ethics in research involving human subjects at the beginning of life

Upload: dr-liza-manalo

Post on 07-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    1/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 46

    ETHICS IN RESEARCH

    Test-Tube Babies, Cloning, andTissueTransplants from Aborted and Anencephalic Children:

    Is There Anything Wrong With These?

    Maria Fidelis C. Manalo, MD, MSc.

    Consider the following scenario. A one-year-old baby dies in an accident.

    The parents were really fond of him, and decide to have some of his cells frozen

    and eventually cloned. They say that this way they will have their baby boy back.Is there anything wrong with this? (1)

    Scientific Progress And Experimental Research

    A therapeutic action which is apt to be increasingly beneficial to health is

    for that very reason open to new investigative possibilities. These are the result

    of a progressive and ongoing activity of research and experimentation, which

    thus succeeds in arriving at new medical advances.

    To proceed by way of research and experimentation is a law of every

    applied science: scientific progress is structurally connected with it. Biomedical

    sciences and their development are subject to this law also. But they operate in a

    particular field of application and observation which is the life of the human

    person.

    Department of Community and Family Medicine, Far Eastern University - Nicanor ReyesMedical Foundation, Fairview, Quezon City, 1118, Philippines. Email: [email protected],[email protected]

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    2/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 47

    Care For The Dignity Of Human Life

    The human person, because of his unique dignity---that of bearing the

    image and likeness of the Creator and that of being destined to share in the

    divine life, --- can be the subject of research and clinical experimentation with the

    safeguards due to a being with the value of a subject and not an object. Mans

    dignity resides in the fact that he is a who and not a what, a unique being,

    irreplaceable, endowed with privacy, intelligence, will, freedom, and the ability to

    love and open himself to others. For this reason, biomedical sciences do not

    have the same freedom of investigation as those sciences which deal with things.

    (2)

    A unique responsibility belongs to health care personnel: doctors,

    pharmacists, nurses, chaplains, men and women religious, administrators and

    volunteers. Their profession calls for them to be guardians and servants of

    human life. In todays cultural and social context, in which science and the

    practice of medicine risk losing sight of their inherent ethical dimension, health

    care professionals can be strongly tempted at times to become manipulators of

    life, or even agents of death. (3) This happens when one does not know or when

    one forgets the ultimate basis of human dignity. A deep and thorough

    understanding of this will help one understand the reason behind the ethical

    norms guiding human experimentation and research especially those involving

    embryos and fetuses. Let us thus make certain definitions and answer some

    basic questions.

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    3/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 48

    What Do We Mean by Human?

    The adjective human is used to describe that which is characteristic of

    man as a species distinguished from other animals. Biologically there are two

    criteria of what is human, one intrinsic, one extrinsic. Extrinsically, that which is of

    human origin is human. By this criterion human applies to such things as sounds,

    footprints, excrement, etc., as well as human beings. The intrinsic criterion

    depends upon genetic constitution. Normally this constitution is contained in a set

    of 46 chromosomes which is present in almost all the cells of the human body.

    When Does Life Become Human?

    The answer is never. Like life, humanity is continuous. Intrinsically, the

    sperm, the ovum, the zygote, and all the cells, tissues, and stages that arise from

    the zygote are human. None of them can ever be characterized as belonging to

    any other species. Human life is not started---it is transmitted. There is no instant

    or interval of time between fertilization and birth when the unborn offspring is

    anything but human.

    But if life is continuous and humanity is continuous, what is the differencebetween the sperm and ovum before fertilization and the zygote after

    fertilization? They are all human life, are they not? Which brings us to our next

    question.

    When Does Life Become a Human Being?

    There are several differences between a zygote and either a sperm or an

    ovum. One is in information content. The haploid gametes have only half the

    genetic information that a zygote has. But that would not alone indicate a

    difference between the zygote and the gametes taken together.

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    4/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 49

    The destiny of the ovum is either to be fertilized or to die. In either case it

    ceases to exist as a gamete. The similar destiny of the sperm is to fertilize or to

    die. In fertilization the gametes lose their identity and individuality and fulfill their

    destiny. The result is a new individual, with a new life and a new unique identity

    and a new unique destiny. One way to illustrate the unique importance of this

    new individual is to look at the question

    When Does Human Life Begin?

