocial assessment. Clinical Social Work Journal, 22(1), 27-43.

Suter, S. M. (2002). The routinisation of prenatal testing. American Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics., 28, 233-270.

Tankard - Reist, M. (2005). Defiant birth: Spinifex Press. Tartaglia, M., Niemeyer, C. M., Fragale, A., Song , X., Buechner, J., Jung, A., et al.

(2003). Somatic mutations in PTPN11 in juvenile myelomonocytic leukaemia, myelodysplastic syndromes and acute myeloid leukaemia. Nat Genet, 34(2), 148-150.

Taylor, C. (1988). The moral topography of the self. In S. B. Messer, L. A. Sass & R. L. Woolfolk (Eds.), Hermeneutics and psychological theory: Interpretive perspectives on personality, psychotherapy, and psychopathology. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Taylor, K. (1996). Why psychological models of adult development are important...

Adult Education Quarterly, 47(1), 54. Tennstedt, C., Chaoui, R., Bollman, R., Korner, H., & Dietel, M. (1998). Correlation

of prenatal ultrasound diagnosis and morphological findings of foetal autopsy. Pathol Res Pract, 194(10), 721-724.

Thomas, C. (1999). Female forms: Experiencing and understanding disability. Buckingham, Philadelphia: Open University Press.

Thorne, B. (2004). "You still takin' notes?" Fieldwork and problems of informed consent. In N. S. Hesse - Biber & P. Leavy (Eds.), Approaches to qualitative research. A reader on theory and practice. New York: Oxford University Press.

Thornton, J. G., Hewison, J., Lilford, R. J., & Vail, A. (1995). A randomised trial of three methods of giving information about prenatal testing. British Medical Journal, 311, 1127-1130.

Tomlinson, T. (1997). Perplexed about narrative ethics. In J. Lindeman - Nelson (Ed.), Stories and their limits. New York: Routledge.

Tong, R. (1998). The ethics of care: a feminist virtue ethics of care for health care practitioners. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 23(2), 131- 152.

Tong, R. (2002). Teaching Bioethics in the New Millennium: Holding Theories Accountable to Actual Practices and Real People. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 27(4), 417 - 432.

Tonti -Filippini, N. (2004). Smoking cessation and elective surgery: The cleanest cut. Medical Journal of Australia, 181(5), 283.

Page 353: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

353

Toombs, K. (2001). Reflections on bodily change: The lived experience of disability. In K. Toombs (Ed.), Handbook of phenomenology and medicine. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Toulmin, S. (1990). Cosmopolis. The hidden agenda of modernity. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Towle, A., & Godolphin, W. (1999). Framework for teaching and learning informed shared decision making. British Medical Journal, 319, 766 - 771.

Towle, A., Godolphin, W., Manklow, J., & Wiesinger, H. (2003). Patient perceptions that limit a community based intervention to promote participation. Patient Education and Counselling, 50, 231 - 233.

Trevena, L., & Barrat, A. (2003). Integrated decision making: Definitions for a new discipline. Patient Education and Counseling, 50, 265-268.

Tschudin, V. (2003). Approaches to ethics: Nursing beyond boundaries. Edinburgh: Butterworth - Heinemann.

Tyzack, K., & Wallace, E. M. (2003). Down syndrome screening: What do health professionals know? The Australian and New Zealand Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 43(3), 217-221.

van den Berg, M., Timmermans, D. R. M., Kleinveld, J. H., Garcia, E., van Vugt, J. M. G., & van der Wal, G. (2005). Accepting or declining the offer of prenatal screening for congenital defects: test uptake and women's reasons. Prenatal Diagnosis, 25(1), 84-90.

van den Brink-Muinen, A., van Dulmen, S., de Haes, C., Visser, A., Schellevis, F. G., & Bensing, J. M. (2006). Has patients' involvement in the decision making process changed over time? Health Expectations, 9, 333-342.

