dworkin and hart on law

11
22 DWORKIN AND HART ON “THE LAW”: A POLANYIAN RECONSIDERATION Ira H. Peak, Jr. INTRODUCTION It is the purpose of this paper to propose and defend a potential resolution of a long-standing conundrum in the philosophy of law. The conundrum is posed by the conceptual impasse emerging from the debate between H.L.A. Hart and Ronald Dworkin over the nature of “the law.” The paper is developed in three sections. The first contextualizes the debate between these giants in the field of jurisprudence. The second section develops in some detail the positions of each thinker on this central issue in legal philosophy ? the “rules” approach of Hart and the “principles” approach of Dworkin. This section also sharpens these differences in terms of the broader issues which their debate poses for the larger field of philosophy of law. A third section proposes a Polanyian model for reconsidering this apparent impasse. The model develops an approach to decision-making in terms of “universal intent.” The paper’s conclusion seeks to establish that this model can be applied to the philosophy of law and effectively forge a compromise between the competing views of Hart and Dworkin. I. Perhaps the simplest way to contextualize the Hart-Dworkin debate is to sketch (all too) briefly the poles between which each sought to position himself, i.e. natural law theory (exemplified preeminently by St. Thomas) and “legal positivism” (articulated classically by the 19th century British jurist John Austin). In Summa Theologica, St. Thomas organizes his discussions of “the nature of law” around his notion of “natural law.” Law, in this view, is universal because it springs from reason possessed by all people. It is this natural law that shapes the positive law of which we ordinarily speak in referring to “the law.” Positive law stands in contrast both to natural law and to divine law, and the relations among the three in the ordering of human life are explained by St. Thomas. In this connection the question of special importance is whether (and in what way) human law is derived from natural law. Positive law, for St. Thomas, is determined by the natural law for the common good. It is binding upon the conscience, because it is just. The “angelic doctor’s” concept of law, then, is of an ideal to be found in laws. It is absent when unjust exercise of power produces laws in name only. For the most part these need not be obeyed. St. Thomas’s views on law and morality actually anticipate more modern views regarding conscientious objection to unjust laws. For, on his understanding, only moral wrongs that are socially significant, such as harm to others, properly concern the law.

Upload: ria

Post on 13-Oct-2014

46 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Dworkin and Hart on Law

22

DWORKIN AND HART ON “THE LAW”:A POLANYIAN RECONSIDERATION

Ira H. Peak, Jr.

INTRODUCTION

It is the purpose of this paper to propose and defend a potential resolution of a long-standing conundrumin the philosophy of law. The conundrum is posed by the conceptual impasse emerging from the debate between H.L.A.Hart and Ronald Dworkin over the nature of “the law.” The paper is developed in three sections. The first contextualizesthe debate between these giants in the field of jurisprudence. The second section develops in some detail the positionsof each thinker on this central issue in legal philosophy ? the “rules” approach of Hart and the “principles” approachof Dworkin. This section also sharpens these differences in terms of the broader issues which their debate poses forthe larger field of philosophy of law. A third section proposes a Polanyian model for reconsidering this apparent impasse.The model develops an approach to decision-making in terms of “universal intent.” The paper’s conclusion seeks toestablish that this model can be applied to the philosophy of law and effectively forge a compromise between thecompeting views of Hart and Dworkin.

I.

Perhaps the simplest way to contextualize the Hart-Dworkin debate is to sketch (all too) briefly the polesbetween which each sought to position himself, i.e. natural law theory (exemplified preeminently by St. Thomas) and“legal positivism” (articulated classically by the 19th century British jurist John Austin).

In Summa Theologica, St. Thomas organizes his discussions of “the nature of law” around his notion of“natural law.” Law, in this view, is universal because it springs from reason possessed by all people. It is this naturallaw that shapes the positive law of which we ordinarily speak in referring to “the law.” Positive law stands in contrastboth to natural law and to divine law, and the relations among the three in the ordering of human life are explained bySt. Thomas. In this connection the question of special importance is whether (and in what way) human law is derivedfrom natural law.

