internet and self identity

Upload: dweiss99

Post on 03-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    1/10

    THE INTERNETAND SELF-IDENTITY

    Dr. Dennis M. Weiss

    York College of Pennsylvania

    In the age of the Internet, the World Wide Web, and cyberspace, more

    and more of our contact with one another is not of the traditional face-to-face

    variety. Rather, our communications with one another are increasingly

    mediated by machines, especially computers. We have voice-mail and e-

    mail, participate in discussions on computer discussion lists, meet people in

    computer chat rooms, role play in virtual realities such as MUDs, and satisfy

    our sexual desires with anonymous, virtual others. These forms of computer-

    mediated conversation (CMC) are decidedly different from the traditionalface-to-face contact that was the norm for most of the history of civilization.

    When communicating through the intermediary of the computer we can, if

    we choose, remain anonymous or even create false or alternative identities.

    As Howard Rheingold has noted in The Virtual Community, The grammar

    of CMC media involves a syntax of identity play: new identities, false

    identities, multiple identities, exploratory identities, are available in different

    manifestations of the medium (147-48). Recently, a number of

    commentators on the computer culture have argued that this aspect of

    computer-mediated communication, this identity play, will lead to a newsense of self-identity in our culture. The notion that the self is a stable, fixed,

    unitary, and centered object will ultimately give way in the computer culture

    to the idea of a self that is multiple, decentered, fluid, and fragmented. Sherry

    Turkle, for instance, inLife on the Screen, argues that our contact with

    computers and virtual identities is leading to a new image of the self in terms

    of multiplicity, heterogeneity, flexibility, and fragmentation. In traditional

    communities where face-to-face contact dominates, people developed a

    strong, unitary sense of self. On the Internet, though, we learn to experimentwith different selves, different identities. We learn to fashion for our virtual

    lives new selves. As Turkle puts it, today, many more people experience

    identity as a set of roles that can be mixed and matched, whose diverse

    demands need to be negotiated (180). Social psychologist Kenneth Gergen

    has termed this phenomenon the saturated self. According to Gergen,

    communications technologies saturate us with the various voices of

    1

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    2/10

    humankind and lead to a self that is without foundations, an incoherent,

    fragmentary self in which the notion of authentic self-identity is lost. Gergen

    writes, There is a populating of the self, reflecting the infusion of partial

    identities through social saturation. And there is the onset of a multiphrenic

    condition, in which one begins to experience the vertigo of unlimitedmultiplicity (The Saturated Self, 49). Allucquere Rosanne Stone agrees. In

    her The War of Desire and Technology at the Close of the Mechanical Age ,

    Stone argues that we are witnessing a radical rewriting of our conception of

    the self. In the age of the computer, our belief that to each body there

    corresponds a single self or identity is undermined. Older, stabler structures

    of identity are giving way to a new form of multiple identity. Stone draws

    parallels between this new form of identity and multiple personality disorder,

    suggesting that in the age of the Internet, multiple personalities may becomethe norm, not the disorder. Similar claims are made by Mark Poster in his

    analysis of what he terms the mode of information. Poster argues that the

    shift from an oral to a print to an electronically based culture reconfigures the

    subjects relation to the word and the world. In electronically mediated

    exchanges the self is decentered, dispersed, and multiplied. As he writes, In

    electronically mediated communications, subjects now float, suspended

    between points of objectivity, being constituted and reconstituted in different

    configurations in relation to the discursive arrangements of the occasion

    (11). Similar points are made by Jay David Bolter, in his analysis ofhypertext and the coming network culture, by Elizabeth Reid in her

    discussions of MUDs (multi-user domains) and IRC (Internet Relay Chat),

    and by Amy Bruckman in her analysis of MUDs as identity workshops.

    Ignoring the differences among these various accounts, we can

    identify at least four common claims in this body of work:

    1. There has been a paradigm shift in our sense of self-identity, from acoherent, stable, centered sense of self to a fragmented, decentered,

    multiple sense of self.

