is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

137
Is there a probability theory of non-classical events? Is there a probability theory of non-classical events? Vincenzo Marra Dipartimento di Informatica e Comunicazione Universit a degli Studi di Milano [email protected] November 2 nd , 2009 International Workshop on Probability, Uncertainty, and Rationality Certosa di Pontignano

Upload: others

Post on 12-Feb-2022

1 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classicalevents?

Vincenzo MarraDipartimento di Informatica e Comunicazione

Universita degli Studi di [email protected]

November 2nd, 2009International Workshop on Probability, Uncertainty, and Rationality

Certosa di Pontignano

Page 2: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Outline

1 Prologue

2 From logic to probability: a sketch

3 A many-valued logic

4 Many-valued probability?

Page 3: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

Outline

1 Prologue

2 From logic to probability: a sketch

3 A many-valued logic

4 Many-valued probability?

Page 4: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

A conversation I heard some time ago at a mathematicsconference:

First mathematician – A good talk should alwayscontain at least one theorem and one joke.

Second mathematician – And you better make sure it isclear which is which.

There will be no theorem on many-valued probability in this talk,lest you might mistake it for a joke.In fact, I am really doubtful whether there even is such a thing asmany-valued probability at all.So I guess we better start on the safe side.

Page 5: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

A conversation I heard some time ago at a mathematicsconference:

First mathematician – A good talk should alwayscontain at least one theorem and one joke.

Second mathematician – And you better make sure it isclear which is which.

There will be no theorem on many-valued probability in this talk,lest you might mistake it for a joke.In fact, I am really doubtful whether there even is such a thing asmany-valued probability at all.So I guess we better start on the safe side.

Page 6: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

A conversation I heard some time ago at a mathematicsconference:

First mathematician – A good talk should alwayscontain at least one theorem and one joke.

Second mathematician – And you better make sure it isclear which is which.

There will be no theorem on many-valued probability in this talk,lest you might mistake it for a joke.In fact, I am really doubtful whether there even is such a thing asmany-valued probability at all.So I guess we better start on the safe side.

Page 7: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

A conversation I heard some time ago at a mathematicsconference:

First mathematician – A good talk should alwayscontain at least one theorem and one joke.

Second mathematician – And you better make sure it isclear which is which.

There will be no theorem on many-valued probability in this talk,lest you might mistake it for a joke.

In fact, I am really doubtful whether there even is such a thing asmany-valued probability at all.So I guess we better start on the safe side.

Page 8: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

A conversation I heard some time ago at a mathematicsconference:

First mathematician – A good talk should alwayscontain at least one theorem and one joke.

Second mathematician – And you better make sure it isclear which is which.

There will be no theorem on many-valued probability in this talk,lest you might mistake it for a joke.In fact, I am really doubtful whether there even is such a thing asmany-valued probability at all.

So I guess we better start on the safe side.

Page 9: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

A conversation I heard some time ago at a mathematicsconference:

First mathematician – A good talk should alwayscontain at least one theorem and one joke.

Second mathematician – And you better make sure it isclear which is which.

There will be no theorem on many-valued probability in this talk,lest you might mistake it for a joke.In fact, I am really doubtful whether there even is such a thing asmany-valued probability at all.So I guess we better start on the safe side.

Page 10: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

¡Pierre Fermat (1601 – 1665) Blaise Pascal (1623 – 1662)

Historiographic cliche: Probability theory begins in 1654, with the correspondence

between Fermat and Pascal on the problem of points, proposed to them by the

Chevalier de Mere (born Antoine Gombaud).

Page 11: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

The Fermat-Pascal correspondence. Œuvres de Fermat (ed. Tannery and Henry, Vol. II, p. 288–314, Paris 1894)

Page 12: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

Fermat to Pascal:

“Monsieur,

If I undertake to make a point with a single die in eight throws, and if we

agree after the money is put at stake, that I shall not cast the first throw,

it is necessary by my theory that I take 16

of the total sum to be impartial

because of the aforesaid first throw. And if we agree after that that I shall

not play the second throw, I should, for my share, take the sixth of the

remainder that is 536

of the total. If, after that, we agree that I shall not

play the third throw, . . . ”

Page 13: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

Part of Pascal’s reply:

“I see the truth is the same in Toulouse as in Paris.”

Apart from Pascal’s reference to truth, what does logic have to dowith probability?

Page 14: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

Part of Pascal’s reply:

“I see the truth is the same in Toulouse as in Paris.”

Apart from Pascal’s reference to truth, what does logic have to dowith probability?

Page 15: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Prologue

Part of Pascal’s reply:

“I see the truth is the same in Toulouse as in Paris.”

Apart from Pascal’s reference to truth, what does logic have to dowith probability?

Page 16: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Outline

1 Prologue

2 From logic to probability: a sketchThe role of logic in probability theoryRecap on classical propositional logicProbability assignments

3 A many-valued logic

4 Many-valued probability?

Page 17: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.

An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events. (It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 18: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.

Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events. (It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 19: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).

The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events. (It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 20: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events. (It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 21: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.

Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events. (It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 22: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events.

(It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 23: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

One key primitive notion in probability theory is that of event.An important tradition in the subject regards probability theory asan attempt to model the possible outcomes of idealisedexperiments.Thus, in the letter from Fermat to Pascal quoted above, theexperiment is a sequence of eight throws of a die (with facesnumbered from 1 to 6).The possible outcomes of the experiment are all possible sequencesof points in the eight throws; one such, e.g., is

1, 1, 3, 6, 2, 4, 6, 4 .

The set S of all possible outcomes is called the sample space.Certain subsets of S (not necessarily all) are then selected ashaving special interest for the problem at hand; they form thecollection E of events. (It is customary to ask that E satisfy someadditional assumptions, and we will return to this point later.)

Page 24: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

There is, however, a second approach to the notion of event thatalso has a substantial tradition.

It consists in taking propositions as the primitive notion, and indefining events as a derived notion.

An event is then whatever may be described by a proposition.

Thus, returning to Fermat’s example, the set consisting of the twosequence of points

1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 and 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6

corresponds to an event, because it may be described by aproposition. Say,

“Either one observes, as the outcome of the experiment,the smallest possible point at each throw, or else oneobserves the largest possible point at each throw.”

Page 25: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

There is, however, a second approach to the notion of event thatalso has a substantial tradition.It consists in taking propositions as the primitive notion, and indefining events as a derived notion.

An event is then whatever may be described by a proposition.

Thus, returning to Fermat’s example, the set consisting of the twosequence of points

1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 and 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6

corresponds to an event, because it may be described by aproposition. Say,

“Either one observes, as the outcome of the experiment,the smallest possible point at each throw, or else oneobserves the largest possible point at each throw.”

Page 26: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

There is, however, a second approach to the notion of event thatalso has a substantial tradition.It consists in taking propositions as the primitive notion, and indefining events as a derived notion.

An event is then whatever may be described by a proposition.

Thus, returning to Fermat’s example, the set consisting of the twosequence of points

1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 and 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6

corresponds to an event, because it may be described by aproposition. Say,

“Either one observes, as the outcome of the experiment,the smallest possible point at each throw, or else oneobserves the largest possible point at each throw.”

Page 27: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

There is, however, a second approach to the notion of event thatalso has a substantial tradition.It consists in taking propositions as the primitive notion, and indefining events as a derived notion.

An event is then whatever may be described by a proposition.

Thus, returning to Fermat’s example, the set consisting of the twosequence of points

1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 and 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6

corresponds to an event, because it may be described by aproposition.

Say,

“Either one observes, as the outcome of the experiment,the smallest possible point at each throw, or else oneobserves the largest possible point at each throw.”

Page 28: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

There is, however, a second approach to the notion of event thatalso has a substantial tradition.It consists in taking propositions as the primitive notion, and indefining events as a derived notion.

