fish in harpers

Upload: laura-paduraru-luchian

Post on 06-Apr-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    1/9

    E n \ X i A R [I S A InT H E H' L L Y o F S I 1\1r L IF Y IN l:; IS L AM

    P OST M O DE RN W A R FA R EThe Ignorance of Our Warrior Intellectuals

    By Stanley Fish

    -----------+ -----------

    T H E F OR E ST P RIM E V A L

    A Month in Congo's Wildest Jungle

    By Peter Canby

    IN P R A IS E O F IM I T A TIO N

    On the Sincerest Form of Flattery

    By Nicholas Delbanco

    B IG B E A R , C A L IF O R N IA

    A story by Rebecca Curtis

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    2/9

    E S SAY

    POST~10DERNWARFARE

    The ignorance of our warrior intellectuals

    By Stanley F is h

    W owould have thought, in those first few

    minutes, hours, days, that what we now call 9/11

    was to become an event in the Culture Wars?

    Today, more than nine months later, nothing

    could be clearer, though it was only on Septem-

    ber 22 that the first sign appeared, in a New York

    Times opinion piece written by Edward Roth-

    stein and entitled "Attacks on U.S. Challenge the

    Perspectives of Postmodem True Believers." A few

    days later (on September 27), Julia Keller wrote

    a smaller piece in the Chicago Tribune; her title

    (no doubr the comriburion of a staffer): "After the

    attack, postmodemism loses its glib grip." In the

    September 24 issue ofTime , Roger Rosenblatt an-

    nounced "the end of the age of irony" and pre-

    dicted that "the good folks in charge of Ameri-

    ca's intellectual life" would now have to change

    their tune and no longer say that "nothing was

    real" or that "nothing was to be believed in or tak-

    en seriously." And on October I, John Leo, in a

    piece entitled "Campus hand-wringing is not a

    pretty sight," blamed just about everything on

    the "very dangerous ideas" that have captured

    our "campus culture"; to wit, "radical cultural

    relativism, nonjudgmentalisrn, and a postmod-

    em conviction that there are no moral norms or

    truths worth defending."

    Well, that certainly sounds bad-no truths,

    no knowledge, no reality, no morality, no judg-ments, no objectivity-and if postmodemists are

    saying that, they are not so much dangerous as sil-

    ly. Luckily, however, postmodernists say no such

    thing, and what they do say, if it is understood at

    all, is unlikely to provoke either the anger or the

    alarm of our modern Pau I Reveres. A full ac-

    count or even definition of posrrnodemism would

    be out of place here, but it may be enough for our

    purposes to look at one offered by Rothstein,

    who begins by saying that "Postmodemists chal-

    lenge assertions that truth and ethical judgment

    have any objective validity." Well, it depends

    on what you mean by "objective." If you mean a

    standard of validity and value that is independent

    of any historically emergent and therefore revis-

    able system of thought and practice, then it is true

    that many postmodernists would denyethat any

    such standard is or could ever be available. But :

    if by "objective" one means a standard of validi-

    ty and value that is backed up by the tried-and-

    true procedures and protocols of a well-devel-

    oped practice or discipline-history, physics,

    economics, psychology, etc.-then such stan-

    dards are all around us, and we make use of them

    all the time without any metaphysical anxiety.

    As Richard Rorty, one of Rothstein's targets,

    is fond of saying, "Objectivity is the kind of thing

    we do around here." Historians draw conclusions

    about the meaning of events, astronomers present

    models of planetary movements, psychologists

    offer accounts of the reading process, consumers

    make decisions about which product is best, par-

    ents choose schools for their children-all ofthese things and many more are done with vary-

    ing degrees of confidence, and in no case is the

    confidence rooted in a conviction that the actor

    is in possession of some independent standard of

    Stanley Fish is dean of the College of Liberal Arts and Sciences at the University of Illinois at Chiw!!.o. He is the audlOrof many books, including, mostrecently, The Trouble with Principle an d How Milton Works (Harvard University

    Press). The Stanley Fish Reader, edited by H. Aram Veeser, was published in J 999 ..

