for utopia: the (limits of the) utopian function in

Upload: anonymous-hkexcf

Post on 24-Feb-2018

224 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    1/20

    Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found athttp://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=fcri20

    Download by:["Queen's University Libraries, Kingston"] Date:10 February 2016, At: 17:18

    Critical Review of International Social and PoliticalPhilosophy

    ISSN: 1369-8230 (Print) 1743-8772 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fcri20

    For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function inlate capitalist society

    Ruth Levitas

    To cite this article:Ruth Levitas (2000) For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in late

    capitalist society, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 3:2-3, 25-43,DOI: 10.1080/13698230008403311

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13698230008403311

    Published online: 25 Sep 2007.

    Submit your article to this journal

    Article views: 458

    View related articles

    Citing articles: 3 View citing articles

    http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/13698230008403311#tabModulehttp://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/13698230008403311#tabModulehttp://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/13698230008403311http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/13698230008403311http://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=fcri20&page=instructionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=fcri20&page=instructionshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13698230008403311http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/13698230008403311http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fcri20http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=fcri20
  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    2/20

    For Utopia:

    The

    (Limits

    of the)

    Utopian Function

    in

    Late Capitalist

    Society

    RUTH LEVITAS

    This article isabout the uses of Utopia,and the usesof Utopian studies,

    in the present historical conjuncture: under conditionsof late modernity,

    at

    the

    start

    of a new

    millennium.

    It

    argues that these conditions

    (particularly,

    but not

    only, w hat might

    be

    called

    the

    'pos tm odern turn '

    in

    social and cultural theory) pose very fundamental challenges to the

    project and projection ofUtopia. Responsesto these emergent challenges

    canbeseen inchanges in Utopian thinking, including Utopian texts, over

    the past 30 years,and in thetheo risation of Utopia, the stuff of Utopian

    studiesitself. These transformations involve agreater p rovisiona l ly and

    reflexivityof theUtopian m ode ,and a marked shift from anem phasison

    representation

    or

    content

    to an

    emphasis

    on

    process. While

    it can be

    argued that these changes demonstrate the continuing strength of

    utopianism, astrong casecan alsobe madefor anopposite view: thatthe

    ways in which Utopians and utopists (those who study Utopia) have

    responded to thecondition of late modernity reflect aweakeningof the

    transformative potential of Utopia. Utopia survives, but at a cost, and

    that cost is the retreat of the Utopian function from transformation to

    critique.

    1

    Why Study Utopia?

    The article is also a defence of Utopia, and a claim for the necessity of

    taking

    it

    seriously.

    The

    title begs several questions.

    The

    term 'utopian

    function' raises

    the

    question 'what

    is

    Utopia for?' . 'For' , here, carries

    the

    sense of instrumentality or purpose attributed to Utopia itself. For

    Utopia' assertsacommitment to Utopian studies,and toUtopia itself, on

    my own part , and presumes such acomm i tmen t on the part of Utopian

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    3/20

    26 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    scholars or utopists. Implicitly, therefore, it asks what Utopian studies is

    for. This is dangerous ground: the April 1999 British Sociological

    Association conference had the theme 'What is Sociology For?'. Laurie

    Taylor (1999, p.56) wrote a (spoof) abstract of a paper by Doctor D.W.

    Haberperson entitled 'What is "For" For?':

    This convoluted paper examines the rhetorical assumptions

    implicated within the interrogative formulation, 'What is Sociology

    For?'.After an almost interminable introduction in which repeated

    references are made to Derrida, Lacan and Foucault, the author

    proceeds to delineate the socio-cultural circumstances and

    epistemic regimes that are an essentialist precondition for framing

    a question about an academic discipline that rests upon the implied

    instrumentality of the word 'for'. No conclusions whatsoever are

    reached.

    There are different reasons why intellectuals and academics might be

    interested in studying Utopia. First, since Utopia is the expression of what

    is missing, of the experience of lack in any given society or culture,

    understanding the Utopian aspirations generated by any society is an

    important part of understanding that society

    itself.

    The study of Utopia

    is an essential part of cultural anthropology or the history or sociology

    of culture. Utopianism is proper material for historians, anthropologists,

    sociologists, and for cultural studies. In so far as Utopia takes the form of

    a literary text, it becomes material for literary criticism of various kinds.

    Second, Utopia in the sense of a counterfactual model of all or part of a

    social or political system, may be used as a heuristic device, as an

    exploration of what might be possible or impossible, or in normative

    social theory, as a regulative ideal against which the real world can be

    measured. Third, we may study Utopia, in terms of its content or its

    effects in the world, because we believe the aspirations of others, and

    their attempts to articulate the features of a good society, constitute a

    resource for us in our own pursuit of the good society.

    My suspicion (and my experience) is that most utopists are also to

    some extent Utopians. My own interest in Utopia (and, indeed, in

    sociology) has always been driven by the conviction tha t the worid could

    and should be other than it is. But this does raise questions about the

    proper role of academics. Whereas the first two reasons for an interest

    in Utopia are safe and uncontentious, because they do not require

    commitment to political change, the third reason presumes political

    engagement. More than that, it presumes that political engagement is a

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    4/20

    UTOPIAN FUNCTION

    IN

    LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY

    27

    core element, even the core purpose, of this particular field of

    intellectual enquiry. Academia, however, is inclined to justify its

    existence and its call on the public purse precisely on the grounds of

    being politically neutral

    and

    disengaged. There

    may,

    therefore,

    be a

    tension between

    the

    dema nds placed

    on us as

    academics

    and

    those placed

    on us as engaged intellectuals.

    2

    This tension is not peculiar to utopists,

    butmay be peculiarly acute for usbecauseof Utopia's 'radical otherness'

    and becauseof the potential functions of Utopian thinking.

    The Functions

    o

    Utopia

    The three possible approaches

    to the

    study

    of

    Utopia

    are

    roughly

    paral le led by the different possible functions of Utopia itself.

    Distinguishing these functions dependson thedefinition ofUtopia itself,

    w ithout which no sensible discussion cantake place. Th ere is a tendency

    to think of Utopia as being one of two things: either a totalitarian

    political project, or a literary genre of fictions about perfect societies.

