econ 522 economics of law dan quint fall 2010 lecture 15

55
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 15

Upload: darrell-nash

Post on 05-Jan-2016

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Econ 522Economics of Law

Dan Quint

Fall 2010

Lecture 15

2

HW3 due Friday (5 p.m.)

Second midterm next Wednesday (November 10) Covers property and contract law – no torts

Logistics

3

Let’s recap ourstory so far…

4

Efficiency Maximizing total surplus realized by everyone in society Scarce resources are owned by whoever values them most Actions are taken if social benefit exceeds social cost

Design a legal system that leads to efficient outcomes Once we set up the rules, we don’t expect people to act based on

what’s efficient We expect people to do whatever’s in their own best interest So the goal is set up the rules such that people acting in their

own best interest will naturally lead to efficiency

Our story so far

5

Coase gives us one way to do that If property rights are clearly defined and tradable, and there are

no transaction costs, people have incentive to trade until each resource is efficiently owned

So initial allocation of rights doesn’t matter for efficiency But if there are transaction costs, we may not get efficiency this way

Led us to two normative views of the legal system: 1. Minimize transaction costs (“lubricate” private exchange) 2. Allocate rights as efficiently as possible

Tradeoff between injunctive relief and damages

Our story so far

6

Property law works well for simultaneous trade

Contracts allow for non-simultaneous trade

Contract law can… Enable cooperation Encourage efficient disclosure of information Secure optimal commitment to performance Secure efficient reliance Supply efficient default rules and regulations Foster enduring relationships

Our story so far

7

So far, we’ve been talking about voluntary exchange Coase is predicated on exchange being voluntary for both parties Contracts are an extension of voluntary trade

Up next: involuntary trade You’re bicycling to class, I’m texting while driving and I hit you You didn’t want to deal with me, I didn’t want to deal with you…

Our story so far

8

To put it another way…

Property law covers situations where transaction costs are low enough to get agreement ahead of time Exceptions to property law – private necessity, eminent domain – when

this isn’t the case

Contract law covers situations when transaction costs are low enough for us to agree to a contract, high enough that we may not want to renegotiate the contract later

Tort law covers situations where transaction costs are too high to agree to anything in advance

Our story so far

9

Tort law

10

Tort, noun. from French word meaning injury

Contract law: situations where someone harms you by breaking a promise they had made

Tort law: situations where someone harms you without having made any promises

“If someone shoots you, you call a cop. If he runs his car into yours, you call a lawyer.”

Tort law

11

I hit you with my car, do $1,000 worth of damage You’re $1,000 worse off (No damage to me or my car) Should I have to pay you damages?

As always, we’ll be focused on achieving efficiency

–1,000–1,000–1,000Combined payoffs

–50,000–1,0000My payoff

49,0000–1,000Your payoff

I owe $50,000I owe $1,000I owe nothing

12

Something to remember

distributionbut not

efficiency

efficiency

13

Question: how to structure the law to get people to behave in a way that leads to efficient outcomes?

Deliberate harms: make punishment severe (criminal law)

Accidental harms: trickier Goal isn’t “no accidents”; goal is “efficient number of accidents”

Tort law

14

Question: how to structure the law to get people to behave in a way that leads to efficient outcomes?

Deliberate harms: make punishment severe (criminal law)

Accidental harms: trickier Goal isn’t “no accidents”; goal is “efficient number of accidents”

Unlike nuisance law, injunctive relief is not an option

Unlike contract law, no agreement ahead of time

Cooter and Ulen: essence of tort law is “the attempt to make injurers internalize the externalities they cause, in situations where transaction costs are too high to do this through property or contract rights”

Tort law

15

Plaintiff – person who brings a lawsuit

Defendant – person who is being sued

In a nuisance case, the defendant caused a nuisance, plaintiff was bothered by it, might be asking for injunction or damages

In a contract case, defendant breached a contract or violated its terms

In a tort case, defendant caused some harm to plaintiff, plaintiff is asking for damages

Plaintiff is the victim (person who was harmed)

Defendant is the injurer (person who caused the harm)

Cast of characters

16

Harm

Causation

Breach of Duty

“Classic” legal theory of torts

17

For a tort to exist, the plaintiff needs to have been harmed

“Without harm, there is no tort” Gas company sold gas with a defective additive

Dangerous for cars with turbocharged carburetors You have a car with normal carburetors You might be angry; but you weren’t harmed, so you can’t sue

Similarly, no compensation for exposure to risk Manufacturer exposed workers to some chemical Exposure will cause 15% of them to develop cancer later in life Can’t sue now – have to wait, see who gets cancer, then they can sue

Element 1: Harm

18

Element 1: Harm

Money

Health

Perfect compensation restores victim to original level of well-being generally done through money damages

19

Perfect Compensation

• Emotional harm• Pain and suffering• Loss of companionship

• Medical costs• Lost income• Damaged property

Intangible harmsTangible harms

In theory, perfect compensation should cover all losses Historically, courts have been less willing to compensate for intangible or

hard-to-measure losses Over time, U.S. courts have started compensating for more intangible harms Pro: the closer liability is to actual harm done, the better the incentive to avoid

these harms Con: disparity in award sizes, unpredictability

20

Harm

Causation

Breach of Duty

“Classic” legal theory of torts

21

For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff

Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?”