    ES SAY 3

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    3/9

    objectivity. Rather, the actor, you or I or anyone,

    begins in some context of practice, with its re-

    ceived authorities, sacred texts, exemplary

    achievements, and generally accepted bench-

    marks, and from within the perspective of that

    context-thick, interpersonal, densely elaborat-

    ed-judges something to be true or inaccurate,

    reasonable or irrational, and so on.

    lt seems, then, that theunavailability of absolutely

    objective standards-the

    thesis Rothstein finds re-

    pugnant and dangerous-

    doesn't take anything away

    from us. If, as posrrnod-

    ernists assert, objective

    standards of a publicly ver-

    ifiable kind are unavailable,

    they are so only in the sense that they have always

    been unavailable (this isnot, in other words, a con-

    dition postmodemism has caused), and we have

    always managed to get along without them, doing

    a great many things despite the fact that we mightbe unable to shore them up in accordance with the

    most rigorous philosophical demands. One of the

    things we might be doing, for instance, when

    we're not doing philosophy, is condemning some-

    one or some group, though Rothstein seems to

    think that we can't do that unless we have all

    our philosophical ducks in a row-and in the

    right row. Thus, he says, given postmodernist as-

    sumptions, "one culture, particularly the West,

    cannot reliably condemn another," which means,

    according to him, that we in the United States

    cannot reliably condemn those who attacked the

    World Trade Center and the Pentagon. Again, it

    depends on what you mean by "reliably," a word

    that takes us right back to "objective" and to the

    argument I have been making. If by "a reliable con-

    demnation" you mean a condemnarion rooted in

    a strong sense of values, priorities, goals, and a

    conviction of right and wrong, then such a con-

    demnation is available to most if not all of us all

    of the time. But if by "a reliable condemnation"

    you mean a condemnation rooted in values, pri-

    orities, and a sense of right and wrong that no on e

    would dispute and everyone accepts, then there isno

    such condemnation, for the simple reason that

    there are no such universally accepted values, pri-

    orities, and moral convictions. If there were, there

    would be no deep disputes.

    Now, I would not be misunderstood. I am notsaying that there are no universal values or no

    truths independent of particular perspectives. I

    affirm both. When I offer a reading of.a poem or

    pronounce on a case in First Amendment law, I

    do so with no epistemological reservations. I re-

    gard my reading as true-not provisionally true,

    or true for my reference group only, but true. I am

    as certain of that as I am of the fact that I may very

    POSTMODERNISM IS A SERIES

    OF ARGUMENTS, NOT A

    WAY OF LIFE OR A RECIPE

    FOR ACTION

    34 HARPER'S MAGAZINE IJULY 2002

    well be unable to persuade others, no less edu

    cated or credentialed than I, of the truth so per

    spicuous to me. And here is a point that is often

    missed, the independence from each other, an

    therefore the compatibility, of two assertions

    thought to be contradictory when made by the

    same person: (1) I believe X to be true and (2)

    believe that there is no mechanism, procedure,

    calculus, test, by which the truth of X can be necessarily demonstrated to any sane person who ha

    come to a different conclusion (not that such

    demonstration can never be successful, only tha

    its success is contingent and not necessary). In or

    der to assert something and mean it without qual

    ification, I of course have to believe that it is true

    but I don't have to believe that I could demon-

    strate its truth to all rational persons. The claim

    that something is universal and the acknowledg-

    ment that I couldn't necessarily prove it are log

    ically independent of each other. The second

    does not undermine the first. .

    Once again, then, a postmodern argument

    turns out to be without any deleterious consequences (it is also without any positive conse

    quences, but that is another story), and it certainly

    does not stand in the way of condemning those

    who have proven themselves to be our enemies

    in words and deeds. Nor should this be surprising

    for, after all, postmodcrnism is a series of argu

    ments, not a way of life or a recipe for action. You

    belief or disbelief in postmodem tenets is inde

    pendent of your beliefs and commitments in any

    other area of your life. You may believe that ob

    jectivity of an absolute kind is possible or yo

    may believe that it is not, but when you have t

    decide whether a particular thing is true or false

    neither belief will hinder or help you. What wi

    help you are archives, exemplary achievements,

    revered authorities, official bodies of evidence, re

    evant analogies, suggestive metaphors-all avail

    able to all persons independently of their philo

    sophical convictions, or of the fac

    Ithat they do or do not have any.

    n the end, the post-9/11 flap about postmod

    emism is the blowing of so much smoke, sound an

    furysignifying very little apart from the ignorance

    of those who produced it. There's no there there

    This is not true, however, of what succeeded tha

    flap in the popular and semi-popular media, th

    question of whether this is or isnot a religious wa

    That question was asked against the backdrop othe Bush Administration's desire that the war no

    be characterized as a religious one. Any public

    embrace of Samuel Huntington's clash-of-civi-

    lizations thesis would have at least three bad con

    sequences. First, key Islamic nations could not b

    persuaded to support, or at least to refrain from de

    nouncing, U.S. military operations. Second, mi

    lions of U.S. citizens of the Islamic faith would be

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    4/9

    come the large core of an antiwar coalition. And

    lastly, the United Nations would become polar-

    ized along religious lines, with the possible result

    that any U.S. attack would be censured. In the

    context of these and related anxieties, the official

    party line emerged almost immediately: Although

    Al Qaeda said that its warriors did what they did

    in the service of Allah, theirs was a perverted ver-

    sion of the Islamic faith, and therefore their claim

    to be acting in its name wasfalse and illegitimate;

    they simply did not represent Islam and had mis-

    read its sacred texts.