    2. The role of technology is deeply implicated in this shift, perhaps

    constitutive of it.

    3. The emphasis is on a social constructionist account of the self.

    2

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    3/10

    4. There is a repudiation of the traditional Western Cartesian view of

    the self.

    For the purposes of this discussion, I focus on the central claim that

    communications technology, especially the computer and the Internet, isleading to a shift from a stable, centered sense of self to a multiple,

    fragmentary, decentered self. Despite the growing proliferation and increased

    acceptance of this claim, there are three general reasons for rejecting it. First,

    it is not clear that we can understand the basic claim being made. Second, as

    a descriptive claim purporting to account for changes apparent in our culture,

    this claim rings false. Third, as a normative claim recommending a particular

    view of the self as multiple and fragmented, it undermines many of our

    important moral ideals. Let me address each of these points in turn.

    First, this claim is, simply put, both vague and ambiguous. The

    authors, for instance, fail to distinguish between different varieties of unity

    and fragmentation. It is never clear whether the issue is unity of

    consciousness at any given time or unity of consciousness over time. There

    are a variety of terms used, even within one particular analysis, such as

    self, person, subject, and subjectivity that are not adequately defined

    or distinguished. Furthermore, the central terms of the claim, multiple,

    fragmented, decentered, are never made clear and so the view of the selfthat is being defended is left ambiguous. The authors, for instance, treat

    fragmented and fluid as synonymous and, yet, there may be significant

    differences between a fragmented self and a fluid self. Indeed, a fragmented

    self might be neither fluid nor flexible. Additionally, multiple models of this

    new, multiple self are proposed with little recognition of the significant

    differences among these models. Turkle, for instance, at various points in

    Life on the Screen, mentions Gergens saturated self, Emily Martins flexible

    self, Robert Jay Liftons protean self, Daniel Dennetts multiple drafts modelof the self, and her own metaphor of the self as a distributed system,

    analogous to the multiple windows on a computer screen. No attempt is

    made to distinguish between these competing models. Finally, and I think

    most significantly, the relationship between this multiple, fragmented self

    and technology is never clearly explicated. Is the technology fashioning a

    new sense of subjectivity or is the new sense of subjectivity a product of

    3

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    4/10

    broader cultural forces? Is the fragmented, multiple self an outcome of

    interacting with computers or simply a function of a postmodern, fragmented

    culture? The relationships between the broader culture milieu, technology,

    and subjectivity are obscured in these accounts. And yet, the focus in these

    accounts is clearly on computers, virtual systems, and cyberspace. Thisstrongly implies that the technology is causally implicated in the paradigm

    shift. This claim, though, is never substantiated.

    A larger difficulty concerns the status of the central claim that we are

    witnessing a paradigm shift from a stable, fixed self to a multiple,

    fragmented self. Is this merely a descriptive claim or should it be read

    normatively, as prescribing norms of subjectivity? There is support in the

    work of Turkle, Gergen, and Stone to read this claim either way. Gergen, forinstance, suggests I am not trying to document the societal norm. Rather,

    my hope is to isolate an emerging shift in perspective and related life

    patterns. The case is drawn from specially affected segments of the

    populationyet there is good reason to believe that what is taking place in

    these groups can be taken as a weathervane of future cultural life in general

    (200). The style of writing in both Turkle and Stone suggest a descriptive

    account of a particular culture or subculture, consistent with their

    ethnographic approaches. Stone, for instance, writes, Among the

    phenomena at the close of the mechanical age that it is useful to note is thepervasive burgeoning of the ontic and epistemic qualities of multiplicity in

    all their forms (53). Turkle, too, suggests that these are broad changes

    influencing every sector of culture. And yet, beyond merely reporting on

    these changes, these writers also speak approvingly of the changes they are

    documenting. They are not simply neutral observers. Both Turkle and Stone

    speak approvingly of individuals playing with multiplicity. Stone refers to

    members of the virtual age living happily with multiplicity (43). Gergen

    refers to the self taking pleasure in the expanded possibilities of socialsaturation and being liberated from the demands for coherence. So the

    central claim regarding the multiple, fragmented self can be read either

    descriptively or normatively. Unfortunately, there are problems with either

    reading.