Positive law, for St. Thomas, is determined by the natural law for the common good. It is binding upon theconscience, because it is just. The “angelic doctor’s” concept of law, then, is of an ideal to be found in laws. It is absentwhen unjust exercise of power produces laws in name only. For the most part these need not be obeyed. St. Thomas’sviews on law and morality actually anticipate more modern views regarding conscientious objection to unjust laws.For, on his understanding, only moral wrongs that are socially significant, such as harm to others, properly concernthe law.

Page 2: Dworkin and Hart on Law

23

John Austin’s work in jurisprudence has long been regarded in the Anglo-American tradition as the leadingwork in opposition to natural law theory. Austin seeks to define positive law, and this he does by distinguishing “lawsproperly so called” from other law-like utterances and other things called laws.

Laws properly so called turn out to be “commands” requiring conduct; and some, called positive laws, issuefrom a sovereign to members of an independent political society over which sovereignty is exercised. Commands entaila purpose and a power to impose sanctions on those who disobey; a sovereign is a determinate human superior (thatis, one who can successfully compel others to obey) who is not in a habit of obedience to such a superior and whoalso receives habitual obedience. An independent political society, then, is one in which the bulk of society habituallyobeys a sovereign.

Accordingly, Austin’s “legal positivism” sees the issue of “the law” reducing to the issue of who sets therule (i.e. “command”) and how the command is enforced (i.e. by force or threat of force). Oversimplified, and crudelyso, Austin sees the operative principle in determination of “the law” as something like, (successfully and effectivelyexercised)”might makes (properly “legal”) right.”

Hence, whereas for St. Thomas positive law could be said to be grounded, in some sense, axiologically, forAustin law’s only “grounding” is the effective exercise of power to enforce commands. Stated alternatively, while St.Thomas defines the law in terms de jure, Austin does so in terms de facto.

II.

As one might suppose, much of the literature in this domain of the philosophy of law has been given overto attempts to define mediating positions between these “extremes.” Two such mediating views are articulated by Hartand Dworkin.

The work now generally regarded as the most important twentieth century statement of the positivist positionin the Anglo-American tradition is H.L.A. Hart’s book, The Concept of Law (Hart, 1961). In it, Hart does not seek todefend a narrow, partisan tradition, but rather departs from Austin’s version of positivism by undertaking a broadreexamination of the fundamental questions of jurisprudence, clarifying them and securing their importance.

Hart’s analysis of the concept of law is based on several interrelated ideas (See especially Hart, 1961, “LawAs the Union of Primary and Secondary Rules,” pp. 77ff). He maintains that a legal system—in contrast to a set ofunrelated laws—consists of a union of primary rules of obligation and secondary rules. The most important secondaryrule, which Hart calls “the rule of recognition,” specifies the criteria for identifying a law within the system (e.g. the UnitedStates Constitution). Other secondary rules specify how primary rules are changed or modified and when primary ruleshave been violated.

Furthermore, in distinguishing primary rules of obligation from secondary rules, Hart takes the position thatthere is at least one type of law that imposes an obligation (Hart, 1961, p. 80ff). This type tells citizens that they mustnot do this or must do that. Raising the crucial question of what an obligation with respect to legal rules means, Hartrejects the idea that to say that law imposes an obligation is merely to assert a prediction (about likely behavior of

Page 3: Dworkin and Hart on Law

24

citizens). Nor does he accept the view that laws imposing an obligation are simply coercive orders.

Hart (1961, p. 84ff) attempts to provide a general analysis of obligation in terms of social pressure. He seesthis analysis as clearly distinguishing his view from those of Austin and other positivists.

Finally, in order to understand secondary and primary rules and the obligation the law imposes, Hart (1961,pp. 86-87) insists that the point of view of people who follow and apply the law must be considered. In particular, heemphasizes the importance of an internal point of view of the law ? that is, the point of view of those who operate withinthe law rather than of external observers of the law. So, according to Hart (1961, p. 88ff), a legal theorist who wishesto understand a legal system must view the legal system from the point of view of an actor in the system. InWittgenstein’s categories, perhaps, we might say that Hart views the legal system as a “form of life,” rather than merelyas a formal system.