    If you think about it for a moment, this is an

    amazing line of argument that begs

    the questions contained in its as-

    sertions. Who is it that is autho-

    rizedto determine which version of

    Islam is the true one? What reli-

    gious faith has ever looked outside

    the articles of its creed for guid-

    ance and correction? What is the

    difference between the confident

    pronouncements that the AlQaeda brand of Islam is a deviant

    one and the excommunications

    and counter-excommunications of

    Catholics and Protestants, and

    within Protestantism of Baptists,

    Anglicans, Lutherans, not to men-

    tion jehovah's Witnesses, Seventh-

    Day Adventists, Mormons, and

    Mennonites? Merely to pose these

    questions is to realize that the spec-

    ification of what a religion is and

    the identification of the actions

    that mayor may not be taken in its

    name are entirely internal matters .. This is, after all, the point of a re-

    ligion: to follow a vision the source

    of which is revelation, ecclesiasti-

    cal authority, a sacred book, a

    revered person. One who adheres

    to that vision does not accept de-

    scriptions or evaluations of it from

    non-adherents citing other revela-

    tions, authorities, and texts; and

    the fact that non-adherents regard

    some of the convictions at the heart of the vision

    as bizarre, and regard the actions generated by

    those convictions as inadvisable or even evil, is

    merely confirmation, again from the inside, of

    the extent to which these poor lost souls are in thegrip of error and too blind to see. What this means

    (and here we link up with the worries over post-

    rnodernismlis that in matters of religion-and I

    would say in any matter-there isno public space,

    complete with definitions, standards, norms, cri-

    teria, etc., to which one can have recourse in or-

    der to separate out the true from the false, the

    revolutionary from the criminal. And what that

    means is that there is no common ground, at least

    no common ground on which a partisan flag has

    not already been planted, that would allow some-

    one or some body to render an independent j udg-

    ment on the legitimacy of the declarations that is-

    sue from Bin Laden and his followers about the

    reiigious bases of their actions.

    Indeed, only if there were such a public space

    or common ground could the question "Is this a

    religious war?" be a real question, as opposed to a

    tendentious thesis pretending to be a question,

    which it is. That is to say, the question "Is this a

    religious war?" is not a question about the war; it

    is the question that is the war. For the question

    makes assumptions Al Qaeda members are bound

    to reject and indeed are warring against: that it is

    possible to distinguish between religious and non-

    religious acts from a perspective uninflected byany religion or ideology; or, to put it another way,

    that there is a perspective detached from and

    above all religions, from the vantage point of .

    which objective judgments about what is and is

    not properly religious could be handed down; or

    that it is possible to distinguish between the oblig-

    ations one takes on as a person of faith and the

    obligations one takes on in one's capacity as a

    Aqui es el centro, by Alfredo Castaneda, courtesy Mary-Anne Martin Fine Art, New York City E SS AY

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    5/9

    citizen; i.e., that it is possible to go out into the

    world and perform actions that are not related, ei-

    ther positively or negatively, to your religious

    convictions. And these assumptions make sense

    only in the context of another: that religion is

    essentially a private transaction between you and

    your God and therefore is, at least in principle, in-

    dependent of your actions in the public sphere,

    where the imperatives you follow might be polit-

    ical, economic, philanthropic, environmental-

    imperatives that could be affirmed or rejected by

    persons independently of their religious convic-

    tions or of their lack of religious convictions.

    What I have rehearsed for you, in a nutshell,

    is the core of what has been called America's'

    "Civic Religion," a faith (if that is the word)

    founded on the twin rocks of Locke's declara-

    tion that "the business of laws is not to provide

    for the truth of opinions, but for the safety and se-

    curity of the commonwealth" and Jefferson's more

    colloquial version of the same point: "It does me

    no injury for my neighbor to say that there are

    twenty Gods or no Gods; it neither picks mypocket nor breaks my leg." Jefferson's further con-

    tribution is the famous "Wall of Separation," a

    metaphor that has lent constitutional force to

    the separation of church and state, even though

    it is not in the Constitution. In combination,

    these now canonical statements give us the key

    distinction between the private and the public,

    which in turn gives us the American creed of

    tolerance. It goes like this: If you leave me free to

    believe whatever I like, I'll leave you free to be-

    lieve whatever you like, even though in our re-

    spective hearts we regard each other's beliefs as

    false and ungodly. We can argue about it or pri-

    vately condemn each other, but our differencesof belief shouldn't mean that we try to disen-

    franchise or imprison or kill each other or re-

    frain from entering into relationships of com-

    mercial and social cooperation. Let's live and let

    live. Let's obey the civil, nonsectarian laws and

    leave the sorting out of big theological

    Aquestions to God and eternity.

