john buccanich on thomas mcevilley platonism_vedanta

Upload: billstranger2739

Post on 14-Apr-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    1/20

    International Journal of Hindu Studies 0, 0 (Month Year): 0000 2005 by the World Heritage Press Inc.

    The Roots of Platonism and Vednta:Comments on McEvilley

    John Bussanich

    This encyclopedic study tracks the emergence and development of virtually allthe major thinkers and schools in ancient Greece and India by means of complex

    comparative and historical schemasa truly monumental achievement in thecomparative study of philosophy. This essay has the limited objective ofassessing Thomas McEvilleys account of the trajectories of the Platonic andVedntic traditions, with a particular focus on the various sources of thesereligious philosophies. I shall examine his treatment of these genealogies: ( i)Orphic-Pythagoreans and Presocratics @ Plato @ Plotinus @ later Neoplatonistsand (ii) Upaniads @ BrahmastrasandPur~as @ akara @ later Vedntins.(The valuable analyses of the Buddhist and Jaina traditions and, in the West, ofAristotle and the various Hellenistic schools are beyond the scope of thisinquiry.) According to McEvilleys comparative criteria these traditions share acommitment to a tripartite metaphysical doctrine: (i) the self is identical to theultimate ground of reality; (ii) the self has lost its original unity with the ulti-

    mately real and must seek to regain it through the pursuit of knowledge and theachievement of self-mastery; and (iii) the self attains final union or identity withultimate reality through an experience which transcends knowledge and alllimitations. His cross-traditional comparisons of the expression and of thecontent of these themes are embedded in a diffusionist model of historicaldevelopment according to which Vedic India and to a lesser extent Iran, theAncient Near East, and Egypt comprise the sources of archaic and classicalGreek wisdom traditions. I shall comment on these themes in McEvilleysexposition: (i) the cogency of the diffusionist model, especially as it pertains toarchaic Greece; (ii) traditional texts, oral teachings, and spiritual experience assources of philosophical doctrine; and (iii) the fundamental principles of

    Platonic and Vedntic metaphysics.

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    2/20

    2 / John Bussanich

    ARCHAIC GREECE AND VEDIC INDIA

    McEvilley begins his adventurous project with reflections on the momentoustransition in both Greece and India from mythopoeic to rational and abstractmodes of philosophizing in the first half of the first millenium BCE. He drawsilluminating parallels between (i) substrate monism among the Milesians andin the early Upaniads, (ii) the quasimythic articulation of the cosmic personin late Vedic hymns and in Orphic poetic theology, and ( iii) macrocosm/microcosm homologies in the Pythagoreans, Heraclitus, and Parmenides and inthe Upaniads. With regard to the first theme, he compares Anaximandersapeiron (the unlimited) both with the g Vedas Aditi, the UnlimitedMother of the gods, and with Brahman, as in Taittirya Upaniad 3.1.1. Anattractive feature of his approach at the outset is that it eschews facile analogies.He recognizes that Aditi is a goddess whereas Anaximanders apeiron is anabstract principle, which is designated with a neuter form and thus is essen-tially postmythological, like Uddlakas brahman (32). With the removal ofconcrete imagery from the characterization of the ultimate principles in botharchaic Greece and India, we can discern, McEvilley argues, the emergence ofthe abstract idea of pure being, exempt from qualities, which displaces ortranscends the mythical divinities. He also compares Thales first principlewater with the primordial role of water in late Vedic and in Babyloniancosmogenesis. Unfortunately, he undercuts these mythical associations byoverreliance on Aristotles materialist interpretation of the Milesians, leading

    him to embrace the standard protoscientific reading of the Milesians as physi-calist reductionists, which thus places them at odds with the basic tenor ofUpaniadic thought.