Waithe, W. E. (2005). Community coalitions as sites of transformative learning. Unpublished 3177569, State University of New York at Albany, United States -- New York.

Wald, N. J., Huttly, W. J., & Hackshaw, A. K. (2003). Antenatal Screening for Down's Syndrome with the Quadruple Test. The Lancet [on-line via Proquest], 361(9360), 835-836.

Walker, M. U. (1993). Keeping moral space open: New images of ethics consulting. The Hastings Centre Report, 23(2), 33-40.

Walker, M. U. (1998). Moral understandings: A feminist study in ethics. London: Routledge.

Walker, M. U. (2003). Moral contexts. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.

Watson, M., Hall, S., Langford, K., & Marteau, T. (2003). Psychological Impact of the detection of soft markers on routine Ultrasound scanning: A pilot study investigating the modifying role of information. Prenatal Diagnosis, 22, 569-575.

Wear, S. (1998). Informed consent: Patient autonomy and clinician beneficence within health care (2nd ed.). Washington .D.C.: Georgetown University Press.

Weisberg, M., & Duffin, J. (1995). Evoking moral imagination. The Journal of Medical Humanities, 16(4), 247-263.

Wertz, D. C. (1992). Ethical and legal implications of the new genetics: Issues for discussion. Social Science & Medicine, 35(4), 495-505.

Wertz, D. C. (1998). Eugenics is alive and well. Science in Context, 11, 493-510.

Page 354: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

354

Wertz, D. C., & Fletcher, J. C. (1998). Ethical and social issues in prenatal sex selection: A survey of geneticists in 37 nations. Social Science & Medicine, 46(2), 255-273.

West, H., & Bramwell, R. (2006). Do maternal screening tests provide psychologically meaningful results? Cognitive psychology in an applied setting. Journal of Reproductive and Infant Psychology, 24(1), 61.

Weston, W. (2001). Informed and shared decision making: the crux of patient -centred care. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 165(4), 438-439.

Weston, W., & Belle- Brown, J. (1989). The importance of patients’ beliefs. In M. Stewart & D. Roter (Eds.), Communicating with medical patients. Newbury Park: Sage Publications.

Whittle, M. (1997). Ultrasonographic "soft markers" of fetal chromosomal defects. Detecting them may do more harm than good. British Medical Journal, 314(918).

Whynes, D. K. (2002). Receipt of information and women's attitudes towards ultrasound scanning during pregnancy. Ultrasound Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 19, 7-12.

Widdershoven, G. A. M., & Smit, M. J. (1996). Ethics and narratives. In R. Josselson (Ed.), Ethics and process in the narrative study of lives. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

Wildes, K. W. (1997). Institutional identity, integrity and conscience. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 7, 413-419.

Williams, C., Alderson, P., & Farsides, B. (2002a). 'Drawing the line' in prenatal screening and testing: health practitioners' discussions. Health Risk & Society, 4(1), 61-75.

Williams, C., Alderson, P., & Farsides, B. (2002b). Is non-directiveness possible within the context of antenatal screening and testing? Social Science & Medicine, 54(3), 339-347.

Williams, C., Alderson, P., & Farsides, B. (2002c). Too many choices? Hospital and community staff reflect on the future of prenatal screening. Social Science & Medicine [H.W. Wilson - SSA], 55(5), 743.

Williams, C., Alderson, P., & Farsides, B. (2002d). What constitutes 'balanced information in the practitioners' portrayal of Down's syndrome? Midwifery, 18(3), 230-237.

Williams, C., Sandall, J., Lewando-Hundt, G., Heyman, B., Spencer, K., & Grellier, R. (2005). Women as moral pioneers? Experiences of first trimester antenatal screening. Social Science & Medicine, 61(9), 1983-1992.

Winch, C. (1998). The philosophy of human learning. London: Routledge. Woodcock, C. (2005). The silenced voice in literacy: Listening beyond words to a

'struggling' adolescent girl. Journal of Authentic Learning, 2(1), 47-60. Woods, R. G., & Barrow, R. (1975). An introduction to philosophy of education.

