introduction

69
The concept of information by Birger Hjørland Visiting professor in Latvia October 11, 2006 12.00-13.30

Upload: zyta

Post on 07-Jan-2016

25 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

DESCRIPTION

The concept of information by Birger Hjørland Visiting professor in Latvia October 11, 2006 12.00-13.30. Introduction. "It is said that we live in an "Age of Information," but it is an open scandal that there is no theory, nor even definition, of information that is both broad - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Introduction

The concept of information

by Birger HjørlandVisiting professor in Latvia

October 11, 2006 12.00-13.30

Page 2: Introduction

2

Introduction

"It is said that we live in an "Age of Information,"

but it is an open scandal that there is no theory,

nor even definition, of information that is both broad

and precise enough to make such an assertion meaningful"

(Goguen, 1997)

Page 3: Introduction

3

Introduction

We use the term ”information” all the time. We speak about ”information seeking”, ”information retrieval”, ”organization of information” etc. As part of the scientific language of ”Information Science”.

However, there is not consensus about the meaning of that term (there is even no consensus that this is an important term for the field: Information Science). The differences in the understanding of the term are important for how we understand our tasks.

Page 4: Introduction

4

Introduction

Marcia Bates has recently (2005 and 2006) proposed a definition and an understanding of the concept of information. Here I will demonstrate that more useful conceptions have already been suggested in the literature of information science, and that the arguments put forward by the proponents of these views unfortunately have been ignored by Bates.

These different views are related to very different philosophical views. .

Page 5: Introduction

5

Introduction

The pragmatic philosophers suggest that all theories are provisional and justified or not justified by their utility. Do they meet our needs? So different theories could be useful for different purposes. Thus, in order to make our thoughts clear, we should ask: What practical consequence does it make whether one or another view is taken as true? (Or whether one or another meaning is taken as true?). If no practical implications follow, our theory (or meaning) is of no consequence and thus not important. What are the implications of different definitions and understandings of information for the work of information professionals?

Page 6: Introduction

6

Introduction

The definition of information used by Bates is from Parker “Information is the pattern of organization of matter and energy” (quoted by Bates, 2006, p. 1033), who further writes:  “Information is the pattern of organization of the matter of rocks, of the earth, of plants, of animal bodies, or of brain matter. Information is also the pattern of organization of the energy of my speech as it moves the air, or of the earth as it moves in an earthquake. Indeed, the only thing in the universe that does not contain information is total entropy; that alone is pattern-free” (emphasis in original). And: Information is “an objectively existing phenomenon in the universe.”

Page 7: Introduction

7

Introduction

An alternative understanding of information is presented in short and rejected by Bates: “One approach to information draws on Bateson's [1972] definition of information as a difference that makes a difference . A difference to whom or what? Here, I argue that we must begin prior to that understanding, begin even before a sensing animal detects or assigns meaning to an experienced difference. As we shall see, humans and other animals can usefully identify a number of distinct types of information even prior to meaning assignment. Later, we will relate this definition of information to a more familiar understanding of the term, addressing what happens when we become informed.” (Bates, 2006).

Page 8: Introduction

8

Objective or subjective?

1. The objective understanding (Observer independent, situation independent). Versions of this view have been put forward by, for example, Parker, Dretske, Stonier] and Bates. Bates’ version implies: Any difference is information.

2. The subjective/situational understanding. Versions have been put forward by, for example, Bateson, Yovits, Spang-Hanssen, Brier, Buckland, Goguen and Hjørland: This position implies: Information is a difference that makes a difference (for somebody or for something or from a point of view).

Page 9: Introduction

9

Objective or subjective?

The subjective/situational understanding implies: What is information for one person in one situation needs not be information for another person or in another situation.

This view of information as a noun is related to becoming informed (informing as a verb). Something is information if it is informative (or rather: something is information when it is informative). (This view is also considered by Bates, but is termed “information 2”).

Page 10: Introduction

10

Objective or subjective?