    Attention to Bhadra~yaka Upaniad 1.1.2 and related passages, where theprimordial waters symbolize the divine potentiality of all existence, would haverevealed even more clearly the metaphysical affinities of early Greek and Vediccosmology. He would have profited greatly from consulting the revolutionaryand still fundamental comparative work of A. K. Coomaraswamy, whomMcEvilley completely ignores. Most relevant to the comparison of early Greekand Indian thought is his A New Approach to the Vedas (Coomaraswamy 0000)and the classic essays Vedic Exemplarism (1977) and Vedic Monotheism(2002). Coomaraswamys vision of Vedic metaphysics provides a more compre-

    hensive perspective within which to situate McEvilleys specific comparisons ofthe nature and function of individual physical elements in Milesian thought withtheir Vedic counterparts. Coomaraswamy argues, for example, that Mitr-Varu~au, Sun, Fire, Spirit, etc., are all denotations of one and the same first

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    3/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 3

    principle of manifestation, and the Waters, often called the wives of Varu~a, or

    mothers in relation to the Son, are the possibilities of manifestation (2002:31n15). From the more sophisticated perspectives of Upaniadic and Platonicmetaphysics, the first Greek speculation on the One and the Many involvesmonism to a lesser degree than McEvilley supposes, inasmuch as it specifies onestuff as the symbol for cosmic potentiality but lacks a clearly articulated notionof the absolute.

    Heraclitus deconstructs earlier cosmology by radically reformulating theinteraction among the elements in striking, paradoxical poetry. McEvilleysanalysis displays the characteristic strengths and weaknesses of his method. Hispiecemeal comparisons of Heraclitus flux-doctrine to the Buddhist concept oftransience and his introspective search for hidden unity to the Vedntic tmanare useful but superficial. Much more effective, in my view, is the detailedcomparison of Heraclitus obscure account of the cycle of elemental transforma-tions from fire to water to earth to water to fire (4044, 30400)the ancientreports of which make it sound like primitive meteorologywith the moreelaborate presentation of a similar cycle by Uddlaka in Chndogya Upaniad4,which is connected with the eschatological teachings of Pravha~a Jaivali inChndogya 5 andBhadra~yaka 6. McEvilley skillfully employs the complexVedic scheme of the Path of the Gods (the way of fire) and the Path of theFathers (the way of smoke) as an interpretive aid to explicate Heraclitus theoryof exhalations according to which the bright exhalation of souls goes to the sunand produces day and summer and the dark exhalation of souls goes to the moonand produces night and winter. He convincingly challenges the standard

    physicalist interpretation of Heraclitus theory by showing its affinities with theBrhma~ical interiorization of the sacrifice and even with the emergence of afull-fledged reincarnation theory in seventh century BCE India. Now, Heraclitusdoes not explicitly espouse a theory of reincarnation, but McEvilleys exposi-tion should stimulate further reflection on this question.

    Consideration of Heraclitus thinking on the destiny of the soul is postponeduntil the comprehensive discussion of reincarnation in chapter four. ThereMcEvilley lays out in great detail the multifarious aspects of Upaniadicreincarnation theory which are lacking in the earlier discussion of Heraclitus.1

    This long chapter is a kaleidoscopic excursion through Upaniadic, Egyptian,Orphic, and Greek references to metempsychosis, reincarnation, and astrophysi-cal eschatology which investigates whether Greek theories of reincarnation and

    transmigration depend on non-Greek sources. I agree with the judgment that theGreek theories more closely resemble ancient Indian ones than ideas found inThracian shamanism, in Mesopotamian cultures, or in Iranian Zoroastrianism.However, besides Pythagoras and Empedocles, reincarnation is poorly attested

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    4/20

    4 / John Bussanich

    in other thinkers before Plato. Moreover, the diffusion of Indian ideas through

    Iran may be a more complicated process than he suggests, not to mention thatdifferent ideas arrived from the East at different times with different degrees ofborrowing and assimilation on the part of the Greeks (cf. 126).2 A furthercomplication is McEvilleys reliance on the traditional view, now discredited,that Zoroaster lived in the sixth or fifth century BCE instead of millenia before(see Kingsley 1990).