    4

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    5/10

    As descriptive, this claim rings false. This claim to a new sense of

    identity, it is suggested, captures a widespread shift in our culture.

    Unfortunately, very little is offered as evidence in support of this claim. And

    what evidence is offered is largely biased and based on non-representative

    samples. Turkles sample, it appears, is drawn exclusively fromundergraduates and so-called twenty-somethings, precisely the group one

    would expect to find engaged in identity-play, as their self-identies have not

    yet fully formed. In her central chapter on identity fromLife on the Screen ,

    Turkle profiles eleven individuals. Of these eleven, her four extended

    analyses are all of young male college students. The average age of the

    eleven is 25. Her Note on Method suggests that many of her informants are

    kids from the MIT and Boston area. Outside of individuals with multiple

    personality disorder, the only group Stone mentions accepting the multipleself are hackers and young engineers. But premising claims about social

    trends on the backs of twenty-something hackers is probably not a good idea.

    In studies by Steven Levy, Bruce Sterling, Katie Hafner, and even Turkle

    herself, hackers are often portrayed as loners, maladjusted, uncomfortable

    with themselves. It is doubtful that broad conclusions about identity in the

    wider culture can be soundly based on such a non-representative group of

    individuals. Furthermore, in Turkles ethnographic study, many of her

    subjects use the very same modernist vocabulary of the self (authenticity,

    self-fulfillment, self-development) that she argues is pass in thepostmodern, computer culture. The case of Stewart, for instance, presents a

    young man in search of his ideal self and working towards the goal of an

    integrated self. These are ideas much at odds with the postmodern

    vocabulary championed by Turkle.

    Importantly, Stewarts concern for realizing an ideal and fully

    integrated self still finds parallels in many sectors of our society. While I

    think Stone, Turkle, Gergen, and Poster are right that there are signs ofmultiplicity and fragmentation in contemporary society, there are just as

    many signs of unity, integration, and authenticity. Certainly the self-help and

    new age sections of most major book stores trade on the search for

    authenticity and integrity. As just one brief example, Time magazine recently

    profiled Sarah Ban Breathnach, who has been called the Martha Stewart of

    the Spirit. Ban Breathnachs Simple Abundance: A Daybook of Comfort and

    5

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    6/10

    Joy has been on the best-seller lists for 70 weeks and sold 2.2 million copies

    (far more, I imagine, than all the texts I am considering combined).

    Significantly, Ban Breathnach emphasizes, as she puts it, excavating the

    authentic self. Additionally, just a glance at the best seller lists also suggests

    that memoirs are currently a growth industry in the publishing world. Italmost seems as if a new memoir is published daily. A thorough and more

    complete account of the self in contemporary culture has to account for these

    phenomena as well as the potentially multiple self found in the computer

    culture. Even in the computer culture, it is not clear that technology leads

    inevitably and completely to a fragmentation of self-identity. The

    phenomenon of personal home pages seems to attest to a certain desire to

    represent and fix the self in cyberspace. The growing field of biometrics, the

    use of retinal identification, voice recognition devices, iris scanners suggestfurther ways in which technology operates to fix and preserve a stable and

    nonchanging personal identity. The now ubiquitous camcorders act to

    preserve every moment of our lives so that they can be re-experienced over

    and over again. While all of these phenomena require a deeper analysis than

    they can be given here, they do suggest that it is too simplistic to claim first

    that the self in contemporary society is multiple and fragmented and, second,

    that technology acts solely to fragment the self.

