foundation of quantum mechanics

Upload: hogo69

Post on 05-Apr-2018

224 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    1/29

    The

    FOUNDATIONof

    QUANTUM MECHANICS

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 1 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    2/29

    INDEXPage

    1.0 INTRODUCTION 4-52.0 THE HISTORY OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 6-10

    2.1 Classical mechanics 6

    2.1.1 Isaac Newton 62.1.2 Electro-magnetism 62.1.3 Albert Einstein's influence on mechanics 6-7

    2.1.4 Atoms the 'complete' picture 72.2 Quantum mechanics 7

    2.2.1 The evolution of the atomic model 7-8

    2.2.2 Louis de Broglie 9

    2.2.3 Erwin Schrdinger 9-102.2.4 Werner Heisenberg 10

    3.0 DIFFERENCES BETWEEN CLASSICAL ANDQUANTUM MECHANICS

    10-19

    3.1 Determinism 10-11

    3.1.1 Laplace's Demon 113.2 Indeterminism 11-123.2.1 The 'Copenhagen' interpretation 12

    3.2.2 The Pauli exclusion principle 12-133.3 The differences 13

    3.3.1 Feynman's thought experiments 13-163.3.2 Dirac's notation 16-18

    3.3.3 Heisenberg's uncertainty principle 18-19

    4.0 SCHRDINGER'S EQUATION 19-234.1 The equation 19

    4.2 The 'infinite square well' 19-214.2.1 The quantization of energy (n = 3, 2, 1, 0) 21-23

    5.0 CONCLUSION 24

    6.0 RESUM 257.0 APPENDIX 26-288.0 BIBLIOGRAPHY 29-30

    8.1 Books 29

    8.2 Videos 29-308.3 Websites 30

    The layout of this project was inspired by the layout of Niels Bohr's On the Constitution of

    Atoms and Molecules. It seemed only fitting to make the layout of my project imitate and

    thereby pay homage to the truly inspiring work done by Niels Bohr. Nonetheless, my

    project does reach all requirements and does not overshoot the maximum allowance of

    pages (if the margins were to be set to the normal borders provided by the standard text

    editor programs).

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 2 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    3/29

    1.0 INTRODUCTION

    Since early times, an understanding of the universe has been sought. An

    understanding which could explain the workings of everything. This

    understanding has changed greatly over many thousands of years, even

    impacting other fields of thought such as philosophy. Aristotle (384 322

    BC) had a philosophy which stated that the world consisted of four

    elements, earth, air, fire, and water, and that objects acted to fulfill their

    purpose1. Nave as it may have been, this was the start of a search for what

    can be called a grand unified theory. Once Pythagoras (570 495 BC)

    created the first mathematical proof of a physical phenomenon2 the stage

    was set to describe the entire universe. When Newton (1643 1727 AD), an

    avid mathematician, discovered the laws of gravity, a way of thoughtevolved, determinism, which went unchanged for four centuries3. So

    ingrained and powerful was this way of thought that when a new form of

    mechanics, quantum mechanics (from now on abbreviated as QM),

    appeared, not even the greatest thinker of modern time, Albert Einstein

    (1879 1955 AD), could be dissuaded. This was because QM was based on

    probabilities rather than certainties, leading to indeterminism, to which

    Einstein exclaimed, God doesn't play dice with the world4! The universe

    is an enormously complicated system which no one, even today, has ever

    fully understood. It is therefore no wonder that a theory, that seems to

    explain a lot, is doubted. Moreover, it makes sense as QM is not completely

    understood, yet.

    What this project shall attempt to achieve is a fundamental

    understanding of QM through a review of the experimental basis for our

    view of the structure of atoms. This project will therefore be a short

    historical guide to the persons involved in the establishment of QM and the

    experiments which they performed. Moreover, this project will explain and

    1 The Grand Design, p. 51.2 Fermats Store Stning, p. 37.

    3 Fermats Store Stning, p. 38.

    4 Einstein and the Poet, William Hermann.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 3 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    4/29

    discuss the differences between the determinism of classical mechanics and

    the indeterminism of QM. In order to give the reader a better understanding

    of the intricacies of QM, I will later in the project explain and discuss parts

    of some of the tools of QM, namely Schrdinger's equation and Dirac's

    notation. I will also touch upon a fundamental aspect of QM, Heisenberg's

    uncertainty principle.

    The explanations for the Schrdinger equation and Dirac notation are

    based on a compilation of lectures, videos and other assorted material. It

    would be too time consuming to reference every part of the mathematics.