    Another theme about which McEvilley speculates rather loosely is monism.Indeed, he claims that Upaniadic monism and reincarnation theory aretransmitted together to archaic Greece (122). In certain cases, the doctrinalcomparisons are compelling, most notably in the section Parmenidean Monismand Indian Thought (5255) on the metaphysics of being in Parmenides and innumerous Upaniadic texts.3 But besides Parmenides (and the later EleaticMelissus) few scholars would claim that any other Presocratic is a radical monistof the Upaniadic type. (Milesian material monism is quite a different sort, assuggested above.) Nevertheless, McEvilley thinks early Pythagoreanism ismonistic (4400)which view is flatly contradicted by our earliest sourcesand also the thought of Heraclitus. Despite the latters enigmatic references tothe unity of opposites from the divine point of view and to the One-Wise(Fragments 10, 67, 32, 41), more argument is required than McEvilley offers toclaim him as a monist. To summarize, these opening chapters of the bookarticulate striking cosmological analogies between various Presocratics andseveral Upaniadic texts, but McEvilley has a tendency to homogenize the viewsof the Presocratics and press them too far in a monistic direction. This judgment

    has the effect of making the historical dependence of archaic Greece religiousthought on Vedic India seem inevitable. I say: not so fast.While reading through this impressive collection of parallel passages one

    hungers for an explanation of what motivates and grounds the metaphysical andcosmological speculations of these remarkable early Greek thinkers, one thatdoes not simply refer us to even earlier source-texts. McEvilley consistentlyneglects the experiential sources of Greek teachings and practices, an oversightthat is most problematic in the case of Parmenides. Only briefly does he mentionthe crucial proem, that is, Fragment 1, which recounts Parmenides descent tothe underworld where he meets the Goddess beyond the gates of Night and Day(57), which symbolize phenomenal duality in general. Indeed, he ignores mostof the proems accountembodied in subtle imagery drawn from contemporary

    Greek poetryof Parmenides inner transformation and the dramatic trajectoryof his shamanic, mystical transport. The mystical approach to Parmenides and toother Presocratics like Empedocles and to the Orphics occupies a prominentposition in the work of classical scholars like Walter Burkert, Albrecht

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    5/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 5

    Dieterich, and especially Peter Kingsley, who stress the centrality of incubation

    in Orphic-Pythagorean esoteric piety. Kingsley (1999, 2003) has delineated astriking picture of Parmenides as a priest in the cult of Apollo with its focus onhealing, both physical and spiritual, and its proximate roots in Anatolia thatreach as far as Iran. However extensive the borrowing of images and concepts,the practice of incubation and related techniques throughout the Mediterraneanworld in the first millennium BCE is in my view the ultimate source of thereligious metaphysics disseminated in archaic Greece. To his credit, McEvilleymentions the practice of silence among the Pythagoreans and Parmenides(17879, 598), but he is more interested in the theory of reincarnation and sorefers to incubation, and its central symbol of the descent, primarily in order todistinguish it from the former doctrines image of the ascent. But what is crucialfor understanding the spiritual orientation and the doctrines of the Orphic-Pythagoreansas indeed also of their Vedic counterpartsis their mysticalpractices and experiences. We need only recall that incubationwithdrawing tocaves and other quiet places to enter transcendent realms through dreaming oraltered states of awarenessis just another name for meditation or trance. Itseems to me that the interpretive regress implicit in McEvilleys approachandin other comparativistsmust stop somewhere: Did the Vedic is derive theirinsights from reading even older, anonymous, prehistoric texts; or did they, atsome point, have direct access to the gods and transcendent states of conscious-ness through the practice of meditation and psychophysical disciplines likeyoga? McEvilley appears to accept the second alternative, which I applaud, butthis does not justify or require claiming Vedic India as the source of all Eurasian

    religious metaphysics. So if he wishes to assert that India is the source of archaicGreek doctrines, he needs to provide explanations why the Greeks, or otherancient cultures, were incapable of gaining access to the transcendent withoutinstruction from Indian texts or teachers.