    As descriptive, these claims are simplistic in two further ways. First,they overplay the role of technology in constituting subjectivity while

    simultaneously underplaying other factors that play a role in the formation of

    identity, such as early childhood experiences, human embodiment, and

    human sexuality. In attending to the formation of identity in relation to

    interaction with technology and especially computers, these analyses

    simplistically suggest an almost direct connection between technology and

    identity. The self, though, is more than a product of its interactions with

    machines. Too often, accounts of the power of the media and technology toshape human lives presuppose that human beings live in a vacuum and that

    there are not other influences on our lives. Long before children experience a

    computer they have been formed and shaped by parental influences and

    interactions. Or briefly consider the role of the body in the formation of self-

    identity. There is a long tradition in philosophy that focuses on bodily criteria

    in personal identity and there is growing support in fields such as cogntive

    6

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    7/10

    science and linguistics for the claim that the body plays an important role in

    our sense of self. In these analyses we are considering, though, human

    embodiment receives very little attention. Often, as in the rest of the

    computer culture, the body is portrayed as mere passive stuff, the meat that

    somehow or other supports the self.

    Secondly, these claims simplify the modernist view of the self against

    which they are reacting, a view which often amounts to little more than a

    caricature. The sharp shift these analyses see from a modernist, centered self

    to a postmodern decentered, fragmented, multiple self is simply falsely

    drawn. Alternative theories of the self have been around at least as long as

    Buddhas theory of the no-self and David Humes account of the self as a

    bundle of perceptions. Nietzsche clearly articulated a notion of the multipleself, as did the American Pragmatists James, Mead, and Pierce. The

    phenomena of akrasia, self-deception, and other forms of self-conflict were

    commented on by both Plato and Aristotle. Additionally, it is not clear that

    our sense of self hasnt always embodied at least some degree of flexibility

    and multiplicity. As Jennifer Radden points out in her studyDivided Minds

    and Successive Selves, our lives and selves are marked by a want of oneness,

    wholeness, and homogeneity. She writes, Ordinary selves are at best only

    relatively continuous through time, and at any particular time their unity or

    oneness is not simple (20). Feminist analyses of the self and subjectivityhave been especially noteworthy for revealing the orindariness of the divided

    self.

    As descriptive, then, the claim that technology has led to a shift in the

    sense of self from a stable, centered, unified self to a fragmented, fluid,

    multiple, decentered self is unacceptable. Beyond merely describing this new

    self-identity in the age of the Internet, this claim can also be read

    normatively as recommending that we actively take up a multiple,fragmented, decentered identity. This claim too faces serious problems and I

    wish now to consider several reasons for regarding it as dangerous.

    First, as a number of practicing therapists have argued, the judgment

    that we should embrace a fragmented subjectivity and play with multiplicity

    is overly naive and fails to recognize the terror most patients suffering from

    7

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    8/10

    borderline syndrome experience. As Jane Flax observes, Those who

    celebrate or call for a decentered self seem self-deceptively naive and

    unaware of the basic cohesion within themselves that makes the

    fragmentation of experiences something other than a terrifying slide into

    psychosis (Thinking Fragments, 218). A strongly similar point is made byJames Glass in his analysis of multiple personality disorder and

    postmodernism. Oliver Sacks argues that one cannot live normally, humanly

    in the world without the integrative power implied by a stable self.

    Anthropologists such as Sheri Ortner and Jose Limon, in their study of

    minority populations, write with great eloquence about the striving for unity

    and a coherent life among minorities in this country. Jose Limon argues that

    while life for working-class Mexican Americans is indeed full of

    discontinuity, disruption, and fragmentation, the forms and patterns of theirdancing in south Texas dance halls represents a struggle against these things,

    an effort, however momentary and inadequate, to construct a world of

    meaning and coherence (Limon, Representation, Ethnicity, and the

    Precursory Ethnography). The weakness in these celebrations of

    multiplicity is that they fail to connect to a sense of lived reality, the practical

    sphere in which selves must live out their lives and construct a sense of

    coherence and meaning.

