hegel at the gakhn: between idealism and marxism—on the aesthetic debates in russia in the 1920s

13
Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism— on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s Nikolaj Plotnikov Published online: 23 April 2014 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014 Abstract This contribution analyses the importance of the State Academy of the Study of Arts (GAKhN) in the appropriation of Hegel’s aesthetics in Russia. In immediate connection to this discussion at the GAKhN is Gustav S ˇ pet’s conception of the ontology of art. This concept represents an attempt of a non-metaphysical interpretation of Hegel’s aesthetics. There, art is interpreted as an autonomous mode of the cultural existence as ‘‘aesthetic reality.’’ In this interpretation of art S ˇ pet refers to two of Hegel’s theses in which (1) art is determined as ‘‘appearance’’ which stands as a ‘‘quasi-reality’’ and (2) the aesthetic object gets its ontological status because of ‘‘recognition’’ by humans. These theses help S ˇ pet to develop an alter- native to Marxist aesthetics. Keywords Hegel’s aesthetics Á Phaenomenology in Russia Á Art studies (Kunstwissenschaft) Á Aesthetic appearance (Schein) Á Aesthetical object Á Recognition Hegel’s aesthetics in Russia The discussion of Hegel’s aesthetics plays a paradoxical role in the multifaceted and eventful history of the reception of his philosophy in Russia. On the one hand, aesthetic issues and literary criticism form the leitmotif of Hegel’s thought in Russia during the 1830s–1840s, above all in the so-called Stankevic ˇ Circle. The members of this Circle—Stankevic ˇ himself, M. Katkov and M. Bakunin—not only were in Translated from the Russian by Thomas Nemeth. N. Plotnikov (&) Forschungsstelle ‘‘Russische Philosophie und Ideengeschichte’’/Lotman-Institut fu ¨r Russische Kultur, Ruhr-Universita ¨t Bochum, 44780 Bochum, Germany e-mail: [email protected] 123 Stud East Eur Thought (2013) 65:213–225 DOI 10.1007/s11212-014-9191-4

Upload: nikolaj

Post on 25-Jan-2017

221 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

Nikolaj Plotnikov

Published online: 23 April 2014

� Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Abstract This contribution analyses the importance of the State Academy of the

Study of Arts (GAKhN) in the appropriation of Hegel’s aesthetics in Russia. In

immediate connection to this discussion at the GAKhN is Gustav Spet’s conception

of the ontology of art. This concept represents an attempt of a non-metaphysical

interpretation of Hegel’s aesthetics. There, art is interpreted as an autonomous mode

of the cultural existence as ‘‘aesthetic reality.’’ In this interpretation of art Spet

refers to two of Hegel’s theses in which (1) art is determined as ‘‘appearance’’ which

stands as a ‘‘quasi-reality’’ and (2) the aesthetic object gets its ontological status

because of ‘‘recognition’’ by humans. These theses help Spet to develop an alter-

native to Marxist aesthetics.

Keywords Hegel’s aesthetics � Phaenomenology in Russia � Art studies

(Kunstwissenschaft) � Aesthetic appearance (Schein) � Aesthetical object �Recognition

Hegel’s aesthetics in Russia

The discussion of Hegel’s aesthetics plays a paradoxical role in the multifaceted and

eventful history of the reception of his philosophy in Russia. On the one hand,

aesthetic issues and literary criticism form the leitmotif of Hegel’s thought in Russia

during the 1830s–1840s, above all in the so-called Stankevic Circle. The members

of this Circle—Stankevic himself, M. Katkov and M. Bakunin—not only were in

Translated from the Russian by Thomas Nemeth.

N. Plotnikov (&)

Forschungsstelle ‘‘Russische Philosophie und Ideengeschichte’’/Lotman-Institut fur Russische

Kultur, Ruhr-Universitat Bochum, 44780 Bochum, Germany

e-mail: [email protected]

123

Stud East Eur Thought (2013) 65:213–225

DOI 10.1007/s11212-014-9191-4

Page 2: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

direct contact with Hegel’s disciples in Berlin, who were absorbed with a theory of

art including the editor of the ‘‘Lectures on aesthetics,’’ Heinrich Gustav Hotho. But

they also used their knowledge of Hegelian philosophy to establish and to

consolidate the entire direction of literary criticism, both philosophical and social,

which, thanks to Belinskij and his journalistic activity, set the course of all Russian

discussions of art for many decades.

On the other hand, philosophy was subordinated to journalistic interests and

taken into account only as an instrument to legitimize a particular ideological

direction. For this reason the elaboration of aesthetic issues and of a theory of art on

a Hegelian foundation happened to be pushed to the periphery of intellectual

interests not only in the 1840s, but also in the decades that followed. To illustrate

the general state of disinterest in Hegel’s aesthetic philosophy, we can point out that

the Russian publication of his ‘‘Lectures on aesthetics’’ that appeared in two editions

in 1847 and 1869 (Gegel’ 1847–1859) were prepared from a French edition.

Moreover, the Russian text was not properly speaking even a translation but an

abridged retelling of the French text, which, in turn, was a rather free exposition of

the German original! No other attempts were undertaken to create an edition to

facilitate the study of Hegel’s philosophy of art during the years of the ancien

regime in Russia.

During the second half of the nineteenth century, the intellectual influence of

Hegelianism was replaced throughout Europe by a broad critique of Hegel’s system.