Element 2: Causation

22

For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff

Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?”

Proximate cause Immediate cause – defendant’s action can’t be too distant from the harm Palsgraf v Long Island Railway (NY Ct Appeals, 1928):

Guard pushed a passenger to help him onto train, passenger dropped fireworks he was carrying, they went off, explosion knocked down scales at the other end of the platform, which fell on Mrs. Palsgraf

Guard’s actions were not the proximate cause

Element 2: Causation

23

“A tree fell on a moving trolly, injuring passengers. One of them sued.

He succeeded in demonstrating that in order for the trolly to be where it was when the tree fell on it the driver had to have driven faster than the speed limit at some point during the trip.

Breaking the law is per se negligence, so the driver was legally negligent whether or not his driving was actually unsafe.

If he had not driven over the speed limit, the trolly would not have been under the tree when it fell, so, the plaintiff argued, the driver’s negligence caused the injury.”

Court ruled driver’s negligence “had not caused the accident in the legally relevant sense”

Element 2: Causation

24

Harm

Causation

Breach of Duty

“Classic” legal theory of torts

25

Element 3: Breach of Duty

• Harm• Causation• Breach of duty (fault)

• Harm• Causation

NegligenceStrict Liability

When someone breaches a duty he owes to the defendant, and this leads to the harm, the injurer is at fault, or negligent Injurers owe victims the duty of due care Negligence rule: I’m only liable if I failed to take the required

standard of care – not if I was careful and the accident happened anyway

(Sometimes required, sometimes not)

26

“A tree fell on a moving trolly, injuring passengers. One of them sued.

He succeeded in demonstrating that in order for the trolly to be where it was when the tree fell on it the driver had to have driven faster than the speed limit at some point during the trip.

Breaking the law is per se negligence, so the driver was legally negligent whether or not his driving was actually unsafe.

If he had not driven over the speed limit, the trolly would not have been under the tree when it fell, so, the plaintiff argued,the driver’s negligence caused the injury.”

Hence the language in the trolly example

27

If I breach my duty of due care and injure you, I am liable

If I exercise the appropriate level of care but still injure you, I’m not liable

How is the standard of care determined? That is, how careful do I have to be to avoid liability, and who

decides? Is it negligent to drive 40 MPH on a particular road at a particular

time of day? What about 41 MPH? 42?

So under a negligence rule…

28

Some settings: government imposes safety regulations that set standard for negligence Speed limits for highway driving Requirement that bicycles have brakes Workplace regulations

Some standards are left vague “Reckless driving” may depend on road, time of day, weather… Common law focuses on duty of reasonable care Level of care a reasonable person would have taken (Civil law relies less on “reasonableness” tests, tries to spell out what

level of care is required)

How is the standard of care determined?

29

Strict liability rule: plaintiff must prove harm and causation

Negligence rule: must prove harm, causation, and negligence

A little history Early Europe: strict liability was usual rule By early 1900s, negligence became usual rule Second half of 1900s, strict liability became more common again,

especially for manufacturer liability in American consumer products U.S. manufacturers now held liable for harms caused by defective

products, whether or not they were at fault

Strict liability versus negligence

30

Harm

Causation

Breach of Duty

“Classic” legal theory of torts

31

Economicmodel

32

The more carefully I drive, the less likely I am to hit you But, driving more carefully is also more costly to me Must be some efficient level of care

Similarly… Construction company can reduce accidents with better safety

equipment, better training, working shorter days, all of which cost money

Manufacturer can reduce accidents by designing/inspecting products more carefully – again, more expensive

Precaution

33

Lots of things both victims and injurers can do to reduce number (or harm) of accidents

study warning on medicine

improve warning on medicine

medicine causes side effects

handle bottles carefullyimprove quality control by bottler

exploding coke bottle

back up data at riskbetter design of softwaresoftware fails

walk more safelydrive more safelycar hits pedestrian

park car in safer spacedrive more safelymoving car hits parked car

fireproof housemanufacture wiring more carefully

faulty electrical wiring causes house fire

Victim’s PrecautionInjurer’s PrecautionAccident

Cooter and Ulen, p. 338

34

Precaution: anything either injurer or victim could do to reduce likelihood of an accident (or damage done)

The next two questions should be obvious…

How much precaution do we want? What is efficient level of precaution?

How do we design the law to get it?

