good men (final)

Upload: ssalop

Post on 05-Apr-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    1/25

    1

    A Few Righteous Men: Critical Mass in the Dynamics of Cooperation

    Serge Moresi, Charles River Associates

    Steven Salop, Georgetown University Law Center

    I. Introduction

    In the Wealth of Nations, Adam Smith (1776) wrote that it was self-interest

    guided by the invisible hand of the market that leads the economy to a beneficial

    outcome, not the benevolence or humanity of the butcher, the brewer or the baker.1

    The development of models of strategic interaction and imperfect information by Joseph

    Stiglitz and others have demonstrated the failure of the invisible hand and the ubiquity

    of market failures. Rothschild (1973), Stiglitz (1975), Spence (1976), Dixit and Stiglitz

    (1977). The failure of cooperation also is nicely illustrated in the one-shot Prisoners

    Dilemma game, where defection is the dominant strategy.

    Escape from the Prisoners Dilemma is possible with enforceable agreements,

    fear of legal, religious or social sanctions, altruism and other ethical motivations.

    Ullman-Margarlit (1977), Frank (1988). In a repeated play context, mutual cooperation

    can be sustained through reputation formation or adopting conditional cooperation

    strategies (such as TIT-FOR-TAT and GRIM).2 Shapiro (1982), Kreps and Wilson

    (1982), Axelrod (1984), Taylor (1987). [Evol Equil Cite]

    1 But see Smith (1790). See also Sen (2000).2A player using a conditional cooperation strategy starts cooperating in the first round of play, andcontinues to cooperate as long as his partner cooperated in the previous round. If his partner ever

    defects, the player stops cooperating and punishes his partner by defecting in the next round. TheTIT-FOR-TAT and GRIM strategies differ with respect to the length of the punishment. The GRIMstrategy punishes forever by never cooperating again (even if the partner learns a lesson and starts

    cooperating). The TIT-FOR-TAT strategy leaves it to the partner to decide the length of thepunishment. That is, if the partner starts cooperating while he is being punished, then TIT-FOR-TATwill resume to cooperate (so that the punishment could be as short as one round). For other kinds of

    conditional cooperation strategies, see Shubik (1959) and Taylor (1987).

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    2/25

    2

    If individuals interact in multiple business relationships over time, then conditional

    cooperation strategies would require information about previous interactions with other

    partners. In the absence of this information, incentives to cooperate would seem to be

    reduced. Someone who defects in a current relationship can exit and enter a new

    relationship tomorrow. His incentive to cooperate today might be reduced even further

    if the new partner will not know that he defected in a previous relationship.

    In the context of potentially long-term relationships, cooperators make desirable

    partners because they do not defect. Suppose there is a mass of ethical or religious

    people who never defect (and who leave their partner if he defects). These righteous

    individuals might increase or decrease the incentives of others to defect. On the one

    hand, they might be the proverbial suckers-born-every-minute. A defector could exploit

    this current cooperating partner and then exit the current relationship and find a new

    cooperating sucker to exploit tomorrow. On the other hand, they might spur cooperative

    behavior if it is the self-interest of others to cooperate in new relationships in the hope of

    achieving a long-term relationship with a righteous individual. Salop (1978). In this

    case, ethics and religion would be public goods.

    In this paper, we analyze this public goods issue. We show that under certain

    conditions, the adoption of religious/ethical norms by a critical mass will lead to a

    cooperation bandwagon and increase the equilibrium amount of cooperation. In other

    words, a critical mass of committed moral people can generate a moral rebirth for

    society at large.3

    3For example, in Genesis, God informs Abraham that He is going to destroy Sodom and Gomorrahbecause of its evil behavior. Abraham asks whether God would save the city if there were as few asfifty righteous inhabitants. When God assents, Abraham then asks about the outcome if there were

    only forty-five (or forty or fewer) righteous inhabitants, and God ultimately concludes that the city would

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    3/25

    3

    The paper is organized as follows. In Sections II and III, we set up the basic

    model without any righteous individuals and solve for the steady-state equilibria. In this

    model, there is always an equilibrium with 100% defection. Unlike standard models

    (where players cannot change partner), there is never an equilibrium with 100%

    cooperation. The incentive for opportunism is too strong. Under certain conditions,

    there are also two partial cooperation equilibria, with different incidences of cooperation.

    In Section IV, we discuss the main properties of these partial cooperation equilibria.