In the field of art theory this criticism called for a rejection of ‘‘speculative

aesthetics.’’ It urged the replacement of an ‘‘aesthetics from above,’’ i.e., a

metaphysical argument about the idea of beauty, by a so-called ‘‘aesthetics from

below,’’ i.e., an empirical and psychological analysis of the creative aesthetic

process and the perceiving of art. This criticism of Hegelianism was developed in

Russia against the background of a poorly developed theory of art. Against the

general hegemony of a utilitarian attitude towards art, even feeble attempts to

improve the situation with respect to aesthetic appreciation turned out to be

fruitless: Most of the positions in the history and theory of the ‘‘fine arts’’ that were

created in Russian universities in the wake of the educational decree of 1863

remained vacant for decades. Even the flowering of the arts connected with

symbolism at the beginning of the twentieth century failed to significantly alter this

situation. As late as 1914, a reviewer of new translations in the field of aesthetics

had to admit: ‘‘Of the three categories favored by philosophers of the true, the good

and the beautiful, the last of these is dealt with the least.’’ The reviewer continues

with some bitterness: ‘‘The Russian reader is very suspicious of any kind of

aesthetics.’’ (Il’inskij 1914, 60) However, even the aesthetic theories that had

received attention in Russia at the beginning of the twentieth century focused on the

question of the independent value of aesthetic experience and were approached

primarily from either a psychological or a neo-Kantian standpoint. These theories

demonstrated no particular interest in Hegel’s aesthetic position, regarding it as a

sort of ‘‘philosophical fairy tale’’ (Anickov 1915, 95).

Against such a background, then, we cannot be surprised by the repeated

declarations from representatives of Soviet aesthetics that the scholarly investiga-

tion and publication of Hegel’s philosophy of art initially began only with Soviet

214 N. Plotnikov

123

Page 3: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

Marxism. Two generations of Soviet philosophers contested with each other for the

laurels in mastering Hegel’s philosophy of art. If M. Lifsic dates the beginning of

this enterprise to the mid-1930s (Lifsic 2012, 275–283), i.e., to the period of his own

entry into academia and his collaboration with G. Lukacs in developing Marxist

aesthetics, then an eminent representative of philosophy in the 1960s, Ju.

N. Davydov, on the other hand, claimed that the ‘‘world spirit alighted in

aesthetics’’ only at the beginning of his generation’s activity in the years 1950–1960

(Davydov 2008).

Meanwhile, we should recognize—and the point of the present essay is to

substantiate this thesis—that an intensive and rigorous scholarly exploration of

Hegel’s aesthetics not only began before the advent of Soviet Marxism, but also first

became the focus of attention as an alternative to the Marxist interpretation of art.

This elaboration of the foundations of aesthetic theory was due to a circle of

philosophers and literary critics who came together in Moscow in the 1920s at the

State Academy for the Study of the Arts (GAKhN), under the direction of the

philosopher Gustav Spet. It was thanks to their activity that GAKhN became, in the

short span of its existence from 1921 until its final dissolution in 1929, the central

forum for the discussion of Hegelian aesthetics and for the elaboration of the

fundamental principles of the philosophy of art.1

GAKhN and discussions of Hegel

Founded in autumn 1921 in Moscow with the active participation of painters

(notably V. Kandinskij), philosophers (G. Spet, F. Stepun), art critics and literary

critics (A. Gabricevskij, P. Kogan, M. Gersenzon), the Russian (later State)

Academy for the Study of the Arts was designed to be a research institution that

would establish a new connection between science (nauka) and art. The task of the

Academy, as defined in its charter, was to undertake ‘‘a comprehensive investigation

of every kind of art and artistic culture’’ (§1). To accomplish this meant not only an

expansion of the field of analysis, i.e., expanding the concept of art to range from

the traditional history of art and literature to the study of cinema, theater, decorative

art, etc., but also the integration of various approaches to the study of art, such as

that in experimental psychology, sociology and the specialized sciences and

philosophy. In essence, the Academy’s project required not simply combining all

the artistic disciplines, but creating a new type of humanitarian knowledge capable

of establishing the interrelations between philosophy, historical-cultural studies, and

studies of the human being by the natural and social sciences with the goal being a

‘‘comprehensive investigation of the arts.’’ This project was expected to be realized

in the interaction of the three departments of the Academy: the physico-

psychological (under the direction of V. Kandinskij), a sociological (under the

direction of V. Frice) and philosophical (under the direction of G. Spet).

The common methodological framework that combined these quite different

approaches to the investigation of art in GAKhN was the idea of ‘‘language.’’ The

1 On the perception of German classical aesthetics in GAKhN, see (Dobrokhotov 2014).

Hegel at the GAKhN 215

123

Page 4: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

study of art, taken as the language of artistic forms and their interrelations, and the

rigorous elaboration of art as a system of aesthetic concepts were taken to be the

fundamental directions for the work of the Academy. They took concrete form as a

project to create an ‘‘Encyclopedia of Art’’ or, according to another title for this

project, a ‘‘Dictionary of Artistic Terminology.’’2 The preparation of this

‘‘Dictionary’’ in GAKhN came to include an investigation of the history of the

fundamental aesthetic concepts and of their current usage. The researchers

confronted the fact that the history of aesthetic concepts in Russia not only had

not previously been studied, but that most of classic texts on the philosophy of art

did not exist in a Russian edition, and what was available was unsatisfactory owing

to poorly worked out terminology. For this reason the critical and analytical work in

GAKhN was from the very start combined with translation work and the provision

of commentaries on classic texts from the history of aesthetics. A priority in the

Academy’s plan was accorded to Hegel’s Aesthetics (Kondrat’ev 1923, 419).