An event is then whatever may be described by a proposition.

Thus, returning to Fermat’s example, the set consisting of the twosequence of points

1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1 and 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6, 6

corresponds to an event, because it may be described by aproposition. Say,

“Either one observes, as the outcome of the experiment,the smallest possible point at each throw, or else oneobserves the largest possible point at each throw.”

Page 29: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

Boole on events vs. propositions:

George Boole, An Investigation of The Laws of Thought, pp. 247–248, Dublin 1854

Page 30: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

Keynes on events vs. propositions:

John Maynard Keynes, A Treatise on Probability, p. 5, Cambridge 1920

Page 31: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

Boole remarks that when using propositions in place of (somemathematical model of) events, probabilities will refer to the truthof propositions, rather than to the occurrence of the event.

Keynes openly states that this is “more than a verbalimprovement”. How is it so?

Well, one advantage of the approach based on propositions is thefollowing. Suppose we were concerned with the questions: Whatare events? And how does one observe the occurrence of an event?

Now we would then be concerned with the new questions: what arepropositions? And how does one verify the truth of a proposition?

Page 32: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

Boole remarks that when using propositions in place of (somemathematical model of) events, probabilities will refer to the truthof propositions, rather than to the occurrence of the event.

Keynes openly states that this is “more than a verbalimprovement”. How is it so?

Well, one advantage of the approach based on propositions is thefollowing. Suppose we were concerned with the questions: Whatare events? And how does one observe the occurrence of an event?

Now we would then be concerned with the new questions: what arepropositions? And how does one verify the truth of a proposition?

Page 33: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

Boole remarks that when using propositions in place of (somemathematical model of) events, probabilities will refer to the truthof propositions, rather than to the occurrence of the event.

Keynes openly states that this is “more than a verbalimprovement”. How is it so?

Well, one advantage of the approach based on propositions is thefollowing. Suppose we were concerned with the questions: Whatare events? And how does one observe the occurrence of an event?

Now we would then be concerned with the new questions: what arepropositions? And how does one verify the truth of a proposition?

Page 34: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

Boole remarks that when using propositions in place of (somemathematical model of) events, probabilities will refer to the truthof propositions, rather than to the occurrence of the event.

Keynes openly states that this is “more than a verbalimprovement”. How is it so?

Well, one advantage of the approach based on propositions is thefollowing. Suppose we were concerned with the questions: Whatare events? And how does one observe the occurrence of an event?

Now we would then be concerned with the new questions: what arepropositions? And how does one verify the truth of a proposition?

Page 35: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

This shift of perspective is more than a verbal improvementprecisely in that our new questions have nothing to do with thetheory of probability per se.

We are now in the realm of logic, and this might give us a safervantage point – after all, logic is about 4 times older thanprobability theory.

There indeed are widely accepted answers provided by logicians tothe questions above, and to these we now turn.

To summarise so far:

The role of logic in the theory of probability is to providea formal model for the notion of event.

Added in Proof. There would be much to say about a comparison

between the approach based on propositions and the one based on events.

If I have time I will return to this by way of an Appendix to the main talk.

Page 36: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

This shift of perspective is more than a verbal improvementprecisely in that our new questions have nothing to do with thetheory of probability per se.

We are now in the realm of logic, and this might give us a safervantage point – after all, logic is about 4 times older thanprobability theory.

There indeed are widely accepted answers provided by logicians tothe questions above, and to these we now turn.

To summarise so far:

The role of logic in the theory of probability is to providea formal model for the notion of event.

Added in Proof. There would be much to say about a comparison

between the approach based on propositions and the one based on events.

If I have time I will return to this by way of an Appendix to the main talk.

Page 37: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

This shift of perspective is more than a verbal improvementprecisely in that our new questions have nothing to do with thetheory of probability per se.

We are now in the realm of logic, and this might give us a safervantage point – after all, logic is about 4 times older thanprobability theory.

There indeed are widely accepted answers provided by logicians tothe questions above, and to these we now turn.

To summarise so far:

The role of logic in the theory of probability is to providea formal model for the notion of event.

Added in Proof. There would be much to say about a comparison

between the approach based on propositions and the one based on events.

If I have time I will return to this by way of an Appendix to the main talk.

Page 38: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

This shift of perspective is more than a verbal improvementprecisely in that our new questions have nothing to do with thetheory of probability per se.

We are now in the realm of logic, and this might give us a safervantage point – after all, logic is about 4 times older thanprobability theory.

There indeed are widely accepted answers provided by logicians tothe questions above, and to these we now turn.

To summarise so far:

The role of logic in the theory of probability is to providea formal model for the notion of event.

Added in Proof. There would be much to say about a comparison

between the approach based on propositions and the one based on events.

If I have time I will return to this by way of an Appendix to the main talk.

Page 39: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

The role of logic in probability theory

This shift of perspective is more than a verbal improvementprecisely in that our new questions have nothing to do with thetheory of probability per se.

We are now in the realm of logic, and this might give us a safervantage point – after all, logic is about 4 times older thanprobability theory.

There indeed are widely accepted answers provided by logicians tothe questions above, and to these we now turn.

To summarise so far:

The role of logic in the theory of probability is to providea formal model for the notion of event.

Added in Proof. There would be much to say about a comparison

between the approach based on propositions and the one based on events.

If I have time I will return to this by way of an Appendix to the main talk.

Page 40: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Taking stock of available knowledge about the logical analysis ofpropositions, we use classical propositional logic without furtherado as a formal means of modeling events.

We start with a (finite or infinite) set of propositional variables, oratomic formulæ, that are to stand for propositions. Say, if wecontent ourselves with countably many:

X1, X2, . . . , Xn, . . . .

To these we adjoin two symbols ⊤ and ⊥, say, that are to standfor a proposition that is always true (the verum), and one that isalways false (the falsum), respectively.To construct compound formulæ we use the logical connectives:

∨, for disjunction;

∧, for conjunction;

→, for implication; and

¬, for negation.

Page 41: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Taking stock of available knowledge about the logical analysis ofpropositions, we use classical propositional logic without furtherado as a formal means of modeling events.We start with a (finite or infinite) set of propositional variables, oratomic formulæ, that are to stand for propositions. Say, if wecontent ourselves with countably many:

X1, X2, . . . , Xn, . . . .

To these we adjoin two symbols ⊤ and ⊥, say, that are to standfor a proposition that is always true (the verum), and one that isalways false (the falsum), respectively.To construct compound formulæ we use the logical connectives:

∨, for disjunction;

∧, for conjunction;

→, for implication; and

¬, for negation.

Page 42: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Taking stock of available knowledge about the logical analysis ofpropositions, we use classical propositional logic without furtherado as a formal means of modeling events.We start with a (finite or infinite) set of propositional variables, oratomic formulæ, that are to stand for propositions. Say, if wecontent ourselves with countably many:

X1, X2, . . . , Xn, . . . .

To these we adjoin two symbols ⊤ and ⊥, say, that are to standfor a proposition that is always true (the verum), and one that isalways false (the falsum), respectively.

To construct compound formulæ we use the logical connectives:

∨, for disjunction;

∧, for conjunction;

→, for implication; and

¬, for negation.

Page 43: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Taking stock of available knowledge about the logical analysis ofpropositions, we use classical propositional logic without furtherado as a formal means of modeling events.We start with a (finite or infinite) set of propositional variables, oratomic formulæ, that are to stand for propositions. Say, if wecontent ourselves with countably many:

X1, X2, . . . , Xn, . . . .

To these we adjoin two symbols ⊤ and ⊥, say, that are to standfor a proposition that is always true (the verum), and one that isalways false (the falsum), respectively.To construct compound formulæ we use the logical connectives:

∨, for disjunction;

∧, for conjunction;

→, for implication; and

¬, for negation.