    11of that is precisely what adherents of the

    Al Qaeda version of Islam hate and categorical-

    ly deny, which is why the question "Is this a reli-

    gious war?" will make no sense to them, or, rather,

    will make only the sense of a question issuing

    from an infidel who is by definition wrong and an

    enemy. Not only do Bin Laden and company failto make the distinction between religious and

    civil acts; they regard those who do make it as per-

    . sons without a true religion. If you're really reli-

    gious, you're religious all the time, and no act you

    perform-even the act of having or not having a

    beard-is without religious significance and jus-

    tification. It is the dividing of one's life into the

    separate realms of the public and private that

    3 6 HARPER'S MAGAZINE / JULY 2 0 02

    leads, say the militants, to a society bereft of

    moral center and populated by citizens incapabl

    of resisting the siren call of excess and sin.

    This refusal of Al Qaeda-style Islam to hono

    the public/private distinction is the essence o

    that faith, and not some incidental feature of

    that can be dispensed with or moderated. Com

    mentators who pronounced on the question "

    this a religious war?" tended to see this and no

    see it at the same time. They noted the fact bu

    then contrived to tum it into a correctable mis

    take, either by using words like "criminal," "fa

    natic," and "extremist" or by implying that th

    non-emergence of the public/private distinction

    is some kind of evolutionary failure; they want t

    be like us, but they don't yet know how to do i

    Thus R. Scott Appleby, a professor at Notre

    Dame and an expert on religion and violence

    notes (in the November 2001 issue of Lingua

    Franca), with an apparently straight face, tha

    "Islam has been remarkably resistant to the dif

    ferentiation and privatization of religion that o

    ten accompanies secularization ... and has not undergone a reformation like the one experienced

    by Christianity, which led to a pronounced sep

    aration of sacred and secular." ("What's the mat

    ter with these guys? Why can't they get with th

    program?") But of course there is nothing re

    markable in a faith's refusal of a transformation

    that would undo it. Privatization and seculariza

    tion are not goals that Islam has yet to achieve

    they are specters that Islam (or some versions o

    it) pushes away as one would push away death.

    Appleby's characterization of Islam as a reli

    gion stuck in some stage of arrested development

    and self-blocked from reaching maturity ismatched

    by Andrew Sullivan's condescending descriptionoflslam (in the October 7 issue ofThe New Yor

    Times Magazine) as "a great religion that isnonethe

    less extremely inexperienced in the toleration o

    other ascendant and more powerful faiths." Pre

    sumably, a good dose of John Stuart Mill or Joh

    Rawls would do the trick and move Islam along o

    .the way to health and modernization.

    When Sullivan says of Islam that it is "a grea

    religion," he means a potentially great religion

    Islam will be fine when it rids itself of its impu

    rities, the chief impurity being a stubborn insis

    tence on a fidelity to a set of particular beliefs. I

    the morality Sullivan shares with Appleby, par

    ticularity is a sin, because it sets up barriers be

    tween persons devoted to different particularsThe better way is the way of generality, of a re

    ligious sense so large and capacious that anything

    and everything can be accommodated within i

    The only problem with such a religion would b

    its total lack of content, but as it turns out tha

    is just what Appleby, Sullivan, and company re

    ally want. It is instructive to watch them as the

    take the heart out of religion in the name of re

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    6/9

    ligion-or, as they put it, "true religion." Of

    course you can't have a true religion without a

    false religion. A false religion, Jane Eisner tells us

    in the Phi lade lph ia Inqu i rer of October 14, is a re-ligion that has "failed to master modernity," and

    the sign of this failure is its insistence on a single

    creed in an age of pluralism. The true religion iswhat Eisner calls "the American national reli-

    gion," which she describes as "our nonsectarian

    belief in the freedom of the individual to think,

    speak, and act in his or her best interests." Here

    Eisner is either disingenuousor unaware of the im-

    plications of her own language. By nonsectarian

    belief she would seem to mean, and probably

    thinks she means, belief not limited to any par-

    ticular religious denomination; but what the

    phrase really means in the context of her essay is

    a belief in the evil of anv sectarian belief what-

    soever, of any belief th~t asserts itself strongly

    and is jealous of its priority. She is not, as she

    would have it, defending all beliefs against an

    intolerant exclusionism but attacking belief in

    general, at least as it commits you to the truth of

    a conviction or the imperative of an action. The

    only good belief is the belief you can wear light-

    ly and shrug off when you leave home and stride

    into the public sphere.