    In Sections V and VI, we examine the impact of adding a mass of righteous

    individuals into this model. Any mass of righteous individuals will prevent the total

    defection equilibrium. In fact, if the mass of righteous individuals is sufficiently large,

    then it will create a dynamic bandwagon effect that leads to a stable partial cooperation

    equilibrium with the higher incidence of cooperation. In addition, we show that the

    critical mass of righteous individuals (that is needed to induce other individuals to also

    cooperate) tends to zero as the individuals discount rate tends to zero. Thus, it is true

    that a moral commitment by a few righteous men can lead to a large increase in the

    degree of morality in the long run. However, it is not powerful enough to lead to

    universal cooperation.

    II. Basic Model

    At the beginning of the first period, a large number of ex ante identical individuals

    are randomly paired. Each pair then plays the following (symmetric) Prisoners

    Dilemma game: The players simultaneously decide whether to cooperate or defect. For

    now, we assume that there are no commitments. Each obtains a payoffCif they both

    be saved if there were at least ten moral inhabitants. Genesis (18;16-19:38). One possible

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    4/25

    4

    cooperate or Dif they both defect. If one player cooperates and the other defects, the

    cooperators payoff is S(for sucker payoff)and the defectors is T(for temptation

    payoff). We assume T> C> D> S, so that the game is a Prisoners Dilemma.4

    At the end of each period, after observing their payoffs, the two players

    simultaneously decide whether to stay matched in the relationship and play together

    again next period, or whether to exit the relationship and obtain a new partner from the

    pool of unmatched individuals. The players exit and are re-paired with a different

    partner unless both decide to continue with the relationship. If both decide to remain in

    the match, they play the same game again in the next period. They again will choose

    simultaneously whether to cooperate or defect. That is, we assume that individuals in a

    relationship also cannot make binding commitments about their current or future

    behavior. Similarly, if both exit and return to the pool of unmatched individuals, each

    plays again with a different partner.

    We assume that a new generation of individuals is born and arrives i n the market

    at the beginning of each period. The new generation enters the pool of unmatched

    individuals and joins the pairing process. This assumption ensures that there will

    always be a large number of unmatched individuals. At the same time, a fraction of the

    population may die and exit from their relationships or the unmatched pool. The impact

    of birth and death rates on the equilibria is discussed in Section IV. Individuals

    interpretation of this story is that the ten moral inhabitants might be enough to create a moral rebirth.4

    Axelrod (1984) makes the additional assumption that 2C > T+S. As shown in Kuhn and Moresi (1995),this additional assumption ensures that mutual cooperation is Pareto efficient relative to the set of

    mixed strategies. In Axelrods model, it also ensures that reverse TIT-FOR-TAT is nota bestresponse to TIT-FOR-TAT. In our model, however, this additional assumption is not necessarybecause cooperation can be sustained by threatening to leave a defecting partner (as opposed to

    retaliate with TIT-FOR-TAT).

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    5/25

    5

    evaluate future payoffs using a common discount factor, ? .5 For most of the analysis,

    we assume 0 < ? < 1.

    We focus our attention on steady-state equilibria in which there is a constant

    fraction ? of unmatched individuals in each period who choose to cooperate with their

    (new) partner. Similarly, among the individuals in relationships (i.e., the pairs who

    decided to stay together), a constant fraction ? of them cooperate with their (long-term)

    partner in the equilibria. In what follows, we derive the conditions under which ? > 0

    and? = 1.

    For an individual, a strategy is a complete plan of action, i.e., a set of decisions

    rules that specify the individuals behavior in every contingency in which the individual

    might be called on to act. In other words, an individuals strategy must specify what the

    individual will do in all possible circumstances. In particular, it must provide an answer

    to the following questions: (a) When the individual arrives in the market and is paired

    up with his first partner, will he cooperate or defect? (b) At the end of that first period,

    will he offer to remain with his partner for another period, or will he exit and re-enter the

    pool of unmatched individuals? (c) If he decides to exit the relationship and obtain a

    new partner, will he defect or cooperate with the new partner? (And at the end of that

    period, will he offer his new partner to stay together or will he leave him too?) (d) If both

    decide to remain matched for another period, will he cooperate or defect in that next

    period? (And at the end of that period, will he exit or will he offer to remain matched?)

    We assume that information is imperfect. Decisions in previous relationships

    are private information.6 As a result, the individual cannot condition his decision on his

    5The discount factor ?reflects both the rate of time preference and the mortality rate.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    6/25

    6

    partners history in previous relationships.7 This assumption is key to our results. It

    rules out a conditional cooperation strategy of punishing (or rewarding) new partners

    based on their conduct in past relationships with others. This assumption is central to

    our analysis because it implies that universal cooperation is never an equilibrium

    outcome, unlike the situation in standard models. In our model, a defector can exit his

    current relationship and start fresh by reentering the pool of unmatched individuals

    incognito.