Page 44: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

The usual recursive definition of general formulæ now reads asfollows.

⊤ and ⊥ are formulæ.

All propositional variables are formulæ.

If � and � are formulæ, so are (�∨ �), (�∧ �), (�→ �), and¬�.

Let us write Form for the set of all formulæ constructed over thecountable language X1, . . . , Xn, . . ., and Formn for the set offormulæ constructed over the first n propositional variablesX1, . . . , Xn, at the most.

Page 45: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

The usual recursive definition of general formulæ now reads asfollows.

⊤ and ⊥ are formulæ.

All propositional variables are formulæ.

If � and � are formulæ, so are (�∨ �), (�∧ �), (�→ �), and¬�.

Let us write Form for the set of all formulæ constructed over thecountable language X1, . . . , Xn, . . ., and Formn for the set offormulæ constructed over the first n propositional variablesX1, . . . , Xn, at the most.

Page 46: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

The usual recursive definition of general formulæ now reads asfollows.

⊤ and ⊥ are formulæ.

All propositional variables are formulæ.

If � and � are formulæ, so are (�∨ �), (�∧ �), (�→ �), and¬�.

Let us write Form for the set of all formulæ constructed over thecountable language X1, . . . , Xn, . . ., and Formn for the set offormulæ constructed over the first n propositional variablesX1, . . . , Xn, at the most.

Page 47: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.

Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 48: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.

These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 49: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 50: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 51: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 52: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 53: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 54: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

As usual, we construct a formal semantics in order to interpretformulæ.Namely, we consider assignments of truth-values, or evaluations, orinterpretations.These are functions

w : Form→ {0, 1}

subject to the usual conditions:

w(⊤) = 1, w(⊥) = 0;

w(� ∧ �) = 1 if and only if both w(�) = 1 and w(�) = 1;

w(� ∨ �) = 1 if and only if either w(�) = 1 or w(�) = 1 (orboth);

w(�→ �) = 0 if and only if w(�) = 0 and w(�) = 1;

w(¬�) = 1 if and only if w(�) = 0.

Page 55: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

A first easy observation about these definitions is that a valuationw is subject to no restrictions concerning the values it assigns topropositional variables.

Moreover, it is also apparent that any valuation w is uniquelydetermined by such values w(X1), . . . , w(Xn), . . ..This is the principle of truth-functionality (after G. Frege) forclassical propositional logic.Following a well-established tradition going back at least to G. W.Leibniz, it is useful to think of an evaluation w : Form→ {0, 1} asa possible world in which each proposition � either holds – i.e.,w(�) = 1 – or fails to hold – i.e., w(�) = 0.Because of truth-functionality, then, a classical logician’s world issomething very ethereal indeed: it is uniquely determined by thecollection of true atomic propositions that can be uttered.

Page 56: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

A first easy observation about these definitions is that a valuationw is subject to no restrictions concerning the values it assigns topropositional variables.Moreover, it is also apparent that any valuation w is uniquelydetermined by such values w(X1), . . . , w(Xn), . . ..

This is the principle of truth-functionality (after G. Frege) forclassical propositional logic.Following a well-established tradition going back at least to G. W.Leibniz, it is useful to think of an evaluation w : Form→ {0, 1} asa possible world in which each proposition � either holds – i.e.,w(�) = 1 – or fails to hold – i.e., w(�) = 0.Because of truth-functionality, then, a classical logician’s world issomething very ethereal indeed: it is uniquely determined by thecollection of true atomic propositions that can be uttered.

Page 57: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

A first easy observation about these definitions is that a valuationw is subject to no restrictions concerning the values it assigns topropositional variables.Moreover, it is also apparent that any valuation w is uniquelydetermined by such values w(X1), . . . , w(Xn), . . ..This is the principle of truth-functionality (after G. Frege) forclassical propositional logic.

Following a well-established tradition going back at least to G. W.Leibniz, it is useful to think of an evaluation w : Form→ {0, 1} asa possible world in which each proposition � either holds – i.e.,w(�) = 1 – or fails to hold – i.e., w(�) = 0.Because of truth-functionality, then, a classical logician’s world issomething very ethereal indeed: it is uniquely determined by thecollection of true atomic propositions that can be uttered.

Page 58: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

A first easy observation about these definitions is that a valuationw is subject to no restrictions concerning the values it assigns topropositional variables.Moreover, it is also apparent that any valuation w is uniquelydetermined by such values w(X1), . . . , w(Xn), . . ..This is the principle of truth-functionality (after G. Frege) forclassical propositional logic.Following a well-established tradition going back at least to G. W.Leibniz, it is useful to think of an evaluation w : Form→ {0, 1} asa possible world in which each proposition � either holds – i.e.,w(�) = 1 – or fails to hold – i.e., w(�) = 0.

Because of truth-functionality, then, a classical logician’s world issomething very ethereal indeed: it is uniquely determined by thecollection of true atomic propositions that can be uttered.

Page 59: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

A first easy observation about these definitions is that a valuationw is subject to no restrictions concerning the values it assigns topropositional variables.Moreover, it is also apparent that any valuation w is uniquelydetermined by such values w(X1), . . . , w(Xn), . . ..This is the principle of truth-functionality (after G. Frege) forclassical propositional logic.Following a well-established tradition going back at least to G. W.Leibniz, it is useful to think of an evaluation w : Form→ {0, 1} asa possible world in which each proposition � either holds – i.e.,w(�) = 1 – or fails to hold – i.e., w(�) = 0.Because of truth-functionality, then, a classical logician’s world issomething very ethereal indeed: it is uniquely determined by thecollection of true atomic propositions that can be uttered.

Page 60: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Analytic truths, or tautologies after L. Wittgenstein, are nowdefined as those formulæ � ∈ Form that are true in every possibleworld, i.e. such that w(�) = 1 for any assignment w.

Tautologies are of central interest in logic proper, but not inprobability theory – they are just linguistic descriptions of the sureevent, an event that always occurs. Nonetheless, let us recall whythey are important to logic, omitting details.

Selecting an appropriate collection of formulæ as axioms, and usingmodus ponens as deduction rule, one defines the notion ofprovable formula. We do not need to recall details here.Writing ⊢ � to mean that a formula � is provable, and writing ∣= �to mean that � is a tautology, we can now state the all-important(soundness and) completeness theorem: for any � ∈ Form,

⊢ � if and only if ∣= � .

Page 61: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Analytic truths, or tautologies after L. Wittgenstein, are nowdefined as those formulæ � ∈ Form that are true in every possibleworld, i.e. such that w(�) = 1 for any assignment w.Tautologies are of central interest in logic proper, but not inprobability theory – they are just linguistic descriptions of the sureevent, an event that always occurs. Nonetheless, let us recall whythey are important to logic, omitting details.

Selecting an appropriate collection of formulæ as axioms, and usingmodus ponens as deduction rule, one defines the notion ofprovable formula. We do not need to recall details here.Writing ⊢ � to mean that a formula � is provable, and writing ∣= �to mean that � is a tautology, we can now state the all-important(soundness and) completeness theorem: for any � ∈ Form,

⊢ � if and only if ∣= � .

Page 62: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Analytic truths, or tautologies after L. Wittgenstein, are nowdefined as those formulæ � ∈ Form that are true in every possibleworld, i.e. such that w(�) = 1 for any assignment w.Tautologies are of central interest in logic proper, but not inprobability theory – they are just linguistic descriptions of the sureevent, an event that always occurs. Nonetheless, let us recall whythey are important to logic, omitting details.

Selecting an appropriate collection of formulæ as axioms, and usingmodus ponens as deduction rule, one defines the notion ofprovable formula. We do not need to recall details here.

Writing ⊢ � to mean that a formula � is provable, and writing ∣= �to mean that � is a tautology, we can now state the all-important(soundness and) completeness theorem: for any � ∈ Form,

⊢ � if and only if ∣= � .