    Both these approaches are very different from that of Ernst Bloch

    (1986),

    whose 1400-pageDas

    Prinzip Hoffnung

    The

    Principle

    of

    Hope)

    is

    the

    most important theoretical treatment

    of

    Utopia. Bloch's argument

    was that the propensity to reach for a better life ism anifest in everyday

    life, in popular culture, in 'high' culture, and in religion. It is a way of

    expressing the experience of lack, of dissatisfaction, of ' something 's

    missing', in the actuality of human existence. Expressions of Utopian

    longingare notnecessarily pro fou nd :at onepointhew rote 'm ost people

    in the street look as if they are thinking about something else entirely.

    The something else

    is

    predominantly money,

    but

    also what

    it

    could

    be

    changed into. ' (Bloch,

    1986,

    p.33.) Following from Bloch,

    it is

    possible

    to develop a broad definition of Utopia which encompasses this rangeof

    Utopian expression: namely, that Utopia is the expression of the desire

    for a better way of being. Such a definition is analytic rather than

    descriptive, that is, it enables one to look at the Utopian aspects of

    cultural forms rather than classify them into Utopian or notUtopian(and

    is thus singularly

    and

    properly unhelpful

    in

    sett ing boundaries

    for

    'utopian studies').

    But it

    enables

    us to ask

    questions about

    the

    historical

    shiftsin the content, form, location and function ofUtopia,and theways

    in which specific social and historical circumstances encourage or block

    different kindsof Utopian expression and sensibility.

    3

    The suggestion that Utopia

    is

    expressive immediately calls into

    question the idea that it is for anything:is it, perhaps, expressive rather

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    5/20

    28 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    than instrumental? To talk about the function of ideas or institutions is

    always to risk confusing purpose and effect, and there is some point in

    separating these. For while the expression of lack and of desire may have

    no purpose beyond

    itself,

    no deliberate instrumentality, it may

    nonetheless have political effects. In this sense, we can think of Utopia as

    potentially having three functions: compensation, critique and change.

    'Nowhere, the place of our own',

    4

    may simply be somewhere that we go

    to as an escape: into our daydreams about winning the lottery, and thus

    perhaps having the resources to escape physically. Most lottery winners

    buy a new house - and this can be seen as the creation of a personal

    Utopian enclave, as was Monet's garden at Giverny. On a smaller scale,

    endless television programmes, such asChanging

    Rooms, Ground

    Force

    and

    Charlie s

    Army, are dedicated to the transformation of homes and

    gardens - programm es which have the additional fantasy element of

    someone else doing the work. The other escape dreamed of by millions

    and favoured by lottery winners is travel: the travel industry is probably

    the most significant repository of compensatory Utopian dreams, and

    advertises itself in explicitly Utopian, or at least paradisaical, terms. This

    dreaming transforms only the dreamer's place in the world, not the

    world itself - or not directly or intentionally, although of course both

    the travel industry and the DIY industry have profound physical, social

    and economic effects both locally and globally.

    Utopia may be more critical than this. It is implicit in Bloch's

    argument that even the most com pensatory of Utopian fantasies has some

    critical function, as it articulates the sense that the present is

    unsatisfactory. But Utopia as critique (as, for example, in More's Utopia)

    foregrounds this and makes it explicit. Identifying the problem as

    somehow more general than one's own position in the world is a

    necessary, but by no means sufficient, condition for Utopia's third

    function, that of catalysing change. Utopia's strongest function, its claim

    to being important rather than a matter of esoteric fascination and

    charm, is its capacity to inspire the pursuit of a world transformed, to

    embody hope rather than simply desire.

    Furthermore, if there is a tension between the intellectual and

    political motivations of utopists, so there is a tension between the

    expressive and instrumental functions of Utopia, between desire and

    hope. Part of the appeal of Bloch's work is that he insists on the

    importance of all forms of dreaming of a better life, all forms of thinking

    beyond the present, including those that are pre-political expressions of

    desire. But his major work was called

    The

    Principle

    of

    HOPE.Bloch, like

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    6/20

    UTOPIAN FU NC TIO N IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 29

    all other utopists for whom the ultimate value of Utopia lay in its

    transformative potential, was forced to make a distinction between

    wishful and will-full thinking, between abstract and concrete Utopia,

    which is ultimately a distinction between desire and hope.

    5

    Raymond

    Williams argued that the willed transformation of the social world was

    an essential characteristic of the Utopian mode, and that without this

    there was the danger of Utopia settling into 'isolated and in the end

    sentimental "desire", a mode of living with alienation' (1980, p.203);

    one of his pieces was called

    Resources For A Journey Of H ope,

    and a

    posthumous collection simply Resources of Hope.

    Challenges to U topia: O ld An ti-Utopianism

    Where are we now placed in relation to these possible functions of

    Utopia, and the distinction between desire and hope? The year 1999 saw

    the publication of at least three anthologies of Utopias: John Carey's

    Faber Book of Utopias; a Penguin volume, simply called Utopias (Kelly,

    1999) ; and Claeys and Sargent's The Utopia Reader. The Centre for the

    Human Sciences at Durham and the Critical Theory Group at Bristol

    conducted seminar series on Utopia and the millennium. There was an

    inter natio nal co nference called 'A M illenn ium of U top ias' at the

    University of East Anglia in June. Despite this upsurge of interest in

    utopianism, and despite much millennial hype, popular social thought

    does no t app ear to be filled with Utopian hop es for the future -

    apocalypse, yes; Utopia, not so obviously. Apocalyptic fears were

    attached to the 'Y2K bug', although in the event, disaster failed to

    strike;

    6

    and the survivalist movement (especially in the USA) had a new

    lease of life as people stockpiled supplies for the millennium. In April

    1999 ,

    there were two apocalyptic and dystopian series running on

    British terrestrial television. One was

    The Tribe,

    in which all adults are

    wiped out by a mystery virus, leaving young people to form themselves

    into scavenging bands and warring gangs, or simply to hang out

    streetwise in semi-derelict shopping malls. The other was The Last Train,

    in which the world is destroyed by a meteorite. A group of passengers in

    a train in a tunnel between Chesterfield and Sheffield are cryogenically

    preserved thanks to a canister of gas released by one of them, and thaw

    out 50 years later for an action-packed journey through ruins.