    There will, therefore, be a complete list of the all the relevant references in

    the bibliography to supplement the lack of individual references.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 4 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    5/29

    2.0 THE HISTORY OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

    Quantum mechanics is a culmination of the work done by various scientists,

    sometimes by accident, sometimes by design. However, it all starts with the

    advent of what we today call 'classical' mechanics.

    2.1 Classical mechanicsClassical mechanics is the name given to the mathematically natured

    science which gave us the law of gravity. This was thanks to the work

    of the intuitive Isaac Newton who invented, independent of Gottfried

    Leibniz, calculus, or rather the rules of differentials and integrals

    which are still used today.

    2.1.1 Isaac Newton

    Thanks to the invention of calculus, Isaac Newton was able toaccurately calculate the movement of terrestrial and heavenly

    bodies and the force of gravity, among many others5. This was an

    incredible tour de force of science which allowed scientists to

    accurately predict the course of an event. Scientists could now

    understand the dynamics of a system and continued to apply

    Newton's methods to other aspects of physics. This led to the

    discovery of magnetism and electricity.

    2.1.2 Electro-magnetism

    At the beginning of the 19th century, scientists believed that

    magnetism and electricity were two separate forces, H.C. rsted

    did not. He believed that they had the same origin6. By passing

    electricity through a conductor, H. C. rsted created a magnetic

    field, thus proving his theory of electro-magnetism.

    2.1.3 Albert Einstein's influence on mechanics

    Albert Einstein, a genius of unforeseen magnitude, greatly

    influenced the interpretation of classical mechanics because of his

    discovery of the law of the photoelectric effect. Here Albert

    Einstein postulated that electro-magnetic radiation consisted of

    5 Taming the infinite. p. 141

    6 Fysikkens Verden 3. p. 210-211

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 5 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    6/29

    light quanta(photons) moving at the speed of light7. With this he

    proved that a photon's energy is:

    Ephoton = h v (1)

    Where h is Planck's constant and v is the electro-magnetic

    radiation's frequency. This discovery eventually helped lead to the

    conceptualization of the wave-particle duality which we shall

    expand upon later.

    2.1.4 Atoms the 'complete' picture

    At this point in time, the idea of atoms had seemingly been

    completed, that is to say, scientists believed atoms to be the

    smallest parts of matter. An indivisible part. However, there

    seemed to exist a great many atoms for such a unique and

    fundamental building block8. This is why J. J. Thomson's

    discovery of electrons may have been shocking yet welcomed.

    2.2 Quantum mechanics

    2.2.1 The evolution of the atomic model

    After J. J. Thomson (1856 1940) discovered electrons,

    mechanics and physics as a whole, took a

    turn towards the infinitesimally small. No

    longer was the atom the smallest functional

    particle, now it consisted of electrons. J. J.

    Thomson was led to conclude, based on the

    evidence provided by his experiments, that

    the electron is thousands of times less massive than the atom9.

    This conclusion led to the 'plum-pudding' picture of the structure

    of the atom. In the 'plum-pudding' atom, the negative electrons are

    randomly dispersed over the positive body of the atom, see figure

    7 Elementr kvantemekanik. p. 5

    8 The ideas of particle physics. p. 2

    9 The ideas of particle physics. p. 3

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 6 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    7/29

    A. This atomic model, however, could not account for the results

    of Hans Geiger and Ernest Marsden. Geiger and Marsden

    discovered that when high-energy -particles collide with thin

    metal-foil, a tiny fraction of the -particles are deflected up to

    18010

    . It was first explained when Ernest Rutherford (1871

    1937) theorized that atoms must consist of tiny nuclei that make

    up the majority of the mass of an atom, and an amount of

    negatively charged electrons at rest around the nucleus that

    manage to neutralize the positively charged nuclei. Classical

    mechanics, however, dictated that if that were the case, the

    electrons would gravitate inwards, towards the nucleus, as

    opposites attract. Even if the electrons are not at rest but in anaccelerated orbit around the nucleus, they would emit electro-

    magnetic waves (see (1)) thus losing energy and spiralling

    towards the nucleus11. This is not what was found experimentally.

    It was up to Niels Bohr (1885 1962) to create a modern atomic

    model which could answer the question of the orbits of electrons.

    In Bohr's theory, he postulates that electrons revolve around the

    nucleus in stationary orbits that allow for the movement of the

    electrons without their necessitated emission of radiation12.

    Although this model is not the complete atomic model that is used

    today, it is still the most stable and understandable model and is a

    major influence on QM. We will not expand upon the history of

    the atomic model further as this visualization allows us to

    ascertain the approximate workings and purpose of an electron; to

    orbit a nucleus, at a quantized distance with a variable but limited

    speed(slower than or equal to the speed of light), at a variable

    time, and neutralize the charge of the nucleus.