Within this framework, the members of the philosophy department of GAKhN by

no means treated Hegel’s aesthetic conception simply as a historical source in

connection with their analysis of the history of aesthetic terminology. In its

programmatic formulation by the philosophers in GAKhN, the task of providing a

theoretical definition of art concerned Hegel’s aesthetics in at least two respects.

First, there was the matter of grounding a rigorous examination of art in contrast to

the immediate experience of it and to its interpretation by artists and art critics. That

is, these philosophers saw as their concern the delineation of the general

methodological principles of ‘‘the rigorous study (nauka) of art.’’ Within their

work at GAKhN, this ‘‘rigorous study,’’ or ‘‘science,’’ was to include the individual

empirical fields of aesthetic studies (ranging, for example, from studies of literature,

painting, and music to book design and cultural folklore). At the same time, the

project of the philosophy department was also to show the possibility of rigorously

investigating art as an independent object of analysis, separate from the diverse field

of aesthetic experience. Thus, the problem of treating art as an object of a

‘‘scientific’’ cognition, which was posed by Hegel in his Aesthetics, acquired a new

sense for the philosophers and scholars at GAKhN (Spet 1926). It was now a

problem of the boundaries of the subject-matter of their study, given the explosive

development of new artistic practices, such as cinema, design, free dance, etc.) and

the transformation of earlier ones.3

The turn to Hegel on the part of the scholars at GAKhN was not limited, then,

only to translation work, although it should be noted that a translation of Hegel’s

‘‘Introduction to aesthetics,’’ made by N. Volkov, was edited along with a

commentary by Spet already in the 1920s. It was not published owing to the

dissolution of GAKhN. Nonetheless, all three translators of the Lectures on

aesthetics included in the Soviet edition of Hegel’s collected works (1930s–1950s),

(Gegel’ 1938, 1940, 1958) namely Boris G. Stolpner, Boris S. Cernysev and Pavel

2 See the partial publication: (Slovar’ khudozestvennykh terminov G.A.Kh.N. 2005).3 Cf. in connection with detailing the fundamental directions of the work of the philosophy department,

Spet’s question addressed to his colleagues: ‘‘Do art historians really know what history they are

studying?’’ (Spet 1926, 4).

216 N. Plotnikov

123

Page 5: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

S. Popov, were colleagues in the philosophy department of GAKhN and were

involved with translation issues and questions concerning aesthetic terminology.

Popov, who also translated Schelling’s Philosophy of art, was the director of a

section (commission) at GAKhN concerned with historical terminology.

However, in addition to translation work and their investigations into the history

of ideas those in the philosophy department turned to Hegel in connection with

interpreting key problems in the philosophy of art. Aleksej Losev constructed a

system of aesthetic forms on the basis of the Neoplatonic and Hegelian dialectic

(Losev 1927; Dunaev 1991; Dobrokhotov 2011) Boris Cernysev analyzed how

social factors in the history of art are reflected in Hegel’s aesthetics (Cernysev

1927), and Aleksej Toporkov discussed the possibility of future additional artistic

periods beyond three historical forms in the Hegelian scheme of symbolic, classical

and romantic (Toporkov 1925). To an even greater degree the turn to Hegel applied

to Spet’s closest colleagues and students in the philosophy department, who, in their

work, relied directly on the fundamental principles of Hegelian aesthetics. An

example of this is Spet’s student Apollinarija Solov’eva, who sought the criteria to

distinguish art and aesthetic experience (Solov’eva 1925, 1926), or the philosopher

and psychologist Nikolaj Zinkin, who rehabilitated the Hegelian concept of art form

(Kunstform) in a polemic with the psychologism and formalism of contemporary

aesthetics (Zinkin 1927).

All of this brings us back to the issue of what role the turn to Hegel’s

philosophical principles played in Spet’s own philosophical project. This question

was repeatedly raised earlier, but it did not receive a detailed resolution owing to the

paradoxical character of the turn (Kline 1999; Steiner 2003; Tihanov 2009; Scedrina

2010). On the one hand, Spet has long been known as the translator of Hegel’s

Phenomenology of spirit into Russian, and he himself repeatedly stressed the need

to update Hegel’s conception in light of contemporary philosophical developments.4

On the other hand, Spet left no specific interpretations of Hegel, preferring instead

to refer to Hegel’s arguments in his own analyses of Husserl, Dilthey and von

Humboldt. Focusing on these analyses, Spet scholars have examined them primarily

in the context of phenomenology and the philosophy of language. Seen from this

perspective, however, Spet’s conception seems to be only a formal aesthetic that

extends and enlarges Russian formalism by incorporating a hermeneutic aspect

(taking language from the point of view of interpreting linguistic expression).

However, we can consider Spet’s elaboration of the philosophy of art as an attempt

to identify and ground the ‘‘autonomy’’ of art as a cultural phenomenon within the

scope of GAKhN’s project and activities rather than as an application of his

hermeneutic phenomenology of language and culture to the particular field of art (as

itself a sort of language). By doing so, Spet’s reliance on Hegel’s arguments appears

far more understandable. His criticism of the psychological and normative

grounding of contemporary aesthetics has its common source in Kantian formalism.

