greco. error

Upload: caduff

Post on 02-Apr-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    1/10

    Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696

    The ambivalence of error: scientific ideology in the history of

    the life sciences and psychosomatic medicine

    Monica Greco*

    Department of Sociology, Goldsmiths College, University of London, New Cross, London SE14 6NW, UK

    Abstract

    This paper discusses the concept of scientific ideology as it appears in the work of the historian and philosopher ofmedicine Georges Canguilhem, whose work is becoming increasingly well known and used amongst anglophone social

    scientists. Whilst addressing the problematic of legitimacy and illegitimacy in the history of science, the concept of

    scientific ideology does something different and more complex than either the opposition between science and false

    science, or the one between orthodoxy and heresy, allow for. On the one hand, it enables us to preserve a crucial

    acknowledgment of the specificity of science in general, and of medical science in particular. On the other hand, it also

    allows us to challenge the sharp contrast between science and non-science by setting that contrast in a diachronic

    perspective. Drawing also on the work of Isabelle Stengers, the last part of the paper discusses an application of the

    concept of scientific ideology in relation to the field of psychosomatic medicine and psychoneuroimmunology.

    r 2003 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved.

    Keywords: Canguilhem; History of science; Psychosomatic medicine; Psychoneuroimmunology

    Introduction

    The opposition of orthodoxy and heresy self-con-

    sciously differs from the distinction between science and

    false or pseudo-science in that it explicitly avoids

    ascribing a privileged status to science as a form of

    knowledge, suggesting in fact that it can be analyzed in

    the same terms as religion. At the same time, just like

    science and false science, orthodoxy and heresy describe

    forms of legitimacy and illegitimacy.

    This paper discusses the concept of scientificideology as it appears in the work of the historian

    and philosopher of medicine Georges Canguilhem,

    whose work is becoming increasingly well known and

    used amongst anglophone social scientists (see Osborne

    & Rose, 1998). Whilst addressing the problematic of

    legitimacy and illegitimacy in the history of science, the

    concept of scientific ideology does something different

    and more complex than either the opposition between

    science and false science, or the one between orthodoxy

    and heresy, allow for. On the one hand, as I hope to

    illustrate, it enables us to preserve a crucial acknowl-

    edgment of the specificity of science in general, and of

    medical science in particular. On the other hand, it also

    allows us to challenge the sharp contrast between science

    and non-science by setting the contrast within a

    diachronic perspective.

    This is not the place to attempt a systematic

    introduction to the content and context of Canguilhems

    thought.1

    For those not already familiar with his work,however, it is important to mention that Canguilhems

    originality as a historian and philosopher of science lies

    partly in his choice to focus on the life sciences

    biology, medicine, and psychologyand in his life-long

    endeavor to describe and account for their specific

    rationality. He argued that these sciences, which differ

    from physics, mathematics, or chemistry in their degree

    of formalization and fitness for mathematisation, lead us

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    *Corresponding author. Institut fuer Sozialforschung, Senck-

    enberganlage 26 Frankfurt-am-Main 60325, Germany.

    E-mail address:[email protected] (M. Greco).

    1Useful starting points are Foucault (1989), Tiles (1987),

    Osborne and Rose (1998), Spicker (1987) and Bowker and

    Latour (1987).

    0277-9536/03/$ - see front matter r 2003 Elsevier Science Ltd. All rights reserved.

    doi:10.1016/S0277-9536(03)00220-X

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    2/10

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    3/10

    order to understand them in their proper context, it is

    necessary to turn to the epistemology of Gaston

    Bachelard, who was Canguilhems mentor and prede-

    cessor as professor of the history and philosophy of

    science at the Sorbonne. The concept of scientific

    ideology, as we shall see, represents both a continuation

    and a transformation of Bachelards legacy.

    Gaston Bachelard: judgement and the history of science

    Gaston Bachelard described his epistemological pro-

    ject as an attempt to provide a philosophy that was

    adequate to the movement of contemporary science.

    Living and writing in the first half of the 20th century,

    Bachelard witnessed what Mary Tiles describes as

    traumatic changes in the character of physics through

    the emergence of relativity theory and quantum

    mechanics. As Tiles explains (1987, pp. 143144):

    [These] were not just theories to be added to the

    existing stock, or to replace parts of that stock. Their

    acceptance entailed the disruption of the whole

    framework of classical physics; its concepts of space,

    time causality and substance, concepts definitive not

    only of the thought-space of physics but also,

    according to Kant, constitutive of our conception

    of the objective, physical world and thus vital to the

    way in which the distinction is drawn between inner

    and outer, subject and object.

    The word traumatic is therefore significant, since these

    changes were experienced and interpreted as a disrup-

    tion in the very order of reason, calling for a

    reconstruction capable of accommodating the possibility

    of a new disruption in the future. In Bachelards own

    words, a philosophy which professes to be adequate for

    scientific thought, which is in a constant state of

    evolution, must expect that scientific knowledge will

    [a]ffect the structure of the mind (Bachelard, 1968).