    We do assume that previous decisions within the relationship are known to both

    matched players. Thus, both the decision to cooperate or defect next period and the

    exit decision can be made conditional on the partners behavior in the current period.

    III. Steady-State Equilibria

    There is always an equilibrium with zero cooperation. There is never an

    equilibrium with universal cooperation. They may be partial cooperation (i.e., less than

    universal cooperation) equilibria.

    Theorem 1. There is an equilibrium with zero cooperation (i.e., ? = ? = 0).

    The proof of Theorem 1 is straightforward. Consider the following strategy: In

    each period, I defect and then change partner. Clearly, if everybody is using that

    strategy, nobody has an incentive to use a different strategy. Therefore, if everybody

    uses that strategy then the market is in equilibrium and no cooperation ever arises.

    Theorem 2. Universal cooperation (i.e., ? = ? = 1) is notan equilibrium.

    6Nor does an individual know whether his partner is a new entrant or not.

    7One could allow his decision rule to be conditional on his own history. However, this would not change

    the set of equilibrium outcomes.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    7/25

    7

    The proof of Theorem 2 is also straightforward. If all the unmatched people

    always cooperate, each individual has an incentive to defect and change partner in

    every period. Thus, universal cooperation is not an equilibrium.

    While universal cooperation is not possible, under certain conditions, there are

    partial cooperation equilibria. By partial cooperation, we mean a situation in which

    only a fraction of the unmatched individuals cooperate (i.e., 0 < ? < 1), and all the

    matched individuals in long -term relationships cooperate (i.e., ? = 1). We now derive

    the necessary and sufficient conditions for these equilibria to exist.

    Let EW(d) be the expected present value of the current and future payoffs of an

    unmatched individual who decides to defect on the partner he is paired with in the

    current period. Similarly, let EW(c) be the expected present value of the current and

    future payoffs of an unmatched individual who decides to cooperate with his current

    partner. We then have:

    EW(d) = ? T + (1-?)D + ? max{EW(d),EW(c)}, (1)

    where ? T+(1-?)Dis the expected payo ff from defecting in the current period, given that

    a fraction ? of unmatched individuals cooperates and a fraction 1-? defects. The term ?

    max{EW(d),EW(c)} is the present value of future payoffs, given that the individual will

    re-optimize his strategy at the beginning of next period. (We will check later that an

    individual who defects will indeed be thrown back into the pool of unmatched

    individuals.)

    Similarly, if an unmatched individual cooperates, we have:

    EW(c) = ? C/(1-?) + (1-?)[S +? max{EW(d),EW(c)}]. (2)

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    8/25

    8

    Intuitively, his partner will also cooperate with probability ? , and the two players will

    decide to enter a long-term relationship of mutual cooperation. (We will check later that

    they indeed have an incentive to stay together and cooperate.) Thus, the expected total

    payoff is equal to C/(1-? ) with probability ? . With probability (1-? ) his partner defects

    and the two players then exit and re-enter the pool of unmatched individuals. (We will

    check later that they indeed have an incentive to terminate their relationship.) The

    expected total payoff is then equal to Sin the current period plus ? max{EW(d),EW(c)}

    in future periods.

    In any equilibrium with partial cooperation, an unmatched individual must be

    indifferent between defecting and cooperating (since individuals are identical ex ante),

    that is,

    EW(d) = EW(c). (3)

    One can show that Equation (3) is quadratic in ? , i.e., of the form:

    A? 2- B? + F = 0, where (4)

    A =? (T - D), F = (1-?)(D - S ) and B = A + F - (T - C). (5)

    By the quadratic formula, Equation (4) has two solutions, i.e.:

    ? 1 = [B - (B2 4AF)1/2] / (2A), and (6)

    ? 2 = [B + (B2 4AF)1/2] / (2A). (7)

    There are two real solutions (? 1and ? 2) that lie between 0 and 1, if and only if:8

    B2> 4AF, B > 0, and 2A > B + (B2-4AF)1/2. (8)

    8One can show that the two solutions are either both smaller than 1 or both greater than 1.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    9/25

    9

    These conditions are necessary for a steady-state equilibrium with partial

    cooperation to exist. However, an additional condition is needed for sufficiency. In

    particular, we need to show that ? =1, that is, that a matched individual prefers to

    cooperate again with his (old) partner rather than defect on the second play and go

    back to the pool of unmatched individuals. It is better to cooperate again if and only if:

    C/(1-?) ? T + ? EWi, (9)

    where EWi is the expected present value of the current and future payoffs of an

    unmatched individual when ? =? i.