London: Methuen & Co. Ltd. Yang, Q., Wen, S. W., Leader, A., Chen, X. K., Lipson, J., & Walker, M. (2007).

Paternal age and birth defects: how strong is the association? Human Reproduction [NLM - MEDLINE], 22(3), 696.

Young, M. I. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Zamerowski, S. (1999). The psychosocial impact on high risk pregnant women of a non-invasive prenatal diagnostic test. Fetal Diagnosis and Therapy, 14(2).

Page 355: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

355

Zaner, R. (2005). Sisyphus without knees: Exploring self-other relationships through illness and disability. Literature and Medicine, 22(2), 188-207.

Zecca, G., Gradi, E. C., Nilsson, K., Bellotti, M., & al, e. (2006). "All the rest is normal". A pilot study on the communication between physician and patient in prenatal diagnosis. Journal of Psychosomatic Obstetrics and Gynaecology, 27(3), 127.

Page 356: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

356

APPENDIX I – Topic List

Experience with doctors Communication power /imbalances

Decision making about testing Amniocentesis

Lack of support or understanding MSAFP

Chorionic villus sampling Ultrasound Education

Time given to discussing options Ideas for a better experience

Choice to participate (optional?)

Attitude to disability Blood tests

Fear Voluntary testing Becoming informed

Re-assurance - if so of what? Does routine-ness obscure choice?

Anxiety Barriers of Language and Terminology Declining testing

Specific fears Experience with midwives

Attitude in general to reproductive technologies Ethical concerns

Medicalisation of pregnancy Next step after diagnosis.

Attitude to abortion Learning in a medical environment

Informed choice Trust in medical system/doctor (loyalty)

Trust in science Good or bad experience

Page 357: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

357

APPENDIX II A Participant Information Pack - Mothers Information Sheet Project Title Ethical Practice in Prenatal Screening – Facilitating Women’s’ Choices by Eleanor Milligan What is this research project about? The research project is about how women become informed about prenatal screening tests when they are accessing antenatal care. It will look at how women make decisions about whether or not to participate in screening, in addition to how health care professionals dispense educational material about the tests offered. Who can participate? I would like to interview women who have recently (within the past two years) been offered any sort of prenatal screening, who are no longer pregnant. I would like to hear your story of what tests you were offered, your reasons for accepting or declining these tests and your overall impressions of the experience. What is involved if I decide to participate? You will be invited to participate in an individual discussion, which will be held at a time and place suitable to you. This interview will be recorded and later transcribed for analysis. What type of questions will be asked? During the interview, you will be asked to recount your own experience and explain, in your own words, the reasons for your decisions. You will be able to talk about any experiences which you feel influenced the choices made. While the interview will be guided to cover certain topics, how much information you choose to share is completely up to you. You do not have to answer any direct question and can stop the interview at any time without explanation. You will be provided with a list of topics and words to help initiate conversation. You do not need to discuss any topic that you feel uncomfortable with. Will my details be confidential? Yes. Every effort will be made to maintain your confidentiality. None of your personal details will be made public and transcripts of your interview will be kept at a secure location which is not accessible to the general public. You will not be personally identified in any report as the source of specific comments.

Page 358: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

358

Will it benefit me to participate? There are no direct personal benefits, ie, you will not be paid to participate. You will be given the opportunity to discuss your experiences in a confidential, supportive and non-judgmental forum and will have the chance to express your views, both positive and negative, in a way which may benefit women facing these choices in the future. Are there any risks involved? Because some of the topics discussed revolve around personal choices relating to yourself and your family, you may feel uncomfortable recounting or justifying your personal actions or beliefs. However, you are not obliged to discuss any topic you feel uncomfortable with and can stop the interview at any time without justification. You can also withdraw from the project at any time without consequence. If as a result of this project you feel you need counselling support, this is available through Lifeline – 13 11 14 Parent Help Line – 1300 30 1300 Or with your own GP. What information will I be given about the project? If you desire, you will be given a transcript of your interview and will be provided with regular feedback on the progress of the study. At the end of the study, you will be given a report summarising the findings. I would also encourage you to contact me at any time to ask any question about your involvement in this project. Concerns or Complaints? If you have any concerns or complaints about the ethical conduct of this project, you can contact the Research Ethics Officer on 3864 2340. Alternatively, an e-mail can be sent to [email protected] , or a letter to Research Ethics Officer Office of Research O Block Podium QUT GPO Box 2434 Brisbane. 4001.