    The point worth noting, which gives us the key to

    many of the other features of Bachelards thought, is

    that he presents the structure of the mind as

    dependent on scienceit is shaped by science. This isthe reason why a philosophy adequate for scientific

    thought cannot be a philosophy grounded in a

    metaphysical and unchanging faculty of reason, or in

    the subject understood as a given. Quite the reverse,

    reason is the product of sciencenot its raw material.

    Reason is instructed by science, in the sense that its

    objects and concepts are never immediate givens, but

    always objects and concepts that have already been

    produced through the work of science itself.

    In the most synthetic terms, Bachelard describes

    science as a form of work, a form of work mediated by

    instruments. The role of instruments is crucial; they are

    not simply aids to the scientist, they are organs of

    intelligence (Canguilhem, 1975a, p. 191), which reor-

    ganize and transform what is given, which create the

    real. To quote again from Bachelard (1951, p. 84):

    Contemporary science has entirely broken with the

    prehistory of sensory data. It thinks through its

    instruments, not through its sense organs. Thisinnovation does not merely mark a peculiarity of

    contemporary science; it throws an entirely different

    interpretation on what scientists in the past were doing

    as well.

    The work of science is also described as a work of

    verification, in the etymological sense that it is a work of

    making true. This is an important point for it reminds us

    that just as reason is the product and not the a priori

    condition of science, so scientific truth is the product of

    a reorganization of experience. In fact, for Bachelard

    what the work of science performs is not discovery, but

    rather a gesture of refusalof saying no to theimmediacy of phenomena.2 Canguilhem (1975a, p. 191)

    coins the term antilogics in order to describe this

    gesture: it is the refusal to receive ready-made concepts,

    designated objects, an ordinary language; and corre-

    spondingly, it is the decision y to reorganize the order

    of syntaxy to produce phenomena instead of register-

    ing them. This is the reason why, for Bachelard and

    Canguilhem alike, science is not entirely equivalent to

    other forms of culturea point to which I shall return

    below.

    Through its work of reorganization, science thus sets

    new norms for the use of rational categories. As an

    example, Bachelard offers the case of arithmetics.

    Arithmetics, he claims, is not founded on reason; it is

    reason that is founded on elementary arithmetics, since

    this practice has repeatedly confirmed itself to be an

    efficient and consistent system of organization of

    experienceso much so that it would be unthinkable

    to abandon it. What would be a function without

    occasions for functioning? What would be a reason

    without occasions for reasoning? (1988, p. 144). He

    cites the mathematician Destouche as saying that if

    arithmetics should, in a hypothetical future, reveal itself

    to be contradictory, reason would be reformed to erase

    the contradiction and arithmetics would be preservedintact. Bachelard goes further: he suggests that what

    might in fact happen is not that a contradiction suddenly

    appears within arithmetics, but that the practical need

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    2For a powerful illustration of the epistemological break

    that science operates with respect to everyday categories, see pp.

    7582 of Lactivit!e rationaliste de la physique contemporaine

    (1951) where Bachelard compares how the term corpuscule is

    understood in physics and philosophy. The commonsense and

    philosophical use of terms such as corpuscule, mass, or

    temperature bears the inherited traces, or a mixture of traces,

    of the concepts of outdated sciences.

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696 689

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    4/10

    arises for a contradictory use of arithmetics, calling for a

    transformation of reason.

    To reiterate once more: reason, for Bachelard, cannot

    be known independently of its applications because it is

    generated through those applications. The inadequacies

    of the applications are, accordingly, the inadequacies of

    reason, and scientific progress is the rectification of thoseinadequacies. This is the sense in which Bachelard (1951,

    p. 27) understands scientific development to be the

    progress of rationalism, and the history of science to be

    the history of the defeats of irrationalism. This notion

    of rationalismfor which Bachelard coined the expres-

    sion applied rationalismis therefore necessarily a

    form ofhistorical reason, laden with the full implications

    of historicity. These implications refer, on the one hand,

    to the future: scientific truth, understood not as what is

    revealed but as what is produced, is explicitly provi-

    sional and always subject to correction. On the other

    hand, the past of science stands as a series of irrevocableprecedents, and new science can only emerge as a

    function of them.

    On this basis, it seems clear that contemporary

    scienceand hence reasoncannot but look upon its

    past with a discriminating eye. Episodes in the history of

    science cluster around two opposite poles, one positive

    and one negative, according to whether they can be seen

    as contributions or obstacles towards the present state of

    knowledge/reason. The provisional character of the

    truth spoken by contemporary science means, of course,

    that the judgment of value it imparts on historical

    episodes is equally open to correction. We have, in this

    sense, a form of relativity. But it should be stressed that

    the task of pronouncing a judgment cannot be eschewed,

    and this profoundly distinguishes Bachelards position

    from a form of relativism.