    Intuitively, suppose that all the pairs of matched individuals cooperate and stay

    together. The expected present value of the current and future payoffs of a individual

    that remains matched in a long-term relationship equals C/(1-?). If a matched individual

    instead unilaterally decided to defect on his old cooperating partner, his payoff would be

    equal to Tin the current period (since his old partner is cooperating) plus ? EWi in

    future periods (since his old partner would exit at the end of the current period).

    Equation (9) thus says that a matched individual prefers to maintain mutual cooperation

    with his old partner rather than defect and go back to the pool of unmatched individuals.

    Using Equations (1) and (3), we have:

    EWi = [? iT + (1-? i)D] / (1-?). (10)

    This is the expected utility of an unmatched individual who defects and changes partner

    in every period. Substituting Equation (10) into Equation (9), we have the condition for

    a player to prefer to remain in a cooperative relationship,

    T - C ? ? (1-? i) (T D). (11)

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    10/25

    10

    This is an additional necessary condition for a partial cooperation equilibrium to exist.

    This also leads to the following theorem and corollary.

    Theorem 3. There are two symmetric partial cooperation mixed strategy

    equilibria if and only if the conditions in Equations (8) and (11) are satisfied. In that

    case, the common probability of cooperation among unmatched individuals in the two

    equilibria (? 1 and ? 2) are given by Equations (6) and (7), respectively.

    Corollary to Theorem 3. There are two partial cooperation pure strategy

    equilibria in which a fraction ? 1 (or ? 2) of unmatched individuals cooperate and a

    fraction 1-? 1 (or 1-? 2) defect with certainty.

    To summarize, partial cooperation can be sustained as an equilibrium by

    adopting the following three-pronged strategy: (1) When placed in the pool of

    unmatched individuals with a new partner, the player cooperates with probability ? (and

    defects with probability 1-? ). (2) If the current outcome is not mutual cooperation, then

    the player exits the relationship and re-enters the pool of unmatched individuals. If the

    current outcome is mutual cooperation, then the player offers to stay together for

    another period. (Of course, if his partner decides to exit, then the player re-enters the

    pool of unmatched individuals.) (3) If both players in a period each choose to stay

    together, then the player cooperates with probability 1 in the next period. (After that

    play, the player follows Rule 2 again to decide whether or not to exit the relationship.) 9

    9The partial cooperation equilibria can also be supported by an alternative three-pronged strategy where

    both Rule 2 and Rule 3 are different from those described above. The modified Rule 2 is: If his partnerdefected in the current period, the player terminates the relationship and re-enters the pool ofunmatched individuals. If instead his partner cooperated, the player offers to stay together one more

    period. The modified Rule 3 is: If both players in a period each choose to stay together then, in thenext period, the player cooperates with probability 1 if both players always cooperated (and he defectswith probability 1 if they did not always cooperate). If all the individuals change both Rule 2 and Rule 3

    in this way, the market remains in equilibrium and the outcome is not affected. One can prove this

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    11/25

    11

    The proof of Theorem 3 (and the Corollary) is contained in the Appendix. In a

    nutshell, the proof involves showing that deviating from the three-pronged equilibrium

    strategy reduces a players returns, when the conditions in Equations (8) and (11) are

    satisfied.10 For example, when T= 5, C= 3, D= 1 and S= 0, the conditions are

    satisfied if ? = 0.9. The conditions in Theorem 3 are less likely to be satisfied for lower

    discount factors.11

    IV. Equilibrium Properties

    We assume hereafter that the conditions of Theorem 3 are satisfied at both ? =? 1

    and ? =? 2, so that there are two equilibria with partial cooperation (in addition to the

    equilibrium with no cooperation).

    The following comparative statics results are straightforward and are thus stated

    without proof:12

    i) An increase in the discount factor (? ) reduces ? 1 and increases ? 2.

    ii) As?

    tends to 1,?

    1 tends to zero and?

    2tends to (C-D)/(T-D).

    iii ) An increase in the payoff from mutual cooperation (C) reduces ? 1 and increases

    ? 2.

    iv) As Ctends to T, ? 1 tends to F/A and ? 2tends to 1.

    These results are generally intuitive. As individuals become more patient, the

    high cooperation equilibrium incidence of cooperation (? 2) increases. However, even

    when individuals are infinitely patient (i.e., as ? ? 1), the high cooperation equilibrium

    version of Theorem 3 by showing that the modified three-pronged strategy is also a symmetric

    equilibrium strategy. The proof is available upon request from the authors.10

    We ignore the possibility of a single partial cooperation equilibrium when B2

    = 4AFin Equations (6) and(7). As discussed in the section VI, this equilibrium is unstable.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    12/25

    12

    falls short of universal cooperation (i.e., ? 2< 1). This is not surprising in light of

    Theorem 2. The result that the high cooperation equilibrium increases with the payoff

    from mutual cooperation (C) is also very intuitive. Not surprisingly, as Ctends to T, the

    temptation to defect vanishes and universal cooperation becomes possible in

    equilibrium.