Bates has an example of a frosted window representing information. Before considering that example, let us review an example put forward by Hjørland (1997): “A stone on a field could contain different information for different people (or from one situation to another). It is not possible for information systems to map all the stone´s possible information for every individual. Nor is any one mapping the one "true" mapping. But people have different educational backgrounds and play different roles in the division of labor in society. A stone in a field represents typical one kind of information for the geologist, another for the archaeologist. The information from the stone can be mapped into different collective knowledge structures produced by e.g. geology and archaeology.

Page 11: Introduction

11

Objective or subjective?

Information can be identified, described, represented in information systems for different domains of knowledge. Of course, there are much uncertainty and many and difficult problems in determining whether a thing is informative or not for a domain. Some domains have high degree of consensus and rather explicit criteria of relevance. Other domains have different, conflicting paradigms, each containing it own more or less implicate view of the informativeness of different kinds of information sources. “ (Hjørland, 1997, p. 111)

Page 12: Introduction

12

Objective or subjective?

In a similar way, it should be possible to say that a frosted window might be regarded as answers to different kinds of questions and thus represent different kinds of information (e.g. for the artist, the physicist and the meteorologist). The problem with understanding frosted windows as objective information is: what should the purpose be in representing this information in an information system? How does the concept of information serve us in relation to this example?

Page 13: Introduction

13

Objective or subjective?

These examples demonstrate in my opinion that the domain-specific understanding is the way of understanding most in correspondence with ordinary views of science and knowledge: Researchers in each domain looks at the world from a specific perspective and define and process information accordingly. Scientists do not just describe or collect differences mechanically. On the contrary, they usually describe differences from a theoretical point of view or from a stated purpose.

Page 14: Introduction

14

Objective or subjective?

While I do agree with Bates that, for example, genetic information is encoded in the DNA, I do not consider this information to be independent of the biological theories. It may be “objective” in the way that different observers describe it the same way (although I prefer to use the term intersubjective in this connection). But this objectivity (or intersubjectivity) is dependent on a scientific consensus in biology. It is only within this theoretical framework that DNA may be understood as information in an “objective” way).

Page 15: Introduction

15

Semiotics

“In the language used here, information can be seen as the raw material, the fodder, that goes into the process of semiosis, as well as into individual acts of interpretation. For example, in various cultures over the years, waving a hand toward oneself has come to mean, come here. Thus, a long-term semiotic process has resulted in that association being present in many human beings' minds. My culture shares that association. When, at a party, I interpret that hand motion from a friend across the room as a sign to come join him, I am selecting out a certain subset of all the information around me. From all the patterns of organization of sound, sight, smell, and touch that I experience in the room, I separate out the hand motion and read it as come here, and then heed the call “ (Bates, 2006).

Page 16: Introduction

16

Semiotics

Again: For Bates, the physical pattern of a moving hand is information, while in semiotics it is a sign if interpreted as such. An objective understanding of information, like Bates’ consider the hand motion a kind of information independent of whether it is observed or not and independent of how it is interpreted. In this way there is a conflict between whether somebody is being informed about that hand waving or not. The hand waving is information whether anybody is informed or not. Information as a noun is not by Bates linked to the verb to inform.

Page 17: Introduction

17

Semiotics

In order to cope with this problem Bates has to establish another concept, “information 2”, which is defined in this way: “Information 2: Some pattern of organization of matter and energy given meaning by a living being (or its constituent parts).”

Blair (2006) interprets at length for Information Science Wittgenstein's later philosophy. The position is rigorously sustained that the meanings ascribed to words do not arise from the words themselves, but arise from the ways in which words are used in discourses. The position that words have only meanings temporarily and situational given to them is compatible with Bates’ Information 2 but not with Information 1.

Page 18: Introduction

18

“Information 2”

Bates have thus two concepts: ”Information” (or ”information 1”) and ”Information 2”. She insists that information is not subjective/situational.

Information 2” may be seen as an indication of a problematic understanding of information, possibly a way of admitting that an objective conception of information cannot do the work we need it to do. Bates suggests that we understand "information" to be objective, while "information2" is subjective. By introducing two definitions: “information” and “information 2” one may say that Bates is trying to have it both ways.