    Relativity not relativism

    It will be instructive to consider the relativist position

    in more detail for the benefit of comparison. Kuhns

    account of scientific activity in terms of the conventional

    norms of communities was read by many in the social

    sciences as producing a circular definition of thedistinctive character of science: science appears to be

    simply what we find practiced in a scientific community

    and vice versa (see Lakatos & Musgrave, 1970). This, in

    turn, encouraged interpretations of his work as a

    defence of irrationalism, and as a refusal of the notion

    of scientific progress. Despite the fact that Kuhn

    explicitly attempted to counteract this reading of his

    work (Kuhn, 1970, postscript), it was embraced by some

    social scientists. The positions of Barry Barnes offer a

    good, if not the most recent, example of this form of

    relativism. The borderline between science and non-

    science (and between true and false science in a historical

    sense), according to Barnes (1982), is a matter of

    convention. This line circumscribes a finite aggregate

    of concrete examples of science without implying that

    they share a common essence or rationality. Under-

    standing where the borderline lies, Barnes maintains,

    requires not the formulation of a principle of demarca-

    tion, but the empirical study of the social processesthrough which it is sustained and made visible.

    Similarly, to prefer one paradigm to another ultimately

    comes down to expressing a preference for one way of

    life over another; the emergence of paradigms is the

    result of a choice by their users. Accordingly, it is wrong

    to ever speak of truth or falsity in connection with

    science, since all rational elaboration is always and

    everywhere conventional in character, and there are no

    external units of measure against which the value of any

    particular episode can be judged. The correct employ-

    ment of a concept should not be seen as a manifestation

    of rationality, but as a discretionary capacity of socio-logical interest.

    The latent concept of rationalism to which this form

    of relativism stands opposed differs from Bachelards in

    important respects, and is more plausibly exemplified by

    the propositions of thinkers like Lakatos and Popper.

    As Alan Chalmers synthetically put it, this version of

    rationalism is characterized by the fact that it presumes

    the universality and ahistoricity of rational criteria

    (Chalmers, 1976). Both these features contradict the

    features of what Bachelard calls applied rationalism.

    Rationalism, understood as both universal and ahisto-

    rical, indeed involves a reference to principles external to

    the linguistic community and logically prior to it, whose

    existence is what Kuhn and Barnes deny. But Bachelard

    understands history itself as the informing principle of

    his applied rationalism. For this reason, applied

    rationalism is intrinsically linked to the (scientific)

    practices of communities, and indeed Bachelard (1949,

    pp. 131132) recognizes a plurality of rationalisms that

    correspond to different regions of scientific activity.

    These regional rationalisms, as he calls them, must be

    considered in their own right before any attempt is made

    to institute, a posteriori, an integrating rationalism. The

    crucial point of difference between Bachelards position

    and the strong relativist one lies in the fact that appliedrationalism, however plural and regional, is never

    contingent, and never available for arbitrary choice. This

    is at least in part because of its diachronic, temporal

    character. We can speak of rationalism, therefore, not

    because science borrows it from a platonic dimension, but

    because science itself is intelligibly overdetermined by its

    past achievements. And we can mark the particularity of

    science as precisely that which institutes its procedures as

    the rationality of a linguistic community.

    From the fact that concepts never correspond to

    unmediated objects, relativists propose that their mean-

    ing is conventional, the result of a synchronic choice by

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696690

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    5/10

    its users. For Bachelard, scientific work is the specific

    place where culture meets this choice as a productive

    task, and actually performs it. It is the locus where the

    norms of meaningfulness are creatively transformeda

    locus characteristically set apart from commonsense, but

    that inevitably feeds back into the commonsense of later

    generations (see Bachelard, 1951, pp. 7582). Inpronouncing ourselves on the past of science, therefore,

    we cannot abstract from the contemporary state of

    scientific knowledge for two different sets of reasons.

    Firstly, because it is the only available point of reference

    we can adopt unless, like many relativists, we wish to

    maintain that we can and should abstain from judgment.

    Secondly, as a matter of intellectual honesty, it is a

    means of rendering explicit the elements of historical

    bias that are intrinsic to any form of thought.

    To conclude this necessary detour into the philosophy

    of Bachelard, let me return to its implications for the

    historiography of science. One of the consequences ofapplied rationalism is the need to distinguish between

    the past of a science and science in the past. The first

    expression designates an order of conceptual progress,

    visible only after the fact, and of which the present

    notion of scientific truth is the provisional point of

    culmination (Canguilhem, 1988, p. 9; Gutting, 1989). It

    is the history of science, whose pertinent objects are

    highlighted through the projection of contemporary

    knowledge onto episodes of the past. All other efforts

    belong to the story of science, the flat chronology of

    events which includes those once called scientific and

    later disqualified from that claim. For Bachelard, such

    events are not simply neutral sidelines of scientific

    development leading to a series of dead-ends. They carry

    a definite negative value as impediments or obstacles to

    scientific progress. They are mistakes, errors whose

    inscription in history nonetheless makes them an active

    presence in the language of posterity and forms part of

    the epistemological inheritance which must be counter-

    acted by any effort to think scientifically. Sometimes, as

    in the case of Newtonian mechanics, errors are such that

    they can be preserved in a rectified form. They are

    apparent errors, where the mistake lies not in the concepts

    themselves but in their unconditional use; the Newtonian

    universe is a valid conceptual subsystem, as it were, of theEinsteinian one. In these cases, Bachelard speaks of

    histoire sanctionn!ee (sanctioned history). When errors only

    have a negative value, and their rectification amounts to

    their elimination from the map of scientific knowledge,

    Bachelard speaks of histoire p!erim!ee (lapsed history).