    10 Elementr Kvantefysik. p. 18-19

    11 Elementr Kvantefysik. p. 20

    12 Elementr Kvantefysik. p. 21

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 7 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    8/29

    2.2.2 Louis de Broglie

    Louis de Broglie (1892 1987) was the next physicist to advance

    the concept of QM. In his doctoral thesis, de Broglie suggested

    that electrons could act like waves in a manner where the

    wavelength is inversely proportional to its momentum13

    :

    =h

    p(2)

    Where h is Planck's constant. The beauty of his theory consists of

    the notion that this applies to all particles, not just electrons or

    photons. One might say that if a human were to have a small

    enough momentum, the human would also exhibit wavelike

    properties. De Broglie's hypothesis managed to explain the nature

    of Bohr's atomic model as the electronic orbits are only allowed if

    they contain an integral number of de Broglie wavelengths 14.

    However, de Broglie did not manage to create a resounding theory

    of mechanics which could trump Newton's classical theory but his

    work did set the stage for the development of one15.

    2.2.3 Erwin Schrdinger

    Erwin Schrdinger (1887 1961) took de Broglie's hypotheses on

    particle waves and developed them into wave mechanics16.

    Schrdinger's approach was to look at the waves' behaviour in

    space and time. What he discovered was an equation which

    describes the behaviour of matter through a description of a

    particle by its wavefunction. This equation shows how a wave

    might behave given a set of limits. Given such limits, the

    Schrdinger equation is able to predict the theoretical interference

    of particles. Practically, however, the measurement of such

    13 The ideas of particle physics. p. 17-1814 The ideas of particle physics. p. 18

    15 The ideas of particle physics. p. 19

    16 The ideas of particle physics. p. 19

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 8 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    9/29

    behaviour is affected by the measurement itself.

    2.2.4 Werner Heisenberg

    Werner Heisenberg (1901 1976) essentially formulated that only

    a system which is observed can be defined but that this

    observation in itself is an interaction with the system. The

    interaction with the system affects it denying perfect knowledge

    of the system to the observer17. He formulated this principle

    mathematically in what is today known as, the uncertainty

    principle.

    3.0 DIFFERENCES BETWEEN CLASSICAL AND QUANTUM

    MECHANICSClassical mechanics had been the supreme way of thinking for hundreds of

    years when QM appeared. This new method of understanding the universe

    brought with it a new way of thinking which forcefully rejected the ways of

    determinism. Now, scientist were led to believe in probabilities instead of

    certainties. But why could the two mechanics not coexist? What made them

    so different?

    3.1 Determinism

    Determinism states that, given the state of the universe at one time, a

    complete set of laws fully determines both the future and the past18.

    The metaphor that Newton grants us is of a clockwork universe19 in

    which every action is followed by a definite reaction. As a practical

    example, imagine an object moving in a vacuum. If that object is

    moving with the speed of 10m/s then we can, through simple

    arithmetic, figure out how long it takes the object to traverse a

    distance. Newton's laws of motion even allow us to figure out the

    starting acceleration of an object as long as we know the distance and

    speed over which the acceleration, at observation, has acted over. This

    17 The ideas of particle physics. p. 20

    18 The Grand Design. p. 30

    19 The Number Mysteries. p. 230

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 9 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    10/29

    is a simple universe with no surprises, no miracles, except perhaps for

    the creation of the universe.

    3.1.1 Laplace's Demon

    This scientific determinism was formulated into what is today

    known as Laplace's Demon:

    We may regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its

    past and the cause of its future. An intellect which at a certain

    moment would know all forces that set nature in motion, and all

    positions of all items of which nature is composed, if this intellect

    were also vast enough to submit these data to analysis, it would

    embrace in a single formula the movements of the greatest bodiesof the universe and those of the tiniest atom; for such an intellect

    nothing would be uncertain and the future just like the past would

    be present before its eyes.20

    In this analogy, Laplace basically states the view of determinism,

    that all is determined. It is a neat philosophy in the sense that it

    allows for the total knowledge and understanding of the entire

    universe at any time as long as we know all data at a given point

    in time. Though, if it were completely true, nothing would be left

    to chance, not even free will21.

    3.2 Indeterminism

    Indeterminism, unlike determinism, certainly allows for free will. In

    indeterminism, everything is governed by chance, or rather,

    probabilities. At the macroscopic level indeterminism is diminished,

    that is to say, the chance of all the particles in a human being suddenly

    spreading out in their own unique direction, is incredibly small.