Page 19: Introduction

19

“Information 2”

Consequently Bates should explain carefully when we need to speak about “information 1” and when we need to speak about “information 2”. In my opinion she fails to demonstrate that what we are working with in information science is “information 1”. My claim is that what we are working with in her terminology is “information 2”.

Page 20: Introduction

20

“Information 2”

Bates and I agree that we need the subjective concept of information, but we disagree on how is should be labeled because we disagree about the need for an objective understanding of information. In analyzing the practical implications, Bates does not maintain a clear argument for the usefulness of an objective understanding. By introducing "information 2" Bates uses the concept of meaning which is almost as difficult a concept as information itself, why it should not be used without a careful analysis and explication of its meaning

Page 21: Introduction

21

“Meaning”

Bates uses the concept of meaning which is almost as difficult a concept as information itself. There are different views of where to find the meaning of a text, for example:

1) Meaning is in the text

2) Meaning is in the writer

3) Meaning is in the reader.

These different views of text-meaning often lead to heated debates in semiotics, literary theory, the philosophy of language, and semantics. We see that the same problem of objectivity/subjectivity is related to the term meaning.

Page 22: Introduction

22

Information in computers

Bates defined: “Information 2: Some pattern of organization of matter and energy given meaning by a living being”.

In computers, the same string of characters, the same “pattern of organization of matter and energy” are “interpreted differently” by different programs and in different context. One string of characters may in one context mean a telephone number, in an other context a fax number. This example demonstrates more far-reaching problems with the objective understanding.

Page 23: Introduction

23

“Information theory”

"Information theory" (Shannon & Weaver, 1949) is also important to consider in this perspective. Although shortly discussed by Bates the problem of whether this theory is subjective or objective is not addressed. According to Qvortrup (1993) Shannon and Weaver were unclear as to whether they conceive information as a substance or as a sign.

"Thus, actually two conflicting metaphors are being used: The well-known metaphor of information as a quantity, like water in the water-pipe, is at work, but so is a second metaphor, that of information as a choice,

Page 24: Introduction

24

“Information theory”

, a choice made by an information provider, and a forced choice made by an information receiver. Actually, the second metaphor implies that the information sent isn't necessarily equal to the information received, because any choice implies a comparison with a list of possibilities, i.e. a list of possible meanings. Here, meaning is involved, thus spoiling the idea of information as a pure "Ding an sich". Thus, much of the confusion regarding the concept of information seems to be related to the basic confusion of metaphors in Shannon’s theory: is information an autonomous quantity, or is information always per se information to an observer?

Page 25: Introduction

25

“Information theory”

Actually, I don't think that Shannon himself chose one of the two definitions. Logically speaking, his theory implied information as a subjective phenomenon. But this had so wide-ranging epistemological impacts that Shannon didn't seem to fully realize this logical fact. Consequently, he continued to use metaphors about information as if it were an objective substance. This is the basic, inherent contradiction in Shannon's information theory. " (Qvortrup, 1993, p. 5).

Page 26: Introduction

26

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

Karpatschof (2000, p. 128ff) provides an understanding of information. In order to define this concept he introduces the concept of release mechanisms, being systems or organisms having at their disposal a store of potential energy, the systems being ”designed” to let this energy out in specific ways, whenever trigged by a signal fulfilling the specifications of the release mechanism. The signal that triggers a certain release mechanism is a low energy phenomenon fulfilling some release specifications.

Page 27: Introduction

27

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

The signal is thus the indirect cause, and the process of the release mechanism the direct cause of the resulting reaction, which is a high-energy reaction compared to the energy in the signal. Information is thus defined as a quality by a given signal relative to a certain mechanism. The release mechanism has a double function: (1) it reinforces the weak signal and (2) it directs the reaction by defining the functional value of a signal in the pre-designed system of the release mechanism.