And although Spet’s contemporaries and subsequent scholars saw this criticism as a

4 Cf. ‘‘At this point, German idealist philosophy in the person of Hegel attained results acceptable to us

although only formally. For Hegel did not hold back from hypostatizing the ‘‘identical’’ moment that he

found in absolute metaphysical reality’’ (Spet 1992, 50).

Hegel at the GAKhN 217

123

Page 6: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

critique of psychologism and a continuation of Husserl’s phenomenological anti-

psychologism, it has more in common with the cultural and historical arguments of

Hegel and Dilthey than with a phenomenological aesthetics. Indeed, the latter was

formed precisely as a formal aesthetics on the basis of the perceptual experience of

things and the grounding of such experience in the subject.

We must recognize, of course, that this philosophical direction in GAKhN

remained to a large extent at the ‘‘non finito’’ stage. The publication of Hegel’s

Aesthetics remained incomplete, many of the planned works by Spet and his closest

associates were still to be finalized, and specialized investigations of Hegel were not

written. Nevertheless, on the basis of the texts that were published and also archival

materials, including accounts of the discussions within GAKhN, we can reconstruct

the sense of the turn to Hegel’s aesthetics by Spet and his colleagues. The ‘‘ontology

of art,’’ which Spet developed on the basis of a philosophy of culture, was a

deliberate attempt to renew Hegelian aesthetics in a post-metaphysical era. This

attempt also intended to elaborate the general criteria for rigorous scholarly

discourse about art that could include the various differentiated artistic disciplines in

addition to a justification of an independent role for art in an era when scientific

reflection is predominant. The guiding thread of Spet’s philosophical project was the

‘‘project of reality’’ and its extension to the sphere of art objects.

The problem of aesthetic reality

The dissolution of the State Academy for the Study of the Arts (GAKhN) in 1929

was accompanied by a campaign of public accusations in which GAKhN was

declared the ‘‘last citadel and refuge of bankrupt idealism’’ (Politika nastuplenija

1929). This ideological label (‘‘citadel of idealism’’) was repeatedly used in the

Bolshevik press at the time for the purpose of prosecuting and persecuting those

who thought differently (in particular in connection with the dissolution of such

other ‘‘formalistic’’ groups as the Society for the Study of Poetic Language and the

State Institute for the History of the Arts, and indeed in the process of a ‘‘cleansing’’

of GAKhN). The absurdity of the accusation against the GAKhN philosophers

becomes even more apparent if we consider that for Spet the problem of ‘‘reality’’

and of its ‘‘justification’’ in reason, in practical life and in art is the fundamental task

and the ultimate goal of every philosophy (Spet 1927, 37). For this reason, he

preferred to characterize his own position as a ‘‘realism’’ or even as ‘‘genuine social

realism’’ (Spet 1927, 195).

The problem of reality is a matter of distinguishing the modes of reality and,

correspondingly, the modes of consciousness directed towards it. This problem lies

at the heart of Spet’s philosophy of art in the form of the question of the specific

status of the being of aesthetic objects. In formulating the problem in this manner,

or, in a broader sense, the problem of ‘‘aesthetic reality,’’ Spet sought to distinguish

his position from two other directions in the interpretation of art that question the

reality of the aesthetic object in general and define the aesthetic sphere as one of

‘‘unreality,’’ i.e., as a consequence or a secondary effect of some other instance. As

such an instance, there is, on the one hand, the inner ‘‘experience’’ of the subject—

218 N. Plotnikov

123

Page 7: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

be it the artist or the viewer—on the basis of which a certain physical thing is

transformed into an aesthetic object. As a rule, everything that is connected with the

personal, subjective intention behind the work or that belongs within one’s

perceptual field (the ‘‘de-automatization of perception,’’ ‘‘aesthetic pleasure’’ or the

‘‘structure of the visual experience,’’ etc.) belongs to this sphere. In all of these

approaches, regardless of whether it be from a psychological aesthetic or a formal

one, the aesthetic object is held to have no independent existence of its own, but is

merely a consequence of mental acts (or, in the terminology of the time,

‘‘experiences’’) of the subject.5

On the other hand, Spet opposed—although not so clearly—sociological

objectivism, which believed that all of the fundamental traits of the aesthetic

object, as such, were merely a matter of social and institutional relations and have a

conventional character depending, for example, on the role and function of its social

class. Although there are but few express statements concerning Marxism in Spet’s

works, in aesthetics it still was far from monolithic in the 1920s and presented quite

different approaches.6 However, from Spet’s critical comments regarding the

‘‘copying of reality’’ and the determinism of ‘‘social roles,’’7 we can conclude that

from his point of view the Marxist understanding of art as a ‘‘reflection’’ of social

relations deprives the art work of its reality. This he would have held regardless of

whether it was a matter of the sociological determinism of Plekhanov and

Lunacarskij or the dialectical ‘‘theory of reflection’’ of Lukacs and Lifsic.

According to Marx, ‘‘art’’ as well as all other ideological forms of consciousness

have no independent history and development (Marx and Engels 1969, 27).

Consequently, they cannot be regarded as one variety of reality.

In contrast to both interpretations, Spet faced the issue of the aesthetic object

seeing this object as not just the result of a subjective aesthetic attitude, but also not

just the result of social conventions that would make it merely derivative of its

social (economic, institutional, etc.) status. Rather, the aesthetic object has an

autonomous mode of being, an ‘‘aesthetic reality’’ (Spet 1923, 65). However, how is

this mode determined and how is it differentiated from what is simply experienced

in our everyday practical reality, from our known reality and from the reality of

religious experience and of ethical behavior, etc.? (Spet 1923, 65).