    Admittedly, Utopia is resurrected right at the end, since the protagonists

    discover that ' the ones we were running from are the ones we were

    looking for', and hostilities (including a couple of crucifixions) are ended

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    7/20

    30 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    by the prospect of new hope for the future symbolised by a baby (or two)

    and a bit of new age music. Perhaps this does distinguish millennial

    dreams from those of the 1980s. The last apocalyptic television drama

    set in Sheffield was the post-nuclear Threads, which also ended with a

    birth, but the final shot was of the mother's horrified scream at the sight

    of her child. Cinema in the 1990s is replete with images of Utopia as

    dystopia, as in

    The Truman Show

    and

    Pleasantville,

    or straightforward

    dystopias such as

    Dark City

    and

    The Matrix

    - the latter being the cult

    video sold in huge numbers for Christmas 1999 in the UK.

    7

    True, the

    hugely popular film Antz has a Utopian them e, but ' insectop ia' is a

    rubbish heap, and the clear reference to Metropolis in the ant world itself

    is satirical. These trends need not reflect unremitting pessimism: as

    Rafaella Baccolini (1999) argues, 'the critical dystopia is the preferred

    form of resistance at the end of the century'; but resistance and survival,

    rather than transformation and redemption, are the best that can be

    hoped for. Despite the millennium, we may be said to live in dystopian

    t imes,

    in that both reality and most projections for the future are deeply

    depressing or downright terrifying.

    These are also anti-utopian times. Russell Jacoby (1999) deplores

    The End of Utopia,

    the absence of any transforming imagination or

    energy in contemporary political culture. Anti-utopianism involves an

    active denial of the merits of imagining alternative ways of living,

    particularly if they constitute serious attempts to argue that the world

    might or should be otherw ise. Political anti-utopianism was intensified at

    the end of the 198 0s. W he n the com m unist regimes of eastern E urop e

    collapsed, there were repeated references to the 'end of Utopia' . The

    discourse of Anglo-American news coverage contained implicit (and

    sometimes explicit) equations:

    Utopia = Totalitarianism = Co m m unism = M arxism = Socialism

    and

    Co m m unism = Totalitarianism = Fascism.

    Some ten years on, the spate of television programmes representing

    those events as history was framed within the same discourse. The BBC's

    W ar of the Century

    argu ed th at the massive loss of life (both military a nd

    civilian) in the nazi invasion of the Soviet Union was as much Stalin's

    fault as Hitler's, despite fascinating archive footage and contemporary

    testimony which suggested rather the reverse. In addition, almost on the

    eve of the millennium, Channel 4 broadcast Hitler and Stalin: Twin

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    8/20

    UTOPIAN FU NC TIO N IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 31

    Tyrants, a lengthy interwoven parallel biogr aphy - althou gh this did

    mention in passing that some people still thought that there were

    important and substantive differences between the two. Partly as a result

    of this discourse, capitalism is widely held to be the only game in town,

    and the range of political alternatives in much of Europe has narrowed

    to disputations about the true third way: Clinton, Blair, and Schroeder

    versus Lafontaine a nd Jospin . P ost-19 89 , it might be said th at w e live, in

    an almost biblical sense, after the fall, but with no hope of redemption.

    On the other hand, it is arguable that this kind of anti-utopianism is a

    constant feature of the dominant ideology, even if its targets change, and

    that Utopian currents are identifiable in the growth of nationalism, in

    green ideas and movements, and elsewhere. The third way might be

    analysed as a Utopia, and is occasionally represented by its proponents as

    such (Giddens, 1995; 1998). However, this is best understood as the

    incorporation and suppression of utopianism, rather than an opening up

    to its radical and transformative potential. What is asserted here as

    permissible, for instance in Rorty's (1998) endorsement of 'romantic

    uto pian ism ', is a pragm atic, limited reformism - th e very pragma tism

    which is essentially anti-utopian in its rejection of radical Utopian

    otherness or fundamental social t ransformation. Even Immanuel

    Wallerstein rejects utopianism in favour of what he terms 'utopistics'

    (that is, possible, 'realistic' futures), although his pragmatism is less

    reformist than Rorty's since he still apparently believes in some kind of

    cataclysmic collapse of global capitalism. The terms of Wallerstein's

    rejection of Utopia are conventional:

    The real problem with all Utopias ... is not only that they have

    existed nowhere heretofore but that they seem to me, and to many

    others, dreams of heaven that could never exist on earth. Utopias

    have religious functions and they can also sometimes be

    mechanisms of political mobilisation. But politically they tend to

    rebound. For Utopias are breeders of illusions and therefore,

    inevitably, of disillusions. And Utopias can be used, have been used,

    as justifications for terrible wrongs. The last thing we really need is

    more Utopian visions. (Wallerstein, 1999, p.l.)

    Challenges to Utopia: Postmodernity and Utopia

    The political case against Utopia is not new. It argues that where there is

    vision, the pe ople pe rish. It imp utes to Utopia bot h a claim to perfection,

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    9/20

    32 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    which is then dismissed as impossible, and the imposition of uniformity

    on Utopia's inhabitants, rejected as immoral. It argues that Utopia can be

    realised only by violence and maintained only by political repression.

    Utopia is totalitarian. These arguments are familiar, and the responses to

    them have been frequently rehearsed. Utopian writers do not all claim

    that their systems are perfect; usually, just that they are considerably

    better than those actually prevailing at the time of writing. Not all

    Utopias are totalitarian; some, indeed (and William Morris's N ews from

    Nowhere

    is conventionally cited here, but M arge Piercy's

    Wom an on the

    Edge of Time

    would be a more recent example) are quite the reverse.

    Furthermore, Jacoby argues strongly that the attribution of the genocidal

    consequences of nazism and Stalinism to 'utopianism' is historically

    sloppy, not to say ideological.