Page 28: Introduction

28

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

Karpatschof’s understanding of information has many merits. Among them is that it explains the basic mechanism in computers as well as in living beings. It is also possible, as done by Hjørland (2002) to use it to explain basic principles in information systems and services, including in what Bates terms "the curatorial sciences". Karpatschof's understanding is also in important ways in accordance with views held by prominent contributors to information science such as Michael Buckland.

Page 29: Introduction

29

Four aspects of Information(After Buckland, 1991, p. 6)

       INTANGIBLE            TANGIBLE

ENTITY "Information-as-knowledge"   Knowledge

"Information-as-thing" Data, documents, recorded knowledge

 PROCESS

"Information-as-process" Becoming informed  

 "Information Processing" Data processing, document processing, knowledge engineering 

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

Page 30: Introduction

30

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

According to Buckland, things can be informative. A stump of a tree contains information about its age on its rings - as well as information about the climate during the lifetime of the tree. In similar ways, everything can be informative: "We conclude that we are unable to say confidently of anything that it could not be information" (Buckland, 1991, p. 50, emphasis in original).

Page 31: Introduction

31

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

But if everything is information, then the concept of information is all embracive. If the concept of information has no limits, it becomes too vague and useless. What kind of advise can that concept provide with regard to what to represent in information systems?

Page 32: Introduction

32

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

To say about something that it is informative means that this thing may answer a question for somebody. The informativeness is thus a relation between the question and the thing. No thing is inherently informative. To consider something information is thus always to consider it as informative in relation to some possible questions. We do not always realize this, because it is mostly implied. It is implied, for example, that a paper about a disease may help answering questions about that disease. It is less obvious, however, that a meteorite from outer space may answer questions about the origin of life.

Page 33: Introduction

33

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

A good deal of scientific knowledge is needed to understand why this is the case (and a claim about the informativeness of something is theory-dependent and may turn out to be wrong). In the wider sense, background knowledge is always important to establish the informativeness of any object (including documents and texts).

Page 34: Introduction

34

The alternative: The situated understanding of information

    “Conclusion: The analysis of the concept of information made above implies that informational objects should not only be analyzed and described according to an objectivistic epistemology. It is not sufficient to describe information according to universalistic principles, as permanent, inherent characteristics of knowledge. Instead, information must be analyzed, described and represented in information systems according to situational, pragmatic and domain-specific criteria." (Hjørland, 1997, p. 111).

Page 35: Introduction

35

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

Bates (2005) suggests an evolutionary framework for information science. Her evolutionary point of view is based on philosophical realism: "The first assumption is that there is a real universe out there, that we are not solipsists, that is, what we see as being outside ourselves is not a movie we are running in our minds, but an actual universe independent of ourselves."

These views are shared by the present author and by, for example, Karpatschof (2000).

Page 36: Introduction

36

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

One advantages of the activity-theoretical point of view as developed by the Russian psychologist Leontyev (1940/1981) is that the biological development is specified in levels, which may be interpreted as more advanced kinds of information processing mechanisms. He described the development of psychological functions as a set of functions developed by higher animals in order to improve their adaptation to the changing conditions of life and distinguished five stages or levels from primitive organisms to Homo sapiens:

Page 37: Introduction

37

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

1. The stage of irritability is characteristic of the absorption of food particles through the surface of the body of one-celled animals. Leontyev does not see such behavior as evidence of something psychical. (It is a pre-form of psychological behavior).

 2.   The stage of sensory psyche can be exemplified by insects, birds and fish. It is characterized by the ability of the organism to sense influences, but the animal cannot integrate different influences into a whole. Animals at this stage of development show stiff or rigid patterns of reactions, i.e. instinctive forms of behavior. Leontyev sees this stage as psychical in its most primitive form.

Page 38: Introduction

38

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

3.  The stage of perceptual psyche is first and foremost characterized by the perception of objects. The organism is now not just limited to sensing and responding to sound, light, simple forms, etc., but perceives specific objects (e.g. flies). This allows much more flexible forms of behavior directed towards that object.

4.  The stage of intellect is associated with actions, which presuppose the use of tools. The organism is no longer solely dependent on its own body. This stage is found in man and chimpanzees.