How then, one might inquire, do Hart’s notions of “law” and “legal system” impact the crucial issue of judicialinterpretation? Clearly, he has moved away from a strict legal formalism, the view that legal interpretation is alwayssimply the straightforward application of a legal rule to a case. Hart does believe that there are instances where thisformalist approach is appropriate, but he denies that it always is. Sometimes the judge must exercise discretion, anda mechanical application of rule to case is impossible.

Note the difficulty which this issue poses for a legal positivist who is equally displeased with a natural lawform of “legal foundations” and the extreme position of rule skepticism (the notion that judges always have widediscretion and that the application of rules to cases plays no significant role in judicial decision). I will return to thisissue a bit later. For the present, I will merely note that across the years Hart’s position on this issue has undergonechange. To be fair, therefore, I will attempt to characterize his position on judicial interpretation in terms of his maturethought on this problem, some of which has evolved in his ongoing debate with Ronald M. Dworkin.

Dworkin, the most famous critic of Hart’s theory of judicial interpretation, was Hart’s successor to the Chairof Jurisprudence at Oxford University. Against Hart, Dworkin maintains that even in unclear cases there is always onecorrect decision, although what this decision might be is unknown. In addition, Dworkin argues that a judge’s decisionin unclear cases is characteristically determined, and should be, entirely by principles specifying rights andentitlements. But I am here getting ahead of myself. I must first summarize in more specific terms exactly how Dworkin’sposition differs from Hart’s.

Professor Ronald Dworkin has presented a fascinating critical tool in philosophy of law for critiquing legalpositivism, i.e., his notion of “legal principles” (Dworkin, 1986 a, p. 153ff). He describes principles as “a standard thatis to be observed, not because it will advance or secure an economic, political, or social situation deemed desirable,but because it is a requirement of justice or fairness or some other dimension of morality” (153). He argues that thedifference between “principles” and “rules” is (1) “logical” (154); (2) related to the fact that principles (not rules) differin their “weightiness” (156); but (3) not always recognizable from their form (156).

Although “principles” are sometimes well-established (for example, by judicial precedent), at times they donot become established until there is adjudication of “hard cases” (157). Yet these principles become (indeed are usedfor) the justification of decisions in cases, which (in turn) become rules of law (157).

Page 4: Dworkin and Hart on Law

25

Although Dworkin defends his concept of “legal principles” with explicit intent and systematic vigor in “TheModel of Rules,” the nature and subtlety of his position emerges more clearly from his more popular article “On NotProsecuting Civil Disobedience” (Dworkin, 1968). For our purposes here, however, the foregoing summary of Dworkin’sposition will suffice.

It would appear that the net effect of Dworkin’s firm opposition to legal positivism is a kind of conundrumfor philosophy of law. On the one hand, Dworkin is able to demonstrate that the “rules” (or “pedigree”) approach ofH.L.A. Hart to “certifying” valid positive law does not account for the presence of (and appeal to) “principles” (notreducible to “rules”) within jurisprudence. Indeed, it does appear that “principles” in fact play a role in some judges`arriving at decisions, interpreting their reasoning, and justifying their claims.

On the other hand, Dworkin is unable to identify all such principles (since some remain unnoticed/undiscovered until a judge is forced to rule on a “hard case”). Moreover, he cannot specify their status, although hebelieves quite clearly that they are “legally binding” upon judges in making rulings or handing down decisions.

Hence, the conundrum. It would appear that there is a functioning critical apparatus at work within our legalsystem (and, perhaps, beyond), the legal status of which cannot be established.

In “On Not Prosecuting Civil Disobedience,” Dworkin does at least begin to lay bare why this anomaly exists.He argues that there is what he calls “doubtful law” (Dworkin, 1968, p. 15ff), law the validity of which is in dispute (oris otherwise suspect). “In the U.S., at least, almost any law which a significant number of people would be tempted todisobey on moral grounds would be doubtful ? if not clearly invalid ? on constitutional grounds as well. The constitutionmakes our conventional political morality relevant to the question of validity: any statue that appears to compromisethat morality raises constitutional questions, and if the compromise is serious, the constitutional doubts are seriousalso” (1968, p. 16). Moreover, Dworkin believes that in draft resistance cases of the late 1960’s, the connection betweenmoral and legal issues were made especially (even starkly) clear.