    This issurelywhat Sullivan means (whether he

    knows it or not) when he declares that this "is a

    war of fundamentalism against faiths of all kinds

    that are at peace with freedom and modernity."

    A faith at peace with freedom and modernity is

    a faith that has given up its franchise and has

    made itself into something occasional and cos-

    metic. It is only in the name of such a faith-i-emp-

    tied of all content and committing you to noth-

    ing but the gospel of noncommitment-that

    Sullivan can say, again with a straight face, that

    by denying "the ultimate claims of religion" we

    "preserve true religion itself"; that is, we preserve

    this vague, nonbinding, light-as-air spirituality,

    the chief characteristic of which isthat it claims-

    and believes-nothing.

    Although it may not at firstbe obvious,the sub-

    stitution for real religions of a religion drained of

    particulars is of a piece with the desire to exorcise

    postmodernism. In both instances, what isfeared

    isthe absence of a public spaceor common ground

    in relation to which judgments and determina-

    tions of value can be made with no reference to

    the religious, ethnic, racial, or national identities

    of the persons to whom they apply. It should, to

    Sullivan's way of thinking, be obvious to all,

    including those Muslims not blinded by fanati-

    cism, that Bin Laden and his followers are crim-

    inal terrorists and not religious freedom fighters;

    and if they quote the Koran at us and rehearse his-

    tories in which we are the oppressors and vil-

    lains, that just means that they are misreading

    h i i i i h i hi

    tory, and we have the experts at Johns Hopkins,

    George Washington, and Yale universities to

    prove it. This can't be a religious war. It must be

    a war of common sense or common ground

    against the fanatical and the

    "T irrational.

    , 'hat must be protected, then, is the gener-

    al, the possibilityof making pronouncements from

    a perspective at once detached from and superi-

    or to the sectarian perspectives of particular na-

    tional interests, ethnic concerns, and religious

    obligations; and the threat to the general is posed

    by postmodernism and

    strong religiosityalike,post-

    modernism because its cri-

    tique of master narratives

    deprivesus of a mechanism

    for determining which of

    two or more fiercely held

    beliefs is true (which is not

    to deny the category of true

    belief, just the possibility

    of identifying it uncontroversially), strong reli-

    giosity because it insists on its own norms and re-

    fusescorrection from the outside. The antidote to

    both is the separation of the private from the pub-

    lic, the establishing of a public sphere to which all

    could have recourseand to the judgments of which

    all, who are not criminal or insane, would assent.

    The point of the public sphere is obvious: it is

    supposed to be the location of those standards

    and measures that belong to no one but apply to

    everyone. It is to be the location of the universal.

    The problem is not that there isno universal-the

    universal, the absolutely true, exists, and I know

    what it is. The problem is that you know, too,

    and that we know different things, which puts us

    right back where we were a few sentences ago,

    armed with universal judgments that are irrec-

    oncilable, all dressedup and nowhere to go for an

    authoritative adjudication.

    What to do? Well, you do the only thing you

    can do, the only honest thing: you assert that

    your universal is the true one, even though your

    adversariesclearly do not accept it, and you do not

    attribute their recalcitrance to insanity or mere

    criminality-the desired public categories of con-

    demnation-but to the fact, regrettable as it may

    be, that they are in the grip of a set of beliefs

    that is false. And there you have to leave it, be-

    cause the next step, the step of proving the false-

    ness of their beliefs to everyone, including those

    in their grip, is not a step available to us as finite

    situated human beings. We have to live with the

    knowledge of two things: that we are absolutely

    right and that there is no generally accepted mea-

    sure by which our rightness can be independently

    validated. That's just the way it is, and we should

    " I S THIS A RELIGIOUS WAR?"

    NOT A QUESTION ABOUT THE

    WAR; IT IS THE QUESTION

    THAT IS THE WAR

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    7/9

    true beliefs (what else could we do?) without ex-

    pecting that some God will descend, like the

    duck in the old Groucho Marx TV show, and

    tell us that we have uttered the true

    rJ" and secret word.