Page 39: Introduction

39

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

 5.  The stage of consciousness is specifically human. According to the theory of Leontyev it is associated with language and societal production.

What is described here can be interpreted as a theory of the development of biological stages of information utilization behavior from more primitive, specific and passive forms of sensing information towards more advanced, complex, flexible and active forms of information utilization.

Page 40: Introduction

40

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

Leontyev’s perspective are psychical and subjective phenomena naturalistic; they developed with birds, fish and insects, and further through evolution. Activity theory is in fact a semiotic theory (a biological-social semiotic theory). Organisms are seen as reacting to informative objects as signs[1]. Information is not a thing or substance but a sign. [1]For Charles Sanders Peirce a sign is a triadic unity of something (the sign vehicle, e.g. a footprint) which stands to somebody (the interpretant) for something else (the object, e.g. that a person has passed by).

Page 41: Introduction

41

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

Most evolutionary theories suffer from a neglecting of human cultural development. They tend to regard human information processing in a biological perspective assuming species-general ways of processing information. This is also the case with Bates (2005). There is no discussion of how information processing in individuals is different by, for example, people in oral cultures compared to people in literate cultures. This is the important contribution of activity theory as outlined by, for example, Karpatschof (2000) and Hjørland (2002). The biological-evolutionary perspective is thus supplemented with a developmental view of information processing in the perspective of cultural history.

Page 42: Introduction

42

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

Compared to other species human beings are far less depending on their biological cognitive systems and much more depending on their cultural heritage. This is something strongly neglected by mainstream behavioral and cognitive theories from the 20th century. A person's capacity to process and store information is not just depending on her biological make-up, but also on the language and symbolic systems that the person masters.

This is empirically shown by cultural anthropologists like Goody (1987) and theoretically mostly developed in activity theory.

Page 43: Introduction

43

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

“The line of theory developed by Vygotsky . . . maintains that when an individual comes to master writing, the basic system underlying the nature of his mental processes is changed fundamentally as the external symbol system comes to mediate the organization of all his basic intellectual operations. Thus, for example, knowledge of a writing system would alter the very structure of memory, classification and problem-solving by altering the way in which these elementary processes are organized to include an external (written) symbol system.” (Goody, 1987, p. 205)

Page 44: Introduction

44

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

How, for example, our concepts are influenced by our languages is shown in the figure below. It shows that there is no one-to one relation between meanings in different languages. Languages affect the way we conceptualize the world. According to Hjelmslev (1943) puts each language arbitrary borders on reality, while activity theory finds that our symbolic systems tend to capture functional aspects or affordances in the things we perceive.

Page 45: Introduction

45

Page 46: Introduction

46

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

The view of activity theory is that meanings, signs and documents are developed to function in relation to standardized practices in communities. We use, e.g. the Bible and the Hymn Book in our standardized religious practices. We use textbooks in our standardized teaching practices, law books in standardized legal practices etc. Concepts and documents have more or less stable functional values in relation to such standardized practices.

Page 47: Introduction

47

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

There are of course always different views of whether such standardized practices should be changed or remain unchanged, and there are always different kinds of possible changes of those practices. Consequently there is a corresponding need for a change in meanings and documents.

Often scientific and technological development changes standardized practices in a rather uncontroversial way. In other cases, however, changes in practices are related to different political interests, to different theories or "paradigms".

Page 48: Introduction

48

The evolutionary and cultural point of view

Different paradigms tend to influence given practices in different ways, and by doing so they also tend to change our symbolic systems as well as our production of documents and the form, content and use of those documents.

The proper study of symbols and documents is thus based on the study of the functions and interests those documents are serving.

Page 49: Introduction

49

Critique of “behavioral” views

It is very naive and reductionistic to disregard such kinds of cultural inter-mediating factors in people's relationship with information.

The dominant traditions in both information science and in behavioral and cognitive sciences have, however, neglected such cultural aspects and just tried to study generalized persons' relation to something termed "information". This dominant approach may broadly be termed "behavioral" in spite of different attitudes to versions of behaviorism.