    A much more interesting set of challenges (more interesting

    because more ambiguous, and both theoretical and political) arises

    from the condition of postmodernity. Here, the negative consequences

    of Utopia are attributed to the pitfalls of modernity, in particular,

    to the post-Enlightenment insistence on reason and universal values,

    which is potentially totalitarian. The challenges revolve around

    questions of hope and desire, and the distinction between them.

    Postmodernity and postmodernism are such broadly used terms that a

    little clarification may be in order. The term 'postmodernity' can be

    used to refer to a structural change in the nature of the society we live

    in, or a broad cultural, political and theoretical condition which results

    from this structural change, or a narrower artistic or aesthetic

    movement more properly termed 'postmodernism', or any combination

    of these. The question of the relationship between postmodernity and

    modernity, or postmodernism and modernism, has occupied many

    hours of scholarly time and will doubtless figure prominently in many

    RAE returns (the RAE is the British university system's 'Research

    Assessment Exercise', on the basis of which state funding is distributed)

    as well as having caused the destruction of a large number of trees. In

    all three senses, and especially at the structural level, what is called

    postmodernity can be seen to be an intensification and continuation of

    trends within modernism, as much as a sharp break from it.

    Furthermore, especially at the structural level, it may be preferable to

    talk about late modernity or even late capitalism. Thus postmodernity

    in the broad cultural sense, and postmodernism in the narrower sense,

    can be seen, as Fredric Jameson (1984; 1991) argues, as the cultural

    logic of late capitalism.

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    10/20

    UTOPIAN FUNCTION IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 33

    To say that postmodernity presents a challenge to Utopia is not an

    uncontroversial statement. Tobin Siebers, for example, argues that far

    from this being the case, postmodernism embraces Utopia, that indeed

    'utopia has emerged as the high concept of postmodernism' (1994,

    p p . 2 - 3 ) . Utopia is essentially about desire, and 'postmodernism turns on

    questions of desire' . Aesthetics is central to postmodern theory because

    objects of art are 'al legories of desire ' . Desire is central to

    postmodernism. This is certainly born out by Deleuze and Guattari 's

    Anti-Oedipus

    (1984), one of postm odern ism 's founding texts, which was

    first published in 1972. Deleuze and Guattari object to both Freudian

    and Lacanian psychoanalytic theory. The Oedipal triangle, they argue, is

    a formulaic representation which does not describe the 'natural '

    development of desire, frustration, and healthy transcendence or

    otherwise. Rather, Freudian psychoanalysis demands that we understand

    our blocked desires in terms of the Oedipus myth, which both constrains

    and denies our experience, and proves our desires to have been

    illegitimate in the first place. Desire should be understood as a much

    more various complex of libidinal flows, and indeed substantive flows of

    milk, shit and semen (it is a very androcentric text). Desire is not

    oriented solely sexually, nor is it oriented to parental figures, but to

    fragmentary, partial objects. Their argument also differs from Lacan in

    two ways. The centrality of the phallus, like the Oedipal triangle, is a

    totalising myth, which denies the fragmented character of flows of

    desire. Moreover, it intrinsically links desire to lack, a formulation which

    Deleuze and Guattari repeatedly oppose (Deleuze and Guattari , 1984;

    Goodchild, 1996).

    Desire is also central to utopianism. But Williams (1980, p.200)

    argues , perha ps in implicit response t o D eleuze, 'We cannot ab stract desire.

    It is always desire for something specific, in specifically impelling

    circumstances.' Bloch does connect desire with lack. 'What is missing' is

    central not only to Bloch, but to most of critical theory. For Bloch, the

    importance of Utopian imagining, even abstract Utopia, is precisely that it

    is difficult to identify a lack, a desire, other than in terms of what

    might fulfil it. Re presentation is thu s the first step to fulfilment, altho ugh

    representation is also usually (and perhaps necessarily) misrepresentation.

    Arguably, Utopia requires the representation, the objectification, of

    desire. In Siebers' collection, Utopia is focused on the body as the locus

    of desire and human happiness. One might argue that this is a kind of

    utopianism which is expressive of desire (despite the fact that Deleuze

    and Guattari specifically argue against conceptualising desire as

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    11/20

    34 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    expressive), rather than instrumental and transformative, although it

    would be more true to say that the shift is in what is to be transformed

    (compare Sargisson, 2000), since postmodern aesthetics involve the

    willed transformation of the body by ornament, diet, exercise and

    surgical intervention. As David Morris argues, 'utopia in the postmodern

    era has largely fixed its new location in the solitary, private, individual

    body', reflecting 'a belief that the only valid remaining space of

    perfection lies ... in our own individual flesh: a paradise of curves and

    muscle' (Siebers, 1994, p. 152). If Utopian thought of all kinds is

    expressive of a desire for a better way of being, its projection onto the

    body, rather than the body politic, may be seen as an important retreat

    from hope, at least social hope, to desire. Furthermore, it is a retreat

    from understanding desire, as Deleuze and Guattari, Reich, and Marcuse

    did, in terms of a libidinal energy suffusing the realm of the social, and

    thus fuelling capitalism and fascism as well as their potential Utopian

    alternatives. For these writers, desire may emanate from the body in an

    essentialist, vitalist way, but it does not stay there.