Page 63: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Analytic truths, or tautologies after L. Wittgenstein, are nowdefined as those formulæ � ∈ Form that are true in every possibleworld, i.e. such that w(�) = 1 for any assignment w.Tautologies are of central interest in logic proper, but not inprobability theory – they are just linguistic descriptions of the sureevent, an event that always occurs. Nonetheless, let us recall whythey are important to logic, omitting details.

Selecting an appropriate collection of formulæ as axioms, and usingmodus ponens as deduction rule, one defines the notion ofprovable formula. We do not need to recall details here.Writing ⊢ � to mean that a formula � is provable, and writing ∣= �to mean that � is a tautology, we can now state the all-important(soundness and) completeness theorem: for any � ∈ Form,

⊢ � if and only if ∣= � .

Page 64: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Finally, let me recall that in classical logic there also is a strongerversion of completeness than the above one.

By a theory Θ one means a deductively closed set of formulæ.One generalises syntactic and semantic consequence to theories.Thus, for � ∈ Form,

Θ ⊢ �

means that � is deducible from Θ via modus ponens, whereas

Θ ∣= �

means that � is true in each possible world wherein each formulaof Θ is true.The completeness theorem for theories now reads: for any� ∈ Form and any theory Θ,

Θ ⊢ � if and only if Θ ∣= � .

Page 65: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Finally, let me recall that in classical logic there also is a strongerversion of completeness than the above one.By a theory Θ one means a deductively closed set of formulæ.

One generalises syntactic and semantic consequence to theories.Thus, for � ∈ Form,

Θ ⊢ �

means that � is deducible from Θ via modus ponens, whereas

Θ ∣= �

means that � is true in each possible world wherein each formulaof Θ is true.The completeness theorem for theories now reads: for any� ∈ Form and any theory Θ,

Θ ⊢ � if and only if Θ ∣= � .

Page 66: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Finally, let me recall that in classical logic there also is a strongerversion of completeness than the above one.By a theory Θ one means a deductively closed set of formulæ.One generalises syntactic and semantic consequence to theories.

Thus, for � ∈ Form,Θ ⊢ �

means that � is deducible from Θ via modus ponens, whereas

Θ ∣= �

means that � is true in each possible world wherein each formulaof Θ is true.The completeness theorem for theories now reads: for any� ∈ Form and any theory Θ,

Θ ⊢ � if and only if Θ ∣= � .

Page 67: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Finally, let me recall that in classical logic there also is a strongerversion of completeness than the above one.By a theory Θ one means a deductively closed set of formulæ.One generalises syntactic and semantic consequence to theories.Thus, for � ∈ Form,

Θ ⊢ �

means that � is deducible from Θ via modus ponens, whereas

Θ ∣= �

means that � is true in each possible world wherein each formulaof Θ is true.

The completeness theorem for theories now reads: for any� ∈ Form and any theory Θ,

Θ ⊢ � if and only if Θ ∣= � .

Page 68: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Recap on classical propositional logic

Finally, let me recall that in classical logic there also is a strongerversion of completeness than the above one.By a theory Θ one means a deductively closed set of formulæ.One generalises syntactic and semantic consequence to theories.Thus, for � ∈ Form,

Θ ⊢ �

means that � is deducible from Θ via modus ponens, whereas

Θ ∣= �

means that � is true in each possible world wherein each formulaof Θ is true.The completeness theorem for theories now reads: for any� ∈ Form and any theory Θ,

Θ ⊢ � if and only if Θ ∣= � .

Page 69: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

Having summarised our notation for classical logic, let us move onto probabilities.

Fix a theory Θ. A probability assignment (relative to Θ) is afunction

P : Form→ ℝ

that satisfies Kolmogorov’s axioms:

(K0) P (�) = P (�) whenever Θ ⊢ (�→ �) ∧ (� → �).

(K1) P (⊥) = 0 and P (⊤) = 1.

(K2) P (�) ⩽ P (�) whenever �→ � holds.

(K3) P (� ∨ �) + P (� ∧ �) = P (�) + P (�).

Page 70: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

Having summarised our notation for classical logic, let us move onto probabilities.

Fix a theory Θ. A probability assignment (relative to Θ) is afunction

P : Form→ ℝ

that satisfies Kolmogorov’s axioms:

(K0) P (�) = P (�) whenever Θ ⊢ (�→ �) ∧ (� → �).

(K1) P (⊥) = 0 and P (⊤) = 1.

(K2) P (�) ⩽ P (�) whenever �→ � holds.

(K3) P (� ∨ �) + P (� ∧ �) = P (�) + P (�).

Page 71: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

Having summarised our notation for classical logic, let us move onto probabilities.

Fix a theory Θ. A probability assignment (relative to Θ) is afunction

P : Form→ ℝ

that satisfies Kolmogorov’s axioms:

(K0) P (�) = P (�) whenever Θ ⊢ (�→ �) ∧ (� → �).

(K1) P (⊥) = 0 and P (⊤) = 1.

(K2) P (�) ⩽ P (�) whenever �→ � holds.

(K3) P (� ∨ �) + P (� ∧ �) = P (�) + P (�).

Page 72: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

Having summarised our notation for classical logic, let us move onto probabilities.

Fix a theory Θ. A probability assignment (relative to Θ) is afunction

P : Form→ ℝ

that satisfies Kolmogorov’s axioms:

(K0) P (�) = P (�) whenever Θ ⊢ (�→ �) ∧ (� → �).

(K1) P (⊥) = 0 and P (⊤) = 1.

(K2) P (�) ⩽ P (�) whenever �→ � holds.

(K3) P (� ∨ �) + P (� ∧ �) = P (�) + P (�).

Page 73: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

Having summarised our notation for classical logic, let us move onto probabilities.

Fix a theory Θ. A probability assignment (relative to Θ) is afunction

P : Form→ ℝ

that satisfies Kolmogorov’s axioms:

(K0) P (�) = P (�) whenever Θ ⊢ (�→ �) ∧ (� → �).

(K1) P (⊥) = 0 and P (⊤) = 1.

(K2) P (�) ⩽ P (�) whenever �→ � holds.

(K3) P (� ∨ �) + P (� ∧ �) = P (�) + P (�).

Page 74: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

Having summarised our notation for classical logic, let us move onto probabilities.

Fix a theory Θ. A probability assignment (relative to Θ) is afunction

P : Form→ ℝ

that satisfies Kolmogorov’s axioms:

(K0) P (�) = P (�) whenever Θ ⊢ (�→ �) ∧ (� → �).

(K1) P (⊥) = 0 and P (⊤) = 1.

(K2) P (�) ⩽ P (�) whenever �→ � holds.

(K3) P (� ∨ �) + P (� ∧ �) = P (�) + P (�).

Page 75: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

It should be stressed that these axioms, as is the case for allwell-established mathematical notions, did not come out of theblue.

When Kolmogorov’s celebrated Grundbegriffe derWahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung appeared in 1933, a huge amount ofinteresting mathematics in measure and probability theory wasalready available. And it would be ludicrous even to suggest thatthe importance of Kolmogorov’s work in the field amounts to hisaxiomatic definition.So from certain points of view – the conceptual development ofmathematics, for instance – it is entirely appropriate to hold thatthis definition was already fully justified in 1933.It is equally true, nonetheless, that from different perspectives it isreasonable – even necessary – to ask for a different sort ofjustification.

Page 76: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

It should be stressed that these axioms, as is the case for allwell-established mathematical notions, did not come out of theblue.When Kolmogorov’s celebrated Grundbegriffe derWahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung appeared in 1933, a huge amount ofinteresting mathematics in measure and probability theory wasalready available. And it would be ludicrous even to suggest thatthe importance of Kolmogorov’s work in the field amounts to hisaxiomatic definition.