    According to Bohr's Correspondence Principle, the macroscopic

    effects of QM are actually rather deterministic because of the scale of

    20 A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities. p.4

    21 On Determinism, Sean Carroll.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 10 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    11/29

    the macroscopic universe in comparison to Planck's constant 22,23. At the

    microscopic level though, probabilities play a huge role.

    3.2.1 The 'Copenhagen' interpretation.

    The 'Copenhagen' interpretation of QM is an attempt to

    understand this complex nature of QM. This interpretation, named

    after the place where most progress within the field was made at

    the time, was a summation of multiple points which, in essence,

    describe QM. These points are, at their simplest24(see Appendix I

    for full list):

    1. A system is represented by its state in the form of a

    wavefunction.

    2. Nature is probabilistic and the square of the amplitude of awavefunction is the wavefunction's probability.

    3. All values of a system cannot be known at the same time.

    4. Matter exists in a wave-particle duality.

    5. Measuring devices can only measure classical properties

    as they themselves are classical in nature.

    6. The description of a macroscopic system will be

    approximately deterministic.

    3.2.2 The Pauli exclusion principle

    The Pauli exclusion principle, hypothesized by Wolfgang Pauli

    (1900 1958), is a principle which explains the spreading of

    electrons in an atom. According to Pauli, electrons cannot

    simultaneously occupy precisely the same quantum state (i.e.

    have identical values of momentum, charge and spin in the same

    region of space)25. The principle explains the reason as to why

    electrons will not huddle in the lowest quantum state but spread

    out in additional orbits. In the innermost orbit, only two electrons

    22 Kvantemekanik, Tom Andersen. p. 423 Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Jan Faye.

    24 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Copenhagen_interpretation

    25 The ideas of particle physics. p. 23

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 11 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    12/29

    can coexist as there are only two different kinds of spin. Outer

    orbits allow for varying degrees of angular momentum and

    therefore allow more electrons in the same orbit. This means that

    if we were to find a system with isolated electrons, extending over

    all of space or a definite size, then only two electrons, with

    opposite spins, would be allowed the same momentum.

    3.3 The differences

    As has already been stated, classical and quantum mechanics are

    represented by determinism and indeterminism, two polar opposites.

    These differences do not just appear in the use of probabilities as

    opposed to certainties but in fact appear in the very nature of QM.

    3.3.1 Feynman's thought experimentsThe following is a short account of some experiments, used by

    Richard Feynman in his lectures on physics26; used to develop an

    understanding of the nature of probabilities in QM and the

    mechanics in their most basic aspects.

    Figure B. Interference experiment with bullets

    27

    Electrons and photons behave alike, therefore, what we find

    applying to electrons will also apply to photons. Electrons behave

    as waves and particles which we shall show but in order for us to

    26 The Feynman lectures on physics Vol 3.

    27 http://quantummechanics.ucsd.edu/ph130a/130_notes/node68.html

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 12 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    13/29

    do that, we must first consider the implications of them being

    either particles or waves. Consider, for example, a gun which

    sprays bullets in random directions along a plane. If we were to

    design an experiment in which we weanted to find out where the

    bullets landed, we would use a backstop which could stop these

    bullets. In between the gun and the backstop we place a wall with

    two holes. After firing the gun we could count the bullets that

    passed through the holes in the wall and their distance from the

    point on the backstop directly opposite the gun, x,using a detector

    of sorts, see Figure B. This way we can measure the probabilistic

    outcome of our experiment in relation to x, where probability is

    measured along the first axis and the correspondingx value alongthe second axis. This way we find that the probability of the

    bullets through the first hole (P1) plus the probability of the bullets

    through the second hole (P2) equal the total probability

    distribution of the bullets reaching the backstop (P1 2). We also

    find that there is no interference in this experiment. What we have

    discovered, already with this first experiment, is the use of

    probabilities in order to explain and, in some respects, quantify a

    sequence of measurements. Now let us consider a wave, such as

    the kind one would expect in a pond. Suppose that an object in a

    water trough is bobbed up and down creating a steady source of

    waves in the same kind of configuration as the previous

    experiment, see Figure C.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 13 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    14/29

    Figure C. Interference experiment with water waves28

    Here the detector measures the intensity of the wave. As we can

    see in this example, the total intensity, I1 2 , is interestingly

    different from the previous experiment. This is caused by

    diffraction of the waves at the holes in the wall. Unlike in the first

    experiment, I1 2 , is not the sum of the intensities of the individual

    intensities but rather only happens when both holes are open. In

    this example, the waves interfere, both constructively and

    destructively, creating this pattern. If we were to try this

    experiment with an 'electron gun', a device which fires electrons

    towards a target in much the same way as our gun, we would find

    that the result is a curve such as the one in figure C (see P 1 2 in

    figure D).