Draft dissenters, in Dworkin’s view, were not asserting a privilege to disobey valid laws. They believed firmlythat the laws being broken were unconstitutional. Under these conditions, it is not always clear how such dissentersin a complex society are to “play the game” (1968, p. 17). This metaphor is ironic. It is the legal positivists who haverelied heavily on images and metaphors like “playing a game” to emphasize the law’s rule-like character and process.Yet, Dworkin has presented a challenge, asking now what (or whose?) move is next. (For a detailed examination of theseissues in a format comparing Hart and Dworkin, see Soper, 1984.)

How then does Hart’s position respond to Dworkin’s challenge? We must recall that Hart sees law as aninstitution within a larger social system. It is a form of rule-making, rule-applying, and rule-enforcing behavior. Theserules do indeed have connection to morality, both in origin (on occasion) and in interpretation, as well as in applicationand enforcement. This overlapping of differing kinds of rules ? in this case moral ones and legal ones ? does not implythe dependence of one upon the other in any “ultimate” sense, any more than other social rules (e.g. “rules of etiquette”)might be (Hart, 1986, p. 82). What alternative, then, does Hart offer for explaining the “foundations” of law? Hartintroduced the notion of “rules of recognition” (Hart, 1961, p. 94).

The “rule of recognition” is a secondary rule used to identify primary rules of obligation (1961, p. 94ff). Thisrule of recognition is more complex in modern legal systems where there are a variety of “sources” of law (1961, p. 97ff).The relationship of one set of rules to the other is one of “relative subordination,” not derivation.

Page 5: Dworkin and Hart on Law

26

In his more mature thought, Hart has broadened his concept of “rules” applied by judges in their decisions to embrace“legal standards” (Soper, 1984, pp. 7-9). Although Hart now believes that these legal standards constrain a judge’sdecision in unclear cases, he maintains that there may be alternative decisions in such cases that are equally justifiedin terms of these standards. In Dworkin’s view, Hart’s position remains truncated and unsatisfying.

Hence, the conundrum cited above remains. It can be summarized as follows. If Hart’s positivist account ofthe nature of “the law” ? a system of primary and secondary rules, validated by a (secondary) “rule of recognition”and supplemented by emerging “legal standards” in the process of judicial interpretation ? is accepted, his approachseems unable to account for the role played by principles in many judicial decisions, especially “hard cases.” If, bycontrast, Dworkin’s claims ? that some principles appealed to in judicial decisions and opinions are in fact “legalprinciples” and “obligatory” for judges to follow ? are accepted, then it would seem that he should be able to identifythese principles or to state how they are themselves justified or validated. But, alas, he cannot. How then is “the law”to be related to “principles”?

It would appear that the impasse reached by Hart and Dworkin remains. Yet, there may be another alternative.The key to identifying that alternative may be lurking in Dworkin’s characterization of judicial decisions in “hard cases.”Dworkin admits that judges sometimes face cases where the “right” principle of law (to which appeal should be madein determining the case) is not known. Not only is it not known by the particular judge presiding; but it is not knownby anyone else as well! In fact, says Dworkin, it is only when such hard cases are adjudicated that a judge’s attentioncan be directed to that principle (which is the right principle). In other words, it is only in the judicial process itself thatsome such principles emerge. They are actual, but previously unrecognized, principles of law. The principle for decidingthe case rightly, it would seem ? given this characterization, is present only tacitly, not explicitly.

Yet, this hypothesizing takes us outside the parameters of either Hart’s position or Dworkin’s. To developa model, then, for moving beyond their conundrum, I propose that we consider a model for decision-making developedfrom the thought of Michael Polanyi.

III.