    We now turn to the population dynamics. The steady-state equilibria involve a

    constant fraction of cooperating individuals in the unmatched pool in every period. With

    constant and exogenous birth rate band mortality rate m, the population growth rate is

    equal to b-m.13

    Given that a fraction ? of unmatched individuals cooperate, one can

    show that the fraction Rof unmatched individuals in the entire population converges

    to:14

    11In the example, the equilibrium conditions are not satisfied if ? = 0.8.

    12These results follow directly from differentiating Equations (7) and (8).

    13If b

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    13/25

    13

    R = [b + (1-m)m] / [b + (1-m)m + (1-m)2? 2)]. (13)

    Thus, as long as there are positive births and deaths, the pool of unmatched individuals

    does not disappear. The steady-state fraction of unmatched individuals, R, is higher if

    the birth rate is higher, if the mortality rate is higher, or if the fraction of cooperative

    unmatched individuals is lower (all else equal).

    The mortality rate also affects the discount rate, i.e., the discount factor ? equals

    (1-m)/(1+r), where ris the rate of time preference. A higher mortality rate thus implies a

    lower discount factor, which in turn affects the equilibrium fraction of cooperative

    unmatched individuals, increasing ? 1 and reducing ? 2. Comparing the high cooperation

    equilibria, an increase in the mortality rate leads to a new steady state in which the

    unmatched individuals cooperate less (? 2falls)and account for a greater fraction of the

    population (Rrises). The fraction of defectors in society equals (1-? 2)R, and hence

    increases with the mortality rate.15

    V. Committed Cooperators

    In this section, we assume that the market is initially in a steady-state equilibrium

    with zero cooperation (i.e., ? = ? = 0) and the entire population is in the pool of

    unmatched individuals (i.e., R=1). We then assume that a fraction ?of the population

    become righteous individuals (i.e., committed cooperators). The behavior of righteous

    individuals is exogenous; they cooperate in every period and change partner if and only

    if their current partner defects. We assume that righteousness reproduces itself in

    Ris a stable steady state since the derivative of Rt+1 with respect to Rt is less than 1.15

    Comparing the low cooperation equilibria, an increase in the mortality rate leads to a new steady state

    in which the unmatched individuals cooperate more (? 1 rises). In this case, the effect on the fraction R

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    14/25

    14

    families; the offspring of righteous individuals also are righteous. The remaining fraction

    1-? of the population are maximizers and their behavior is endogenous (as in the

    previous sections).

    We assume that an individuals type (i.e., whether he is righteous or a maximizer)

    is private information. However, it is common knowledge that a fraction ?of the current

    population are righteous individuals. In addition, it is also common knowledge that

    maximizers and righteous individuals have the same mortality rate (m) and the same

    birth rate (b), so that the fraction of righteous individuals in the entire population remains

    constant over time.

    Suppose for the moment that the maximizers do not change their behavior

    despite the presence of righteous individuals. That is, each maximizer continues to

    defect and change partner in every period. We then can derive the following

    relationship between the fraction Rtof unmatched individuals in the entire population (in

    period t) and the fraction ? tof cooperating individuals in the pool of unmatched

    individuals:

    1 - Rt + Rt? t = ?. (14)

    Note that in the period in which the righteous individuals are first introduced into the

    model (say, period T), we have ? T=? and RT=1. Then, in the following periods (i.e.,

    periods T+1, T+2, etc.), both ? t and Rtfall over time as righteous individuals are

    randomly matched together and enter long-term relationships.

    of unmatched individuals is ambiguous. The ? 1 equilibrium, however, is unstable, as explained in

    Section VI.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    15/25

    15

    One can show that, if the maximizers continue to defect and change partner in

    every period, then Rt and ? twill converge to R(?) and ? (?), respectively, where R(?) and

    ? (?) are the solution of Equations (13) and (14). In particular, ? (?) is the steady-state

    fraction of righteous individuals in the pool of unmatched individuals as a function of the

    fraction ? of righteous individuals in the entire population. One can then show that ? >0

    implies ? (?) >0. Thus, the market outcome will never converge to a steady state

    equilibrium with zero cooperation. There will always be at least a fraction ? (?) of

    unmatched individuals who cooperate (even if all the maximizers defect).