    28 http://dbanach.com/feyn1.htm

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 14 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    15/29

    Figure D. Interference experiment with electrons29

    From this experiment we see that if we were to close off hole 1 we

    would obtain P2 and if we close off hole 2 we would get P 1. As we

    could guess, the sum of P1 and P2 should equal the same

    probability curve as obtained in the bullet experiment. It does not.

    However, the square of the sum of the complex numbers 1 and 2

    does create such a probability curve and the squares of the

    individual complex numbers also equal their respective, isolated,

    probability curves. What we can conclude is that electrons, andtherefore also photons and other particles, sometimes behave as a

    wave and sometimes as particles.

    3.3.2 Dirac's notation

    One of the things we discovered in the above, is that, the

    probability that a particle will arrive at x, when let out at the

    source s, can be represented quantitatively by the absolute square

    of a complex number called a probability amplitude30. This is

    also called the first general principle of QM. The second general

    principle of QM simply states that, when a particle can reach a

    given state by two possible routes, the total amplitude for the

    29 http://quantummechanics.ucsd.edu/ph130a/130_notes/node68.html

    30 The Feynman lectures on physics Vol 3. Chapter 3, page 2.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 15 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    16/29

    process is thesum of the amplitudes for the two routes considered

    separately31 which we also discovered in the above. In QM, a

    common practice used to represent these principles is what is

    called the Dirac notation. Dirac notation is also known as Bracket

    notation as it consists of a left 'Bra', < |, giving the final condition

    of a probability amplitude, and a 'Ket', giving the starting

    condition of a probability amplitude. Using this Dirac notation we

    are able to simplistically write up the general principles as the

    following:

    (3)

    both holes open = through hole 1 + through hole 2 (4)

    If we consider that the process with which the electron moves

    through a hole is a two-part movement we can rewrite the notation

    for the second general principle to include which hole the electron

    has passed through:

    both holes open = + (5)

    Because of what we discovered for the probability curve P1 2 in

    figure D, we can state the probability of the electron passing

    through one of the holes and towards the screen as32:

    P1 2 = |1 + 2|2 = | + |2 (6)

    Though, it must be said, this only occurs if we do not observe the

    electron itself. This is because of the interference of the wave

    nature of the particles. If we were to observe the electron as a

    particle then the interference pattern would cease and we would

    31 The Feynman lectures on physics Vol 3. Chapter 3, page 3.

    32 Kvantemekanik, Tom Andersen. p. 6

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 16 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    17/29

    not get the same type of probability curve as the one in figure D.

    This is is a consequence of Heisenberg's uncertainty principle.

    3.3.3 Heisenberg's uncertainty principle

    These types of experiments, were one to attempt them, would also

    be governed by another part of the uncertainty principle. As stated

    earlier, Heisenberg formulated a principle expressing that an

    observation on a system, impacts the system. This impact also

    seeks to verify the existence of a system as a lack of observation

    leads to an indefinite system which is therefore irrelevant33.

    Imagine we wanted to observe an electron's position. We would

    use a photon with a very high momentum as it gives the photon a

    very short wavelength. This way, we can measure the position ofthe electron, at impact, but it's momentum will be highly uncertain

    because of the momentum of the photon. This is formulated

    mathematically as:

    p x with =h

    2(7)

    Where h is again Planck's constant. This is a statement which says

    that the product of the uncertainties in the two conjugate

    parameters must always be greater than or equal to some small

    measure of the effect of measurement34. It turns out that

    Heisenberg's uncertainty principle also applies to the energy and

    time of a system.

    E t (8)

    Heisenberg, through other work, also managed to represent

    observations on a quantum system mathematically leading to

    33 The ideas of particle physics. p. 20

    34 The ideas of particle physics. p. 20

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 17 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    18/29

    results that were the same as the wave mechanics presented by

    Erwin Schrdinger.

    4.0 SCHRDINGER'S EQUATION

    Schrdinger formulated an equation to describe the wave mechanics of

    matter. Schrdinger used a wavefunction, , to describe how a particle's

    wavefunction evolves in space and time under a specific set of

    circumstances35.