    It seems to me that doctrinal similarity is insufficient grounds for adoptingsuch a horizontal explanation according to which Greeks or Etruscans orEgyptians require contact with Hindus or Buddhists or Jainas from South Asiato entertain or accept the truth of monism or reincarnation or divinization.Surprisingly, McEvilley does not even mention, let alone refute, the perennialistclaim that most saints, sages, and philosophers discover for themselves andexpress the same core metaphysical doctrines and promote similar ethicalpractices with only variations of local color. Not that this rules out cross-cultural

    influences and borrowings. But his history of ideas presentation of metaphysi-cal doctrines ignores the possibility that exceptional individuals in any and everyculture have direct access to transcendent realities through spiritual practiceslike contemplation under the direction of a guru or divine being. This vertical

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    6/20

    6 / John Bussanich

    model of explanation does not exclude the horizontal diffusion of new ideas or

    practices through reading scriptures or dialectical exchangeswhether in onesown tradition or imported from another. But even where such contacts play arole it must be recognized that religious experiences are expressed throughsymbols indigenous to a culture or region and that spiritual practices becomeactual only within the soul of the seeker. In commenting on Upaniadic doctrineCoomaraswamy points out that

    the realization of the corresponding state in which the Intellect does not intel-ligize, which is called in our text the Eternal Mystery [UVI.22] and in KUVI.10, the Supreme Goal and which cannot be taught, is the ultimatesecret of initiation. It must not be supposed that any mere description of thesecret, such as can be found in Scripture or exegesis, suffices to communi-cate the secret of de-mentation (amanbhva) [that is, the cessation ofthought]; nor that the secret has ever been or could be communicated to aninitiate or betrayed to anyone, or discovered by however much learning. It canonly be realized by each one for himself; all that can be effected by initiationis the communciation of an impulse and an awakening of latent potentialities;the work must be done by the initiate himselfuntil the very end of the roadhas been reached (1977: 21314).

    From this more inclusive and vertical perspective, written and oral teachingsmay be taken as preconditions, but the individual must tread the path himself orherself. Moreover, the essential teachings in any tradition themselves derive

    from the great souls who have already achieved the goal and embodied theirexperiences in them. I suspect that McEvilley would agree with much of this.Yet he gives the impression that whats most important is the diffusion ofconcepts and images from one region or culture to another.

    Lets consideranother case where an individuals religiousexperience contrib-utes to the emergence of philosophical views. A few fragments of Heraclitusstrongly suggest a radically new interest in archaic Greece in exploring the selfas subject of inquiry which is distinct from the natural world: I searched outmyself (Fragment 101); You will not be able to find the boundaries of the souleven if you walk every path, so deep is its measure (Fragment 45). Virtuallythe same idea is expressed at Kautaki Upaniad4.1: A certain wise man insearch of immortality, turned his sight inward and saw the self within. Both

    exemplify the new symbol of the self that emerges from direct experience of theinner infinite. McEvilley adduces other passages in the Upaniads as parallelsto this theme in Heraclitus but concludes, correctly I think, that they do notconstitute an argument for diffusion (39). Nevertheless, because he sees no

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    7/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 7

    precedent in earlier Greek cosmological speculation for Heraclitus (and the

    Orphics) theory of elemental and psychic transformation, McEvilley concludesthat it is in terms of Greek evidence, unaccountable (40). On the basis of hisexcellent comparison of Heraclitus and the Upaniadic theories, he observesthat Heraclitus

    may be presumed to have had some familiarity with the central doctrines ofUpaniadic Hinduism.This extraordinary parallelism is a strong and clearlink between a pre-Socratic and an Upaniad. It amounts to a scholarlyproofmeaning the most reasonable interpretation of the evidence as itcurrently stands. The Heraclitean systemhas not been accounted forhistorically by any other approach. Until the evidence changes, it should standthat elements of Heraclitus and of the Upaniads came either from each otheror from an unknown common source (44).