The model to be developed here out of Polanyi’s thought was anticipated in, and suggested to me by, aparagraph from Richard Gelwick (Gelwick, 1977, pp. 127-128). Following Carl Friedrich’s analysis (Langford and Poteat,1968, pp. 91-110), Gelwick suggests a new possibility for discussing natural law. “Even though Polanyi does not discussnatural law, his grounding of cultural values in a society of universal intent suggests a `natural law theory in humannature’” (Gelwick, 1977, p. 127). “His (Polanyi’s) thought, therefore, bears a fortiori upon the enterprise and itsinterpretation of attempting to embody justice in law . . .” (Friedrich, from Langford and Poteat, 1968, p. 92).

In the analysis which follows, I will develop a model of decision-making which parallels, in some respects theposition articulated by Friedrich; but it is not dependent upon his notion of “natural law.” Hence, while beingappreciative of Friedrich’s illuminating insights, I have developed a model which is independent of his and more closelytied to the phenomenology of moral experience than to the venerable history of natural law theory. (I have developedthe connections between a Polanyian model for decision making and the phenomenological analysis of moral experiencemore explicitly in an unpublished paper, “Can a Moral Judgment be Both Contextual and Objective?”)

Page 6: Dworkin and Hart on Law

27

Taking the conundrum bequeathed to the philosophy of law by Hart and Dworkin as our point of departure,I ask that you recall the plight of the judge hypothesized above, who must decide a “hard case” in which the strictapplication of rules will not suffice. Moreover, he or she may not have access even to a specific principle of law, becausethe “right” principle has not yet been articulated (or otherwise discovered) in the history of judicial interpretation. Yet,in order to become the basis for the adjudication of the case at hand, the judge must appeal to a legal principle, onederived from, and inherent in, the body of existing law (both legislated and interpreted).

Since what is called for, then is a kind of “discovery,” on the part of our hypothetical judge, I would directyour attention back to Polanyi’s discussion of that issue in Science, Faith and Society. You will recall that “discovery”is described by Polanyi there as a process ? which he summarizes in the four words “Preparation, Incubation,Illumination, and Verification” ? a process not unlike consistent efforts at “guessing and experimenting,” in creatinga work of art, .” . . solving riddles, inventing practical devices, . . . diagnosing of an illness,” and perhaps, prayerfully“searching for God” (Polanyi, 1964 b, p. 34). Rather than attempting merely to “achieve results,” the scientist isattempting to make contact with reality. Therefore, the guiding and constraining force by which he/she seeks and sortsevidence must be his/her own conscience-- since there are not set rules for procedure to which he/she can appeal forvalidation of his/her choices and conclusions.

Polanyi devotes the balance of this work (SFS) to showing how the community of scientific discovery andinquiry protects its tradition against mere subjectivism and blatant error and to describing the necessary freedom underwhich science must operate to prohibit the encroachment of either skepticism or totalitarianism. He is concerned to showthat the loyalty of scientists to the discovery of truth for its own sake must not be abdicated to the transient interestsof any lesser authority.

Polanyi notes that the seemingly subjective judgements of scientists are guided by the premises of sciencewhich are twofold. These are (1) “naturalistic assumptions concerning the nature of every day life;” and (2) “moreparticular assumptions underlying the process of scientific discovery and verification” (Polanyi, 1964 b, p. 42). Thesepremises are learned and passed on to succeeding generations of scientists in the manner of artistic tradition andpractice. Hence, there is not a set of cold facts which can be captured in language and memorized by the novice in science.He or she must be guided beyond techniques and principles to a grasping of reality, whereby his/her own judgementcan become operative in both assessment of data and recognition of problems.

In a similar vein, Polanyi demonstrates the way in which mutual discipline in the scientific community protectsagainst the admission of error into premises and tradition. He does so by indicating the kind of self-government inscience which exercises the authority of scientific opinion. He summarizes thus, “It is clear enough then that theself-governing institutions of science are effective in safe-guarding the organized practice of science which embodiesand transmits its premises” (1964b, p. 50). He argues that the functions of these institutions are mainly protective andregulative and based themselves on a “general harmony of views among scientists.” This general harmony is seen asgrowing out of a common tradition in science, as being maintained by the acceptance of mutual bonds of loyalty toscientific ideals, and as depending ultimately on the common exercise of scientific conscience. There can be no appealfor validity in scientific inquiry, other than to scientific opinion itself, without jeopardizing the entire scientific enterprise.The kind of authority operative in the scientific community demands not obedience ? but freedom.