    Consider the case in which the fraction of righteous individuals is relatively small,

    i.e., ?< ? 1. It can nonetheless have an effect on the equilbrium selected. The two

    partial cooperation equilibria described in Theorem 3 are still equilibria. For example,

    the market outcome could move to the high cooperation equilibrium if a fraction (? 2-

    ?)/(1-?) of maximizers decided to cooperate in period T(so that a fraction ? 2of

    unmatched individuals would be cooperating in period T). In period T+1, and in each of

    the following periods, the fraction of unmatched individuals who cooperate could then

    remain equal to ? 2. Thus, the introduction of righteous individuals into the model could

    result in the market moving immediately from the zero cooperation equilibrium to the

    high cooperation equilibrium.16

    In fact, such an immediate jump to the high cooperation equilibrium is possible

    even without introducing any righteous individuals. This is because there is no inertia

    in the pool of unmatched maximizers. That is, an unmatched maximizer is constantly

    16In this case, the fraction of matched individuals in the entire population and the fraction of cooperatingindividuals among unmatched maximizers would gradually increase over time and converge to their

    steady-state level.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    16/25

    16

    re-optimizing his behavior and nothing in the model prevents him from switching to

    cooperation overnight (if that is what he wants to do). More realistically, however,

    individuals do not constantly re-optimize their behavior, and hence the transition from

    zero cooperation to high cooperation would not occur overnight. We return to this point

    in Section VI.

    Consider next the case in which the fraction of righteous individuals is relatively

    large, i.e., ?> ? 1, and assume for simplicity that ?< ? 2. As explained above, the high

    cooperation equilibrium (? =? 2) is still an equilibrium and can be reached immediately.

    However, if ? (?)>? 1, the low cooperation equilibrium (? =? 1) will no longer be a steady-

    state equilibrium. This also leads to the following theorem.

    Theorem 4. For constant birth and mortality rates (b,m), if ? >?*then the only

    steady state equilibrium is the high cooperation equilibrium, where:

    2

    1

    2

    1

    2

    1)1()1(

    )1()1(*

    ?

    ???

    mmmb

    mmmb

    ????

    ????? . (15)

    The proof of Theorem 4 is straightforward. As explained above, ? (?) is the

    steady-state fraction of righteous individuals in the pool of unmatched people as a

    function of the fraction ? of righteous individuals in the entire population, and assuming

    that all the maximizers always defect and change partner. Thus, the inverse function

    ?(?) is the fraction of righteous individuals in the entire population that is needed to

    ensure that the fraction of cooperating unmatched individuals will always be greater or

    equal to ? .17 The right-hand side of Equation (15) is equal to ?(? 1), and thus the fraction

    of cooperating unmatched individuals will always be greater than ? 1 if ? >?*(even if all

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    17/25

    17

    the maximizers always defect). It follows that the only steady-state equilibrium is the ? 2

    equilibrium.

    Corollary of Theorem 4. As the discount factor ? tends to 1, the critical mass ?*

    of righteous individuals tends to zero. In the limit, the only steady-state equilibrium is

    the high-cooperation equilibrium regardless of how small the fraction of righteous

    individuals.

    This result supports the view that a few righteous men may well be enough to

    move society from no cooperation to a high incidence of cooperation.18

    VI. Stability and Dynamics

    In this section, we consider the alternative assumption that maximizers do not

    constantly re-optimize their behavior. This alternative assumption is a useful device to

    assess the stability and dynamics of the equilibria described above. Initially, suppose

    that each maximizer must choose a strategy only once in his lifetime. In particular,

    suppose that when he first arrives into the market, he must decide once and for all for

    his whole life whether to be either (i) meanspirited, that is, always defect and change

    partner in every period, or (ii) gracious, that is, always cooperate in every period and

    change partner if and only if his current partner defects. The offspring of the original

    mass of righteous individuals are all righteous themselves. Therefore, in each period,

    the only individuals who choose their behavior are the new generation of maximizers.

    As above, we assume that an individuals type is private information.

    Figure 1 shows the expected payoff of a maximizer who decides to become

    gracious. His expected payoff is the line labeled EWGand is a function of the fraction ?

    17The function ?(?) can be obtained by using Equation (13) to substitute for Rin Equation (14).

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    18/25

    18

    of unmatched individuals who cooperate. Similarly, the line labeled EWM is the

    expected payoff of a maximizer who decides to become meanspirited.19 One can check

    that the results of the previous sections still hold. On Figure 1, the two points where the

    two lines intersect correspond to the two partial cooperation equilibria (and the origin to

    the zero cooperation equilibrium).