In order to answer this question, however, we need to determine the sense of the

reality that includes the being of the aesthetic object. As a rule, the most elementary

answer is to refer to the things surrounding us, the things that make up our

‘‘original’’ experience of reality. However, the trick in such an appeal to immediate

experience is that physical things are not originally given to us. Correcting the error

5 Cf. Spet’s attacks against the ‘‘idealists’’ and those he called ‘‘experiencers’’ [perezival’scikhi] (Spet

1922, 55).6 Already within the sociology department of GAKhN, which was designated with developing a Marxist

theory of art, quite different conceptions claimed to be ‘‘Marxist’’ including the ‘‘vulgar’’ sociology of V.

Frice, the biologically oriented aesthetics of A. Lunacarskij, the historico-sociological aesthetics of P.

Sakulin, etc. It is noteworthy here that in none of these conceptions did a mastering of Hegel’s aesthetics

play a significant role.7 ‘‘Artist as such refers to any cultured person as such, neither to the highest species of monkey nor also

to a ‘citizen’ or ‘comrade’’’ (Spet 1923, 77).

Hegel at the GAKhN 219

123

Page 8: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

in this theory of knowledge, which up to Husserl rests on a conception of a thing as

an isolated physical object, Spet holds that what we first encounter in the reality

around us are ‘‘social things’’ that we can use in practice. The things found in our

experience appear as instruments, as the material of our actions, as everyday

objects, i.e., as elements and bearers of social relations. In Spet, this claim about the

social character of reality has the significance of a universal ontological postulate:

‘‘In fact, the reality surrounding us is, prima facie, not a ‘natural’ reality, but a

‘social,’ ‘historical,’ ‘cultural’ reality’’ (Spet 1923, 74). And in an even earlier text,

‘‘the state of things is such that we do not even know another reality than social

reality: Sirius, Vega and the most remote stars and nebuli are also social objects’’

(Spet 1994, 90). A physical thing is not an originary givenness, but the result of a

subsequent abstraction of a social thing from among our interrelations in accordance

with definite pragmatic criteria. Spet can easily agree in this regard with Marx’s

definition of ‘‘commodity’’ in Das Kapital as ‘‘a thing which transcends

sensuousness’’ (Spet 1927, 179), if we bear in mind that this definition characterizes

our understanding of reality as a whole. The things given to us in everyday

experience always refer to the social relations in which they are used. That is, they

are not only natural objects, but also signs of the relations in which they take part.8

Therefore, when the question is posed of the difference between aesthetic reality

and the reality ‘‘surrounding us,’’ we should bear in mind that the latter constitutes

pragmatic interrelations between things as signs, means, instruments and so forth.

While recognizing the essentially ‘‘pragmatic’’ character of reality, we can find

within our experiential field objects that are best described as lying outside any

pragmatic relations. Like other things, they surely can also be included within the

relationship of means to ends, but what forms the differentia specifica of their being

lies outside any instrumental usage as a social means. Spet uses the term

‘‘detachment’’ to designate this distinctive feature of aesthetic objects. Accordingly,

the fundamental characteristic of aesthetic reality is its being detached. ‘‘Aesthetic

reality is a detached reality and not a ‘natural’ or a pragmatic one’’ (Spet 2007c, 35).

To explain this characteristic, Spet found it essential also to turn to Hegel and his

concept of ‘‘appearance’’ (Schein) in the ‘‘Lectures on aesthetics,’’ stressing that

most contemporary concepts used to describe the fictional character of the aesthetic,

such as ‘‘isolation,’’ ‘‘illusion,’’ etc. (we can also add that of ‘‘alienation’’), are

unsuitable for characterizing its mode of reality owing to their dependence on

psychologism. Along with Hegel, Spet insists that in speaking of ‘‘detachment,’’ it is

a matter of the mode of being, i.e., of the ontological character, of the aesthetic

object. We can say that this mode of detachment lies ‘‘between’’ sensuous givenness

and ideality. (In Hegel’s formulation of the ‘‘work of art,’’ it is ‘‘the middle between

immediate sensuousness and ideal thought’’ [Hegel 1975, 38]. However, since

according to Spet every object in our surrounding reality appears not only as a

physical object, but also as interpreted in a pragmatic context, this mode of

‘‘detachment’’ needs additional clarification. That an object is detached means that it

8 This is the source of the metaphor ‘‘the language of things,’’ which in the philosophical investations at

GAKhN was understood not as a metaphor, but as an ontological characteristic of social things (Cf.

Gabricevskij 2002).

220 N. Plotnikov

123

Page 9: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

appears ‘‘as if real’’ (as ‘‘quasi-real’’) [Spet 1923, 69, 1927, 177 and others]). That

is, it is excluded from the pragmatic relationship of means and ends. Therefore, the

criterion used for factual reality is inapplicable to it. The object, however, also does

not belong to the sphere of pure ideas, which, like mathematical objects, must

adhere to the principle of logical consistency.