The exercise of decision by which new theories are to be screened and competing theories evaluated must not beusurped.

Page 7: Dworkin and Hart on Law

28

There are divisions among scientists, sometimes sharp and passion-ate, but both contestants remain agreed that scientific opinion willultimately decide right; and they are satisfied to appeal to it astheir ultimate arbiter . . . A common belief in the reality ofscientific ideals and a sufficient confidence in their fellowscientists‘ sincerity resolves among scientists the apparentinternal contradiction in the conception of freedom. It establishesgovernment by scientific opinion, as a General Authority, inherentlyrestricted to the guardianship of the premises of freedom (1964 b,p. 63).

Hence, Polanyi can affirm that the goal of scientific inquiry must never be exclusively utilitarian. Rather, itsgoal must be the discovery of the truth to which it is committed. This can be done only within the context of a societywhich guarantees the freedom and encourages the dedication of its members to the pursuit of transcendent obligations,“particularly to truth, justice and charity” (1964 b, p. 85).

Nevertheless, Polanyi’s belief that knowledge is grounded in personal and tacit commitments does not meanthat he thinks that “knowledge” is simply subjective. It is true that there is no such thing as perfect objectivity inknowledge. No perfect detachment, nothing perfectly explicit is possible ? even in the ideal case of knowledge.

The knower, however, is not thereby condemned to whimsical subjectivity, by the fact that his/her intent inknowledge is universal (Polanyi, 1967, pp. 77-78). The intent is inescapably universal, Polanyi thinks, because the questfor knowledge is a quest for an impersonal reality (Polanyi, 1964 a, p. 300ff) to suppose that one has found it is to supposethat others “similarly equipped,” would also be able to find it (1964 a, p. 324). The knower, therefore, does make useof the rules and standards that he/she supposes to be universal, in the sense of being the “proper” ones for anyoneto use (1964 a, p. 343). On Polanyi’s view the scientific community functions as a kind of moral association of personsby exercising mutual authority. It welds tradition and freedom together in a pursuit of the truth. It upholds the personal,tacit component but also the universal intent of knowing. This touches the central nerve of Polanyi’s epistemology.He is purposing nothing less than the attempt to overcome the split between the subjective and the objective, an attemptwhich is based on the distinction between

. . . the personal in us, which actively enters into our commitments, and our subjective states, in whichwe merely endure our feelings. This distinction establishes the conception of the personal, whichis neither subjective nor objective. In so far as the personal submits to requirements acknowledgedby itself as independent of itself, it is not subjective; but insofar as it is an action guided by individualpassions it is not objective either. It transcends the disjunction between subjective and objective(1964 a, p. 300).

The mutual correlation between the personal and the universal within the framework of commitment, then, isthe “solution” to the paradox of standards which are determined by personal commitment and belief. The answer tothe objection to Polanyi’s view that it implies that “you can believe whatever you like” is, quite simply, that you cannot,if you wish to be responsible within a community of universal intent.

Page 8: Dworkin and Hart on Law

29

While compulsion by force or by neurotic obsession excludes responsibility, compulsion byuniversal intent establishes responsibility . . . While the choices in question are open to egocentricdecisions, a craving for the universal sustains a constructive effort and narrows down this discretionto the point where the agent making the decision finds that he cannot do otherwise. The freedomof the subjective person to do as he pleases is overruled by the freedom of the responsible personto act as he must (1964 a, p. 309).

It is in this limited sense, then, of what Polanyi has called “personal knowledge” that any scientific judgementcan lay claim to being “objective.”

How, then, does this account of “discovery” and exercise of judgement underwrite a model of decision-makingwhich could be employed by a judge deciding a “hard case”?

Both Polanyi’s scientist and the judge presuppose that the respective principles with which each is concernedare ultimately rooted in beliefs and commitments (ones foundational to scientific inquiry and the practice ofjurisprudence, respectively). Yet, in the nature of the case (for each enterprise) these beliefs and commitments arenondemonstrable.

