intro to maths for cs: 2012/13 sets (contd, week 2)

34
Intro to Maths for CS: 2012/13 Sets (contd, week 2) John Barnden Professor of Artificial Intelligence School of Computer Science University of Birmingham, UK

Upload: reed-gamble

Post on 01-Jan-2016

33 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

DESCRIPTION

Intro to Maths for CS: 2012/13 Sets (contd, week 2). John Barnden Professor of Artificial Intelligence School of Computer Science University of Birmingham, UK. Reminder of Week 1. Some Properties of those Operations. Union and intersection are commutative (“can switch”) : A  B = B  A - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Intro to Maths for CS:2012/13

Sets (contd, week 2)

John BarndenProfessor of Artificial Intelligence

School of Computer ScienceUniversity of Birmingham, UK

Reminder of Week 1

Some Properties of those Operations Union and intersection are commutative (“can switch”):

A B = B A

A B = B A

Union and intersection are associative (“can group differently”):

A ( (B C) = (A B) C

A (B C) = (A B) C

Because of associativity, we can omit parentheses: A B C D A B C D

Two Other Properties

Union distributes over intersection: A (B C) = (A B) (A C)

Intersection distributes over union: A (B C) = (A B) (A C)

New for Week 2

Same Difference?

Exercises for bath-time:

Is the difference operation commutative or associative?

And does it take part in any distributivity with the other operations?

Size (Cardinality) of a Set When set AA is finite, the size or cardinality of AA (its number

of members) is denoted ||A||.

Some obvious points (where A, B are finite) …

||| | = 0

|{|{}| }| = 1

If A B but A B, then ||A| < || < |B||

|A|, |B| |A|, |B| |A |A B| B| |A| + |B| |A| + |B|

| A | A B | B | |A|, |B| |A|, |B|

Powersets(reminder from last term)

The set of all the subsets of a set A is called the powerset of

A, denoted ℙ(A) or sometimes 2A

ℙ( {1,2,3} ) = { , {1}, {2}, {3}, {1,2}, {2,3}, {3,1}, A}

ℙ( {1} ) = { , {1} }

ℙ( ) = { }

When A is finite, ||ℙ(A) | | = 2||A| | (remember why?)

So when |A| = 12, ||ℙ(A) | | = 212 = 4096

“Tuples” A “tuple” is an ordered sequence of items of any sort. We

will only deal with finite tuples. Items CAN be duplicated. Can also be called a “vector.”

Notation: 6, JAB, 5, “JAB”, 5, , 9>

Or: (6, JAB, 5, “JAB”, 5, , 9)

Singleton and empty tuples: <6>, <>

<6, 6, 3>, <6,3> , <6,6,3,6> and <6,3,6> are all different.

Ordered Pairs Bernd Bohnet in Term 1mentioned ordered pairs of

numbers, when discussing graphs (textbook p.152).

An ordered pair is simply a tuple of length two:

6, JAB >

“JAB”, >

-6, -6 >

5, -6 >

, >

“Cartesian Products” and “Relations” The set of all possible tuples formed from some sets is called the

Cartesian product of the sets.

Notation, e.g.: D E F G H

if D, E, F, G, H are the sets—not necessarily different.

Each tuple is of form <d,e,f,g,h> where d D, e E, etc.

Any subset at all of that Cartesian product is called a relation on the sets in question (D, E, …)

even the whole of the product (even if infinite) and even the empty set.

I.e., a relation on D, E, …, H is just some set of tuples that are each of form <d,e, …, h> where d D, e E, …, h H.

Examples Let A = {3, 8, 2} and B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’}.

  Then A B =

{ <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <8, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <2, ‘bb’> }.

B B = { <‘jjj’, ‘jjj’>, <‘jjj’, ‘bb’>, <‘bb’, ‘jjj’>, <‘bb’, ‘bb’>}.

A = = A

A {JAB} = { <3, JAB>, <8, JAB>, <2, JAB> }

Some relations on A and B: { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>}

{ <2, ‘bb’> }

A B

Relations from Somewhere to Somewhere

A relation R “from” set A “to” set B is the same thing as a relation “on” A “and” B — just different terminology.

Similarly, a relation from A, B, C to D, E is the same thing as a relation on A, B, C, D, E.

Changing the Sets in a Relation Around

A relation R on A, B, C, D, E, say, obviously “induces” (i.e., gives rise to, in a natural way) a relation on any reordering of the sets, such as D, A, B, E, C, just by reordering each tuple in the same way.

Thus, R induces a relation from, say, D, A to B, E, C.

When there are just two sets A and B, the (only possible) reordering of the sets gives the inverse of R.

Inverse Example

Suppose R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>}

Then the inverse of R, notated

R--1

is the relation { <‘jjj’, 3>, <‘bb’, 3>, <‘jjj’, 2>}

Restriction of a Relation

Consider a relation R from A to B,

and a subset AA of A.

Then the restriction of R to AA is the relation derived from R by restricting attention to AA,

i.e., including only tuples whose first element is in AA.

The new relation is notated R|R|AAAA

Restriction Example A = {3, 8, 2}, B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’, ‘c’}.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘c’>, <2, ‘c’> }

AA = {3, 8}.

Then R|R|AAAA = = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <8, ‘c’>}

Functional Relations(Partial Functions)

A relation R from A to B is functional if, for any a in A, there is AT MOST one (but perhaps no) b in B such that a, b> is in R.

So several things in A can be related to the same thing in B.

But you can’t have several things in B related to the same thing in A.

A functional relation from A to B is also called a partial function from A to B.