    The suggestion that postmodernity challenges Utopia itself rests on

    certain assumptions about what we mean by Utopia. It arises from the

    essentially anti-foundational character of postmodern culture, an anti-

    foundationalism which is epistemological and moral, but it constitutes a

    challenge

    in so far as

    Utopia entails claims about truth and about

    morality. For example, Lyotard's challenge to 'grand narratives' does not

    augur well for projecting into the future wholesale schemes of social

    transformation (if that is how we understand Utopia). The

    'deconstruction of the subject' undermines the possibility of discussing

    interests beyond the self-defined identity and identification of

    individuals, so that collectivities are theoretically disintegrated into

    selves, and further into fragmentary selves. Moral and ethical absolutes

    are impossible; the claim that one society is better than another (a claim

    perhaps fundamental to the Utopian project) is undermined. Even the

    idea of society itself as in some sense a totality, a concept which

    underpins the whole notion of social science, as well as Utopia as a

    society transformed (if that is how we understand Utopia), is called into

    question. There is no t just a loss of hope in the sociai, but a loss of belief

    in it. Krishan Kumar commenting on this anti-utopian character of

    contemporary social theory, argues that if postmodernists are right, 'it is

    not simply that "there aren't any good or brave causes left" to fight for

    anymore', but tha t there cannot be (1996, p . 135). The quest for Utopia

    in this reading is an irretrievably modernist project (compare Clark,

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    12/20

    UTOPIAN FU NC TIO N IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 35

    1999). Notably, the Penguin

    Utopias

    collection (Kelly, 1999) is subtitled

    Russian Modernist Texts 1905-1940. O ne does no t, in fact, hav e to be

    particularly sympathetic to postmodernism to recognise the essential

    contingency of our moral and conceptual frameworks; we are all

    pluralists now. If we see Utopia as intrinsically evaluative about ways of

    life, then pluralism and the recognition of cultural difference certainly

    pose a problem. The kind of Utopia implied, though, in this reading of

    postmodernism as anti-utopian is a totalising (though not therefore

    totalitarian) representation which is holistic, social, future located,

    unequivocally better and linked to the present by some identifiable

    narrat ive.

    This is, I w ou ld argu e, a mistaken view of Utopia, but it is no t wh olly

    mistaken, so these are quite fundamental challenges to the project and

    projection of Utopia. I used to think that the changes in utopianism

    itself,

    illustrated both by changes in Utopian literary texts and in critical

    responses to these over the past 30 years, demonstrated that Utopia could

    answer these challenges. A move from representation to process has

    marked both the texts and the way in which Utopia is understood (as, in

    Miguel Abensour's terms, heuristic rather than systematic) so that Utopia

    in the former sense is either dead or on the point of disappearance. But

    if, as Thomas Osborne suggests is the case for postmodernists, 'hope is

    heuristic not telic', does it really qualify as hope at all?

    8

    To pu t it ano ther

    way, do the ways in which Utopians and utopists have responded to the

    conditions of postmodernity reflect a weakening of the transformative

    potential of Utopia?

    The Utopian Mode

    Abensour argued in the 1970s that after 1850 there was a significant

    disjuncture in Utopian thought. The 'systematic' mode, which involves

    constructing blueprints was replaced by the 'heuristic ' mode, in which

    Utopias become exploratory projections of alternative values merely

    sketched as an alternative way of life. The dating and the completeness

    of the shift is questionable. Abensour was primarily making a point about

    the reading of William Morris 's

    News from Nowhere,

    writ ten in 1890,

    but Edward Bellamy's

    Looking Backward

    (1888) approximates more

    closely to the systematic approach. However, the fact that such claims

    can be made about late nineteenth-century Utopias underlines the point

    that postmodernity develops, rather than contradicts tendencies present

    in m ode rnism itself - or else suggests tha t po stm od ern ism started very

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    13/20

    36 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    early indeed. There is a difference, though, between even Morris's

    heuristic Utopia and what Tom Moylan (1986) has called the critical

    Utopias of the 1970s.

    There is a sense in which Morris's Utopia (unlike Bellamy's) is

    provisional, reflexive and pluralist. But it is provisional and reflexive

    largely in the sense that M or ris u nde rsto od this to be a necessary feature

    of Utopian speculation. He thought it both necessary and ultimately

    impossible to have a vision of the future. It was, he said, 'essential that

    the ideal of the future be kept before the eyes of the working classes, lest

    the continuity of the demands of the people be broken, or lest they be

    misdirected' (M orris and Bax, 18 93 , p.27 8). He un dersto od that all such

    constructions must be provisional, since our capacity to imagine the

    future is socially limited: 'It is impossible to build a scheme for the

    society of the future, for no man can really think himself out of his own

    days. ' (Morris and Bax, 1893, pp.17-18.) Morris is very clear about the

    contingency of his own vision and of Bellamy's, and warns against literal

    readings. 'The only safe way of reading a Utopia is to consider it as the

    expression of the temperament of its author. ' The danger is that Utopias

    will not be read in this way, since 'incomplete systems impossible to be

    carried out are always attractive to people ripe for change, but not

    knowing clearly what their aim is ' (Morris, 1984, p.248). News from

    Nowhere endo rses pluralism to o. N atio n states have been abolished, we

    are told, allowing for the flourishing of cultural diversity between

    peoples. But although the endorsement takes place within the text, the

    diversity itself is placed outside the England of Nowhere: 'Cross the

    water and see. You will find plenty of variety: the landscape, the building,

    the diet , the amusements, al l various. ' (Morris, 1924, pp.99-100.)

    Political difference is accommodated through a system of direct

    democracy, but it is a system which essentially works because there are

    only differences of opinion about the nature of the common interest, not

    differences of interest themselves.

    In the Utopian texts of the 1970s, reflexivity and provisionality about

    the status of the Utopian text become features of the text

    itself.

    As

    Moylan argued in Demand the Impossible, these Utopias have a different,

    more fragmented narrative structure than earlier Utopias. The discrete

    register (which concerns plot and character) is foregrounded, and the

    iconic register (which describes the social structure of both the Utopian

    society and its foil) recedes. The societies portrayed are decentralised

    and differentiated. T he re is a proc ess of self-interrog ation w ithin the

    Utopian society, so that its values and institutions are less unequivocally

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    14/20

    UTOPIAN FU NC TIO N IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 3 7

    endorsed. Many novels contain possible dystopian futures, as well as

    Utopian ones, breaking down the sense of a necessary, determined move

    toward Utopia, the dependence on a grand narrative. As Williams said of

    Ursula Le Guin's

    The Dispossessed,

    originally subtitled 'an ambiguous

    Utopia', 'the Utopian impulse now warily, self-questioningly, and setting

    its own limits, renew s itse lf (198 0, p.2 12 ).

    All these features are present in Marge Piercy's Woman on the Edge

    of Time.

    So, too, is a cultural pluralism, deliberately and actively

    separated from any connection with 'race'. This aspect of pluralism is a

    little unconvincing, in that culture appears as an optional add-on to a

    whole way of life, rather than an intrinsic part of it, but it is very much

    more present than in Nowhere. The political process is also presented as

    more contested than in Nowhere, for here there may be differences of

    interest to resolve. Argument simply continues until agreement is

    reached, and after a major dispute, the winners have to feed the losers

    and give presents. The response to a question about how differences are

    resolved is 'we argue - ho w else?' (Piercy, 197 9, p.153 .)