    In addition, Figure 1 shows that the partial cooperation equilibrium with a low

    incidence of cooperation (? 1) is unstable. Indeed, if ? is slightly smaller (greater) than

    ? 1, then EWG is smaller (greater) than EWM. Thus, starting at ? =? 1, if ? falls (increases)

    by a small amount, then the new generations of maximizers will choose to be

    meanspirited (gracious) which will further reduce (increase) the fraction ? of

    cooperating unmatched individuals. If the market is initially to the left of ? 1, the market

    will converge to the zero cooperation equilibrium (assuming that there are no

    exogenously righteous cooperators among the new generations of individuals). If

    instead the market is initially to the right of ? 1, then it will converge to the high

    cooperation equilibrium (? 2).20 In this model, the maximizers make a one-time decision

    of whether to act cooperatively in all their relationships. In contrast, in the basic

    equilibrium model with committed cooperators, the maximizers choose each period

    18The proof follows directly from Equation (15) and the fact that ? 1 tends to 0 as ? tends to 1.

    19 EWMand EWGare different from EW(d) and EW(c) (as defined by Equations (1) and (2)) because here

    a maximizer must choose whether to defect or cooperate and must then stick to his decision for therest of his life. However, the equation EWM= EWGhas the same two solutions, ? 1 and ? 2, as theequation EW(d) = EW(c). Intuitively, if an unmatched individual is indifferent between cooperating and

    defecting, then it does not matter whether the individual can or cannot re-optimize his decision infuture periods.

    20It is standard practice in stability analysis to assume that individuals react to each other sequentially

    and myopically. That is, each maximizer (among the new generation) sequentially chooses whether to

    become gracious or meanspirited, assuming that the fraction ? of cooperating unmatched individuals

    will remain constant at its current level. Under this assumption, the critical mass ?*of Theorem 4 can

    be reduced to ?*=? 1.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    19/25

    19

    whether to act cooperatively. These two models can be viewed as extreme cases along

    a continuum. That is, an intermediate model could assume that the maximizers make

    an initial choice but then revisit their choice with some probability each period. That

    model would behave similarly to the model set out in this section.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    20/25

    20

    References

    Axelrod, Robert. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Dixit, Avinash and Stiglitz, Joseph E. 1977. Monopolistic Competition and Optimum

    Product Diversity. American Economic Review67, 297-308.

    Frank, Robert. 1988. Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of the Emotions. NewYork: W.W. Norton.

    Kreps, David L. and Wilson, Robert. 1982. Reputation and Imperfect Information.Journal of Economic Theory27, 253-79.

    Kuhn, Steven and Moresi, Serge. 1995. Pure and Utilitarian Prisoners Dilemmas.Economics and Philosophy11, 333-43.

    Rothschild, Michael. 1973. Models of Market Organization with Imperfect Information: ASurvey. Journal of Political Economy81, 1283-1308.

    Salop, Steven C. 1978. Parables of Information Transmission in Markets. In The Effectof Information on Consumer and Market Behavior, ed. A. Mitchell: American MarketingAssociation.

    Sen, Amartya. 2000. What Difference Can Ethics Make?Presented at the InternationalMeeting on Ethics and Development of the Inter-American Development Bank.http://www.iadb.org/etica/ingles/lis-doc1-i.cfm.

    Shapiro, Carl. 1982. Consumer Information, Product Quality, and Seller Reputation. BellJournal of Economics13, 20-35.

    Shubik, Martin. 1959. Strategy and Market Structure: Competition, Oligopoly, and theTheory of Games. New York: Wiley.

    Smith, Adam. 1776 (republished 1910). An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of theWealth of Nations.London: Dent & Sons.

    Smith, Adam. 1790 (republished 1976). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Oxford:Clarendon Press.

    Spence, A. Michael. 1976. Product Selection, Fixed Costs, and Monopolistic Competition.Review of Economic Studies43, 217-35.

    Stiglitz, Joseph E. 1975. Information and Economic Analysis. In Current EconomicProblems,eds. Parkin and Nobay, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 27-52.

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    21/25

    21

    Taylor, Michael. 1987. The Possibility of Cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

    Ullmann-Margalit, Edna. 1977. The Emergence of Norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    < Add Cite to Evolutionary Equilibrium article>

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    22/25

    22

    Appendix: Proof of Theorem 3

    Suppose that every individual uses the three-pronged strategy with ? =? i (where

    either ? i=? 1for every individual, or ? i=? 2for every individual). The proof of Theorem 3

    consists in showing that no individual has an incentive to unilaterally change strategy if

    the conditions in Equations (8) and (11) hold.

    We begin with a few observations. First, the fraction of unmatched individuals who

    cooperate is equal to ? i (since there is a large number of unmatched individuals).