    . ! h e distinction I am trying to make here is notbetween affirminguniversalsand denying them but

    between affirming universals because you strong-

    ly believe them to be such and affirming univer-

    sals because you believe them to have been cer-

    tified by an independent authority acknowledged

    by everyone. Andrew Sullivan teeters between

    these different affirmationswhen he declaresin the

    concluding paragraph of his

    essay that "Weare fighting

    not for our country ... or for

    our flag.Weare fighting for

    the universal principles of

    our Constitution." Is Sulli-

    van here identifying and

    standing by his conviction

    . of what the universal prin-

    ciples are, or is he claiming that it is not his con-

    viction but the world itself that has identified

    them? If he is doing the first, he is acknowledging

    that this is a religious war and that it is our reli-

    gion (embodied, he thinks, in the Constitution)

    against theirs, not their religion against common

    sense. If he is doing the second, he is saying that

    this is a war between the world's religions and

    those crazy outlaws the world universally con-

    demns. His penultimate sentence removes the

    doubt: "Weare fighting for religion against one of

    the deepest strains in religion there is."The deep-

    est strain in a religion is the particular and par-

    ticularistic doctrine it asserts at its heart, in the

    company of such pronouncements as 'Thou shalt

    have no other Gods before me." Take the deep-

    est strain of religion away,as Sullivan wants us to

    do, and what remains are the surface pieties-

    abstractions without substantive bite-

    to which everyone will assent because

    Ithey are empty, insipid, and safe.

    t is this same preference for the vacuouslygen-

    eral over the disturbingly particular that informs

    the attacks on college and university professors

    who spoke out in ways that led them to be brand-

    ed as outcasts by those who were patrolling and

    monitoring the narrow boundaries of acceptable

    speech. Here one must be careful, for there are

    fools and knaves on all sides. On the fool side,

    there is the case of Richard Berthold, the hapless

    University of New Mexico professor of history

    who said in class,on September II, "Anyone who

    can blow up the Pentagon has my vote"-and

    then in the wake of the subsequent protest ac-

    knowledged that he had been a jerk to say it, but,

    f ll " h Fi A d i h

    To SILENCE PROFESSORS WHO

    CROSS AN INVISIBLE LINE IS TO

    NARROW THE DISCOURSE TO A

    FORM OF CHEERLEADING

    to be a jerk." Well, yes and no; the First Amend

    ment does protect him from prosecution by th

    government-unless his formof jerkiness could b

    characterized as libel, incitement to violence, o

    treason-but it does not necessarily protect him

    from disciplinary action by his university if it can

    be determined that what he said amounted to using class time and state dollars to propagate hi

    own political views and thereby undermined hi

    ability to fulfill his appointed duties.

    On the knave side, there isthe politicallymurk

    but conceptually clear case of Sami Al-

    Arian, a professor of computer engineering at the

    University of South Florida, who has been sent

    letter of dismissal because he appeared on Th eO'Reilly Factor, a crime of which I am also guiltyThe university saysthat he is being dismissed no

    because of the views he expressed over a decade

    ago but because the public airing of them pro

    duced a hostile response that took the form othreats from individuals, potential donors, politi

    cians, and trustees;but this iswhat isknown as th

    "heckler's veto" argument-speech is to be si

    lenced or punished because of the actual or po

    tential hostile response to it-an argument re

    jected by a long line of Supreme Court decision

    and almost certain to be rejected again.

    Closer to my home, the University of Illinoi

    at Chicago and Northwestern University hav

    been more adept than South Florida in dealing

    with the cases of Bill Ayers and Bernardine

    Dohrn-one-time Weathermen, fugitives, and

    most-wanted celebrities, and now married,

    middle-class, and distinguished professors-who

    are under firefor actions performedthirty yearsag

    and no longer the object of judicial attention. A

    both universities saw,the only question iswhethe

    Ayers and Dohrn are currently living up to thei

    contractual duties and doing their jobs; and sinc

    the evidence saysclearly that they are, there is n

    case. Contrition for acts long past and not presen

    ly under indictment is not a legal or even a mora

    requirement for university teaching.

    It would be pleasant to linger over these an

    other cases and tease out the doctrines they il

    lustrate, but what finally interests me about them

    is their link to the pattern I have been describ

    ing, the pattern of demonizing the particularism

    of local and partisan perspectives (either philo

    sophical or religious) in favor of a general per

    spective that claims to be universal and has th

    advantage of disturbing no one because it is a

    once safe and empty. The effort of those wh

    would silence or dismiss professors who cros

    some invisible line is at bottom an effort to nar

    row the range of what can be said to a rote pa

    triotic discourse that is a form of cheerleading

    rather than serious thought. This is in fact th

    naked thesis ofW hy We Fight: Moral C larity an

    h b f f d

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    8/9

    cation-and author, at least by his own claim, of

    all the Virtues-William Bennett. In this book

    we learn that the problems not only of the cur-

    rent moment but of the last forty years stem from

    the cultural ascendancy of those "who are unpa-

    triotic" but who, unfortunately, are also "the most

    influential among us." The phrase "among us" is

    a nice illustration of the double game Bennett

    plays throughout the book. On one reading, "thediversity mongers [and] rnulticulturalists," mis-

    taken though they may be in their views, are part

    of "us"; that is, they are citizens, contributing to

    a national dialogue in ways that might provoke

    Bennett's disagreement but contributing never-

    theless in the spirit of deliberative democracy.