    Jurgen Habermas (1989) argues that the shift to late modernity

    produced a shift in Utopian thought such that it is no longer possible to

    say anything about the nature of Utopia

    itself,

    but only the

    communicative processes by which it may be negotiated. Thus the only

    kind of Utopia which is possible is the processual and communicative. In

    practice, such claims tend to sneak assumptions about the actual

    character of Utopia in by the back door, in so far as they explicitly or

    implicitly posit the conditions under which such dialogue may be

    possible. But the prob lem w ith 'we argue - ho w else?' (especially in a

    society which is not, as Piercy's Utopia is not, culturally homogeneous) is

    that it presumes that argument will result in resolution. There is, it

    seems, not only an assumption that shared interests dominate over

    conflicting ones, but also no dispute over the terms of the debate, the

    procedures of discussion, and the frame of the argument.

    A more radical challenge to the Utopian imagination arises if this

    frame is contested. How can Utopia handle the possibil i ty of

    fundamental conflicts of interest, or absence of agreement on the rules

    of the game? Perhaps it cannot. Incommensurability enters into the

    Utopia largely as a dystopian shadow. Arguably, it can only enter in this

    way, if Utopia is a space for the fictional resolution of problems that

    humankind has not (yet) solved. The first volume of Kim Stanley

    Robinson's Mars trilogy, Red Mars (1992), presents a picture of

    incommensurable cultures and value positions within cultures. The issue

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    15/20

    38 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    of language and translation is a common vehicle for such questions

    (Cavalcanti, 1999), as in Suzette Elgin's novel Native Tongue (1985), or

    the Irish singer Christy Moore's (1994) lament 'Natives' , which begins

    'For all of our languages, we can't communicate; for all of our native

    tongues, we're all natives here... ' . The biblical figuration of this is the

    Tower of Babel, which seems to be recurring with increasing frequency

    even in novels which are not part of an explicitly Utopian or dystopian

    genre, such as A.S. Byatt's Babel Tower (1997) and Paul Auster's The

    New York Trilogy (1987).

    Theorising Utopia

    The shift to a greater pluralism, provisionality and reflexivity in the

    substance of Utopia has been paralleled by a theorisation of Utopia which

    treats it as heuristic rather than telic. This, like the texts themselves,

    focuses on process rather than content, but the process in question is one

    of dialogue with, rather than within, the text. It sees the function of

    Utopia as poised betwe en expressive and instrum ental functions. Th ere is

    a convergence between neo-Marxism, cri t ical theory, postmodernism,

    and feminism' in thinking about Utopia in terms of desire, in terms of

    process rather than content, in terms of how the text works rather than

    (simply) what it means.

    Abensour, for example, argues for understanding the function of

    Utopian texts in terms of desire, not expressively or instrumentally in the

    sense of desire for the object portrayed in the text, but in terms of how

    the text acts on the act of desiring. This was taken up both by Edward

    Thompson and Raymond Williams, who remarks that Bellamy's Utopia

    is ' in a significant way a work without desire' (Williams, 1980, p.202).

    To read a Utopia is to embark on an adventure:

    And in such an adventure two things happen: our habitual values

    (the 'common sense' of bourgeois society) are thrown into disarray.

    And we enter into Utopia 's proper and new-found space, the

    education of desire. This is not the same as 'a moral education'

    towards a different end: it is, rather, to open a way to aspiration,

    to ' teach desire to desire, to desire better, to desire more, and

    above all to desire in a different way' (Thompson, 1976,

    p p . 7 9 0 -9 1 ) .

    Utopia here, even the Utopian text, is not a naturalistic representation of

    the good society, but the catalyst of a process in which the reader is an

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    16/20

    UTOPIAN FUNCTION IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 39

    active agent.

    The

    central characteristic

    of

    this process

    is the

    disruption

    and transgression of the normative and conceptual frameworks of

    everyday experience, and the provision of a space within which it is

    possible to imagine not just the satisfaction of familiar wants unmet by

    existing society, but to envisage wanting something other than the

    satisfactions which that society endorses and simultaneously denies:

    above all, to desire in a different way.

    Anglophone utopists, notably Moylan and Jameson, develop a

    similar argument.The function ofUtopian fiction is no longerto be seen

    as providing

    an

    outline

    of a

    social system

    to be

    interrogated literally

    in

    terms of its structural properties, and treated as a goal. The Utopian

    function isestrangement and defamiliarisation, rendering the taken-for-

    granted world problematic, and calling into question the actually

    existing state of affairs, not the imposit ion of a plan for the future.

    Again, w hat is most important about Utopia isless wha t isimagined than

    the act of imagination itself, a process which disrupts the closure of the

    present.

    For

    Jameson,

    10

    as for

    Abensour, this process circles around

    the

    question

    of

    desire:

    we

    might think

    of the new

    onset

    of the

    Utopian

    process as akindof desiringto desire,alearning to desire,the invention

    of the desire called Utopia in the first place' (Jameson, 1994, p.90) - a

    passage bearing a remarkable similarity to Abensour 's .