    Besides the point that the last sentence appears to contradict the first, the argu-ment begs the question by asserting that Heraclitus system mustbe accountedfor historically, namely, through literary borrowing from an earlier text, be itGreek, Indian, or Mesopotamian. Speculating on broader historical patterns atthe end of the section, McEvilley concludes that because the process frompolytheism through Orphic pantheism to philosophical monism seems to havetaken a century or so, whereas in India the analogous transition took five toseven centuries, there is some reason to look for a special cause that precipi-tated such a development, namely, diffusion from India or Mesopotamia to

    Greece (61). I share with McEvilley, and with daring scholars such as WalterBurkert, Eric Voegelin, and M. L. West, a fascination with the development inthese and other ancient cultures from mythical to more abstract and differenti-ated forms of experience, thought, and literary expression. But we must be verycautious about the duration of the developmental stages, given the paucity of theevidence from archaic Greece and the insuperable difficulties of constructingchronology in Vedic India. Again, in my view, we need not rely primarily ontenuous historical connections to understand these texts or their experientialsources. What is crucial for archaic Greece are the spiritual breakthroughsexperienced and expressed in powerful transformational language by Heraclitus,Parmenides, Pythagoras, and Empedocles. Heraclitus explored himself andfound a soul without limitsjust as the Vedic is did. Parmenides learned

    stillness from the Pythagorean Ameiniasthe same mental cessation referredto throughout the Upaniads and later in the Yogastrasand it awakened himto the revelation of truths from the Goddess. Empedocles presents himself as agod, an enlightened being, to the citizens of Acragas, and he functions as a guru

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    8/20

    8 / John Bussanich

    to his student Pausanias to whom he teaches Orphic-Pythagorean meditation and

    the secrets of nature.Another example of ambitious Orientalizing is McEvilleys claim that the

    Orphic doctrines of soul-body dualism, karmic bindings, transmigration, andheaven and hell states for the just and the wicked respectively, which influencedPlato and later Platonists, can be traced to Jaina missionary activity. Thecomparisons of Jaina, Buddhist, and Orphic doctrines are compelling, but thehistorical dependence of Orphic ideas on Jaina is based primarily on unsup-ported speculation by Alain Danilou in his va and Dionysos (1979). Weencounter breathtaking inferential leaps like the following: The transition fromJain missionaries to proto-Orphics such as, perhaps, Pherecydes, is still largelyinvisible, though it must have occurred (204). Unfortunately, McEvilleyrefers to Pherecydes primarily to supply a link in the chain between the Orientand Orphic-Pythagoreans. Significantly, he does highlight the guru-disciple rela-tionship by reference to stories that Pherecydes was a teacher of Pythagoras andAmeinias the Pythagorean of Parmenides (171). But he implies that even thenotion of teaching lineages is imported from India. More emphatically he assertsthat

    It is certain that Pherecydes imported Oriental ideas into the Greek tradition,including some from India. The Indian doctrines he brought entered Greeceenmeshed in a net of Persian ideas. It is a plausible hypothesis that Phere-cydes called them the teachings of Orpheus in order to naturalize them. In thisway he passed them on to Pythagoras[who] combined them with elements

    of number religion, which was derived from other Oriental influences closerto home, and established an organized brotherhood to practice the path topurification (171; emphasis added).

    Classicists in particular will be troubled by the apparent arbitrariness with whichMcEvilley fits relatively obscure figures like Pherecydes, Pythagoras, and evenOrpheus into a spiritual lineage that reaches back into the Asian hinterlands.They will also lament the absence of a sustained discussion of the fragments ofPherecydes and any reference to the definitive book on him by Hermann Schibli(1990). Unconvincing also is the suggestion that Pherecydes indulged self-consciously in a kind of PR by labeling Oriental doctrines Orphic. Finally, thenarrow range of Orphic texts and themes he analyzes is a limitation that could

    have been mitigated by wider consideration of recent scholarship (see, forexample, Parker 1995).