So from certain points of view – the conceptual development ofmathematics, for instance – it is entirely appropriate to hold thatthis definition was already fully justified in 1933.It is equally true, nonetheless, that from different perspectives it isreasonable – even necessary – to ask for a different sort ofjustification.

Page 77: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

It should be stressed that these axioms, as is the case for allwell-established mathematical notions, did not come out of theblue.When Kolmogorov’s celebrated Grundbegriffe derWahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung appeared in 1933, a huge amount ofinteresting mathematics in measure and probability theory wasalready available. And it would be ludicrous even to suggest thatthe importance of Kolmogorov’s work in the field amounts to hisaxiomatic definition.So from certain points of view – the conceptual development ofmathematics, for instance – it is entirely appropriate to hold thatthis definition was already fully justified in 1933.

It is equally true, nonetheless, that from different perspectives it isreasonable – even necessary – to ask for a different sort ofjustification.

Page 78: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

It should be stressed that these axioms, as is the case for allwell-established mathematical notions, did not come out of theblue.When Kolmogorov’s celebrated Grundbegriffe derWahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung appeared in 1933, a huge amount ofinteresting mathematics in measure and probability theory wasalready available. And it would be ludicrous even to suggest thatthe importance of Kolmogorov’s work in the field amounts to hisaxiomatic definition.So from certain points of view – the conceptual development ofmathematics, for instance – it is entirely appropriate to hold thatthis definition was already fully justified in 1933.It is equally true, nonetheless, that from different perspectives it isreasonable – even necessary – to ask for a different sort ofjustification.

Page 79: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

The literature in this direction is abundant. To single out oneexample, let me mention the Ramsey-de Finetti Dutch bookargument (1926, 1937), along with its later utility-based version byL. Savage (1954), that featured in other talks. Of the variousjustifications of probability theory I will say no more here.

Frank P. Ramsey (1903 – 1930) Bruno de Finetti (1906 - 1985)

Page 80: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

From logic to probability: a sketch

Probability assignments

The literature in this direction is abundant. To single out oneexample, let me mention the Ramsey-de Finetti Dutch bookargument (1926, 1937), along with its later utility-based version byL. Savage (1954), that featured in other talks. Of the variousjustifications of probability theory I will say no more here.

Frank P. Ramsey (1903 – 1930) Bruno de Finetti (1906 - 1985)

Page 81: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

Outline

1 Prologue

2 From logic to probability: a sketch

3 A many-valued logic

4 Many-valued probability?

Page 82: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

Let us now consider non-classical logic. I will look at a singleexample, a many-valued logic known as Godel propositional logic.

This is part of a hierarchy of many-valued logics that includes e.g.Lukasiewicz logic, but I will not discuss the larger picture here.

For the syntax, we use exactly the same notation as for classicallogic.Concerning semantics, truth-value assignments

w : Form→ [0, 1]

now take values in the real unit-interval [0, 1] ⊆ ℝ, and are subjectto the following conditions for any formulæ � and �.

Page 83: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

Let us now consider non-classical logic. I will look at a singleexample, a many-valued logic known as Godel propositional logic.This is part of a hierarchy of many-valued logics that includes e.g.Lukasiewicz logic, but I will not discuss the larger picture here.

For the syntax, we use exactly the same notation as for classicallogic.Concerning semantics, truth-value assignments

w : Form→ [0, 1]

now take values in the real unit-interval [0, 1] ⊆ ℝ, and are subjectto the following conditions for any formulæ � and �.

Page 84: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

Let us now consider non-classical logic. I will look at a singleexample, a many-valued logic known as Godel propositional logic.This is part of a hierarchy of many-valued logics that includes e.g.Lukasiewicz logic, but I will not discuss the larger picture here.

For the syntax, we use exactly the same notation as for classicallogic.Concerning semantics, truth-value assignments

w : Form→ [0, 1]

now take values in the real unit-interval [0, 1] ⊆ ℝ, and are subjectto the following conditions for any formulæ � and �.

Page 85: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

w(⊥) = 0, w(⊤) = 1.

w(� ∧ �) = min (w(�), w(�)).

w(� ∨ �) = max (w(�), w(�)).

w(�→ �) =

{1 if w(�) ⩽ w(�)w(�) otherwise

w(¬�) =

{1 if w(�) = 00 if w(�) > 0

A tautology is again a formula true in any possible world, i.e.evaluated to 1 by any assignment.

Page 86: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

w(⊥) = 0, w(⊤) = 1.

w(� ∧ �) = min (w(�), w(�)).

w(� ∨ �) = max (w(�), w(�)).

w(�→ �) =

{1 if w(�) ⩽ w(�)w(�) otherwise

w(¬�) =

{1 if w(�) = 00 if w(�) > 0

A tautology is again a formula true in any possible world, i.e.evaluated to 1 by any assignment.

Page 87: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

w(⊥) = 0, w(⊤) = 1.

w(� ∧ �) = min (w(�), w(�)).

w(� ∨ �) = max (w(�), w(�)).

w(�→ �) =

{1 if w(�) ⩽ w(�)w(�) otherwise

w(¬�) =

{1 if w(�) = 00 if w(�) > 0

A tautology is again a formula true in any possible world, i.e.evaluated to 1 by any assignment.

Page 88: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

w(⊥) = 0, w(⊤) = 1.

w(� ∧ �) = min (w(�), w(�)).

w(� ∨ �) = max (w(�), w(�)).

w(�→ �) =

{1 if w(�) ⩽ w(�)w(�) otherwise

w(¬�) =

{1 if w(�) = 00 if w(�) > 0

A tautology is again a formula true in any possible world, i.e.evaluated to 1 by any assignment.

Page 89: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

w(⊥) = 0, w(⊤) = 1.

w(� ∧ �) = min (w(�), w(�)).

w(� ∨ �) = max (w(�), w(�)).

w(�→ �) =

{1 if w(�) ⩽ w(�)w(�) otherwise

w(¬�) =

{1 if w(�) = 00 if w(�) > 0

A tautology is again a formula true in any possible world, i.e.evaluated to 1 by any assignment.

Page 90: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

w(⊥) = 0, w(⊤) = 1.

w(� ∧ �) = min (w(�), w(�)).

w(� ∨ �) = max (w(�), w(�)).

w(�→ �) =

{1 if w(�) ⩽ w(�)w(�) otherwise

w(¬�) =

{1 if w(�) = 00 if w(�) > 0

A tautology is again a formula true in any possible world, i.e.evaluated to 1 by any assignment.

Page 91: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

For an appropriate axiomatisation with modus ponens as deductionrule, one obtains completeness with respect to this many-valuedsemantics.

Godel logic can in fact be axiomatized as the schematic extensionof the intuitionistic propositional calculus by the prelinearity axiom

(�→ �) ∨ (� → �) .

Actually, Godel logic is, so to speak, what you get taking theintersection of (schematic extensions of) intuitionistic logic with(schematic extensions of) many-valued logic in the sense of PetrHajek.

Page 92: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

For an appropriate axiomatisation with modus ponens as deductionrule, one obtains completeness with respect to this many-valuedsemantics.Godel logic can in fact be axiomatized as the schematic extensionof the intuitionistic propositional calculus by the prelinearity axiom

(�→ �) ∨ (� → �) .

Actually, Godel logic is, so to speak, what you get taking theintersection of (schematic extensions of) intuitionistic logic with(schematic extensions of) many-valued logic in the sense of PetrHajek.

Page 93: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

For an appropriate axiomatisation with modus ponens as deductionrule, one obtains completeness with respect to this many-valuedsemantics.Godel logic can in fact be axiomatized as the schematic extensionof the intuitionistic propositional calculus by the prelinearity axiom

(�→ �) ∨ (� → �) .