    When did your life begin? The answer to this question can be phrased

    simply by going backward in time. Before you were an adult, you were an

    adolescent, and before that a child, and before that an infant. Before you were an

    infant---i.e., before you were born---you were a fetus, and before that an embryo.

    Before you were an embryo, around the time of your implantation, you were a

    blastocyst, and before that a morula, and before that a zygote or a fertilized

    ovum. Therefore while life is continuous, your life began when the nucleus of

    your fathers sperm fused with the nucleus of your mothers ovum, or at

    fertilization. So we see that there is something important, something special, that

    occurs at fertilization: A new life, a new human life, begins.

    But Is It a Human Being?

    The term human being is used interchangeably with human individual,

    which is frequently shortened to just individual. It signifies a complete, though

    not completed, living, organized, unique, individual human organism, always

    more or less dependent on other human beings, but always with a certain

    amount of autonomy and charge over its own destiny. The zygote fits all of these

    criteria. The informationally complete cell has an information content equivalent

    to 1000 volumes of the Encyclopedia Britannicaand unlike that of another human

    being. If it does not twin, it will retain this uniqueness. The new cell is

    programmed to divide, differentiate, form hormones and enzymes, implant,

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    5/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 50

    develop organs, brain, nerve and bone, eventually becoming an adult and

    repeating the cycle. (4)

    Immorality of Research Contrary to the True Good of the Person

    In the researchstage, the ethical norm requires that its aim be to promote

    human wellbeing. Any research contrary to the true good of the person is

    immoral. To invest energies and resources in it contradicts the human finality of

    science and its progress.

    In the experimental stage, that is, testing the findings of research on a

    person, the good of the person, protected by the ethical norm, demands the

    respect for previous conditions which are essentially linked with consent and risk.

    (2)

    Let us now elaborate on specific aspects of research and experimentation

    on embryos, human fetuses and anencephalic infants:

    In Vitro Fertilization

    In vitro fertilization consists in putting spermatocytes in contact with

    oocytes inside a test tube. It is an attempt to simulate in a culture medium what

    occurs naturally in the fallopian tube.

    The oocytes are obtained from the mother or a donor by puncture of the

    ovary; the sperms, ordinarily, by masturbation.

    Once fertilization takes place inside the test tube with consequent fusion

    of the pronuclei, division begins. The fertilized ova (zygotes) already in the

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    6/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 51

    embryonic stage are then transferred to the uterus; there they continue their

    normal development.

    Well-known and heralded by the press at that time, the first case of IVF

    was performed by Drs. Edward and Steptoe in England in 1978, with the birth of

    the first test tube baby, Louise Brown. Thereafter, IVF has been employed in

    many parts of the world.

    The first thing that comes to mind when one talks of IVF is homologous

    artificial insemination. This utilizes the husbands semen and the wifes ovum.

    The zygote produced is implanted in the uterus of the wife.

    Other methods of artificial insemination are:

    fertilization of the ova of the wife with the sperm of an anonymous

    donor

    fertilization of the ova of the wife with the sperm of the husband but the

    embryo produced is transferred to the uterus of another woman

    (surrogate mother or mother for hire) fertilization of the ovum of a donor by the sperm of the husband and

    the embryo is transferred to the uterus of the wife

    fertilization of the ovum of a female donor with the sperm of a male

    donor and the embryo is transferred into the uterus of the wife

    The possibilities and interchanges may be multiplied leading to varied

    situations including aberrant ones: post-mortem insemination of a single woman

    who wants a child without father, etc. It can be said in jest that a test tube baby

    can have up to 5 parents: the mother and the father who paid the donors; the

    donors of the gametes (who are the genital parents), and the surrogate mother

    who received the embryo and incubated it until it is delivered.

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    7/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 52

    One to 4 embryos are transferred to the uterus because the probability of

    pregnancy is 7%, 21%, and 28% when 1, 2, or 3 embryos are transferred,

    respectively. The transfer of more than 4 embryos increases the risk of multiple

    pregnancy; therefore, it is not advised.