    O neof theconsequences of this readingof Utopiaas heuristic rather

    than systematic, exploratory rather than prescriptive, is that it provides

    an alibi for what otherwise might be seen as the weaknesses, absences

    and failuresof theiconic registerof theUtopian text - thelimitations of,

    for example, both Morris 's and Piercy's treatment of cultural and

    political pluralism. Jameson goes further

    and

    suggests that these failures

    do

    not

    need

    an

    alibi. Failure

    is

    less

    the

    characteristic

    of

    particular

    representationsofUtopia, mo reaninevitable par tof theprocessof trying

    to think Utopia itself. It is habitual to think of Utopia as that which is

    imagined, but Jam eson argues (like M ar x and Morris) that Utopia is

    literally unimaginable. That which can be imagined always falls shortof

    Utopia, so that Utopian texts, for example, 'bring home in local and

    determinate ways ,

    and

    wi th

    a

    fullness

    of

    concrete detai l ,

    our

    constitutional inability

    to

    imagine Utopia itself (Jameson,

    1982,

    p .153) ;

    they enable the exploration of the structural limits of wha t we can

    imagine in order to get a better senseof wha t it isabout the future that

    we are unable or unwilling to imagine' (Jameson, 1998, p .76) . The

    function of the Utopian text is to provoke ... to jar the mind into some

    heightened but unconceptualizable consciousness of its own powers ,

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    17/20

    40 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    functions, aims and structural limits' (Jameson, cited in Siebers, 1994,

    p.94). Clark similarly stresses the importance of failure as a crucial

    feature of modernism (rather than postmodernism ) in art, a movement

    which he sees as intrinsically Utopian, claiming that 'the courting of

    failure and indescribability is one main key to ... the visual culture of the

    last two hundred years' (1999, p. 164). His reasons are perhaps similar to

    Jameson's: 'It is only in discovering the system [of representation's]

    antinomies and blank spots - discovering them in practice I mean - that

    the first improvised forms of contrary imagining come to light.' (Clark,

    1999,

    p.165 .) For Jameson, referring back to Louis Marin (1984), Utopia

    is always 'organised ... around a blind spot or a vanishing point'

    (Jameson, 1998, p.75), a point of disappearance."

    These appealing formulations may show how Utopia and Utopian

    interpretation have adapted to the postmodern requirement for

    provisionality, reflexivity and pluralism. On the other hand, these

    adaptations themselves have dangers and limitations. One danger is the

    adoption of a kind of pathological pluralism, in which the

    acknowledgement of the positions and standpoints of others effectively

    undermines the capacity to occupy, even critically and provisionally, a

    ground of one's own, so that commitment is impossible. It is unclear that

    Utopia thus understood can move beyond the function of critique, the

    disruption of the

    ideological

    closure of the presen t. But the

    transformative function of Utopia requires the disruption of the

    structuralclosure of the present, and it requires us to imagine both what

    this might mean and how it might be possible, in order that we may be

    able to hope. A 'heightened but unconceptualizable consciousness' of the

    mind's own powers will not do. Perhaps forms of Utopian thought which

    are more than expressive of desire are intrinsically holistic, totalising and

    evaluative. Perhaps prescription is necessary. As Raymond Williams once

    said, we must define ourselves in terms of what we are for, not just what

    we are against. Content, not just process, remains essential. It is, of

    course, also essential that Utopia embraces provisionality, reflexivity and

    pluralism, and that Utopians recognise the contingency of their hopes

    and desires. This is not incompatible with commitment, with taking

    responsibility in conditions where there can be no cpistemological,

    moral or historical certainty. The effective synthesis of provisionality and

    responsibility may be the condition of keeping Utopia open as a space in

    which to reach out to the real possibility of a transformed future.

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    18/20

    UTO PIAN FUN CTIO N IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 4 1

    NOTES

    1.

    I have been helped and forced to clarify my argum ent by utopists and others on

    several occasions in 1999, including by participants in the conferences on

    'Nowhere: A Place of Our Own' at Warwick and 'A Millennium of Utopias' at the

    University of East Anglia, and by members of the Critical Theory Seminar at the

    University of Bristol and the Department of Sociology at the University of Essex.

    I would particularly like to thank Vincent Geoghegan, Gregor McLennan, Tom

    Moylan, Thomas Osborne, Lucy Sargisson and Carolyn Wilde for perceptive and

    constructive comments and stimulating disagreements.

    2.

    As Thom as O sborne (1998) observes, there are different ways in which

    'engagement' can be construed, not all of which are overtly political, while

    Forrester (1999) similarly insists that thinking itself is a political act. The

    argument that academics, and sociologists in particular, should be 'engaged

    intellectuals' has been made forcibly in relation to sociology (in answer to the

    question 'What is sociology for?'). See McLennan (1999), Giddens (1998), Rorty

    (1998), and Bourdieu (1998).

    3. I have argued this at greater length elsewhere. See Levitas (1990a).

    4. 'Now here - a place of our own' was the title of an interdisciplinary conference

    on the uses of Utopia at the University of Warwick, May 1999.

    5. The importance of this distinction is discussed in Levitas (1990b), reprinted in

    Daniel and Moylan (1997).

    6. The British government, which had spent huge sums of money combating and

    encouraging others to combat the Y2K bug, argued, of course, that this was why

    nothing had happened. They would of course. But sceptical respondents

    wondered why, if this were indeed the case, Blair's government was so insistent

    that throwing money at problems was not the solution, as is persistently argued

    in relation to poverty, education and the collapsing National Health Service.

    7. See Moylan (1999). For an analysis of these films, and a theorisation of the

    character of 1990s dystopianism, see Fitting (1999) and Moylan (2000,

    forthcoming).

    8. I am grateful for this formulation in response to an earlier version of this paper.

    9. Irigaray's utopianism is exemplary here . See Sargisson (1996).

    10. Fitting (1998) provides an excellent account of Jameson's use of the concept of

    utopia.

    11 . The impo rtance of perspective, of the 'vanishing po int', and of 'hor izo n' is a

    common theme in Bloch, Jameson and Marin. John Berger argues that the

    absence of perspective and horizon are fundamental to the effectiveness of

    Hieronymous Bosch's depiction of Hell: this visual strategy removes continuity

    between actions, between past and future and creates a 'spatial delirium' in which

    'nothing flows through, everything interrupts'. Hope, he argues, 'is an act of

    faith, and has to be sustained by other concrete actions. For example, the action

    of approach, of measuring distances and walking towards (Berger, 1998/99,

    pp.1-4), and therefore depends upon perspective.

    REFERENCES

    Auster, P. 1987.The New York Trilogy. London: Faber and Faber.

    Baccolini, R. 1999. Feminist open/critical dystopias. Paper presented at A Millennium of

    Utopias: The Theory, History and Future of Utopianism, University of East Anglia,

    23-26 June 1999.

    Bellamy, E. 1888 .LookingBackward. Boston: Ticknor.