    What is the value of errors? Scientific ideologies as

    ambivalent obstacles

    We are now in a position to return to the concept of

    scientific ideology which, let us remember, arises in

    the practice of the history of science. In particular, it

    arises in the practice of the history of the life sciences,

    and in a sense it marks the specificity of that subject.

    The distinction between sanctioned and lapsed knowl-

    edge, for Bachelard, is a relatively rigid one. It implies

    the idea that it is possible to assign an unequivocal

    epistemological value to different episodes in the historyof science. Unless errors are rectifiable and rectified

    that is, unless it is possible to specify conditions under

    which they remain valid from the perspective of

    contemporary sciencetheir value is entirely negative;

    they count simply as obstacles. Canguilhem (1989)

    develops these ideas to their logical consequences and,

    we might say, he rectifies them in the Bachelardian sense

    by specifying the limited conditions to which they apply

    in their original form. In particular, as Gary Gutting has

    suggested, through the notion of scientific ideology,

    Canguilhem offers an implicit correction to the concept

    of epistemological obstacle, by introducing thepossibility that errorseven ones that cannot be

    rectifiedmay play a positive role in the development

    of science.

    There is, of course, a sense in which the ambivalence

    of epistemological obstacles is simply a logical conse-

    quence of the notion that all scientific truths are

    provisional in character and open to revision. The value

    of what is incompatible with present explanations

    cannot be fully assessed until the limits of these

    explanations have been reached. What we gather from

    reading Canguilhem, however, is that ambivalence can

    be more or less significant for the historian of science

    depending on his or her specific field of inquiry. As we

    have seen, it was Bachelard who first spoke of a plurality

    of rationalisms corresponding to different regions of

    scientific practice (rationalismes r!egionaux). In line with

    this notion, Canguilhem argues that Bachelards episte-

    mology is particularly suited to the scientific regions in

    reference to which it was developed, namely the regions

    of mathematical physics and nuclear chemistry. Mathe-

    matics, he points out, offers a perfect illustration of

    Bachelards anti-metaphysical understanding of reason,

    since it is in that discipline that one speaks not of the

    normal, but of the normed (1988, p. 13). Bachelards

    account of rationalism, he observes, is built on aframework of mathematism. The degree of formalisa-

    tion evident in sciences like mathematical physics and

    nuclear chemistry is such that the possibility of

    ambivalence appears relatively insignificant for the

    purpose of studying their history. It is from within this

    horizon that sanctioned episodes look like positive

    contributions to progress, while lapsed episodes look

    like epistemological debris that constitute a wholly

    negative obstacle to the development of knowledge.

    From the perspective of the life sciences, on the other

    hand, contributions and obstacles look altogether more

    ambivalent. The vast body of work that Canguilhem

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696 691

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    6/10

    devoted to the concept of life and to the role of

    vitalism in biological thought illustrates this point.

    Many biologists today tend to use vitalism as a

    derogatory term associated with lack of intellectual

    rigour, anti-scientific attitudes, and superstition (e.g.

    Dawkins, 1988). Canguilhem would certainly agree that

    vitalist doctrines have, in many ways, constituted animpediment towards certain aspects of scientific devel-

    opment. At the same time, this impediment has

    contributed to the development of a science of biology

    in the sense of providing a corrective check, for example,

    on the possibility of physico-chemical reductionism. In

    Canguilhems own words:

    The need to refute vitalism, which still persists today,

    must mean one of two things. Either it is an implicit

    admission that this illusion [vitalism]y is not of the

    same order as those of geocentrism or the phlogiston,

    and that it has a vitality of its own. In which case onemust account philosophically for its vitality. Or it is

    the implicit admission that the resistance of the

    illusion has obliged its critics to sharpen their

    arguments and their weapons. This means re-

    cognizing that the corresponding theoretical or

    experimental gain constitutes a benefit whose im-

    portance cannot be entirely unrelated to that of the

    occasion from which it stemsy (Canguilhem, 1975b,

    p. 84).

    In his introduction to Canguilhems most famous

    work, The normal and the pathological, Michel Foucaultusefully suggests that at the root of this ambivalence

    may well lie a paradox that must be regarded as

    constitutive of the life sciences as such:

    Life and death are never in themselves problems in

    physics y lethal or not, for the physicist a genetic

    mutation is neither more nor less than the substitu-

    tion of one nucleic acid base for another. But it is in

    this very difference that the biologist recognizes the

    mark of his object; and an object of a type to which

    he himself belongs, since he lives and manifests the

    nature of the living being, he exercises it, he developsit in an activity of knowledge which must be

    understood as a general method for the direct or

    indirect resolution of tensions between man and the

    environment (1989, p. 20).

    The biologist, in other words, is not indifferent to the

    forms of knowledge s/he produces, which s/he must

    regard as an expression of life and of the quest to remain

    alive. To deny the specificity of life, for the biologist, is

    not only to deny the raison d#etre of science in general

    but also, in reference to his or her own practice, to

    produce a contradictory form of science.