    On another reading, however, these cultural rel-

    ativists are "among us" as a fifth column might be

    among us, servants of an alien power who pros-

    ecute their subversive agenda under the false col-

    ors of citizenship. That the second is the reading

    Bennett finally intends (though he wants to get

    moral credit for the first) is made clear when he

    charges these peddlers of "relativism" with un-patriotism, and in that instant defines a patriot as

    someone who has the same views he has.

    This also turns out to be Bennett's definition of

    honesty and truth-telling. As the remedy for what

    he and his allies see as the moral enervation of the

    country, Bennett urges "the reinstatement of a

    thorough and honest study of our history," where

    by "honest" he means a study of history that tells

    the same story he and his friends would tell if

    they were in control of the nation's history de-

    partments. Unfortunately (at least as he sees it),

    history departments are full of people like Co-

    lumbia's Eric Foner, who draws Bennett's ire for

    wondering which is worse, "'the horror that en-

    gulfed New York City or the apocalyptic rhetoric

    emanating daily from the White House.''' Rennett

    calls this sentiment "atrocious rot." Maybe it is,

    maybe it isn't, but even if it were atrocious rot, it

    could be honest atrocious rot; that is, it could be

    Foner's honest attempt, as a citizen and historian,

    to take the truthful measure of what the events of

    September 11 and their aftermath mean ..But Ben-

    nett's epistemology does not allow for the possi-

    bility that someone could honestly put forward as

    the truth of a matter an account that differed

    from his. If Foner and all the other "Foners of the

    United States" say things about American histo-

    ry that do not square with the things Bennett and

    Donald Kagan (his hero-historian) say, it mustbe because they are self-conscious enemies of the

    good and the true. They are not merely mistaken

    (which is how we usually characterize those on the

    opposite side of us in what John Milton called

    the "wars of truth"); they are "insidious," they are

    engaged in "violent misrepresentation," they prac-

    tice "distortion," they "sow widespread and de-

    bilitating confusion," they "weaken the country's

    resolve," they exhibit "failures of character," they

    drown out "legitimate patriots" (guess who), they

    display a "despicable nature," they abandon, yes,

    "the honest search for truth."

    This long list of hit-and-run accusations is jus-

    tified in Bennett's eyes because the persons at

    whom it is directed would give different answers

    than he would to questions still being honestly de-

    bated after these many months. It is one thing tobelieve, and believe fervently, that someone has

    got something wrong; it is quite another to believe

    that the someone you think to be wrong is by

    virtue of that error unpatriotic, devoted to lies,

    and downright evil. It has often been the case that

    religions have identified sacred texts and sacred

    persons as the repositories of wisdom and truth

    and have consigned to the deepest circles of hell

    persons who read from another book or assert

    truths contrary to those declared necessary for

    salvation. But I did not know that there was now

    a Book of Bennett, and that the teachers and in-

    tellectuals who inhabit our universities were

    obliged to rehearse its lessons and recite its cat-echisms, lest they be drummed out of the

    Republ ic and cast into outer darkness.

    ~ Live and learn.

    Lere is a tension in Bennett's book--one

    common to jeremiads on the right-between

    his frequent assertions that our cultural condi-

    tion couldn't be worse and his equally frequent

    assertions that the vast majority of Americans

    thinks as he does. How can the enemy at once

    be so small in number and so disastrously ef-

    fective? The answer is to be found in the fact

    that this small band controls our colleges and

    universities, and the result is the "utter failure

    of our institutions of higher learning," a failure

    the product of which is a generation of college

    students ignorant of our history and imbued

    with the virus of "cultural and moral rela-

    tivism." What to do? One proposal put forward

    by some of Bennett's allies-and a surprising

    one given the free-market propensities of this

    crowd-amounts to affirmative action for con-

    servatives. If the professoriat is predominantly

    liberal, let's do something about it and redress

    the imbalance. (Does this sound like rnulticul-

    rural ism and diversity?) David Horowitz-

    once a virulent left-wing editor of Ramparts

    and now a virulent right-wing editor of Hetero-

    doxy--eomplains, for example, that there are"whole departments in the social sciences

    where there are no conservatives," despite the

    fact that "the point of a university is that it

    should be a place of dialogue" (as long, pre-

    sumably, as it is not a dialogue about this war,

    in which case what we want is uniformity of

    opinion, one-sided opinion). But if the univer-

    sity is a place of dialogue (and I certainly

    E SS AY

  • 8/3/2019 Fish in Harpers

    9/9

    think it is) it is supposed to be a dialogue be-

    tween persons of differing views on discipli-

    nary issues-Is Satan the hero ofParadise Lost?