    4.1 The equation

    Schrdinger's equation is a linear partial differential equation which is

    the QM equivalent of Newton's laws. It incorporates the time and

    space that an electron moves in and is actually a deterministic equationas we are able to predict its quantum state36. This is also a theory in

    which the electron inhabits continual states. This, argued Bohr, is not

    possible as the electron can only assume discrete energy values,

    leading to discontinuity. We shall therefore solve the equation for a

    one-dimensional box of sorts popularly called the, 'infinity square

    well', in order to prove or disprove Bohr's notion.

    4.2 The 'infinite square well'37

    We must first introduce the equation as Schrdinger left it, the time-

    dependent, three-dimensional, Schrdinger equation:

    i t

    (r , t)=2

    2 m2(r , t)+V(r , t)(r , t) (9)

    Where m is mass, V is the potential energy of the particle, 2 is the

    Laplacean (a differential operator to take the place of the three-

    dimensional coordinates), and of course is the wavefunction. For the

    'infinite square well' example we will only need a simplified, one-

    35 The ideas of particle physics. p. 19

    36 On Determinism, Sean Carroll.

    37 Quantum mechanics: infinite square well (part I)

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 18 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    19/29

    dimensional and time-independent version of the Schrdinger

    equation:

    2

    2 m

    2

    x2=V (10)

    Before we begin, we will create a sketch of what we intend to find out,

    see figure E.

    In the sketch we have shown our two

    limits, 0 and a. We have also shown that

    the potential, V, has no upper limit at the

    limits, therefore the particle cannot

    penetrate the walls. The particle is,

    however, free to move inside the well.

    That is to say, the sum of the probabilities of finding the particle inside

    the well is 1, definite, and outside the box 0.

    Now, what we can choose to do is, substitute parts of (10) so that we

    get a simple differential equation.

    2

    x2 =k2

    when k

    2

    =

    2mV

    2 (11)

    We can now solve this equation and get the following function for :

    (x )=Acos kx+B sin kx (12)

    WhereA and B are constants. We can now look back at figure E and

    see that:

    (0)=0 and (a )=0 (13)

    If we try to use some of this information in (12) we find that:

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 19 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    20/29

    (0)=A cos0+Bsin 0 (14)

    (0)=A(1)+B(0) (15)

    A=0 (16)

    We can now use (a )=0 and A=0 in (12):

    (a )=B sin ka=0 (17)

    Which means that eitherB = 0 or ka = n, where n is any whole

    integer, as we know from the unit circle that any whole integer

    multiplied by is equal to 0 when coupled with sinus. If we were to

    take B = 0, then the differential equation would always be 0 which

    means that the wavefunction would always be zero. As this would not

    satisfy our condition that the probability inside the well should be

    equal to 1, we will need to consider the alternative our only viable

    option. We can now find the energy values of the system using the

    formula which can be used to equate the different energy values for the

    different values ofn:

    As k2=

    2 mV

    2 then V=

    2

    k2

    2 m

    (18)

    Which means that V=

    2n

    2

    2

    2 ma2 because we found that k=

    n

    a

    (19)

    We will not continue further as we have found what we need in order

    to complete our picture of QM. However, it is possible to find a value

    forB so that it is possible to find the complete wavefunction and

    thereafter its probability.

    4.2.1 The quantization of energy (n = 3, 2, 1, 0)

    We can now attempt to use our findings to calculate actual values

    for the potential energy, V, in an electron. We will only attempt it

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 20 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    21/29

    for the first four values of n, taken in a reverse order. First we

    need to define our variables for an electron; it has a mass (m)

    9.10953 10-31 kg 38 and we will set our limit to 3 10-10 meters for

    a.

    Ifn = 3 then:

    V=

    2n

    2

    2

    2 ma2V(3)=

    (1.054591034)2 32 2

    2(9.109531031)(31010)2(20)

    V(3)=6.024781018Joule (21)

    Ifn = 2 then:

    V=2n

    2

    2

    2ma2V(2)=

    (1.054591034)2222

    2(9.109531031)(31010)2(22)

    V(2)=2.677681018Joule (23)

    Ifn = 1 then:

    V=

    2n

    2

    2

    2 ma2 V(1)=

    (1.054591034)212 2

    2(9.109531031)(31010)2 (24)

    V(1)=6.69421019Joule (25)

    Ifn = 0 then:

    V=2n

    2

    2

    2ma2V(0)=

    (1.054591034)2022

    2 (9.109531031)(31010)2(26)

    V(0)=0Joule (27)

    What we have discovered here is that the lowest possible value for

    n must be 1 as 0 cannot be divided. However, as we have said that

    the potential at the limits is infinite we can also assume that the

    38 Elementr Kvantefysik.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 21 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    22/29

    possibility of the electron having infinite potential is possible.