Moreover, Spet uses Hegel’s arguments not only in his general definition of

aesthetic activity as ‘‘detached’’ or as ‘‘an appearance.’’ He interprets such reality

itself, based on the phenomenon of art, in order to single out its specific features

within aesthetic experience. One defining characteristic of the aesthetic phenom-

enon, according to Spet, is its expression of sense. It is not a matter here of some

subjective conception of the artist nor of the interpretation of the beholder, but of the

fact that the artwork’s objective structure itself essentially ‘‘signifies’’ (Spet 1923,

76).9 If everything in social reality implicitly includes a correlation between its

empirical existence and a pragmatic interpretation (in Hegel’s terminology ‘‘an

sich’’), then the art object is one that explicitly embodies a connection between its

sensuous form and a sense (again in Hegel’s nomenclature ‘‘an und fur sich’’). Art

objects are not only ‘‘social,’’ but also ‘‘cultural’’ things, since they are signs, or

indications, not only of pragmatic relations, but also serve as reflection signs of the

relations embodied in the object. Therefore, as Spet notes, art is a ‘‘signifying’’

mode of reality where the connection between fact and sense is the explicitly

expressed theme. In other words, an art object is always ‘‘about something,’’ in

contrast to a social thing, which stands only as a means in pragmatic relationships.

This ‘‘something,’’ however, is not part of empirical reality, but is the sense of a

detached reality. Detaching the object from its pragmatic context, art exposes the

‘‘meaningfulness’’ or ‘‘interpretedness’’ of reality as that which is a condition of the

object being a social thing. Spet’s polemic with the Futurists and his critique of the

idea of a pure formal language devoid of any sense (Spet 1922) is due, undoubtedly,

to this conviction that assessing the sense of any art object is unavoidable just as it

ultimately is of the ‘‘rationality’’ of all of reality.10

In his analysis of art as a paradigm of aesthetic reality, Spet introduces along with

‘‘detachment’’ and ‘‘significativeness’’ one more element of description based on the

principles of Hegel’s aesthetics. According to this description, art is not only the

expression of a certain sense, not only an expression of cultural existence, but also

itself a manifestation of cultural existence, i.e., a manifestation of a community of

people who are creating and who are perceiving art objects.11 Art is understood here

not as a sign of something else, but as an expression and affirmation of the existence

of participants in a single cultural community. In other words, art can even be said

to be the ‘‘self-consciousness’’ of an association of people as a cultural unit (and

thereby potentially all of humanity), or in Hegelian terminology the being ‘‘for

itself’’ (fur sich) of a cultural community (Spet 2007b, 130).

9 Concerning the ‘‘hermeneutic’’ character of Spet’s aesthetics, see Bird (2009).10 On the peripetias of the thesis ‘‘all that is real is rational’’ in Russian intellectual history, see Plotnikov

(2010).11 In his drafts of the article ‘‘Iskusstvo kak vid znanija,’’ Spet uses the term ‘‘actionality’’ [aktual’nost’]

(as opposed to ‘‘actuality’’ [dejstvitel’nost’] and ‘‘reality’’ [real’nost’]) to designate the mode of this being

(Spet 2007b, 141).

Hegel at the GAKhN 221

123

Page 10: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

‘‘Culture’’ designates here just the community of subjects who, as opposed to the

social communication between separate individuals, show themselves or reveal their

‘‘presence’’ through their involvement in a common self-consciousness. Art

preserves and cultivates this commonality of self-consciousness, ‘‘i.e., the

consciousness of oneself in communication, in a general unity with others,’’12 by

the fact that each time it embodies this commonality anew. Thus, Spet notes in one

of his later texts that literature is a manifestation of a cultural self-consciousness. It

is not a reflection of that self-consciousness, but its active embodiment and

formulation in words. Participating in this ‘‘world of art,’’ a person acquires an

experience of subjectivity—of one’s own as well as that of others’—not as natural

individuals, but as the subjects of some cultural community.13

Art as a defense against the ‘‘tyranny of sense’’

The impression may arise that this model of cultural community that art realizes

bears a striking similarity to the Hegelian-Marxist ideal of non-alienated existence

that Soviet aesthetics cultivated since the 1930s. Indeed, the official communist line

presented aesthetic education as an integral element in the formation of the

communist personality.14 A discussion of these parallels would require a separate

investigation, the goal of which would be to show how, in spite of all the criticism

of it by post-revolutionary Russian avant-garde movements, classical German neo-

humanist aesthetics could have served as a precursor of the ‘‘proletarian’’ humanism

of the Soviet regime.

In fact, Soviet aestheticians since the 1930s actively appropriated the ideas of

Hegel in an effort to develop their own systematically.15 In order to demarcate the

point of greatest divergence between Spet and Marxist aesthetics, we must take note

of one more aspect of this ‘‘problem of reality.’’ For Marxist objectivism, the sense

embodied in art turns out to be simply an unoriginal reflection of a sense formed

externally in reality and apart from the piece of art (as a form of consciousness).

Paraphrasing Marx’s formula, we can say: The world has already long ago been

understood; the point now is simply to change it. Indeed, the world was understood

already from the start; its sense is objective. The only important thing is to take the

correct standpoint with respect to it. Along with this, two standpoints are to be taken

into account. Lifsic, in his early article ‘‘Hegel’s aesthetics and dialectical

materialism,’’ clearly formulated them. Appealing again to Hegelian terminology,

there is either a ‘‘reconciliation’’ with reality or its revolutionary ‘‘negation’’ (Lifsic

2012, 94–95).