    Between internalist and externalist accounts of science

    The notion of epistemological obstacle, even with the

    corrective of ambivalence, does not however exhaust the

    meaning of scientific ideology. The special interest of

    the concept lies in the connection it points out between

    scientific elements and extra-scientific concerns, andtherefore in highlighting the role played by the latter in

    the constitution of science. Scientific ideology is

    ambiguously scientific from the start in the sense that

    it incorporates hypotheses geared to resolve extra-

    scientific questions. Later, new science disclaims these

    hypotheses by conceptually reformulating an agenda

    which is not exclusively of its own making. The pseudo-

    scientific concepts to which scientific work applies itself

    in its task of rectification do not emerge in a vacuum,

    but express the demands of life and action (Gutting,

    1989, p. 45) in terms of a particular historical

    conjuncture. And the fact that, for a time, they plausiblycall themselves scientific means that it is in their

    direction that scientific attention must turn.

    This is best illustrated with reference to one example

    of scientific ideology provided by Canguilhem and

    commented on in detail by Gutting (1989), namely that

    of the controversy over innate versus acquired traits as

    set out in Maupertuis V!enus physique. This controversy

    had a clear raison d#etre in the social and political

    context of its time and place. It was a context dominated

    by the problem, for example, of determining the

    legitimacy of aristocratic power. In the 17th century

    ideology of hereditary transmission, the concept of

    heredity designates an undifferentiated continuum

    ranging from the biological to the social and political.

    There is no epistemological break between the com-

    monsense, everyday meanings of the term and its

    employment within scientific discourse. Similarly, there

    is a two-way line of exchange between the different

    epistemological levels of the term heredity, the social

    questions directly inform the scientific ones, and the

    scientific results yield political answers. The connection

    between science and the social is not merely analogical;

    it is to be found in the co-extensiveness of their concepts.

    The over-ambitious generalization of scientific con-

    clusions on the part of ideology is not therefore rootedin bad faith, but in an epistemological error.

    It was only with Mendels transformation of the

    biological meaning of heredity that the efforts of his

    predecessors could be revealed as ideological or only

    pseudo-scientific. As Gutting (1989, p. 35) has put it,

    Mendels science is not the end point of a trail that can

    be traced back to the ideology it replaced, for it is the

    expression of a method that the ideology neglected; but

    the speculations of ideology are in part responsible for

    the choice of heredity as Mendels own field of

    inquiry. Similarly, what science finds is not what

    ideology suggested looking for (p. 34), but the course

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696692

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    7/10

    of scientific development is not indifferent to these

    suggestions, nor is it simply slowed down by them.

    Scientific ideologies place fresh input into the course of

    scientific development. This input is derived from the

    demands and problems of the cultural community at

    large.

    Scientific ideology is thus a rich epistemologicalconcept that enables us to look beyond the rigid

    distinction between legitimate and illegitimate science,

    as well as internalist and externalist accounts of scientific

    development. By pointing to the articulation of ethical,

    legal, and political dilemmas in scientific terms, it points

    to the notion that science should be regarded as neither

    entirely pure or separate from society and politics nor as

    entirely defined by social and political factors. In this

    sense, it may be read as anticipating the focus on science

    as a complex set of mixed practices that is the

    hallmark of more recent science studies (Latour, 1993,

    1999).

    Scientific ideology and psychosomatic medicine

    Canguilhem offered specific examples of scientific

    ideology in the history of medicine, and I believe the

    concept is best suited for such a specific level of analysis.

    I write this in contrast to a recent suggestion by Osborne

    that medicine may be made up of regional rationalisms

    that have a scientific status, but medicine itself is not a

    science; in its epistemological spirit, it is rather a kind of

    ideology (Osborne, 1998, pp. 259260). Osbornes

    point is not mistaken in the sense that it accurately

    reflects and develops Canguilhems more general refuta-

    tion of the possibility that medicine should ever be a

    positive science. And, undoubtedly, this is a point that

    needs to be propagated and stressed in the current

    political and cultural climate. But to use scientific

    ideology in this sense means to de-specify the concept,

    and to forgo some of its potential for articulating

    differentiation within the history of medicine itself. In

    the following and concluding paragraphs, I would like

    to offer some suggestions of where such an application

    might prove fruitful in relation to the field of psychoso-

    matic medicine.As I have argued at more length elsewhere (Greco,

    1998), psychosomatic medicine is better understood

    as a space of problematization rather than as an

    organized and coherent scientific field. This means that

    we cannot identify the history of psychosomatic

    medicine with the history of any one of the range of

    disciplinesfrom psychoanalysis to psychoneuroimmu-

    nologythat are pertinent to an understanding of its

    configuration. Indeed, psychosomatic medicine looks

    like a very different proposition depending on the

    disciplinary vantage point that is adopted in order to

    describe it. Yet, and this is the crux of my argument, the

    concept of scientific ideology, in both its positive and its

    negative aspects, may facilitate commensurability be-

    tween such radically different perspectives. As I hope to

    show, this offers a dual set of advantages: on the one

    hand it allows us to highlight the pertinence of many

    historical instances that might otherwise be dismissed as

    detracting detours in a linear development towardsscientificity, and on the other hand it allows us to think

    differently about the character of that very scientificity

    towards which psychosomatic medicine strives.