Page 359: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

359

I will contact you within one week of sending this information sheet. If you DO wish to be involved, when I call you, we can discuss any further questions you may have and arrange a suitable time and place to conduct the interview. At our interview I will ask you to sign a consent form like the one supplied with this information pack which states that you understand the purpose of this research and are aware of your right to withdraw at any time. If you DO NOT wish to be involved in this project, when I call you, simply tell me you do not wish to continue. Alternatively you can send me an e-mail ( [email protected]) or leave a telephone message. There is no consequence for deciding not to continue. Thank you for taking the time to consider being involved in this project. Kind regards Eleanor Milligan Ph- 0409 550 671 e-mail- [email protected]

Page 360: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

360

Ethical Practice in Prenatal Screening- Facilitating Women’s Choices. Eleanor Milligan [email protected] ph-3864 4577 mob. 0419 027 126. Yes, I would like to participate in the research project. I agree to participate by taking part in a recorded interview with Eleanor Milligan. I understand that this project is part of a Doctoral thesis being conducted by Eleanor in the School of Humanities and Human Services at the Queensland University of Technology, Carseldine. By signing below, I am indicating that I understand

• The nature and purpose of the project as explained by Eleanor and outlined in the information package previously received.

• That my name and contact details are strictly confidential and my privacy and anonymity will be preserved.

• That I may refuse to discuss any issue at any time. • That I may stop the interview at any time without reason. • That I will have access to my interview transcript if desired. • That I can request information on the progress of this project at any

time • That I will be provided with a summary of the research findings at

the conclusion of this project. • That any concerns about the conduct of this research can be directed

to the Research Ethics Officer on 3864 2340 or [email protected]

NAME: ________________________________________________ SIGNATURE: ________________________________________________ DATE: ________________________________________________

Page 361: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

361

APPENDIX II B Participant Information Pack - Practitioners Information Sheet Project Title Ethical Practice in Prenatal Screening – Facilitating Women’s’ Choices By Eleanor Milligan What is this research project about? The research project is about how women become informed about prenatal screening tests when they are accessing antenatal care. It will look at how women make decisions about whether or not to participate in screening, in addition to how health care professionals dispense educational material about the tests offered. Who can participate? I would like to interview health care workers involved in antenatal care. I will ask you to recount, in your own words, your overall impressions and experiences of the current practice. What is involved if I decide to participate? You will be invited to participate in an individual interview, which will be held at a time and place suitable to you. The interview will be recorded and later transcribed for analysis. What type of questions will be asked? During the interview, you will be asked to recount your own experience and explain, in your own words, your impressions and ideas. You will be able to talk about any experiences which you feel influenced the opinions you hold. You will be provided with a list of topics and words to help initiate conversation and are not expected to discuss any topic that you feel uncomfortable with. How much information you choose to share is completely up to you. You do not have to answer any direct question and can stop the interview at any time without explanation. All interview transcripts are completely confidential and your privacy will be preserved.