    A large number of embryos must be produced in order to proceed with

    IVF. What happens to the embryos that are not transferred to the uterus? Some

    embryos are discarded, others conserved, frozen to be transferred to the same

    patient in another session or to another patient with the consent of the donor

    couple. The embryos are also utilized in scientific research. In any case IVF

    involves manipulation of human beings. (5)

    Cloning

    Advances in knowledge and related developments in the procedures of

    molecular biology, genetics and artificial fertilization have long made it possible to

    experiment with and successfully achieve the cloning of plants and animals.

    Since the 30s experiments have been made in producing identical individuals by

    artificial twin splitting, a procedure, which can be improperly called cloning. The

    practice of twin splitting in the zootechnical field has been spreading in

    experimental barns as an incentive to the multiple production of select

    exemplars.

    In 1993 Jerry Hall and Robert Stilman of George Washington University

    published data concerning the twin splitting they performed on human embryos

    of two, four and eight embryoblasts. These experiments were conducted without

    the prior consent of the appropriate Ethics Committee and were published,

    according to the authors, in order to stimulate the ethical debate.

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    8/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 53

    The news published in the journal Nature , 27 February 1997, about the

    birth of the sheep Dolly through the efforts of the Scottish scientists Jan Vilmut

    and K.H.S. Campbell and their team at Edinburghs Roslin Institute, however, is

    troubling on two aspects: The first is that it is not a question of splitting but of a

    radical innovation defined as cloning meant to produce individuals biologically

    identical to the adult which provided the nuclear genetic inheritance. The second

    is that until now this type of true and proper cloning was considered impossible. It

    was thought that the DNA in the somatic cells of the higher forms of animal life,

    having already undergone the imprinting of differentiation, could no longer

    recover their original totipotentiality and consequently, their ability to direct the

    development of a new individual.

    In its biological aspects as a form of artificial reproduction, cloning is

    achieved without the contribution of two gametes; therefore it is an asexual and

    agametic reproduction. Fertilization properly so-called is replaced by the fusion

    of a nucleus taken from a somatic cell of the individual one wishes to clone, or of

    the somatic cell itself, with an oocyte from which the nucleus has been removed,

    that is, an oocyte lacking the maternal genome. Since the nucleus of the somatic

    cell contains the whole genetic inheritance, the individual obtained possesses---

    except for the possible alterations---the genetic identity of the nucleus donor. It is

    this essential genetic correspondence with the donor that produces in the new

    individual the somatic replica or copy of the donor itself.

    The Edinburgh event occurred after 277 oocyte-donor nucleus fusions:

    only eight were successful, that is, only eight of the 277 started to develop as

    embryos and only one of these eight embryos reached birth: the lamb called

    Dolly. (6)

    Let us now go back to the hypothetical situation we proposed at the

    beginning of this article. From the ethical point of view, this case of cloning can

    be considered wrong, just like any other act of cloning a human being. But there

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    9/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 54

    is still another reason why this is wrong, this time from the point of view of the

    cloned persons identity. The cloned baby boy will not be the same as the original

    one. Cloning cannot offer that, as what the parents will get will merely be a copy,

    not the first baby boy himself. In the first place, their bodies will not be the same:

    the originals will be buried (or frozen), while the clones will be composed of

    other molecules. Their souls will also be different, as each person receives a

    different soul. Finally, their upbringing will greatly vary, as even the upbringing

    between twins cannot be identical.

    We must also consider how a cloned person might feel about himself or

    herself. The best way to do this is to imagine how we would feel if we were the

    clone of somebody else. People will surely refer to us not as "John" or "Maria",

    but as "Johns clone or Marias clone. The constant point of reference will be

    the original, and we will tend to lose our identity.

    For example, right after his death, your mother decides to clone him, so

    that she could be with him again. In this case you will still be your fathers son.

    But your mother will still want to consider you her husband. She will later find out

    that this is impossible, given the difference in age. But above all, no matter what

    she does, you will always remain a different person and never become your

    father.

    Or how would you feel to be Hitlers clone? People will look at you as

    when they look at an object in a museum. Some of your neighbors will be afraid

    of you and stories about Hitler (I mean you) will circulate all over the country.

    And what if you were Albert Einsteins clone? The time will come when

    you go to school, and everyone will expect you to be a genius. Good if you will

    be, but what if not? You will be the laughing stock of the classa defective Albert

    Einstein. People will pressure you to imitate him. Whether you give in to this

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    10/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 55

    pressure or not will depend on you. But in any case, you will surely rather have

    none of this at all.