    To unfold this rather ambitious proposition, it is

    useful to begin by considering Isabelle Stengers recent

    discussions of the specificity of modern medicine as a

    rational practice (Stengers & Nathan, 1995; Stengers,

    2000). Like many other contemporary practices and

    forms of knowledge, modern medicine derives its claim

    to rationality and legitimacy from a reference to science

    and, in the case of medicine specifically, to the

    theoretico-experimental model. This reference, Stengersargues, allowed historically for a transformation of the

    long-standing conflict between doctors and charla-

    tans, by facilitating a diagnosis of the power of the

    charlatan as unfounded. Stengers illustrates this trans-

    formation in her study of the inquiry led in 1784 on the

    magnetic practices of Mesmer, which established that

    Mesmers magnetic fluid, to the extent that its effects

    might prove its existence, did not in fact exist (see

    Chertok & Stengers, 1992). What the Mesmer inquiry

    demonstrated, paradigmatically, was that a cure as

    such proves nothing; a popular cure-all or a few

    magnetic passes can have an effect, but they do not

    qualify as a cause. The charlatan is thereby disqualified

    as someone who takes this effect as proof (Stengers,

    2000, p. 24). Stengers treats the scene of this inquiry as

    the inaugural act of definition of modern scientific

    medicine; the key to this modernity lies precisely in the

    consciousness of the fact that a cure as such proves

    nothing, and that rational medicine cannot be distin-

    guished from the practice of charlatans simply by the

    goal it pursues or attains (that is, healing) (Stengers &

    Nathan, 1995). Finally, Stengers takes the relevance of

    this historical example to the very heart of contempor-

    ary medical research, by highlighting that the same logic

    is at work when it resorts to the placebo effect as ameans of testing medications. The hypothetical power of

    a medication is disproved if the same effect can be

    obtained by administering a placebo; the placebo, as a

    clandestine effect, is thus the correlate of the

    charlatan.

    This particular framing of the way in which modern

    medicine establishes and understands its own rationality

    is interesting because it acknowledges both the gains and

    the losses afforded to medicine itself by its reliance on

    the theoretico-experimental method. In the theoretico-

    experimental framework, the living bodys ability to be

    healed through the imagination, through hope, through

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696 693

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    8/10

    faithin other words through bad reasonsis clearly

    and crucially acknowledged, as the practice of clinical

    trials demonstrates. Simultaneously, however, and by

    the logic of the experiment itself, that very ability is

    explained away as irrational, as a parasitic and

    annoying effect (Stengers, 2000, p. 24) that interferes

    with the pursuit of valid medicine. One might go as faras to speculate, on the basis of this argument, that

    scientific medicine could not acknowledge the placebo

    effect in a veritably positive way (that is, as a true

    effect, due to good reasons, worthy of investigation in

    themselves) without risking its claim to the ability to

    speak in the name of science.

    This last point brings me to the discussion of

    psychosomatic medicine in the spirit of scientific

    ideology. Stengers analysis enables us to see clearly

    the rather singular position that modern psychosomatic

    medicine occupies in terms of the question of how

    medical science relates to medical non-science. In asense, as we shall see, this question lies at the heart of

    psychosomatics as a form of problematisation. One way

    of describing psychosomatic medicine generically might

    be to say that it is a form of medicine that acknowledges

    the placebo effect (or the effect of the imagination) as a

    true effect, and seeks therefore to understand and to

    explain it in order to incorporate it into medicine as a

    rational scientific practice (Harrington, 1997). This

    ambition, which may be articulated in a variety of

    locally specific ways, can indeed be regarded as a kind of

    minimal common denominator shared by otherwise

    deeply heterogeneous disciplines involved in the field.

    Whether it is in terms of the materialization of

    infrapsychic conflict as a symbolic conversion or of

    the neuroimmunological processes involved in coping

    with subjectively stressful life events, psychosomatics

    is characterized by the positive acknowledgment of the

    bodys capacity to exploit, and to succumb to, the power

    of fiction. As we have seen, this is an acknowledgment

    that involves putting medicines claim to scientificity,

    and therefore to legitimacy, at risk. This risk is the

    interpretive key through which many recurrent themes

    in the discursive space of psychosomatics become

    intelligible: the fact, for example, that some figures in

    the history of psychosomatics described their ownpractice as heretical with respect to medical, scientific,

    and even psychoanalytic orthodoxy (Groddeck, 1970),

    and as likely to produce socially transgressive or

    undesirable outcomes (Weizs.acker, 1986/1949); the fact

    that many see their work as anticipating a scientific

    revolution that nevertheless continues to remain elusive

    (Uexk .ull & Pauli, 1986; Levin & Solomon, 1990;

    Todarello & Porcelli, 1992), and whose character is

    constantly in danger of being misunderstood (Weizs-

    .acker, 1986/1949; Morelli, 1982); the fact that others still

    strive to present modern psychosomatic research simply

    as a linear and unproblematic extension of scientific

    rigour into what used to be personal convictions,

    anecdotes and medical folklore (Lipowski, 1986, p. 5).