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    9/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 9

    PLATONISM AND VEDNTA

    McEvilleys multifaceted comparisons of Plato, Plotinus, and the laterNeoplatonists with the Vedntic tradition take greater account of religiousexperience as a doctrinal source than his survey of Orphic-Pythagorean andUpaniadic figures. This focus is quite welcome, given contemporary scholarspreoccupation with abstract and theoretical problems, especially in Platosphilosophy. He begins with the observation that Plato synthesized various pre-Socratic tendencies into a syncretic whole analogous to the synthesis ofPur~ic Hinduism by Vedntins like akara and Rmnuja. In his view, thePlatonic synthesis although it seems to have emerged, ultimately, out of Indianprototypes, nevertheless took shape much earlier than the parallel syncretism inIndia (164). To evaluate this developmental hypothesis, one must consider thepossibility that the distinct trajectories in the development of the two traditionsfrom the classical to the medieval periods depend at least in part on the indige-nous features in each culture, including the originality of geniuses like Plato andthe authors of the Upaniads and the local literary histories.

    Regarding the literary expression of philosophical ideas, McEvilley says verylittle, which is understandable given the vast scale of his project, but a fewpoints are worth noting. Despite the lack of canonical scriptures in archaicGreece, many Greek philosophersincluding Plato and continuing through thelate Neoplatonistsinvoke archaic wisdom teachings, especially those transmit-ted in the Orphic-Pythagorean tradition, as quasi-scriptural sources for much of

    their own discursive philosophizing. Also, Platos dialogues are much closer inform and style to some Upaniads and early Buddhist texts than they are to theclassical Vedntic texts of akara and Rmnuja, which comprise commen-taries on the Upaniads, Brahmastras, andBhagavad Gt. The dialectical,psychological, and literary brilliance of Platos dialogues is unmatched in Hinduor Buddhist literature, though Indian philosophers easily match the Greeks inlogical sophistication. Indeed, there are hardly any direct precedents in Greekliterature for Platos dialogues. Once again we must consider factors unique toPlato and his age, for example, Socrates, the agonistic features of Greek culture,and perhaps Greek tragedy. Another distinguishing characteristic is that unlikethe Vedntic commentators neither Plato nor Plotinus are involved in writingcommentaries on scriptural texts, noted by McEvilley in the case of Plotinus

    (552). There is however a revelatory dimension to early Greek religious thought,as I have argued above, which is embodied in a variety of forms: mysterydoctrines, traditional oral teachings, Delphic maxims (for example, knowthyself and nothing in excess), the Socratic paradoxes (derived from his

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    10/20

    10 / John Bussanich

    Apollonian daimonion), and so forth. Orphic-Pythagorean teachings about

    the nature of the soul and its transmigration, purification, and divinization,Parmenides on being, just to mention the most prominent, are embraced byPlatonists as revelatory truths and in certain instances are similar in contentand function to the Upaniadic great sayings or mahvkyas, for example,not this, not this or you are that. Thus, the Orphic-Pythagorean tradition isanalogous in some respects to Vedic ruti, at least for Platonists, though becauseof the decentralized nature of Greek religion as regards scriptures, authority, anddoctrines, the teachings are treated more eclectically than in India.

    I should emphasize that in characterizing these teachings as revelation I donot mean to suggest that they preclude or are opposed to rational or philoso-phical inquiry. Such a faith vs. reason debating point is an artifact of post-Medieval or even post-Reformation dogmatic theological debate and thus has nodirect claim on ancient Greek or Indian speculation. In any case, here I onlywish to point out some of the ways in which mystery teachings are assimilatedand unpacked by Plato and the Neoplatonists, because McEvilley tends to reifyconcepts and doctrines for ease of comparison and to neglect the literary andhistorical contexts within which each writer worked. Ascertaining their attitudestowards their Orphic-Pythagorean heritage will also help defuse an interpretivedilemma that McEvilley has constructed for himself. Because he conceives ofOrphism as a movement distinct from Pythagoreanism he is puzzled how Orphicideas can coexist with Platos logical and analytical side (197). Getting to theroot of the alleged tension between Orphism and analysis requires that weproperly understand Parmenides metaphysics of being, for example, which is

    presented in logico-deductive form but which is inspired by a mysticalrevelation from the Goddess Persephone. McEvilley does not fully recognize theinterdependence of the mystical-magical-eschatological Orphic streams andthe rational-abstract-dialectical tendencies in early thinkers like Parmenides andEmpedocles, and hence arises the imaginary dilemma how they can coexist inPlato (cf. West 1971: 23000).4