Moreover, each of these projects, in its own way, asserts that its judgements represent attempts to makecontact with reality, based on informed perceptions of patterns or “shapes” in the real which manifest themselves toinquiry— whether the inquiry be into the observable behavior of phenomena or into “the facts of the case.” Each kindof judgement is informed by norms or principles embraced by a community of people who share mutual commitments(to the premises of science/to the rule of law) and universal intent (in the pursuit of truth/in the pursuit of justice). Eachone’s judgements claim to be public and authoritative, even if they are original or novel; because they are made withuniversal intent and with the expectation of being ultimately vindicated within the community.

Lest one be inclined to decry this attempt to develop a model for decision-making out of Polanyi’s philosophyof science and epistemology, one which can apply to a judge’s interpretation of “the law,” I would remind you ofPolanyi’s discussion of “systems of spontaneous order” and “systems of intellectual order” in the tenth chapter ofThe Logic of Liberty (Polanyi, 1951, p. 154ff).

The section of this chapter entitled “Systems of Intellectual Order” takes as its first example .” . . the Law, andin particular Common Law” (1951, p. 162).

Consider a judge sitting in court and deciding a difficult case. While pondering his decision, he refersconsciously to dozens of precedents and unconsciously to many more. Before him numberless otherjudges have sat and decided according to statute, precedent, equity and convenience, as he himselfhas to do now; his mind, while he analyses (sic) the various aspects of the case, is in constant contactwith theirs. And beyond the purely legal references, he senses the entire contemporary trend ofopinions, the social medium as a whole. Not until he has established all these bearings of his caseand reasoned to them in the light of his own professional conscience, will his decision acquire forceof conviction and will he be ready to declare it (1951, p. 162).

Page 9: Dworkin and Hart on Law

30

The operation of Common Law constitutes a “sequence of adjustments” ? both between succeeding judgesand (as well) between the judges and the general public. “The result is the ordered growth of the Common Law, steadilyreapplying and reinterpreting the same fundamental rules and expanding them thus to a system of increasing scopeand consistency” (1951, p. 162).

In this process of discovery of legal principles “embedded” in the matrix of legal precedent, relevant law, factsbrought to light by testimony in court, etc., Friedrich rightly affirms that in law, as in science, .” . . tacit knowing playsa decisive role. Polanyi’s insistence that ̀ there are vast domains of knowledge that exemplify in various ways that weare generally unable to tell what particulars we are aware of when attending to a coherent entity which they constitute`,while written with scientific experiment in the foreground of attention, applied equally well to the law” (Langford andPoteat, 1968, pp. 103-104).

IV.

The forgoing analysis, utilizing the categories of Polanyi’s thought, indicates that there is, indeed, .” . . afunctioning critical apparatus at work within our legal system,” the legal status of which we can now establish. (In sodoing, we will demonstrate that the Hart-Dworkin conundrum is subject to resolution.)

The values of a society have a “fiduciary grounding” in the personal backing given to them .” . . by men who,moved as they are by moral and intellectual passions, perceive and uphold these values with universal intent withina convivial order” (Langford and Poteat, 1968, p. 91). Quite clearly, however, the embodiment of justice in laws and injudicial decisions is both necessarily incomplete and yet also achieved in part by more or less skillful judicial assessment.

These skillful feats, supported by moral and intellectual passions with universal intent, are accreditedby and subject to the superintendency of the convivial order within which they are achieved andwhose very basis is in turn precisely these same passions (Langford and Poteat, 1968, p. 92).

Hence, both Hart and Dworkin are right, but incomplete, in their interpretations of “the law.” Hart is correctthat law is legitimated by appeal to secondary rules and a “rule of recognition.” Yet, as Dworkin rightly argued, somedecisions regarding the nature of “the law” can only be settled by appeal to principles (not reducible to rules) withinjurisprudence. It certainly appears that “principles” in fact play a role in some judges` arriving at decisions, interpretingtheir reasoning, and justifying their claims.