    This is also the explanation as to why the problem is called the

    'infinite square well': the electron can never actually leave the

    nucleus, as if it were in an infinite well. What we discovered

    earlier is that n must be a whole integer which means that Bohr

    was right, the electron can only assume discrete energy values,

    leading to discontinuity. If we now choose to plot our values into

    our 'infinite square well' we shall see the effect of our

    calculations:

    Figure F shows the approximate positions of the discrete energy

    levels that an electron can be at for the different integers of n. Of

    course, these values are purely theoretical as we can never

    actually measure the energy levels of electrons with such accuracy

    given Heisenberg's uncertainty principle. It has, however, helped

    proved Bohr's theory of quantization.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 22 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    23/29

    5.0 CONCLUSION

    The invention of the modern approach to science, through rigorous

    mathematics and experiments, led to classical mechanics which answered

    many questions and gave a relatively enormous understanding of the

    universe. Through the impertinence of scientists even more was achieved.

    The discovery of electro-magnetism paved the road to the discovery of the

    inner workings of the atom. This, however, led to more questions being

    raised then answered. Yet again, there was a need for understanding. Only

    through the hard work of theorists and experimentalists was this finally

    achieved. Under way, the foundation of mechanics itself was challenged. No

    longer was determinism the ultimate solution. New methods had to be

    created in order for understanding to be restored. De Broglie set, in thisregard, a continuing trend in motion. From his ideas came a better

    understanding which enabled Heisenberg to formulate his uncertainties,

    Schrdinger to create his equation and Dirac to note the system. The quest

    was not complete. Not even after the realization that a system was

    quantized; as Bohr had predicted and elaborated. Nonetheless, what can be

    concluded from our work is that Bohr was right. Electrons orbit the nucleus

    in integral numbers of de Broglie's wavelength, or in other words, in

    quantized energy states. This proves that the orbits of electrons are not

    continuous. We also found that electrons cannot have zero potential but can,

    on the other hand, have unlimited potential, never really being let go of their

    orbit around the nucleus. With these realizations it is no surprise that as

    Bohr defined the orbits as quantized states, the new mechanics came to be

    known as Quantum Mechanics.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 23 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    24/29

    6.0 RESUM

    Classical mechanics had maintained a deterministic approach to

    understanding the universe. Everything could be figured out, everything was

    specifically designed, everything had a destiny. However, this deterministic

    utopia of classical mechanics led to the evolution of Bohr's atomic model,

    further expanding to the discovery of Quantum mechanics. Here was a new

    way of understanding the universe where everything was indefinite and

    probabilistic. The universe could no longer be described by classical

    methods so new methods had to be invented, enter Heisenberg, Schrdinger

    and Dirac. Through their work, they managed to give us a blueprint of the

    workings of some of the smallest building blocks of the universe, the

    electrons. These electrons, Bohr stated, operated in quantized states, as wehave shown in our project, which was so accurate that it even lent

    inspiration to the name, 'Quantum Mechanics'.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 24 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    25/29

    7.0 APPENDIX

    I.

    From: Faye, Jan, "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum

    Mechanics", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008

    Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),

    http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/qm-copenhagen/

    Bohr's more mature view () on complementarity and the

    interpretation of quantum mechanics may be summarized in the

    following points:

    1. The interpretation of a physical theory has to rely on an

    experimental practice.

    2. The experimental practice presupposes a certain pre-scientific

    practice of description, which establishes the norm for

    experimental measurement apparatus, and consequently what

    counts as scientific experience.

    3. Our pre-scientific practice of understanding our environment is

    an adaptation to the sense experience of separation, orientation,

    identification and reidentification over time of physical objects.4. This pre-scientific experience is grasped in terms of common

    categories like thing's position and change of position, duration

    and change of duration, and the relation of cause and effect,

    terms and principles that are now parts of our common

    language.

    5. These common categories yield the preconditions for objective

    knowledge, and any description of nature has to use these

    concepts to be objective.

    6. The concepts of classical physics are merely exact

    specifications of the above categories.

    7. The classical conceptsand not classical physics itselfare

    therefore necessary in any description of physical experience in

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 25 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    26/29

    order to understand what we are doing and to be able to

    communicate our results to others, in particular in the

    description of quantum phenomena as they present themselves

    in experiments;

    8. Planck's empirical discovery of the quantization of action

    requires a revision of the foundation for the use of classical

    concepts, because they are not all applicable at the same time.

    Their use is well defined only if they apply to experimental

    interactions in which the quantization of action can be regarded

    as negligible.