    Platos repeated visits to South Italy no doubt provided him with direct accessto Orphic-Pythagorean teachings and practices (and teachers), which permeateentire dialogues, like the Phaedoa text which is rich in abstract metaphysicalthought and also in Orphic mysticismor frame many dialogues with conclud-ing eschatological myths. Curiously, McEvilley does not have much to sayabout Platos myths, perhaps because their literary form and sensibility are alien

    to Indian texts, at least any I know of. Because these accounts of the afterlife arein Platos estimation incapable of rational demonstration, Platos Socrates aimsto inculcate faith and hope in the esoteric stories (derived from anonymoussources) about the souls posthumous journeys. Careful study of the myths

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    11/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 11

    reveals many details indigenous to the South Italian spiritual milieu that Plato

    has embellished and imaginatively woven into a unique tapestry.5An examination of how Plato employs ideas from the Orphic mystery tradi-

    tion in dialectical contexts is a valuable supplement to McEvilleys outline ofPlatos religious philosophy. Sometimes Plato introduces these ideas as dialec-tical starting-points or premises. For example, Socrates begins his argumentagainst suicide in the Phaedo by invoking the Orphic maxim that we arepossessions of the gods (62b78), an idea which Plato embraces also in the Lawswhere the Athenian Stranger, when he becomes inspired, frequently refers to ushumans as toys or playthings of the gods (Laws 644d, 803c804b, 902b8).Particularly in the early and middle dialogues, Platos dialectic is imbued witha playfulness that aims to charm and seduce worldly types with the attractionsof philosophy and the possibility of attaining true freedom. At times Platoinvokes mystery teachings to help interlocutors find a way out of an impasse,for example, Socrates invokes the immortality of the soul, transmigration, andthe theory of recollection in order to rescue the inquiry into the nature of virtuewhen Menos paradox threatens to block the way forward. He also tests themin arguments with skeptics or nihilists in order to unfold their intellectualimplications or to show the limitations of dialectical argument. This strategy istypical of the Socratic elenchus (refutation argument) when testing definitions ofthe virtues vis vis the Socratic paradoxes, some of which as Delphic maximsare popular redactions of esoteric Orphic-Pythagorean doctrines. PropheticApollo is the divine source of these traditional sayings and also the divinity thatspeaks directly to Socrates through his personal voice, the daimonion. One

    might suppose that the paradoxical combination of Orphism and analysis issomething Plato learned directly from Socrates.6

    The existential dimension of Platos philosophy is embodied in the figure ofSocrates and in the ways he intervenes in his interlocutors lives. In dialecticalencounters and through the impasses (aporia) induced by Socratic questioning,the desire to seek the truth either grows or is thwarted: one either responds toSocrates or resists. Many dialogues in the Upaniads are also provoked by thevicissitudes of life, though traditionally this aspect of these texts has beenignored by Indologists.7 Grinshpons recent study skillfully unveils the conflictsand crises in the stories and dialogues of the Upaniadic characters, therebysupplementing the universalist context-free metaphysics, which dominates theVedntic commentators and modern scholarship, with a contextual meta-

    physics that reaches into the human heart. Such a literary and dramatic way ofreading the Upaniads, as well as dialogues in the Mokadharma, providesfertile ground for comparing the early Vednta with Plato.8 Both would agree, Ithink, that simply identifying and stating timeless truths is insufficient to awaken