12 (Spet 1926/27, 39verso). This does not appear in the published text.13 Cf. ‘‘Consciousness of oneself as a socio-cultural community is not the same thing as an abstract

individual’’ (Spet 1927, 217).14 See, for example, (Lifsic 1984) and also the article ‘‘Esteticeskoe vospitanie’’ in the dictionary

Naucnyj kommunizm (Rumjancev 1983, 346).15 Particularly in the publications of the journal Literaturnyj kritik.

222 N. Plotnikov

123

Page 11: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

On the one hand, Spet, in agreement with Marx, characterizes the social

objectivity of sense as a ‘‘thing that transcends sensuousness.’’ On the other hand,

Spet, from his point of view, demands one additional factor that is absent in the

Marxist scheme, namely that in order for sense to become a reality consciousness

must recognize it. There must be an unbroken act of interpretation that can be

renewed every time. Thanks to this, social being is affirmed as a reality, i.e., as

factually given and at the same time as a result of an action of the spirit. ‘‘The spirit

is neither some metaphysical Sesame nor some vital elixir. It is not real ‘in itself,’

but in its recognition’’ (Spet 1922, 40).

The concept of recognition as a confirmation and validation by consciousness of

the reality of a certain being plays a key role in Spet’s philosophy. He himself

stressed quite clearly in one letter from exile in 1936 to the translator and philologist

Natalja Ignatova: ‘‘You forgot one of my brilliant ideas. In order for something to be

socially real, socially valuable … the relevant society must recognize it.

Recognition (come on, old man: Anerkennung) is a determinative [sic!] category

of the social!’’ (Spet 2005, 389).

Although Spet does not explicitly name the source of this, as he put it ironically,

‘‘brilliant idea,’’ it is not difficult to establish that it harks back to the Hegelian

dialectic of ‘‘recognition’’ (Anerkennung) from the Phenomenology of spirit, the

translation of which occupied Spet at this very time. As with Hegel, the problem of

recognition for Spet lies in the fact that a confirmation of reality as objective

requires the independent consciousness as a necessary condition, the act of carrying

out a confirmation. In other words, in the dialectic of recognition it is found that

reality is not simply a matter of being factually present, but that it is ‘‘fulfilled’’ by

consciousness, just as a musical work is performed in order to become a cultural

reality. ‘‘Recognition’’ is the free fulfillment of reality by consciousness, both of

social things and of other subjects who exist for each other thanks to an act of

‘‘recognition.’’16

Only by admitting such an act of recognition can we avoid an automatism of

objective sense, that ‘‘tyranny of sense’’17 in a totally intelligible world which

becomes the Marxist proclaimed fatalism of objective historical necessity. In Spet’s

conception of recognition, consciousness retains a measure of freedom that allows it

to reject reality’s right to exist. Reason, as Spet notes, certainly does not create

reality, but it has in this regard a right to an ‘‘ontic veto’’ (Spet 2007b, 132).

By the fact that it refers to an unreal, detached reality—to an ‘‘appearance’’

(Schein)—art at the same time reveals an act of recognition and also together with it

the freedom that is necessary to affirm reality as a whole. Even before scientific

reason recognizes reality on logical grounds, art confirms the being that shows it.

Spet writes, ‘‘The artist affirms reality before the philosopher, because before any

cognition there is intuition’’ (Spet 1922, 53). Here, we have in the form of a

16 Cf. ‘‘The concrete social subject exists and remains so only if it is recognized as a social subject by

others who are recognized by it and as long as this recognition lasts’’ (Spet 1927, 188).17 The allusion here is to the exhibition ‘‘The Tyranny of Beauty. The Architecture of Stalin-Time’’

(1994) at the Museum fur angewandte Kunst of Vienna, co-organized by Boris Groys.

Hegel at the GAKhN 223

123

Page 12: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

cooperation between artists, art critics and philosophers one more Hegelian point

embodied in GAKhN’s institutional structure.

References

Anickov, E. V. (1915) Ocerk razvitija _esteticeskich ucenij. Cast’ 1. In Voprosy teorii i psikhologii

tvorcestva, vol. 6, pp. 1–242.

Bird, R. (2009). The hermeneutic triangle: Gustav Spet’s aesthetics in context. In G. Tihanov (2009),

pp. 28–44.

Cernysev, B. S. (1927). Sociologiceskie motivy v estetike Gegelja. In Iskusstvo, no. 4, pp. 5–54.

Davydov, Ju. N. (2008). Dukh mirovoj togda osel v _estetike, [Inter’vju s Ju. N. Davydovym]. In: Id. Trud

i iskusstvo. Moskva, pp. 5–22.

Dobrokhotov, A. (2011). GAKhN: An aesthetics of ruins, or Aleksej Losev’s failed project. In Studies in

East European thought, vol. 63, pp. 31–42.

Dobrokhotov, A. L. (2014). Recepcija nemeckoj klassiceskoj _estetiki v trudakh i diskussijach GAKhN. In

N. S. Plotnikov (Ed.), Iskusstvo kak jazyk. Gosudarstvennaja akademija khudozestvennykh nauk

(1921–1931) kak forum teorii iskusstva. Tom 1. Moskva: Territorija buduscego (in Print).

Dunaev, A. G. (1991). Losev i GAKhN (issledovanie arkhivnykh materialov i publikacija dokladov 20-kh

godov). In A. F. Losev i kul’tura XX veka. Moskva, pp. 197–220.

Gabricevskij, A. G. (2002). Jazyk vescej. In Id. Morfologija iskusstva (pp. 31–39). Moskva: Agraf.