Page 50: Introduction

50

Critique of “behavioral” views

In this tradition people are expected to react to something in a specific, mechanical way without considering the culturally determined meanings and without considering the different goals and values in the meanings and in the documents.

This has, in my opinion, brought about a situation in which we have inherited very little useful knowledge from these areas on which to advance our field and practice.

Page 51: Introduction

51

Consequences for LIS and related fields

One discussion within LIS is whether we need the concept of information at all? Should we rather speak of documents? Some researchers, including Buckland, Furner and myself has been arguing along these lines.

Nevertheless, when we speak of information, we need to clarify what we are speaking about. It is in my opinion very important whether we understand information in the subjective/situational way or in the objective way.

Page 52: Introduction

52

Consequences for LIS and related fields

Epistemological questions are important in the process of clarifying and constructing concepts in information science:•Is information in the author/sender of the information?•Is information in the texts/symbols/messages?•Is information in the receiver understood as a biological being?•Is information in the receiver understood as a social/cultural/specialized being?

Page 53: Introduction

53

Consequences for LIS and related fields

Let us consider, for example, the indexing of a document or the description of an informative object.

Should such indexing or description be based on a theory intended to inform the users and be based on a kind of semiotic understanding that signs (and document descriptors) have different meaning for different target groups?

This is the kind of questions at stake when discussing the objectivity/subjectivity of informative objects or documents.

Page 54: Introduction

54

Consequences for LIS and related fields

Capurro & Hjørland (2003, p.377ff.) argue that information scientists have to specify what kind of information belongs to sciences like astronomy and biology, and what kind of information belongs to information science. What is the social division of labor in relation to studies of information phenomena? A concrete proposal is provided in this paper. Information science is seen as a metascience based on the findings and documents of other fields. An astronomer process information about stars and produce documents on his observations and conclusions.

Page 55: Introduction

55

Consequences for LIS and related fields

Information science study for example, documents and genres of scientific communication, citation patterns in astronomy, how to optimize knowledge organizing systems to serve astronomers. Both astronomers and information scientists may thus be said to deal professionally with information. Capurro & Hjørland (2003, p.377ff.) and Hjørland (1997, 2002) offer a view of the respective jobs of ordinary professionals and LIS-professionals in relation to dealing with information. And we offer an information concept that we believe makes this view coherent.

Page 56: Introduction

56

References

Bar-Hillel, Y. & Carnap, R. (1953). Semantic information. British Journal of Science, 4, 147-157.

 

Bates, M. J. (2005). "Information and knowledge: an evolutionary framework for information science"   Information Research, 10(4) paper 239. Available at http://InformationR.net/ir/10-4/paper239.html

 

Page 57: Introduction

57

References

Bates, M. J. (2006). Fundamental forms of information. Journal of the American Society for Information Science, 57(8), 1033-1045.

 

Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. New York: Ballantine.

 

Blair, D. (2006). Wittgenstein, Language and Information: "Back to the Rough Ground!" Berlin: Springer.

Page 58: Introduction

58

References

Brier, S. (1996). Cybersemiotics: A new interdisciplinary development applied to the problems of knowledge organisation and document retrieval in information science. Journal of Documentation , 52(3), 296-344.

 

Briet, S. (1951). Qu’est-ce que la documentation? Paris: Documentaires Industrielles et Techniques.

 

Buckland, M. (1991). Information and information systems. New York: Greenwood Press.

Page 59: Introduction

59

References

Buckley, G. (2001). Semantics. http://web.archive.org/web/20010509042930/http://www.ling.upenn.edu/courses/Spring_2001/ling001/semantics.html [visited 2006-07-25]  Capurro, R. & Hjørland, B. (2003). The concept of information. Annual Review of Information Science and Technology, 37, 343-411.  Dretske, F.I. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press

Page 60: Introduction

60

References

Frohmann, B. (2004). Deflating information. From science studies to documentation. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.  Furner, J. (2004). Information studies without information. Library Trends, 52(3), 427-446.  Goguen, J. A. (1997). Towards a Social, Ethical Theory of Information. IN: Social Science Research, Technical Systems and Cooperative Work: Beyond the Great Divide, edited by Geoffrey Bowker, Les Gasser, Leigh Star and William Turner, Erlbaum, 1997, 27-56. Available at: http://www-cse.ucsd.edu/~goguen/ps/sti.pdf