    The risk implicit in the premise of psychosomatics, in

    itself, would by no means justify addressing psychoso-

    matic medicine as a form of scientific ideology. What

    matters is how different historical instances of psycho-

    somatic research and practice relate to the risk, andwhat may be sacrificed in the name of security. On the

    basis of this broad interpretive framework, it is possible

    to construct something like a typology and a mapping of

    psychosomatic propositions and lines of research. I must

    defer the details of this typology to another occasion,

    but I can offer here some general orientative remarks.

    Among the propositions of psychosomatics, I would

    suggest, those that come close to Canguilhems idea of

    scientific ideology are those that deny the risk posed by

    psychosomatics to the contemporary configuration of

    medical science whilst retaining the ambition to account

    for what, in shorthand, I have referred to as the role ofthe imagination in health and disease. Paradoxically,

    but entirely in line with Canguilhems definition of

    the concept, it is those instances that currently enjoy

    the highest degree of scientific plausibilitynamely the

    varieties of psychosomatic research that rely on the

    theoretico-experimental methodthat may come to

    count as a form of ideology from the perspective of a

    medicine of the future.

    I have in mind, among likely candidates, the experi-

    mental practices of psychoneuroimmunology. Two

    notes of caution: firstly, we should not be deceived by

    the fact that key figures in the field describe psychoneur-

    oimmunology as heralding and anticipating a radical

    transformation in the order of medical science, or as

    somehow being itself already of the future (Solomon,

    1999, 2000). What matters is that the field continues to

    rely on the experimental method as something like a

    royal way towards establishing the scientificity and

    rationality of practice in psychosomatic medicine. When

    Solomon advocates the development through laboratory

    research, of non-linear, non-mechanistic understand-

    ings [of health and disease] based on systems, chaos, and

    informational theories (Solomon, 1999, p. 2), he

    advocates a transformation of medicine along models

    that are current in the practices of physics andchemistry. In the vocabulary of scientific ideology, he

    is extrapolating from the context of adjunct scientific

    fields and extending concepts that may not be relevant

    or pertinent in medicine in the same way as in relation

    to, say, atmospheric phenomena (Stengers & Nathan,

    1995). At a meta-theoretical level, one might say that he

    is advocating a linear progression towards non-linearity.

    The second note of caution, which is closely related to

    the first, is that what is ideological about psychoneur-

    oimmunology in this description is not the recourse to

    experimental practice as such, but rather the privilege

    that is ascribed to it in conferring rationality (and

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696694

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    9/10

    respectability) to psychosomatics. As the royal way

    for psychosomatic medicine, psychoneuroimmunology

    proposes itself as an arbiter with the power to confirm or

    disqualify other practices theoretically, regardless of

    their effectiveness in the management of health and

    disease (Koenig & Cohen, 2002).3 In this sense, the

    ambition of psychoneuroimmunology can be describedas ideological in terms of being both excessive and

    na.ve with respect to the requirements of medical

    rationality.

    To conclude, I propose to reflect on how the example

    of psychoneuroimmunology may relate to Canguilhems

    (1988, p. 38) proposition that, in every domain,

    scientific ideology precedes the institution of science.

    What, if any, is the science that psychoneuroimmunol-

    ogy anticipates? And what, if any, is the science that

    might reveal the general claims of psychoneuroimmu-

    nology as ideological? As we have seen, the theme of

    anticipating a new science is part of the self-descriptionsof practitioners in the field. They refer to concepts and

    models developed in contemporary physics and chem-

    istry in relation to complex systems as the key to

    imagining a scientific medicine of the future. I have

    argued that this illustrates a typically ideological

    extrapolation of concepts, and I now suggest that it may

    also represent a misunderstanding of the significance of

    scientific developments in physics and chemistry, and of

    their relevance for medicine. The example of physics and

    chemistry, as Stengers and Nathan (1995) and Stengers

    (1997) have powerfully argued, is relevant not in so far

    as it may offer a new model that medicine should seek to

    imitate or import, but in so far as it reorganizes our very

    conception of rationality. According to Stengers, the

    significance of the new science lies in its capacity to

    reconfigure the structure of our thinkingtruly in line

    with the spirit of Bachelards applied rationalism.

    The science of complex systems demonstrates that we

    do not need to suppose the existence of irrational entities

    or forces in order to recognize the reality of phenomena

    that may not fit with the requirements of experimental

    methods. In other words, we cannot dismiss as irra-

    tional all that is not amenable to verification in a

    laboratory. The physics and chemistry of complex

    systems, therefore, does not suggest that we may extendthe methods and concepts of those sciencesincluding

    the concept of a systemto the study of human

    bodies in health and disease. On the contrary, their

    relevance lies in exploding the conflation of rationality

    with experimentation (Stengers & Nathan, 1995). For

    the practice of medicine in general, and psychosomatic

    medicine in particular, this has some important implica-

    tions. It means that the relevant question may not be

    when or how medicine will finally become scientific,

    but whether its claims to rationality and legitimacy must

    be drawn primarily or exclusively from a reference to

    science, as is currently the case. The answer, most

    evidently in the context of psychosomatics, is aresounding no. To the extent that psychoneuroimmu-

    nology presents itself as a royal way to transform

    medicine on account of being able to speak in the name

    of science, it would seem to exemplify precisely what

    Canguilhem described as a scientific ideology.