Gegel’, G. V. F. (1938, 1940, 1958). Lekcii po _estetike. In Id. Socinenija, t. XII, XIII, XIV, Moskva, 1938,

1940, 1958.

Gegel’, V. F. (sic!). (1847–1859). Kurs _estetiki, ili nauki izjascnogo, perevel Vasilij Modestov. Sankt

Peterburg, cast’ 1 and 2, 1847; cast’ 3, 1859.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1975). Aesthetics, lectures on fine art, trans. T. M. Knox. Oxford, vol. 1.

Il’inskij I. [Bruk. I.D.] (1914). Review of Rikhard Gaman, _Estetika, Moskva, 1913. In Zavety, no. 2,

pp. 60–64.

Kline, G. L. (1999). Gustav G. Spet as interpreter of Hegel. In Archiwum Historii Filozofii i Mysli

Społecznej, vol. 44, pp. 181–190.

Kondrat’ev, A. I. (1923). Rossijskaja Akademija Khudozestvenykh Nauk. In Iskusstvo, #1, pp. 407–449.

Lifsic, M. A. (1984). Marksizm i esteticeskoe vospitanie. In Id. Sobranie socinenij, vol. 1. Moskva:

Iskusstvo, pp. 388–430.

Lifshic, M. A. (2012). O Gegele. Moskva: Grundrisse.

Losev, A. F. (1927). Dialektika khudozestvennoj formy. Moskva: Izdanie avtora.

Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1969). Die deutsche Ideologie. In Werke, vol. 3. Berlin: Dietz.

Plotnikov, N. S. (2010). ‘Vsje dejstvitel’noe razumno’: Diskurs personal’nosti v russkoj intellektual’noj

istorii. In Issledovanija po istorii russkoj mysli, 8(2006–2007) (pp. 191–210). Moskva: Modest

Kolerov.

Politika nastuplenija (1929). In Pecat’ i Revoljucija, kn. IV, April, p. 3.

Rumjancev, A. M. (Ed.). (1983). Naucnyj kommunizm. Moskva: Politizdat.

Scedrina, T. G. (2010). K voprosu o gegel’janstve … Gustava Speta. In N. V. Motroshilova (Ed.),

‘‘Fenomenologii dukha’’ Gegelja v kontekstve sovremennogo gegelevedenija (pp. 588–597).

Moskva: Kanon?.

Spet, G. G. (1922). Esteticeskie fragmenty, vyp. 1. Moskva: Kolos.

Spet, G. G. (1923). Problemy sovremennoj estetiki. In Iskusstvo, no, 1, pp. 43–78.

Spet, G. G. (1926) K voprosu o postanovke naucnoj raboty v oblasti iskusstvovedenija. In Bjulleteni

GAKhN, nos. 4–5, pp. 3–20.

Spet, G. G. (1926/27). Iskusstvo kak vid znanija. In NIOR RGB, f. 718, kart. 7, Ed. khr. 3, L. 39verso.

Spet, G. G. (1927). Vnutrennjaja forma slova. Moskva: GAKhN.

Spet, G. G. (1992). Stat’ja dlja _enciklopediceskogo slovarja ‘Granat’. In Nacala, no. 1, pp. 50–51.

Spet, G. G. (1994). Soznanie i ego sobstvennik [1916]. In Id. Filosofskie etjudy (pp. 20–116). Moskva:

Progress.

Spet, G. G. (2005). Zizn’ v pis’makh. Epistoljarnoe nasledie, ed. T. G. Scedrina. Moskva: Rosspen.

Spet, G. G. (2007a). Iskusstvo kak vid znanija. Moskva: Rosspen.

224 N. Plotnikov

123

Page 13: Hegel at the GAKhN: between idealism and Marxism—on the aesthetic debates in Russia in the 1920s

Spet, G. G. (2007b). Iskusstvo kak vid znanija. In Spet 2007a, pp. 112–149.

Spet, G. G. (2007c). Teatr kak iskusstvo. In Spet 2007a, pp. 19–39.

Slovar’ khudozestvennykh terminov G.A.Kh.N. (2005). Ed. I.M. Cubarov. Moskva: Logos-Al’tera.

Solov’eva, A. K. (1925). Letter to G. G. Spet of 2 December 1925 with a supplementary text ‘‘Zametki k

vozmoznomu razliceniju problem _estetiki i filosofii iskusstva v postroenijakh Gegelja’’. In NIOR

RGB, f. 718, k. 25, Ed. Khr. 43.

Solov’eva, A. K. (1926). ‘‘O vzaimootnosenii problem _estetiki i filosofii iskusstva na osnovanii postroenij

Gegelja’’ [Report in GAKhN of 9 March 1926]. In RGALI. f. 941. Op. 14. Ed chr. 20. L.

30-31verso.

Steiner, P. (2003). Tropos Logikos. Gustav Spet’s philosophy of history. In Slavic review, vol. 62, no. 2

(Summer), pp. 343–358.

Tihanov, G. (Ed.). (2009). Gustav Spet’s contribution to philosophy and cultural theory. West Lafayette,

Ind.

Toporkov, A. K. (1925). Gegel’ i razrusenie _estetiki [Report in GAKhN of 2 April, 1925]. In RGALI, f.

941, Op. 14, Ed. 14. L. 46.

Zinkin, N. I. (1927). Problema esteticeskikh form. In A. G. Cires (Ed.), Khuzestvennaja forma. Moskva:

GAKhN, pp. 7–50.

Hegel at the GAKhN 225

123