Transcript
  • 8/10/2019 Let Us Now See How Kelsen Thought That the Basic Norm

    1/2

    Let us now see how Kelsen thought that the basic norm helps to explain the sense in which law is a

    normative domain and what this normativity consists in. The first and crucial point to realize is that

    for Kelsen the idea of normativity is tantamount to a genuine ought, as it were; it is a justified

    demand on practical deliberation. A certain content is regarded as normative by an agent if and only

    if the agent regards that content as a valid reason for action. As Joseph Raz noticed, Kelsen agrees

    with the Natural Law tradition in this particular respect; both assume that the normativity of law can

    only be explained as one would explain the normativity of morality, or religion for that matter,

    namely, in terms of valid reasons for action (Raz 1979, 134137). But then, the problem for Kelsen is

    how to explain the difference between the normativity of law and that of morality; if legal ought is

    a genuine ought, what makes a legal obligation distinct from a moral one? Kelsen's answer is that

    the relevant ought is always relative to a given point of view. Each and every type of ought, be it

    religious, moral or legal, must presuppose a certain point of view, a point of view which is

    constituted by the basic norm of the relevant normative system.

    In other words, Kelsen's conception of legal normativity turns out to be a form of Natural Law

    completely relativized to a certain point of view. However, in Kelsen's theory the relevant point of

    view is distinctly a legal one, not some general conception of morality or Reason. That these two

    basic norms, or points of view, can come apart, is nicely demonstrated by Kelsen's comment that

    even an anarchist, if he were a professor of law, could describe positive law as a sys tem of valid

    norms, without having to approve of this law (PT2 218n). The anarchist does not endorse the legal

    point of view as one that reflects her own views about what is right and wrong. Anarchism is

    understood here precisely as a rejection of the normative validity of law; however, even the

    anarchist

    can make an argument about what the law in this or that context requires; and when she makes

    such an argument, she must presuppose the legal point of view, she must argue as if she endorses

    the basic norm of the relevant legal system. Joseph Raz has called these kinds of statements

    detached normative statements; the anarchist argues as if she endorses the basic norm, without

    actually endorsing it. Another example that Raz gave is this: suppose that at Catholic priest is an

    expert in Jewish Law; the priest can make various interpretative arguments about what Jewish law

    really requires in this or that context. In such a case, the priest must argue as if he endorses the basic

    norm of Jewish Law, but of course, being a Catholic, he does not really endorse it, it does not reflect

    his own views about what is right and wrong (Raz 1979, 153157).

    So here is what emerges so far: the concept of normativity, the sense in which normative content is

    related to reasons for action, is the same across all normative domains. To regard something as

    normative is to regard it as justified, as a warranted requirement on practical deliberation. However,

    the difference resides in the difference in points of view. Each basic norm determines, as it were, a

    certain point of view. So it turns out that normativity (contra Kant) always consists of conditional

    imperatives: if, and only if, one endorses a certain normative point of view, determined by its basic

    norm, then the norms that follow from it are reason giving, so to speak. This enables Kelsen to

    maintain the same understanding of the nature of normativity as Natural Law's conception, namely,

    normativity qua reasons for action, without having to conflate the normativity of morality with that

    of law. In other words, the difference between legal normativity and, say, moral normativity, is not a

    difference in normativity (viz, about the nature of normativity, per se), but only in the relevant

  • 8/10/2019 Let Us Now See How Kelsen Thought That the Basic Norm

    2/2

    vantage point that is determined by their different basic norms. What makes legal normativity

    unique is the uniqueness of its point of view, the legal point of view, as it were.

    We can set aside the difficulties that such a view raises with respect to morality. Obviously, many

    philosophers would reject Kelsen's view that moral reasons for action only apply to those who

    choose to endorse morality's basic norm (whatever it may be). Even if Kelsen is quite wrong about

    this conditional nature of moral imperatives, he may be right about the law. What remains

    questionable, however, is whether Kelsen succeeds in providing a non-reductive explanation of legal

    normativity, given the fact that his account of legal validity turned out to be reductive after all. The

    trouble here is not simply the relativity to a point of view; the trouble resides in Kelsen's failure to

    ground the choice of the relevant point of view in anything like Reason or reasons of any kind. By

    deliberately avoiding any explanation of what it is that might ground an agent's choice of endorsing

    the legal point of view, or any given basic norm, Kelsen left the most pressing questions about the

    normativity of law unanswered. Instead of providing an explanation of what makes the

    presupposition of the legal point of view rational, or what makes it rational to regard the

    requirements of law as binding requirements, Kelsen invites us to stop asking.


Top Related