At the same time, we now can account for why Dworkin was unable to identify all such principles, as well aswhy some legal principles remain unnoticed or undiscovered until a judge is forced to rule on a “hard case.”

Important legal principles implicit within the legal framework of legislation, judicial interpretation, etc., arepresent only tacitly. The principles are present and operative within the jurisprudential community, a community ofuniversal intent. In certain “hard cases,” one or more members of the community are forced (by the incompletenessof explicit case law) to render a decision which requires the application of the tacitly held principle. Under theseconditions, that which is “tacit” becomes the object of focal awareness. Accordingly, the “right legal principle,” thusdiscovered, was present all along.

Page 10: Dworkin and Hart on Law

31

SOURCES CONSULTED

Dworkin, Ronald M. (ed.) (1986a), “The Model of Rules,” from Feinberg, Joel and Gross, Hyman, Philosophyof Law (Third Edition). Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, pp. 149-166.

_____(1986b), “Is There Really No Right Answer In Hard Cases?” from Feinberg, Joel and Gross, Hyman,Philosophy of Law (Third Edition). Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, pp. 174-191.

_____(1977), The Philosophy of Law. London and Oxford: Oxford University Press._____(1968), “On Not Prosecuting Civil Disobedience,” New York Review of Books, 10 (June 6, 1968), pp.

14-21._____(1966), “Lord Devlin and the Enforcement of Morals,” Yale Law Review, 75, pp. 986-1005.Gelwick, Richard (1977), The Way of Discovery: An Introduction to the Thought of Michael Polanyi. New

York: Oxford University Press.Gill, Jerry H. (1978), “Reasons of the Hearts: A Polanyian Reflection.” Religious Studies 14 (June), pp. 143-157._____(1975), “Tacit Knowing and Religious Belief.” International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion

6 (Summer), pp. 73-88._____(1971), “The Case for Tacit Knowledge.” Southern Journal of Philosophy 9 (Spring), pp. 49-60.Grene, Marjorie (1972), “Polanyi et la Philosophie Francaise.” Archives de Philosophie 35 (January), pp. 3-5.Grant, Patrick (1974), “Michael Polanyi: The Augustinian Component.” New Scholasticism 48 (Autumn), pp.

438-63.Hart, H.L.A. (1986), “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” from Feinberg, Joel and Gross, Hyman,

Philosophy of Law (Third Edition). Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, pp. 69-87._____(1983), Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy. Oxford: The Clarendon Press._____(1967), “Social Solidarity and the Enforcement of Morality,” University of Chicago Law Review, 35,

pp. 1-13._____(1961), The Concept of Law. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.Jensen, A.D. (1975), “Polanyi’s Personal Language.” Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 6 (Fall), pp. 95-107.Kroger, Joseph (1977), “Polanyi and Lonergan on Scientific Method.” Philosophy Today 21 (Spring), pp. 2-20.Langford, Thomas A., and Poteat, William H. (1968), Intellect and Hope. Durham, North Carolina: Duke

University Press.Mackie, John (1984), “The Third Theory of Law,” from Cohen, Marshal (ed.), Ronald Dworkin and

Contemporary Jurisprudence. Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman and Allenheld, pp. 161-170.Martin, Michael (1987), The Legal Philosophy of H.L.A. Hart. Philadelphia: Temple University PressPolanyi, Michael (1975), Meaning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press._____(1974), “On the Introduction of Science into Moral Subjects,” from Schwartz, Fred (ed.), Scientific

Thought and Social Reality. New York: International Universities Press, Inc._____(1969), Knowing and Being. Edited by Marjorie Grene. London: Routledge G.K. Paul._____(1967), The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Company._____(1964a), Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. New York: Harper and Row,

Publishers._____(1964b), Science, Faith and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original edition published

in 1946.)_____(1960), Beyond Nihilism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Page 11: Dworkin and Hart on Law

32

_____(1959), The Study of Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press._____(1951), The Logic of Liberty: Reflections and Rejoinders. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Soper, E. Philip (1984), “Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin Dispute,” from Cohen,

Marshall (ed.), Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence. Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman and Allenheld, pp.3-27.