Examples A = {3, 8, 2, 100}, B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’, ‘c’, ‘x’, ‘y’}.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘c’>, <2, ‘c’> }

NOT functional, because 3 maps to both ‘jjj’ and ‘bb’, and …

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <100, ‘x’>}

IS functional

(NB: 8 doesn’t map to anything, and both 3 and 2 map to ‘jjj’)

Totality of Relations

A relation R from A to B is total (on A) if it relates everything in A to AT LEAST one thing in B.

I.e., for every member a of A, there is at least one b in B such that

a, b >> is in R.

A relation may be merely partial (on A above) in not being total. However, technically all relations are “partial”, with total being a special case.

Examples A = {3, 8, 2, 100}, B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’, ‘c’, ‘x’, ‘y’}.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘c’>, <100, ‘y’>}

IS total

(NB: 3 maps to more than one thing)

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <100, ‘x’>}

NOT total, because 8 fails to map to anything.

Functions A total functional relation from A to B is called a function from

A to B.

Each thing in A is related to exactly one thing in B. (But two different things in A can be related to the same thing in B, and not everything in B needs to be related to anything in A. So the inverse relation is not necessarily either functional or total.)

Caution: every function is also a partial function.

Examples A = {3, 8, 2, 100}, B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’, ‘c’, ‘x’, ‘y’}.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <3, ‘bb’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘c’>, <100, ‘y’>}

NOT a function, because 3 maps to more than one thing

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <100, ‘x’>}

NOT a function, because 8 fails to map to anything.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <2, ‘jjj’>, <100, ‘x’>, <8, ‘x’>}

IS a function.

From Partiality to Totality by Restriction

We can always turn a merely-partial R from A to B into a total one by slimming A down enough! Just remove the members of A that aren’t related to anything by R, to get a new set AA. We don’t remove any tuples from R.

R (as a relation from AA to B) is total on AA.

And note that R|AA = R.

AA is called the domain of R, notated dom(R).

Totality contd. and “Onto”

A relation R from A to B is onto if for everything in B there is at least one thing in A that is related by R to it. I.e.:

For every member b of B,

there is at least one a in A such that a, b> is in R.

Onto-ness is just totality in the other direction.

You can also say that R is total on B, or that the inverse of R is total.

Other Categories of Relation A relation R from A to B is one-to-one (1-1) if, for any a in A,

there is at most one b in B such that a, b> is in R, AND for any b in B, there is at most one a in A such that a, b> is in R.

That is, both the relation and its inverse from B to A are functional. (But they don’t need to be total.)

To put it another way: it is functional and different members of A map to (= are related to) different members of B.

Or again: Different members of A map to different members of B and different members of B map to different members of A.

Example A = {3, 8, 2, 100}, B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’, ‘c’, ‘x’, ‘y’}.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘c’>, <100, ‘y’>}

IS 1-1

Other categories, contd.

A one-to-one correspondence between a set A and B is a SPECIAL one-to-one relation from A to B (or B to A):

it is not only one-to-one but also TOTAL (on A) and ONTO (B). (Or we can say: total on both A and B.)

Example A = {3, 8, 2, 100}, B = {‘jjj’, ‘bb’, ‘c’, ‘y’}.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <8, ‘c’>, <100, ‘y’>}

NOT a 1-1 correspondence between A and B, even though it is 1-1, as 2 is left out from A, and ‘bb’ is left out from B.

R = { <3, ‘jjj’>, <2, ‘bb’>, <8, ‘c’>, <100, ‘y’>}

IS a 1-1 correspondence between A and B

Other categories, contd.

But any 1-1 relation from A to B is a 1-1 correspondence between the subsets of A, B consisting of those members that do happen to feature in the relation!

Countable and Uncountable Sets [Brief Intro]

A set X is countable countable if it can be placed in a one-to-one one-to-one correspondencecorrespondence with some subset of N, the set of natural numbers from 1.

Trivial case: X = N

Let R be the relation {<x,x> | x {<x,x> | x X}. X}. This is the identity relation on X.

Then R is a 1-1 correspondence between X and X.

Countable Sets, contd 1 Similarly for any proper subset X of N: just use the identity

relation on X again.

More interesting case: X = the set of all whole numbers (negative, positive and zero).

Let R be the relation

{<x, 2x> | x {<x, 2x> | x X, x X, x 0} 0} {<x, -1-2x> | x {<x, -1-2x> | x X, x < 0 } X, x < 0 }

So R = {(0,0), (-1,1), (1,2), (-2,3), (2,4), (-3,5), (3,6), …}

Then R is a 1-1 correspondence between X and N.

Countable Sets, contd 2 Yet more interesting case: X = the set of positive rational numbers.

Can get our relation R by putting the possible fractions (with positive whole number parts) in a square infinite table with numerators increasing horizontally and denominators increasing vertically:

1/1 2/1 3/1 4/1 5/1 6/1 … 1/2 2/2 3/2 4/2 5/2 6/2 … 1/3 2/3 3/3 4/3 5/3 6/3 … 1/4 2/4 2/5 2/6 : : … : : : : : : … Then traverse through the numbers in sequence by going up and down

diagonals, with steps on edges as necessary, and missing out fractions that are not in simplest form (missed out ones are shown in brackets):

1/1, 2/1, 1/2, 1/3, (2/2), 3/1, 4/1, 3/2, 2/3, 1/4, 1/5, (2,4), (3,3), (4,2), 5/1, … Count as: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11

Uncountable Sets All finite sets are countable. And they needn’t be sets of numbers!

The set of socks in this class is countable.

We have seen that some infinite ones are countable …

Even if the set X contains the natural numbers as a tiny proper subset!! E.g., X = the set of rational numbers.

But some infinite sets are not countable:

notably the set of real numbers (rational and irrational numbers together), or even the set of real numbers between 0 and 1.

Can be shown by a “diagonalization” argument based on the decimal representations of the numbers.