Actually, Godel logic is, so to speak, what you get taking theintersection of (schematic extensions of) intuitionistic logic with(schematic extensions of) many-valued logic in the sense of PetrHajek.

Page 94: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A many-valued logic

Figure: All one-variable formulæ in Godel logic, up to logical equivalence,ordered by � ⩽ � if and only if ⊢ �→ �.

Page 95: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Outline

1 Prologue

2 From logic to probability: a sketch

3 A many-valued logic

4 Many-valued probability?

Page 96: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

To help us proceed, forgive the bad form of quoting from theabstract of my own talk:

Since Boolean events may be denoted by formulæ in classicalpropositional logic, by analogy one is tempted to regardformulæ in a non-classical propositional logic as linguisticdescriptions of non-classical events – whatever the latter are.And since Boolean events may be assigned (subjective)probabilities, one is lured into attempts at defining probabilitiesof non-classical events.

So each formula in the previous picture should denote one of thesix “Godelian events” that can be described with one propositionalvariable X.Unfortunately, one can have published several papers on Godellogic, and still have no clue at all as to what such an event mightlook like. Compare: everybody will start talking about tossingcoins as soon as you ask them about classical events, even if theynever even heard of classical logic.

Page 97: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

To help us proceed, forgive the bad form of quoting from theabstract of my own talk:

Since Boolean events may be denoted by formulæ in classicalpropositional logic, by analogy one is tempted to regardformulæ in a non-classical propositional logic as linguisticdescriptions of non-classical events – whatever the latter are.And since Boolean events may be assigned (subjective)probabilities, one is lured into attempts at defining probabilitiesof non-classical events.

So each formula in the previous picture should denote one of thesix “Godelian events” that can be described with one propositionalvariable X.Unfortunately, one can have published several papers on Godellogic, and still have no clue at all as to what such an event mightlook like. Compare: everybody will start talking about tossingcoins as soon as you ask them about classical events, even if theynever even heard of classical logic.

Page 98: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

To help us proceed, forgive the bad form of quoting from theabstract of my own talk:

Since Boolean events may be denoted by formulæ in classicalpropositional logic, by analogy one is tempted to regardformulæ in a non-classical propositional logic as linguisticdescriptions of non-classical events – whatever the latter are.And since Boolean events may be assigned (subjective)probabilities, one is lured into attempts at defining probabilitiesof non-classical events.

So each formula in the previous picture should denote one of thesix “Godelian events” that can be described with one propositionalvariable X.

Unfortunately, one can have published several papers on Godellogic, and still have no clue at all as to what such an event mightlook like. Compare: everybody will start talking about tossingcoins as soon as you ask them about classical events, even if theynever even heard of classical logic.

Page 99: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

To help us proceed, forgive the bad form of quoting from theabstract of my own talk:

Since Boolean events may be denoted by formulæ in classicalpropositional logic, by analogy one is tempted to regardformulæ in a non-classical propositional logic as linguisticdescriptions of non-classical events – whatever the latter are.And since Boolean events may be assigned (subjective)probabilities, one is lured into attempts at defining probabilitiesof non-classical events.

So each formula in the previous picture should denote one of thesix “Godelian events” that can be described with one propositionalvariable X.Unfortunately, one can have published several papers on Godellogic, and still have no clue at all as to what such an event mightlook like.

Compare: everybody will start talking about tossingcoins as soon as you ask them about classical events, even if theynever even heard of classical logic.

Page 100: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

To help us proceed, forgive the bad form of quoting from theabstract of my own talk:

Since Boolean events may be denoted by formulæ in classicalpropositional logic, by analogy one is tempted to regardformulæ in a non-classical propositional logic as linguisticdescriptions of non-classical events – whatever the latter are.And since Boolean events may be assigned (subjective)probabilities, one is lured into attempts at defining probabilitiesof non-classical events.

So each formula in the previous picture should denote one of thesix “Godelian events” that can be described with one propositionalvariable X.Unfortunately, one can have published several papers on Godellogic, and still have no clue at all as to what such an event mightlook like. Compare: everybody will start talking about tossingcoins as soon as you ask them about classical events, even if theynever even heard of classical logic.

Page 101: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

With some amount of hindsight, let’s see what we can do.

Many-valued logics are supposed to provide a formal model ofvague statements.“The coin lands heads” is non-example.“It rains” might work better. Of course, we can always regard thissimply as a classical proposition.However, say we now select one observable feature of the classicalevent “It rains”; say, the amount of rainfall during a whole day.Then we might agree to interpret a sentence such as “It rains alot” as a many-valued proposition with respect to that observablefeature: namely, we agree that this proposition is the more true,the more it rains.

Page 102: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

With some amount of hindsight, let’s see what we can do.Many-valued logics are supposed to provide a formal model ofvague statements.

“The coin lands heads” is non-example.“It rains” might work better. Of course, we can always regard thissimply as a classical proposition.However, say we now select one observable feature of the classicalevent “It rains”; say, the amount of rainfall during a whole day.Then we might agree to interpret a sentence such as “It rains alot” as a many-valued proposition with respect to that observablefeature: namely, we agree that this proposition is the more true,the more it rains.

Page 103: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

With some amount of hindsight, let’s see what we can do.Many-valued logics are supposed to provide a formal model ofvague statements.“The coin lands heads” is non-example.

“It rains” might work better. Of course, we can always regard thissimply as a classical proposition.However, say we now select one observable feature of the classicalevent “It rains”; say, the amount of rainfall during a whole day.Then we might agree to interpret a sentence such as “It rains alot” as a many-valued proposition with respect to that observablefeature: namely, we agree that this proposition is the more true,the more it rains.

Page 104: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

With some amount of hindsight, let’s see what we can do.Many-valued logics are supposed to provide a formal model ofvague statements.“The coin lands heads” is non-example.“It rains” might work better. Of course, we can always regard thissimply as a classical proposition.

However, say we now select one observable feature of the classicalevent “It rains”; say, the amount of rainfall during a whole day.Then we might agree to interpret a sentence such as “It rains alot” as a many-valued proposition with respect to that observablefeature: namely, we agree that this proposition is the more true,the more it rains.

Page 105: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

With some amount of hindsight, let’s see what we can do.Many-valued logics are supposed to provide a formal model ofvague statements.“The coin lands heads” is non-example.“It rains” might work better. Of course, we can always regard thissimply as a classical proposition.However, say we now select one observable feature of the classicalevent “It rains”; say, the amount of rainfall during a whole day.

Then we might agree to interpret a sentence such as “It rains alot” as a many-valued proposition with respect to that observablefeature: namely, we agree that this proposition is the more true,the more it rains.

Page 106: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

With some amount of hindsight, let’s see what we can do.Many-valued logics are supposed to provide a formal model ofvague statements.“The coin lands heads” is non-example.“It rains” might work better. Of course, we can always regard thissimply as a classical proposition.However, say we now select one observable feature of the classicalevent “It rains”; say, the amount of rainfall during a whole day.Then we might agree to interpret a sentence such as “It rains alot” as a many-valued proposition with respect to that observablefeature: namely, we agree that this proposition is the more true,the more it rains.

Page 107: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

So we now have two different propositions.

First, we can utterX = “It rains a lot”

as a many-valued proposition with respect to the amount ofrainfall.Second, we can utter

¬¬X = “It rains”

as a classical proposition: true if it rains, however little or much,and false otherwise.Finally, we also consider the proposition

¬X = “It does not rain”,

and we agree to interpret this as a classical proposition, thecomplement of ¬¬X – we are not interested in degrees ofnon-rain, in this example.

Page 108: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

So we now have two different propositions.First, we can utter

X = “It rains a lot”

as a many-valued proposition with respect to the amount ofrainfall.

Second, we can utter

¬¬X = “It rains”

as a classical proposition: true if it rains, however little or much,and false otherwise.Finally, we also consider the proposition

¬X = “It does not rain”,

and we agree to interpret this as a classical proposition, thecomplement of ¬¬X – we are not interested in degrees ofnon-rain, in this example.