    References

    Bachelard, G. (1949). Le rationalisme appliqu!e. Paris: Presses

    Universitaires de France.

    Bachelard, G. (1951). Lactivit!e rationaliste de la physique

    contemporaine. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Bachelard, G. (1968). The philosophy of no. New York: The

    Orion Press.

    Barnes, B. (1982). T. S. Kuhn and social science. London:

    Macmillan.

    Bowker, G., & Latour, B. (1987). A booming discipline short of

    discipline: (Social) studies of science in France. Social

    Studies of Science, 17, 715748.

    Canguilhem, G. (1975a). !Etudes dhistoire et de philosophie des

    sciences. Paris: Vrin.

    Canguilhem, G. (1975b). La connaissance de la vie. Paris: Vrin.

    Canguilhem, G. (1988). Ideology and rationality in the history of

    the life sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Canguilhem, G. (1989). The normal and the pathological. New

    York: Zone Books.

    Chalmers, A. (1976). What is this thing called science?. St. Lucia:

    University of Queensland Press.

    Chertok, L., & Stengers, I. (1992). A critique of psychoanalytic

    reason: Hypnosis as a scientific problem from Lavoisier to

    Lacan. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Dawkins, R. (1988). The blind watchmaker. London: Penguin.

    Foucault, M. (1989). Introduction to G. Canguilhem. The normal

    and the pathological. New York: Zone Books.

    Greco, M. (1998). Illness as a work of thought: A Foucauldian

    perspective on psychosomatics. London: Routledge.

    Groddeck, G. (1970). Der mensch und sein es. Wiesbaden: Limes

    Verlag.

    Gutting, G. (1989). Michel Foucaults archaeology of scientific

    reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Harrington, A. (Ed.) (1997). The placebo effect: An interdisci-

    plinary exploration. Cambridge, MA, London: Harvard

    University Press.

    Koenig, H. G., & Cohen, H. J. (Eds.) (2002). The link between

    religion and health. Psychoneuroimmunology and the faith

    factor. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions.

    Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Lakatos, I., & Musgrave, A. (Eds.) (1970). Criticism and the

    growth of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University

    Press.

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    3While this collection generally illustrates the view that PNI

    might provide a scientific rationale for religious belief, note the

    cautionary essay by Howard Kaye (a sociologist) on the

    implications of PNI for society and culture (including medical

    practice).

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696 695

  • 7/27/2019 Greco. Error

    10/10

    Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. New York and

    London: Harvester.

    Latour, B. (1999). Pandoras hope: essays on the reality of

    science studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Levin, D. M., & Solomon, G. F. (1990). The discursive

    formation of the body in the history of medicine. Journal

    of Medicine and Philosophy, 15, 515537.Lipowski, Z. J. (1986). Psychosomatic medicinepast and

    present. Parts IIII. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry, 31,

    221.

    Morelli, R. (1982). Dove va la medicina psicosomatica. Milan:

    Riza Libri.

    Osborne, T. (1998). Medicine and ideology. Economy and

    Society, 27, 259273.

    Osborne, T., & Rose, N. (Eds.) (1998). Society and the life

    sciences: In honour of Georges Canguilhem (Special issue).

    Economy and Society, 27, 154329.

    Solomon, G. F. (1999). Immune & nervous system interactions.

    The Fund for Psychoneuroimmunology. www.pnirs.org/

    pages/bibliography.htlm

    Solomon, G. F. (2000). From psyche to soma and back. XLibrisCorporation.

    Spicker, S. (1987). An introduction to the medical epistemology

    of Georges Canguilhem: Moving beyond Michel Foucault.

    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 12, 397411.

    Stengers, I. (1997). Power and invention. Minneapolis, London:

    University of Minnesota Press.

    Stengers, I. (2000). The invention of modern science. Minnea-

    polis and London: University of Minnesota Press.Stengers, I., & Nathan, T. (1995). M!edecins et sorciers.

    Manifeste pour une psychopathologie scientifique le m !edecin

    et le charlatan. Paris: Les Empcheurs de penser en rond.

    Tiles, M. (1987). Epistemological history: The legacy of

    Bachelard and Canguilhem. In A. G. Phillips (Ed.),

    Contemporary French philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Todarello, O., & Porcelli, I. (1992). Psicosomatica come

    paradosso. Turin: Boringhieri.

    Uexk.ull, T., & von Pauli, H. G. (1986). The mindbody

    problem in medicine. Advances, 3, 158164.

    von Weizs.acker, V. (1986 [1949]). Psychosomatische Medizin.

    In P. Achilles, D. Janz, M. Schrenk, & C. F. von Weizs .acker

    (Eds.), Gesammelte Schriften, Vol. 6. Frankfurt: SuhrkampVerlag.

    ARTICLE IN PRESS

    M. Greco / Social Science & Medicine 58 (2004) 687696696

    http://www.pnirs.org/pages/bibliography.htlmhttp://www.pnirs.org/pages/bibliography.htlmhttp://www.pnirs.org/pages/bibliography.htlmhttp://www.pnirs.org/pages/bibliography.htlm