    So far we have been talking about successful clones. But at least for the

    near future, the cloning will involve producing many candidate clones, from whom

    one (or any number needed) will be selected and brought to maturity. What will

    be done with the other copies that are not lucky enough to be considered fit or

    needed? They may either be simply killed and thrown away, used in experiments

    (human experiments, that is) or maybe frozen until somebody else wants to use

    them.

    Clones can also be used for other purposes. Some say that clones might

    be made to order to provide us with needed replacement parts. Why take a

    kidney from a donor relative to have transplant, when you can simply bring one of

    your cells to a laboratory, order a clone, and harvest the clones kidney?

    However, you will still probably have to wait long before your clone grows up and

    reaches your age (but since meanwhile you too will grow older, the clone will

    never reach your age), or at least reach an age wherein the clones organ could

    already be used. To solve this problem, clones can also be farmed or mass-

    produced. Then, depending on what kind of antibodies you have, you can choose

    the organ you need from a wide range of clones, to ensure no rejection after the

    transplant. Meanwhile, some of these clones will be frozen, while others will still

    be alive.

    Another very important issue in transplant of clones will be consent. In the

    same way that you have to obtain a donors consent before taking out his kidney

    (as you also have to give your consent before giving your kidney to anyone), you

    will also have to get the clones consent before harvesting his kidney. Most likely,

    the clone will not be happy about your having cloned him or her in the first place

    to obtain your needed spare parts, much less allow himself to lose a kidney.

    Who wants to be a clone, anyway?!? (1)

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    11/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 56

    Cells From Aborted Children Said To Stop Parkinsons Disease

    The results of a new study said most Parkinsons disease patients, but

    especially younger ones, stand to benefit from a transplant of brain cells from

    aborted children.

    The University of Colorado Health Sciences Center said the

    comprehensive study showed that the cells flourished in all the patients, but did

    best in younger patients. Tremors, rigidity, and the inability to control movements

    characterize Parkinsons disease. The illness is linked to the death of brain cells

    that produce a chemical called dopamine.

    The procedure in the study used tissues from unborn children aborted at

    the 7th or 8th week of pregnancy, and each patient in the study required brain

    cells from about 4 children. Researchers said the cells were only harvested from

    previously scheduled abortions not taken specifically for the study. (7)

    Organ Donation from Children with Anencephaly

    The remarkable technique of organ transplantation has raised a question

    about the child with anencephaly as an organ donor. Organs from fetuses and

    infants may be especially helpful for transplantation because at early stages of

    life the physiological factors that may cause a transplant to be rejected by its

    recipient are not yet fully present. In addition, organs can also be subject to rapid

    deterioration after death.

    Anencephaly is a congenital anomaly characterized by failure of

    development of the cerebral hemispheres and overlying skull and scalp,

    exposing the brain stem. This condition exists in varying degrees of severity.

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    12/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 57

    Most infants who have anencephaly do not survive for more than a few days after

    birth.

    The fact that the life of a child suffering from anencephaly will probably be

    brief cannot excuse directly causing death before viability or gravely

    endangering the childs life after viability as a result of complications of

    prematurity.

    In both cases of stem-cell transplants from aborted children and organ

    donation from children with anencephaly, we have to consider that while the

    donation of organs to another is an act of true charity which has the full support

    of the Church, certain criteria must be observed:

    (a) Persons may not be killed as a means to obtain organs, either before

    the removal of the organs, or when its removal kills the donor.

    (b) Living donors must give free and informed consent, but must refuse

    this consent if the donation would put their own life or health to grave

    risk. In the case of anencephalic children and still-living aborted

    fetuses, it is obvious that their consent cannot be obtained and the

    proxy consent from the parents or other legal guardians must take into

    consideration that it is always and gravely wrong to use an evil means

    even to a good end, in this case to kill a child by removing his or her

    tissues or organs for transplantation.

    (c) Organs may be taken from the dead, provided due respect is shown

    the corpse and if their families give consent, or if this is required by law

    for the common good. (8)

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    13/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 58

    Norms on Experimentation On Embryos And Human Fetuses

    Going back to the question raised by the title of this article on whether

    anything is wrong with test-tube babies, cloning, tissue transplants from aborted

    or anencephalic infants, the answer is: definitely.