    Second, if an unmatched individual unilaterally decides to defect, then his expected

    payoff is given by Equation (1) since his current and future partners are using Rule 1

    and Rule 2. If instead he decides to cooperate, then his expected payoff is given by

    Equation (2) if the individual himself is using Rule 2 and Rule 3. Therefore, if the

    individual uses Rule 2 and Rule 3, then he has no incentive to (unilaterally) change Rule

    1. Indeed, the individual is indifferent between defecting and cooperating with a new

    partner. This follows from the conditions in Equation (8) and the definition of ? i. We are

    thus left with proving that the individual has no incentive to change Rule 2 or Rule 3 (or

    both).

    Third, according to Rule 2, if the current relationship is not one of mutual

    cooperation, then the individual terminates the relationship. If instead the individual

    decides to offer his partner to stay together (despite the lack of mutual cooperation), the

    individuals expected payoff does not change because his partner terminates the

    relationship anyway (given the lack of mutual cooperation). Thus, the individual has no

    incentive to change Rule 2 in this way (even if he can also change Rule 1 and Rule 3 at

    the same time).

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    23/25

    23

    Fourth, according to Rule 2, if the current relationship is one of mutual

    cooperation, then the individual offers his partner to stay together. Suppose that the

    individual instead decides to terminate the relationship, and let EWibe his expected

    payoff evaluated at the beginning of the following period. Consider now the alternative

    decision of staying with his old partner one more period and defect on him in that

    period. This would give the individual a payoff equal to T +? EWi, which is necessarily

    greater than EWi. (Indeed, EWi > T +? EWiis not possible since it implies EWi > T/(1-

    ?), and T/(1-?) is the maximum feasible payoff.) Therefore, it is not a rational decision to

    terminate a relationship of mutual cooperation (given that the partner is using the three-

    pronged strategy). It follows from this observation (and the previous one) that the

    individual has no incentive to change Rule 2. We are left with checking the rationality of

    Rule 3.

    According to Rule 3, if an individual stays with his partner, then he cooperates.

    Given that his partner is cooperating and willing to stay together, the individual will have

    no incentive to terminate the relationship. Thus, if the individual follows Rule 3, the two

    players will stay together and cooperate in every period. This gives the individual an

    expected payoff equal to C/(1-?).

    Suppose that the individual instead decides to defect on his old partner. Since

    the latter is using Rule 3 and Rule 2, the individual obtains a payoff equal to Tin the

    current period and then goes back to the pool of unmatched people. There are two

    cases to consider:

    a) Suppose it is optimal to defect on new partners. Then, the individuals

    expected future payoff is equal to ? EWi, where EWi is given by Equation (10). Thus,

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    24/25

    24

    his total payoff from defecting on his old partner is equal to T +? EWi, which is not

    greater than C/(1-?) because of condition (11). Therefore, in this case, the individual

    has no incentive to change Rule 3.

    b) Suppose instead that it is optimal to cooperate with new partners. Then, the

    individuals expected future payoff is equal to ? EWi, where:

    EWi = (1-? i)(S +? EWi) +? i(C +? (T +? EWi)). (A1)

    Intuitively, with probability 1-? i, his new partner will defect and thus his future payoff will

    equal Sin that period plus ? EWiin the following periods. With probability ? i, his new

    partner will cooperate and thus his future payoff will equal Cin that period plus ? (T +?

    EWi) in the following periods. (If it is rational to defect on the current old partner, it will

    also be rational to defect on future old partners.) Thus, his total payoff from defecting

    on his old partner equals T +? EWi, where EWiis given by Equation (A1). One can

    then check that T +? EWiis smaller than C/(1-?) because of condition (11). This

    shows that the individual has no incentive to change Rule 3. This also completes the

    proof of Theorem 3.

    Finally, the Corollary of Theorem 3 follows from three observations. First, the

    pure-strategy and mixed-strategy equilibria differ with respect to Rule 1 only. Second,

    in a pure-strategy equilibrium, each individual faces the same decision problems as in

    the corresponding mixed-strategy equilibrium (because there is a large number of

    unmatched individuals). Third, each unmatched individual is indifferent between

    cooperating and defecting. Thus, any strategy profile where Rule 1 results in a fraction

    ? iof cooperating unmatched individuals is an equilibrium strategy profile (holding Rule 2

    and Rule 3 unchanged).

  • 8/2/2019 Good Men (Final)

    25/25

    Figure 1: Steady-State Equilibria(T=35,C=25, D=10, S=0, d=0.9)

    0

    50

    100

    150

    200

    250

    300

    350

    400

    0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1

    EWM

    EWG

    aa1 a2