    Is there such a thing as Universal Grammar?

    What historical factors led to the Reform Bill

    . of 1832? Could World War I have been avoid-

    ed?-and not a dialogue between persons who

    identify themselves as Democrats or Republi-

    cans. That dialogue takes place in the arenasof elections, lobbying, and political fund-rais-

    ing, and while there may be some overlap be-

    tween academic disagreements and disagree-

    ments in the realm of partisan politics, the

    overlap is not structural, even if it is statisti-

    cally significant; moreover, altering it is not an

    academic imperative, because it is not the

    business of the academy to assure proportional

    representation of different political positions.

    But what about affirmative action? someone

    might ask. By this argument, it isn't the business

    of the academy to assure proportional represen-

    tation of women, blacks, and Hispanics either. No

    disciplinary concern demands such arJ"' correction, so what's the difference?

    ~e difference is an historical one. For decades

    and indeed centuries, women, blacks, and His-

    panics have been actively excluded from the

    academy, and while one might debate whether or

    not universities have an obligation to redress past

    inequities, the effort to do so can be given at

    least a plausible historical justification. No such

    justification is available to support affirmative

    action for conservatives, who have never been ex-

    cluded, and in fact were once greatly in the as-

    cendancy, and who are no longer in the ascen-

    dancy in some disciplines because they have

    chosen to go into others. It would be interesting. to study why humanities departments do not by

    and large attract the politically conservative, but

    I would bet that such a study would not reveal that

    they have been denied entry or badly treated

    when they have attained it. The case for bring-

    ing more conservatives into the humanities and

    social sciences is a nonstarter.

    The second, and related, argument invoked

    to justify the current spate of professor-bashing has

    a bit more going for it, as evidenced by the fact

    that it has been made across the political sp~c-

    trum, from Stanley Kurtz, a contributing editor for

    the National Review, to David Glenn, writing in

    The Nation. It is the argument that the professo-riat is reaping what it sowed in those years when

    so many of its members (including, no doubt,

    some now facing criticism an.ddiscipline) worked

    for the implementation of campus speech codes.

    The chickens are just coming home to roost. (Ex-

    actly the line of thought so vehemently rejected

    by the gatekeepers of our patriotism.)

    Aside from a certain historical inaccuracy-

    40 HAR PER' S MAGAZINE! JULY 2002

    most speech codes were never implemented, and

    none has survived judicial scrutiny-the logic de

    ployed by Kurtz and Glenn is flawed in what

    should now be seen as a familiar way: it depends

    on a general equivalence that takes no notice o

    the relevant historical differences. The equiva-

    lence is supposed to be between disciplining and/or

    stigmatizing persons because they have produced

    speech hurtful to women, blacks, Hispanics, andgays, and disciplining and/or stigmatizing persons

    because they have produced speech deemed to

    be politically inappropriate. If you were for the firs

    kind of regulation, the logic goes-i.e., if you sup

    ported speech codes-you have no complaint

    when you become the object of the second. Bu

    this works only if one assumes that all restrictions

    on expression have the same status (a universal-

    izing, flattening assumption that generated the

    category of reverse racism), and that assumption

    runs up against the tradition of the First Amend-

    ment, in which one restriction-the restriction on

    speech critical of government policies-has al

    ways been regarded as a violation of the amend-ment's core.

    What this means is that restraints on political

    speech and restraints on what has been called

    hate speech are simply not the same thing--one

    restraint nullifies the First Amendment at it

    heart, while the other is arguably faithful to it

    spirit, though the point is contested-and are no

    interchangeable as pieces of cultural currency.

    The real equivalent to hate-speech restriction

    would have to be a restriction on a form of speech

    that, like hate speech, has a disputed constitu-

    tional status. So if a professor were for speech

    codes but against restrictions on pornography, hemight be asked to address what would seem to b

    a contradiction. But there is no contradiction inbeing against restrictions on speech critical of the

    government and in favor of restrictions on pornog

    raphy, because speech critical of the government

    stands alone as indisputably protected and there-

    fore cannot be in a relation of equivalence to

    speech of any other kind. No matter what those

    professors thought or didn't think about speech

    codes, their right to be critical of their government

    remains their undoubted possession. That is wha

    the Constitution says and has alway

    Asaid.

    summary, then, and a scorecard: Is post

    modernism either dead or one of the causes of oupresent distress? No. Is this a religious war? You

    bet. Are professors as a class unpatriotic and thu

    deserving of the condemnation William Bennett

    and so many others rain down on them for the

    crime of saying things these pundits don't like?No

    again. Can the complex reality of particular sit

    uations be captured by the abstract vocabulary o

    so-called universals? No, in thunder.