    Since the human individual, in the prenatal stage, must be given the

    dignity of a human person, research and experimentation on human embryos

    and fetuses is subject to the ethical norms valid for the child already born and for

    every human subject.

    Research in particular, that is the observation of a given phenomenon

    during pregnancy, can be allowed only when there is moral certainty that there

    will be no harm either to the life or the integrity of the expected child and the

    mother, and on the condition that the parents have given their consent.

    Experimentation, on the other hand, is possible only for clearly therapeutic

    purposes, when no other possible remedy is available. No finality, even if itself

    noble, such as the foreseeing of a usefulness for science, for other human

    beings or for society, can in any way justify experimentation on live human

    embryos and fetuses, whether viable or not, in the maternal womb or outside of

    it. The informed consent, normally required for clinical experimentation on an

    adult, cannot be given by the parents, who may not dispose of the physical

    integrity or the life of the expected child. On the other hand, experimentation of

    embryos or fetuses has the risk, indeed in most cases the certain foreknowledge,

    of damaging their physical integrity or even causing their death. To use a human

    embryo or the fetus as an object or instrument of experimentation is a crime

    against their dignity as human beings. The practice of keeping human embryos

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    14/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 59

    alive, actually or in vitro, for experimental or commercial reasons, is especially

    and altogether contrary to human dignity. (2)

    Conclusion

    The most urgent need now seems to be that of re-establishing the

    harmony between the demands of scientific research and indispensable human

    values. The scientist cannot regard the moral rejection of in vitro fertilization,

    human cloning, and organ donation from still living aborted fetuses and

    anencephalic infants for example as a humiliation; on the contrary, this

    prohibition eliminates the demiurgic degeneration of research by restoring its

    dignity. The dignity of scientific research consists in the fact that it is one of the

    richest resources for humanitys welfare.

    Moreover, there is a place for research, including cloning, in the vegetable

    and animal kingdoms, wherever it answers a need or provides a significant

    benefit for man or for other living beings, provided that the rules for protecting the

    animal itself and the obligation to respect the biodiversity of species are

    observed.

    When scientific research in mans interest aims to cure diseases, to

    relieve suffering, to solve problems due to malnutrition, to make better use of the

    earths resources, it represents a hope for humanity, entrusted to the talent and

    efforts of scientists.

    To enable biomedical science to maintain and strengthen its relationship

    with the true welfare of man and society, it is necessary to foster, as the pope,

    John Paul II, recalls in the Encyclical Evangelium vitae, a contemplative outlook

    on man himself and the world, with a vision of reality as Gods creation and in the

    context of solidarity between science, the good of the person and of society.

  • 8/4/2019 Ethics in Research Involving Human Subjects at the Beginning of Life

    15/15

    Far Eastern University Medical Journal December 1998, Vol. 4. No. 2 60

    It is the outlook of those who see life in its deeper meaning, who grasp its

    utter gratuitousness, its beauty and its invitation to freedom and responsibility. It

    is the outlook of those who do not presume to take possession of reality but

    instead accept it as a gift, discovering in all things the reflection of the Creator

    and seeing in every person his living image. (6)

    References:

    1. Gaston, Gregory, Who Wants To Be A Clone? Documentation Service,

    1998 January XI: 1, 10-13.

    2. Pontifical Council for Pastoral Assistance to Health Care Workers, Charter

    for Health Care Workers1996, 72-79.

    3. Pope John Paul II, Evangelium Vitae (The Gospel of Life) 1995, 158-159.

    4. Freiling, Edward, When Does Human Life Begin? Documentation Service,

    1991 July IV: 7, 19-27.

    5. Monge, Michael. Ethical Practices in Health & Disease Sinag-tala

    Publishers, Inc. Manila, 1994, 147-153.

    6. Pontifical Academy for Life, Reflections on Cloning Documentation Service,

    1998 January XI: 1, 2-8.

    7. Achacoso, Jaime, ed., Theological Centrum Newsletter 1999 May XIV: 5, 5.

    8. Committee on Doctrine of the U.S National Conference of Catholic Bishops,

    Moral Principles Concerning Infants With Anencephaly LOsservatore

    Romano, 1998 September, 6-10.