Page 61: Introduction

61

References

Goody, J. (1987). The Interface Between the Written and the Oral. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hirst, G. (2006). Views of text-meaning in computational linguistics: Past, present, and future. In: Computing, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science, Dodig-Crnkovic, Gordana and Stuart, Susan (editors), Cambridge Scholars Press, Newcastle-upon-Tyne, 2006. [to appear]. http://ftp.cs.toronto.edu/pub/gh/Hirst-ECAP-2006.pdf 

Page 62: Introduction

62

References

Hjelmslev, L. (1943) Omkring sprogteoriens grundlæggelse. København: B. Lunos bogtrykkeri a/s. (Many later editions and translations, e.g. Prolegomena to a theory of language. translated by Francis J. Whitfield. Baltimore : Waverly Press, 1953).

Hjørland, B. (1997): Information Seeking and Subject Representation. An Activity-theoretical approach to Information Science. Westport & London: Greenwood Press. 

Page 63: Introduction

63

References

 

Hjørland, B. (1999). Review of Tom Stonier: Information and Meaning: An Evolutionary Perspective (Berlin: Springer, 1997). World Futures, (ISSN: 0260-4027), 53(4), 1999, 371-375. (Stoniers response: 375-376).  Hjørland, B. (2000). Documents, memory institutions, and information science. Journal of Documentation, 56, 27-41. http://www.db.dk/bh/publikationer/Filer/Documents_memory%20institutions%20and%20IS.pdf

Page 64: Introduction

64

References

Hjørland, B. (2002). Principia informatica: foundational theory of information and principles of information services. In H. Bruce, R. Fidel, P. Ingwersen, & P. Vakkari (Eds.), Emerging Frameworks and Methods: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Conceptions of Library and Information Science (CoLIS4) (pp. 109-121). Greenwood Village, CO: Libraries Unlimited.  Karpatschof, B. (2000). Human activity. Contributions to the Anthropological Sciences from a Perspective of Activity Theory. Copenhagen: Dansk Psykologisk Forlag. 

Page 65: Introduction

65

References

Leontyev, A. N. (1981). Problems of the Development of the Mind. Translated from Russian. Moscow: Progress. (Originally published 1940) 

Page 66: Introduction

66

References

Parker, E. B. (1974). Information and society. In C. A. Cuadra & M.J. Bates (Eds.), Library and information service needs of the nation: proceedings of a Conference on the Needs of Occupational, Ethnic and other Groups in the United States (pp. 9-50). Washington, DC: U.S.G.P.O.  Qvortrup, L. (1993). The controversy over the concept of information. An overview and a selected and annotated bibliography. Cybernetics & Human Knowing 1(4), 3-24. Raber, D. & Budd, J. M. (2003).Information as sign: semiotics and information science. Journal of Documentation, 59(5), 507-522.

Page 67: Introduction

67

References

Shannon, C. E. & Weaver, W. (1949/1964). The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Urbane: University of Illinois Press, 1964. (Original: 1949). 

Spang-Hanssen, H. (2001). How to teach about information as related to documentation. Human IT, (1), 125-143. http://www.hb.se/bhs/ith/1-01/hsh.htm

 

Stonier, T. (1997). Information and meaning: an evolutionary perspective. Berlin: Springer.

Page 68: Introduction

68

References

Wersig, G. (2003). Information theory. In J. Feather, & P. Sturges (Eds.), International encyclopedia of library and information science (pp. 310 319). London & New York: Routledge.

 

Yovits, M.C. (1969). Information Science: Toward the development of a true scientific discipline. American Documentation, vol. 20, 369–376.

Page 69: Introduction

69

References

Yovits, M. C. (1975). A theoretical framework for the development of information science. IN: International Federation for Documentation: Theoretical problems of informatics (FID 530), 90-114.