Page 362: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

362

Will my details be confidential? Yes. Every effort will be made to maintain your confidentiality. None of your personal details will be made public and transcripts of your interview will be kept at a secure location which is not accessible to the general public. You will not be personally identified in any report as the source of specific comments. Will it benefit me to participate? There are no direct personal benefits, i.e., you will not be paid to participate. You will be given the opportunity to discuss your experiences in a confidential, supportive and non-judgmental forum and will have the chance to express your views, both positive and negative, in a way which may benefit both women and health care professionals in dealing with these issues in the future. Are there any risks involved? Because some of the topics discussed are concerned with your personal views, you may feel distressed by recounting or justifying your personal actions or beliefs. However, you are not obliged to discuss any topic you feel uncomfortable with and can stop the interview at any time without justification. You can also withdraw from the project at any time without consequence. If as a result of this project you feel you need counselling support, this is available through Lifeline on 13 11 14, Parent Help Line on 1300 30 1300, or with your own GP. What information will I be given about the project? If you desire, you will be given a transcript of your interview and will be provided with regular feedback on the progress of the study. At the end of the study, you will be given a report summarising the findings. I would also encourage you to contact me at any time to ask any question about your involvement in this project. Concerns or Complaints? If you have any concerns or complaints about the ethical conduct of this project, you can contact the Research Ethics Officer on 3864 2340. Alternatively, an e-mail can be sent to [email protected] , or a letter to Research Ethics Officer Office of Research O Block Podium QUT GPO Box 2434 Brisbane. 4001.

Page 363: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

363

APPENDIX III Ethics Approval UHREC 3911H 18th April 2005 Dear Eleanor, I write further to the response provided in relation to ethical clearance for your project, "Ethical Practice in Prenatal Screening-Facilitating Women’s' choices" (QUT Ref No 3911H). On behalf of the Chair, University Human Research Ethics Committee, I wish to advise that this response has addressed the information required by the Expedited Ethical Review Panel. Consequently, you are authorised to immediately commence your project on this basis. The decision is subject to ratification at the 14 June 2005 meeting of UHREC. I will only contact you again in relation to this matter if the Committee raises any additional questions or concerns in regard to the clearance. The University requires its researchers to comply with:

• the University’s 9Hresearch ethics arrangements and the 10HQUT11H Code of Conduct for Research;

• the standard conditions of ethical clearance; • any additional conditions prescribed by the UHREC; • any relevant State / Territory or Commonwealth legislation; • the policies and guidelines issued by the NHMRC and AVCC (including the

National Statement on Ethical Conduct in Research Involving Humans).

Please do not hesitate to contact me further if you have any queries regarding this matter. Regards Wendy

Wendy Heffernan Research Ethics Officer Office of Research O Block Podium Gardens Point Campus Tel: 07 3864 2340 Fax: 07 3864 1304

Page 364: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

364

APPENDIX IV

Topic List Key Informed consent Constraints on

Choice

Education Transformative Contrapuntal voices

Informed choice

Declining testing

Voluntary testing

Next step after

diagnosis

Ethical concerns

Becoming informed

Does routine-ness

obscure choice?

Time given to

discussing options

Choice to participate

(optional?)

Communication

power /imbalances

Decision making

about testing

Attitude to abortion

Specific fears

Time given to

discussing

options

Medicalisation

of pregnancy

Trust in science

Trust in medical

system/doctor

(loyalty)

Barriers of

Language and

Terminology

Re-assurance -

if so of what?

Communication

power

/imbalances

Attitude to

abortion

Medicalisation

of pregnancy

Attitude to

disability

Next step after

diagnosis

Fear

Anxiety

Risk

Learning in a

medical

environment

Time given to

discussing

options

Educational

opportunities

Communication

power

/imbalances

Barriers of

Language and

Terminology

Attitude to

abortion

Support or

understanding

Becoming

informed – who

educates?

Ideas for a better experience Good or bad

experience

Experience with

doctors/patients

Communication

power

/imbalances

Certainty /Clarity

(Professional and

personal)

Self doubt

Awakened

Capitulation

Reproach

Self interest/control

Resistance

Self preservation

Condescension

Care

Professional

defensiveness

Detachment

Page 365: ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN… · ENHANCING ETHICAL PRACTICE IN PRENATAL SCREENING: FACILITATING WOMEN’S ETHICAL CHOICES by Eleanor Milligan

365


Top Related