    Additionally, these claims celebrating the fragmented self ignore thepotential dangers of accepting multiplicity as a normative standard. Norms

    are often appropriated for disciplinary ends and the norm of multiplicity can

    itself become disciplining when connected, for instance, to the demand that

    one ignore integrity or coherence of the self or that one continuously reshape

    oneself according to flexible and changing social standards. Stone herself

    recognizes the connection between self-identity and regimes of discipline

    and control. She argues that the unitary monistic identity characteristic of the

    modern period, what she terms the fiduciary subject, is the product of tacticsof discipline, control, and violence directed at the body and institutionally

    maintained by what she refers to as location technologies: psychological

    tests, phone numbers, census taking, etc. As an account of the formation of

    self-identity, Stones is very simplistic, reducing what surely must be an

    exceedingly complex story to a one-dimensional account of the violence of

    the law reigning in the multiplicitous psyche. Equally simplistic, though, is

    8

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    9/10

    Stones corrollary suggestion that the multiple self, created in the

    cybersystems of the virtual age, escapes that disciplining process. The

    technosocial space of virtual systems, Stone argues, has an iruptive ludic

    quality, a potential for experimentation and play that undermines the

    disciplining forces of real space. How exactly this technosocial realm is ableto escape the discipline and control of real space is never precisely made

    clear in Stones analysis. It is as if the mere presence of play in cyberspace is

    powerful enough to guarantee a degree of freedom not normally encountered

    in real life.

    Relatedly, when it becomes normal to reinvent oneself and when

    social standards are missing or themselves fragmented and multiplied, the

    self risks losing itself in slavish devotion to social trends and fads. Robert

    Jay Lifton, who has developed a notion of the protean self, points to onepotential danger of the fragmented self, what he terms doubling, evident in

    the ability of German doctors during world war two to move easily between

    their practices as healers and their Auschwitz self. Lifton writes,

    Use of the term doubling calls attention to the creation of two

    relatively autonomous selves: the prior ordinary self, which for

    doctors includes important elements of the healer, and the Auschwitz

    self, which includes all of the psychological manoeuvres that help

    one avoid a conscious sense of oneself as a killer. The existence of anoverall Auschwitz self more or less integrated all of these mechanisms

    into a functioning whole, and permitted one to adopt oneself to that

    bizarre environemnt. The prior self enabled one to retain a sense of

    decency and loving connection. (qtd. in Glover, 23)

    InHabits of the Heart, Robert Bellah and his colleagues speak

    eloquently of the danger of what they term the unencumbered self, the self

    completely unencumbered by ties to others, communities, or traditions.Bellah describes this self as a fluid self, moving easily from one social

    situation and role to another without trying to fit life into any one set of

    values and norms, even ones own. In fact, ones values are not really a

    single system, since they vary from one social situation and relationship to

    the next (77). This is the view of selfhood championed by Turkle, Stone,

    Gergen, and others. As Bellah warns, though, such a self defined by this kind

    9

  • 7/28/2019 Internet and Self Identity

    10/10

    of absolute autonomy is not really self-defining and self-constituting, but

    simply becomes a slave to the social situation and socially defined values.

    The only basis for choosing becomes ones own idiosyncratic preferences,

    which come to define the true self (74).

    Finally, this multiple self also presupposes a socially isolated andindividualistic view of the self that is antithetical to our social existence and

    leaves no room for the development of character, virtue, care, integrity, and

    future concern. In this respect, the multiple, fragmented self is not far afield

    from the highly individualistic, Cartesian self that it is defined against. Both

    stress the self as ultimately an atomistic individual, making its way through

    the real world or the chat rooms of cyberspace, defining and redefining itself

    as it moves from situation to situation, adopting first this role, then that

    persona. Such a self seems incapable of including the ties that bind a familytogether or constitute friendships that progress beyond mere acquaintances or

    role-playing others. The view of the self as described in works by Turkle,

    Stone, Gergen, Poster and others is often portrayed as a self at play, a free

    spirit, positively recommended for life in the virtual age. But it is also a self

    without attachments, with little coherence, perhaps lacking integrity,

    completely unencumbered by ties to others or to a stable community of

    family and friends. Before adopting this playful approach to multiplicity, we

    ought to ask ourselves whether we really want to play such a part in life.

    10