Page 109: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

So we now have two different propositions.First, we can utter

X = “It rains a lot”

as a many-valued proposition with respect to the amount ofrainfall.Second, we can utter

¬¬X = “It rains”

as a classical proposition: true if it rains, however little or much,and false otherwise.

Finally, we also consider the proposition

¬X = “It does not rain”,

and we agree to interpret this as a classical proposition, thecomplement of ¬¬X – we are not interested in degrees ofnon-rain, in this example.

Page 110: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

So we now have two different propositions.First, we can utter

X = “It rains a lot”

as a many-valued proposition with respect to the amount ofrainfall.Second, we can utter

¬¬X = “It rains”

as a classical proposition: true if it rains, however little or much,and false otherwise.Finally, we also consider the proposition

¬X = “It does not rain”,

and we agree to interpret this as a classical proposition, thecomplement of ¬¬X – we are not interested in degrees ofnon-rain, in this example.

Page 111: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Figure: All one-variable formulæ in Godel logic, up to logical equivalence,ordered by � ⩽ � if and only if ⊢ �→ �.

Page 112: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

What are the logical relations that we intuitively expect betweenthese three propositions, given the assumptions above?

Nothing to say a about ¬¬X and ¬X – they are the usualBoolean alternative, it rains vs. it does not rain.What about X (lots of rain)?The implication

X → ¬¬X

must be true: whenever it rains a lot, then surely it must rain.But the converse implication is not necessarily true: it may wellrain, without raining a lot.These properties actually are the ones that hold in Godel logic; sofar, so good.

Page 113: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

What are the logical relations that we intuitively expect betweenthese three propositions, given the assumptions above?Nothing to say a about ¬¬X and ¬X – they are the usualBoolean alternative, it rains vs. it does not rain.

What about X (lots of rain)?The implication

X → ¬¬X

must be true: whenever it rains a lot, then surely it must rain.But the converse implication is not necessarily true: it may wellrain, without raining a lot.These properties actually are the ones that hold in Godel logic; sofar, so good.

Page 114: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

What are the logical relations that we intuitively expect betweenthese three propositions, given the assumptions above?Nothing to say a about ¬¬X and ¬X – they are the usualBoolean alternative, it rains vs. it does not rain.What about X (lots of rain)?

The implicationX → ¬¬X

must be true: whenever it rains a lot, then surely it must rain.But the converse implication is not necessarily true: it may wellrain, without raining a lot.These properties actually are the ones that hold in Godel logic; sofar, so good.

Page 115: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

What are the logical relations that we intuitively expect betweenthese three propositions, given the assumptions above?Nothing to say a about ¬¬X and ¬X – they are the usualBoolean alternative, it rains vs. it does not rain.What about X (lots of rain)?The implication

X → ¬¬X

must be true: whenever it rains a lot, then surely it must rain.

But the converse implication is not necessarily true: it may wellrain, without raining a lot.These properties actually are the ones that hold in Godel logic; sofar, so good.

Page 116: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

What are the logical relations that we intuitively expect betweenthese three propositions, given the assumptions above?Nothing to say a about ¬¬X and ¬X – they are the usualBoolean alternative, it rains vs. it does not rain.What about X (lots of rain)?The implication

X → ¬¬X

must be true: whenever it rains a lot, then surely it must rain.But the converse implication is not necessarily true: it may wellrain, without raining a lot.

These properties actually are the ones that hold in Godel logic; sofar, so good.

Page 117: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

What are the logical relations that we intuitively expect betweenthese three propositions, given the assumptions above?Nothing to say a about ¬¬X and ¬X – they are the usualBoolean alternative, it rains vs. it does not rain.What about X (lots of rain)?The implication

X → ¬¬X

must be true: whenever it rains a lot, then surely it must rain.But the converse implication is not necessarily true: it may wellrain, without raining a lot.These properties actually are the ones that hold in Godel logic; sofar, so good.

Page 118: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Now that we understand the logic of these three propositions, letus go one step further.

How would we attach probabilities to the three (events denoted bythe three) propositions?Let us write p1 and p2 for the probabilities of ¬¬X and ¬X,respectively, and p11 for the probability of X. Let us assume thesenumbers lie in [0, 1].Again, nothing special to say about p1 and p2: we must havep1 + p2 = 1.What about p11? Well, because of the implication X → ¬¬X, wemust have

p11 ⩽ p2 .

But now an interesting thing happens: there are two options.

Page 119: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Now that we understand the logic of these three propositions, letus go one step further.How would we attach probabilities to the three (events denoted bythe three) propositions?

Let us write p1 and p2 for the probabilities of ¬¬X and ¬X,respectively, and p11 for the probability of X. Let us assume thesenumbers lie in [0, 1].Again, nothing special to say about p1 and p2: we must havep1 + p2 = 1.What about p11? Well, because of the implication X → ¬¬X, wemust have

p11 ⩽ p2 .

But now an interesting thing happens: there are two options.

Page 120: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Now that we understand the logic of these three propositions, letus go one step further.How would we attach probabilities to the three (events denoted bythe three) propositions?Let us write p1 and p2 for the probabilities of ¬¬X and ¬X,respectively, and p11 for the probability of X. Let us assume thesenumbers lie in [0, 1].

Again, nothing special to say about p1 and p2: we must havep1 + p2 = 1.What about p11? Well, because of the implication X → ¬¬X, wemust have

p11 ⩽ p2 .

But now an interesting thing happens: there are two options.

Page 121: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Now that we understand the logic of these three propositions, letus go one step further.How would we attach probabilities to the three (events denoted bythe three) propositions?Let us write p1 and p2 for the probabilities of ¬¬X and ¬X,respectively, and p11 for the probability of X. Let us assume thesenumbers lie in [0, 1].Again, nothing special to say about p1 and p2: we must havep1 + p2 = 1.

What about p11? Well, because of the implication X → ¬¬X, wemust have

p11 ⩽ p2 .

But now an interesting thing happens: there are two options.

Page 122: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Now that we understand the logic of these three propositions, letus go one step further.How would we attach probabilities to the three (events denoted bythe three) propositions?Let us write p1 and p2 for the probabilities of ¬¬X and ¬X,respectively, and p11 for the probability of X. Let us assume thesenumbers lie in [0, 1].Again, nothing special to say about p1 and p2: we must havep1 + p2 = 1.What about p11? Well, because of the implication X → ¬¬X, wemust have

p11 ⩽ p2 .

But now an interesting thing happens: there are two options.

Page 123: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Now that we understand the logic of these three propositions, letus go one step further.How would we attach probabilities to the three (events denoted bythe three) propositions?Let us write p1 and p2 for the probabilities of ¬¬X and ¬X,respectively, and p11 for the probability of X. Let us assume thesenumbers lie in [0, 1].Again, nothing special to say about p1 and p2: we must havep1 + p2 = 1.What about p11? Well, because of the implication X → ¬¬X, wemust have

p11 ⩽ p2 .

But now an interesting thing happens: there are two options.

Page 124: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Option 1. On the one hand, we can just ask

(p1 − p11) + p11 + p2 = 1 ,

that is, we treat the three sentences:

“It rains, but not a lot”, “It rains a lot”, “It does not rain”

as three classical, mutually exclusive cases.

It turns out that thiscorresponds to axiomatising probability assignments to formulæ inGodel logic by precisely Kolmogorov’s axioms shown above.But there is a problem here: there is no real connection betweenGodel logic and this sort of probability assignments. In particular,you can replicate this probability distribution at once in theclassical case – so why on earth use a non-classical logic?