    Downloadedby["Que

    en'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    19/20

    4 2 THE PHILOSOPHY OF UTOPIA

    Berger, J. 1998/99. Against the great defeat of the world. Race and Class, Vol.40, N o .2 / 3 ,

    p p . 1 - 4 .

    Bloch, E. 1986.

    The Principle of Hope.

    Oxford: Blackwells.

    Bourdieu, P. 1998.

    Acts of Resistance: Against the New My ths of Ou r Time.

    Cambridge:

    Polity Press.

    Byatt, A.S. 1997 .

    Babel Tower.

    London: Chat to and Windus.

    Carey, J. 1999 .

    The Faber Book of Utopias.

    London: Faber and Faber.

    Cavalcanti, I. 1999. Utopias of(f) language in contemporary feminist Utopias. Paper

    presented at Nowhere: A Place of Our Own: Exploring the Uses of Utopia, University

    of Warwick, 8 May 1999.

    Claeys, G. and Sargent, L. 1999. The Utopias Reader. New York: New York University

    Press.

    Clark, T.J. 1999. Farewell to an Idea. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Daniel , J .O. and M oylan, T. 199 7. N ot Yet: Reconsidering Ernst B loch. London: Verso.

    Deleuze, G. and Guattari , F. 1984.Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. London:

    Athlone Press.

    Elgin, S.H. 1985.

    Native Tongues.

    London: The Women's Press .

    Fitt ing, P. 1998. The concept of Utopia in the work of Fredric Jameson. Utopian Studies,

    Vol.9, N o . 2 , p p . 8 - 1 7 .

    1999 . Unmaking the real? Critique and Utopia in four recent films, Society for

    Utopian Studies Annual Conference, San Antonio, 1999.

    Forrester, V. 199 9. The Economic Horror. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Giddens, A. 1995.Beyond Left and R ight. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    1 9 9 8 . The Third Way: The Renewal of Social Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Goodchild, P. 1996. Deleuze and G uattari: An Introduction to the Politics of Desire.

    London: Sage.

    Haberm as , J . 198 9.

    The New Conservatism.

    Ca mb ridge : Polity Press.

    Jacoby, R. 1999. The End of Utopia: Politics and Culture in an Age of Apathy. Ne w York:

    Basic Books.

    Jameson, F. 1982. Progress versus Utopia: or, can we imagine the future? Science-Fiction

    Studies, Vo l. 27 , No . 9 , pp . 147 -58 .

    1984. Postmodernism, or the cultural logic of late capitalism. New Left Review, 146,

    July-August , pp.13-92.

    1991 .

    Postmod ernism: Or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Lond on: Verso.

    1994. The Seeds of Time. New York: Columbia University Press.

    1998. Comments . Utopian Studies, Vol.9, No .2 , pp .74 -7 .

    Kelly, C. ed. 1999. Utopias: Russian Modernist Texts 1905-1940. Lond on: Penguin.

    Kumar, K. 1996.

    From Post-Industrial to Post-Modern Society.

    Oxford: Blackwells.

    Le Guin, U. 1974. The Dispossessed. London: Victor Gollancz.

    Levitas, R. 1990a. The Concept of Utopia. Hemel Hempstead: Philip Allan.

    1990b. Educated hope: Ernst Bloch on abstract and concrete Utopia. Utopian Studies,

    Vol.1,

    N o . 2 , p p . 1 3 - 2 6 .

    Marin, L. 1984. Utopics: Spatial Play. London: Macmil lan.

    McLennan, G. 1999. The ways ahead . History of the Hum an Sciences, Vol .12 , No.4 ,

    pp .1 4 7 - 5 5 .

    Moore, C. 1994. Nat ives.

    Christy Moore Live At the Point.

    London: Grapevine.

    Morris , W. 1924 [1891].News From Nowhere. London: Longmans Green and Co.

    1984 [1889]. Looking backward. In Political Writings of William Morris, ed . Morton ,

    A.L. London: Lawrence and Wishart.

    Morris, W. and Bax, E.B. 1893. Socialism: Its Growth and O utcome. Lon don: Swan

    Sonnenschein.

    Moylan, T. 1986.Demand the Impossible. London: Methuen.

    1 9 9 9 .

    Warm and cold utopianism : reconsidering dystopia in the 1990 s. Paper

    Downloadedby["Queen'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,

    Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016

  • 7/25/2019 For Utopia: The (limits of the) Utopian function in

    20/20

    UTOPIAN FUN CT ION IN LATE CAPITALIST SOCIETY 43

    presented at A Millennium of Utopias: The Theory, History and Future of

    Utopianism, University of East Anglia, 23-26 June 1999.

    2 0 0 0 .

    Scraps of the U ntainted Sky: Sc ience Fiction, Utopia, Dystopia. Ne w York:

    Westview Press.

    Osborne, T. 1998.

    Aspects of Enlightenment.

    Lon don : UCL Press.

    Piercy, M. 1979.

    Woman on the Edge of Time.

    London: The Women's Press .

    Porter, E. 1999. Irigaray's utopianism and anti-utopianism. Paper presented at Nowhere:

    A Place of Our Own: Exploring the Uses of Utopia, University of Warwick, 8 May

    1999 .

    Robinson, K.S. 1992.

    Red Mars.

    London: HarperColl ins .

    Rorty, R. 1998. Achieving O ur Country: Leftist Thought in Twen tieth Century Ame rica.

    Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.

    Sargisson, L. 1996.

    Contem porary Fem inist Utopianism.

    London: Routledge.

    2 0 0 0 . Utopian Bodies and the Politics of Transgression. Londo n: Routledge.

    Siebers, T. ed. 1994. Heterotopia: Postmode rn Utopia and the Body Po litic. University of

    Michigan Press.

    Taylor, L. 1999.

    Times Higher Education Suppleme nt,

    9 April 199 9.

    Thompson, E.P. 1976. William Morris: Romantic to Revolutionary. Lon don : Me rlin Press.

    Wallerstein, I. 1999. Utopistics. New York: The New Press.

    Williams, R. 1980.

    Problems in Materialism and Culture.

    London: Verso.

    Downloadedby["Queen'sUniversityLibrarie

    s,Kingston"]at17:181

    0February2016