We will call all these things precaution

35

Car hits a bicycle In real life: driver probably has insurance In real life: some damage to bicycle, some damage to driver’s car In real life: driver and bicyclist may not even know what the law is

We’ll simplify things a lot, by assuming… Only one party is harmed Parties know the law, don’t have insurance (for now) We’ll focus on one party’s precaution at a time

To answer these questions, we’ll introduce a very simple model of accidents

36

Unilateral harm – just one victim

Precaution – costly actions that make accident less likely Could be taken by either victim or injurer We’ll focus on one at a time

Notation x – the amount of precaution that is taken w – the cost of each “unit” of precaution

so total cost of precaution is wx p(x) – probability of an accident, given precaution x

p is decreasing in x A – cost of accident (to victim)

so expected cost of accidents is p(x) A

Model of unilateral harmx level of precautionw marginal cost of precautionp(x) probability of an accidentA cost of an accident

37

Model of unilateral harmx level of precautionw marginal cost of precautionp(x) probability of an accidentA cost of an accident

Precaution (x)

$

p(x) A (Cost of Accidents)

wx (Cost of Precaution)

wx + p(x) A(Total Social Cost)

x* (Efficient Level of Precaution)

38

efficient precaution: minx { wx + p(x) A }

w + p’(x) A = 0

w = – p’(x) A

Under reasonable assumptions (p(x) convex)… x < x* w < – p’(x) A

MSC < MSB more precaution efficient x > x* w > – p’(x) A

MSC > MSB less precaution efficient x = x* MSC = MSB

Model of unilateral harmx level of precautionw marginal cost of precautionp(x) probability of an accidentA cost of an accident

marginal social cost of precaution

marginal social benefit of precaution

39

Model of unilateral harmx level of precautionw marginal cost of precautionp(x) probability of an accidentA cost of an accident

x

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

x*x < x* x > x*

40

We haven’t yet said who is taking precaution

Some situations, only injurer can reduce accidents

Some situations, victim can too

Bilateral precaution is a little bit tricky, but if we look at the two parties one at a time, everything works fine

Wednesday: consider effect of different liability rules on precaution

Model of unilateral harm

41

Effect of Liability Ruleson Precaution

42

Three rules we’ll consider:

No liability

Strict liability

Negligence

Effect of liability rules on precaution

43

In a world with no liability… Victim bears the cost of any accidents, plus the cost of any

precaution he takes Injurer bears cost of any precaution he takes, does not have to pay

for accidents

Rule 1: No Liability

44

Rule 1: No LiabilityInjurer precaution

x

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

x*

Injurer’s private cost is just wx Injurer minimizes private cost by setting x = 0

Private cost to injurer

45

Rule 1: No LiabilityVictim precaution

x

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

x*

Victim’s private cost is wx + p(x) A To minimize this, victim takes efficient level of precaution

Private cost to victim

46

So in a world with no liability…

Injurer takes inefficiently low level of precaution (zero, or minimal amount)

Victim takes efficient amount of precaution

Rule 1: No Liability

47

Perfect compensation: damages D = A

Under strict liability… Injurer pays damages for any accidents he causes So injurer bears cost of accidents, plus his own precaution Victim pays only for his precaution

Rule 2: Strict Liability

48

Rule 2: Strict LiabilityInjurer precaution

x

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

x*

Injurer’s private cost is wx + p(x) A Injurer minimizes this by taking efficient level of precaution

Private cost to injurer

49

Rule 2: Strict LiabilityVictim precaution

x

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

x*

Victim’s private cost is wx No incentive to take any precaution, victim sets x = 0

Private cost to victim

50

Effect of liability rules on precaution

EfficientZeroStrict Liability

ZeroEfficientNo Liability

Injurerprecaution

Victimprecaution

51

When it’s the injurer who can take precautions, a rule of strict liability is more efficient

When it’s the victim who can take precautions, a rule of no liability is more efficient

Each rule works well for one incentive, poorly for other Similar to paradox of compensation we saw in contract law Negligence rule may allow us to get both incentives right

So for accidents with unilateral precaution…

52

“Simple Negligence” rule

Legal standard of care xn

Injurer is liable for damages if precaution level was below the legal standard of care x < xn D = A x xn D = 0

So on our graph from before, private cost to injurer is… wx + p(x) A for x < xn

wx for x xn

Rule 3: Simple Negligence

53

Rule 3: Simple NegligenceInjurer precaution

x

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

xn = x* Private cost is wx + p(x) A if x < xn, only wx otherwise If standard of care is set efficiently (xn = x*), injurer minimizes private cost by taking efficient precaution

Private cost to injurer

54

Rule 3: Simple NegligenceVictim precaution

$

p(x) A

wx

wx + p(x) A

x*

What about victim? We just said, injurer will

take efficient precaution Which means injurer will

not be liable So victim bears costs of

any accidents (Victim bears residual

risk) So victim’s private cost is

wx + p(x) A Victim minimizes private

cost by taking efficient level of precaution too!

Private cost to victim

(assuming injurer takes efficient level of precaution

and is therefore not liable for damages)

55

Effect of liability rules on precaution

EfficientEfficientSimple Negligence,with xn = x*

EfficientZeroStrict Liability

ZeroEfficientNo Liability

Injurerprecaution

Victimprecaution