Page 125: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Option 1. On the one hand, we can just ask

(p1 − p11) + p11 + p2 = 1 ,

that is, we treat the three sentences:

“It rains, but not a lot”, “It rains a lot”, “It does not rain”

as three classical, mutually exclusive cases. It turns out that thiscorresponds to axiomatising probability assignments to formulæ inGodel logic by precisely Kolmogorov’s axioms shown above.

But there is a problem here: there is no real connection betweenGodel logic and this sort of probability assignments. In particular,you can replicate this probability distribution at once in theclassical case – so why on earth use a non-classical logic?

Page 126: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Option 1. On the one hand, we can just ask

(p1 − p11) + p11 + p2 = 1 ,

that is, we treat the three sentences:

“It rains, but not a lot”, “It rains a lot”, “It does not rain”

as three classical, mutually exclusive cases. It turns out that thiscorresponds to axiomatising probability assignments to formulæ inGodel logic by precisely Kolmogorov’s axioms shown above.But there is a problem here: there is no real connection betweenGodel logic and this sort of probability assignments. In particular,you can replicate this probability distribution at once in theclassical case – so why on earth use a non-classical logic?

Page 127: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Option 2. We ask that

(p1 − p11) + p11 + p2 = 1 , but with p1 = 0 whenever p11 = 0 ,

that is, we treat the three sentences:

“It rains”, “It rains a lot”, “It does not rain”

as if it is never completely false that whenever it rains, it rains alot – which is actually the case in Godel logic.

It turns out that this corresponds to axiomatising probabilityassignments to formulæ in Godel logic by Kolmogorov’s axioms,plus one additional axiom that I will not state explicitly here.For various reasons, I am convinced that this latter option with theadditional axiom is the right one. The axiom is a condition thatcomes out whether you want it or not from the structure of Godellogic. One can ignore it, of course, but then one should be doingclassical logic, really.

Page 128: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Option 2. We ask that

(p1 − p11) + p11 + p2 = 1 , but with p1 = 0 whenever p11 = 0 ,

that is, we treat the three sentences:

“It rains”, “It rains a lot”, “It does not rain”

as if it is never completely false that whenever it rains, it rains alot – which is actually the case in Godel logic.It turns out that this corresponds to axiomatising probabilityassignments to formulæ in Godel logic by Kolmogorov’s axioms,plus one additional axiom that I will not state explicitly here.

For various reasons, I am convinced that this latter option with theadditional axiom is the right one. The axiom is a condition thatcomes out whether you want it or not from the structure of Godellogic. One can ignore it, of course, but then one should be doingclassical logic, really.

Page 129: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Option 2. We ask that

(p1 − p11) + p11 + p2 = 1 , but with p1 = 0 whenever p11 = 0 ,

that is, we treat the three sentences:

“It rains”, “It rains a lot”, “It does not rain”

as if it is never completely false that whenever it rains, it rains alot – which is actually the case in Godel logic.It turns out that this corresponds to axiomatising probabilityassignments to formulæ in Godel logic by Kolmogorov’s axioms,plus one additional axiom that I will not state explicitly here.For various reasons, I am convinced that this latter option with theadditional axiom is the right one. The axiom is a condition thatcomes out whether you want it or not from the structure of Godellogic. One can ignore it, of course, but then one should be doingclassical logic, really.

Page 130: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Of course, this leaves us with another problem here: there is noplausible reason why one should estimate zero the probability thatit rains, provided one estimates zero the probability that it rains alot. (Unless, of course, one adds some extra assumption.) Thus,the intended semantics that seemed acceptable to us on logicalgrounds, it is no longer so when we try to develop probability overthis logic.

The one clear thing is that more thought is needed.

Page 131: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Many-valued probability?

Of course, this leaves us with another problem here: there is noplausible reason why one should estimate zero the probability thatit rains, provided one estimates zero the probability that it rains alot. (Unless, of course, one adds some extra assumption.) Thus,the intended semantics that seemed acceptable to us on logicalgrounds, it is no longer so when we try to develop probability overthis logic.

The one clear thing is that more thought is needed.

Page 132: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A mathematical remark

Outline

5 A mathematical remark

Page 133: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A mathematical remark

Added in proof: A mathematical remark. I mentioned two traditionsin probability theory: one that takes events (=fields of sets) as aprimitive notion, and the other that takes propositions (=Booleanalgebras) instead. Yesterday, David Makinson also used a propositionallanguage instead of fields of sets, and seemed to suggest in passing thatthe difference is immaterial. I agree with this completely only insofar asthe language is finite. But suppose it is not. Then I would make a casethat the two approaches – fields of sets vs. Boolean algebras – areconceptually very different, and in fact lead to different mathematicaldevelopments. A related point concerning finite vs. countable additivitywas discussed yesterday over lunch with Mariano Giaquinta.

Sure enough, you can always embed any Boolean algebra into the

Boolean algebra of all subsets of some set. And you can do so quite

canonically after B. Jonsson and A. Tarski, Amer. J. Math. (1951). This

embedding, or variations thereof, has been widely used in measure theory

to extend finitely additive measures from a given field of sets B to a

countably additive measure on the extension of B. Since in the countably

additive setting one can apply results from analysis, this provides a

valuable tool.

Page 134: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A mathematical remark

Added in proof: A mathematical remark. I mentioned two traditionsin probability theory: one that takes events (=fields of sets) as aprimitive notion, and the other that takes propositions (=Booleanalgebras) instead. Yesterday, David Makinson also used a propositionallanguage instead of fields of sets, and seemed to suggest in passing thatthe difference is immaterial. I agree with this completely only insofar asthe language is finite. But suppose it is not. Then I would make a casethat the two approaches – fields of sets vs. Boolean algebras – areconceptually very different, and in fact lead to different mathematicaldevelopments. A related point concerning finite vs. countable additivitywas discussed yesterday over lunch with Mariano Giaquinta.

Sure enough, you can always embed any Boolean algebra into the

Boolean algebra of all subsets of some set. And you can do so quite

canonically after B. Jonsson and A. Tarski, Amer. J. Math. (1951). This

embedding, or variations thereof, has been widely used in measure theory

to extend finitely additive measures from a given field of sets B to a

countably additive measure on the extension of B. Since in the countably

additive setting one can apply results from analysis, this provides a

valuable tool.

Page 135: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A mathematical remark

But here is another theorem that also leads from finite to countableadditivity, in a conceptually very different way. To the given Booleanalgebra B one can associate its Stone space S (B), a compact totallydisconnected Hausdorff space. This association is as canonical andnatural as possible – it’s part of a contravariant categorical equivalence,or duality. Elements a ∈ B will then be uniquely represented by anappropriate continuous function a : S (B)→ ℝ.

Theorem

There is a bijection between finitely additive probability measures on B,and regular Borel (hence of course countably additive) probabilitymeasures on S (B). Specifically, to such a measure � on S (B) oneassociates the finitely additive probability measure E that, to eachelement a ∈ B, assigns

E(a) =

∫S (B)

ad� ,

where∫⋅d� is Lebesgue integration with respect to �.

Page 136: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A mathematical remark

But here is another theorem that also leads from finite to countableadditivity, in a conceptually very different way. To the given Booleanalgebra B one can associate its Stone space S (B), a compact totallydisconnected Hausdorff space. This association is as canonical andnatural as possible – it’s part of a contravariant categorical equivalence,or duality. Elements a ∈ B will then be uniquely represented by anappropriate continuous function a : S (B)→ ℝ.

Theorem

There is a bijection between finitely additive probability measures on B,and regular Borel (hence of course countably additive) probabilitymeasures on S (B). Specifically, to such a measure � on S (B) oneassociates the finitely additive probability measure E that, to eachelement a ∈ B, assigns

E(a) =

∫S (B)

ad� ,

where∫⋅d� is Lebesgue integration with respect to �.

Page 137: Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

Is there a probability theory of non-classical events?

A mathematical remark

Thank you for your attention.