    9. In experimental cases where the quantization of action plays a

    significant role, the application of a classical concept does notrefer to independent properties of the object; rather the

    ascription of either kinematic or dynamic properties to the

    object as it exists independently of a specific experimental

    interaction is ill-defined.

    10. The quantization of action demands a limitation of the use of

    classical concepts so that these concepts apply only to a

    phenomenon, which Bohr understood as the macroscopic

    manifestation of a measurement on the object, i.e. the

    uncontrollable interaction between the object and the

    apparatus.

    11. The quantum mechanical description of the object differs from

    the classical description of the measuring apparatus, and this

    requires that the object and the measuring device should be

    separated in the description, but the line of separation is not the

    one between macroscopic instruments and microscopic objects.

    It has been argued in detail (Howard 1994) that Bohr pointed

    out that parts of the measuring device may sometimes be

    treated as parts of the object in the quantum mechanical

    description.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 26 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    27/29

    12. The quantum mechanical formalism does not provide

    physicists with a pictorial representation: the -function does

    not, as Schrdinger had hoped, represent a new kind of reality.

    Instead, as Born suggested, the square of the absolute value of

    the -function expresses a probability amplitude for the

    outcome of a measurement. Due to the fact that the wave

    equation involves an imaginary quantity this equation can have

    only a symbolic character, but the formalism may be used to

    predict the outcome of a measurement that establishes the

    conditions under which concepts like position, momentum,

    time and energy apply to the phenomena.

    13. The ascription of these classical concepts to the phenomena ofmeasurements rely on the experimental context of the

    phenomena, so that the entire setup provides us with the

    defining conditions for the application of kinematic and

    dynamic concepts in the domain of quantum physics.

    14. Such phenomena are complementary in the sense that their

    manifestations depend on mutually exclusive measurements,

    but that the information gained through these various

    experiments exhausts all possible objective knowledge of the

    object.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 27 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    28/29

    8.0 BIBLIOGRAPHY

    8.1 Books

    1. Hawking Stephen, and Leonard Mlodinow. The Grand Design.

    New York: Random House, 2010.

    2. Singh, Simon. Fermats Store Stning. Trans. Jan Teuber.

    Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1997.

    3. Hermanns, William. Einstein and the Poet. N.p.: Branden

    Books, 1983.

    4. Stewart, Ian. Taming the Infinite: The Story of Mathematics.

    London: Quercus, 2008.

    5. Elvekjr, Finn, and Brge Degn Nielsen. Fysikkens Verden 3.Kbenhavn: Gjellerup & Gad, 1990.

    6. Hansen, William W., and Henrik Parbo. Elementr

    Kvantemekanik. Denmark: Systime, 1981.

    7. Coughlan, G. D., and J. E. Dodd. The Ideas of Particle Physics.

    Cambridge: Cambridge university press, 1991.

    8. du Sautoy, Marcus. The Number Mysteries. United Kingdom:

    Fourth Estate, 2010.

    9. Laplace, Pierre Simon. A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities.

    Trans. into English from the original French 6th ed. by

    Truscott, F.W. and F. L. Emory. New York: Dover Publications

    1951.

    10. Andersen, Tom. Kvantemekanik.

    11. Feynman, Richard P., Robert B. Leighton, and Matthew Sands.

    The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Volume III. United States

    of America: Cambridge Institute of Technology, 1966.

    8.2 Videos

    1. jrgoldma. Quantum Mechanics: Infinite Square Well (part I).

    2. jrgoldma. Quantum Mechanics: Infinite Square Well (part 2).

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 28 of 29

  • 8/2/2019 Foundation of Quantum Mechanics

    29/29

    3. Binney, Professor J.J.. 001 Introduction to Quantum

    Mechanics, Probability Amplitudes and Quantum States.

    University of Oxford. 11 November 2009.

    4. Binney, Professor J.J.. Dirac Notation and the Energy

    Representation. University of Oxford. 12 November 2009.

    8.3 Websites

    1. Carroll, Sean. On Determinism. Discover Magazine. 5

    December 2011.

    2. Faye, Jan. "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum

    Mechanics." The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall

    2008 Edition). Edward N. Zalta (ed.).

    3. Wikipedia. Copenhagen Interpretation.

    4. Branson. Feynman Lectures on Physics, Vol. III Chapter 1.

    22 December 2012.

    5. Banach, David. Quantum Behaviour: from Richard Feynman's

    Lectures on Physics. David Banach's Course Server.

    6. Cal Poly Ponoma. Bubble Chamber Picture.

    The Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 29 of 29