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    12/20

    12 / John Bussanich

    the desire to seek or attain the truth. McEvilley stresses the core of classical

    Vedntic teaching: over against the older Vedic practice of sacrifice andasceticism, what is needed, according to the new doctrine, is not to becomebrahman but to come to know that one already is (558; emphasis in original).But as McEvilley himself shows, because this knowledge is transcendent andsuprarational, it cannot be achieved by intellectual means, by perusing doctrinalsummaries, or without the complete transformation of ones psyche. Hence, thepath involves withdrawal from normal life and the quieting of the mind throughthe practice of meditation and, in Vedntins like Rmnuja, through intensedevotionalism. Certainly, there are significant variations in textual strategiesand doctrinal formulations, not only between the Greek and Indian traditionsbut within each as well. Discontent, tragedy, and crisis motivate many of theUpaniadic characters to seek the truth, whereas akara and his successors,having perfected a literary style devoid of human voices and feelings, systemati-cally coordinate doubts, objections, counter-objections, and dialectically refinedtruths in their scriptual commentaries (see Clooney 1993).9 We find a similarprogressive reification and abstraction in the history of Greek philosophizingalso. The aspiration to seek the truth is prominent at the very beginning ofParmenides poem (he will be carried as far as his heart aspires) and in thefragments of Empedocles. This psychological focus continues to live in Platoscomplex notion of metaphysical eros, while it is rationalized in Aristotle:Socratic aporia becomes an intellectual puzzle and ecstatic eros for the goodbecomes sober desire for the good.

    The role of Socrates as wise man and teacher in Platos dialogues calls for

    more attention than it receives in McEvilleys account of philosophy as a way oflife in chapter 6 Platonic Ethics and Indian Yoga. He effectively demonstratesthat the standard view of a profoundly ignorant Socrates (193) fails to explainSocrates search for knowledge of the self, one of the great themes in theUpaniads (190), and that this is a type of knowledge which transcends whatDescartes and most contemporary philosophers seek (180). He cites a fewpassages (179) from the Phaedo to illustrate how Platos views on the with-drawal of the mind from sense-objects and the inner concentration of awarenessin order to achieve a direct apprehension of transcendent objects of pure thoughtparallel countless texts in the Upaniads and in the Yoga tradition which iden-tify knowledge of the self as the goal and meditation (dhyna) and absorption(samdhi) as the means. This higher type of knowledge is neither objective

    knowledge of the external world nor, ultimately, of anything distinct from theself. Thus, passages like the following support his assertion that Platonicphronsis specifies transcendent wisdom, which is analogous to Vedntic vidy(189) and Buddhistpraj (609):

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    13/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 13

    When the soul investigates by itself it passes into the realm of what is pure,

    ever existing, immortal and unchanging, and being akin to this, it always stayswith it whenever it is by itself and can do so; it ceases to stray and remains inthe same state while it touches things of the same kind, and its experience(pathma) then is what is called wisdom (phronsis) (Source? 79d17).

    Note the concrete language: the soul concentrated in itself touches pure beingand its wisdom is an experience. For Platonists the highest knowledge isexperiential, nondiscursive, nonpropositional, and incommunicable (seeBussanich 1997). Thus, I heartily concur with McEvilleys judgment thatPlatos descriptions of out-of-the-body knowledge have more in common withthe practices of Indian yogis than with that of Descartes (181). This pithyobservation captures nicely the interpretive myopia that afflicts much contempo-rary Plato scholarship. An excellent account of the meditative tranquility atwhich Platonic dialectic aims is this remarkable passage from the Republic , notcited by McEvilley:

    I suppose that someone who is healthy and moderate with himself goes tosleep only after having roused his rational part and feasted it on fine argu-ments and speculations, and having attained to clear self-consciousness;second, he neither starves nor feasts his appetites, so that they will slumberand not disturb his best part with either their pleasure or their pain, but theyllleave it alone, pure and by itself, to get on with its investigations, to yearnafter and perceive something in the past or present or future that it doesnt

    know. Hes also calmed down his passionate part and doesnt go to bed inan emotionally disturbed state because hes been angry with someone. Andwhen he has quieted these two parts and aroused the third, in which reason(logistikon) resides, and so takes his rest, you know that it is then that he bestgrasps the truth and that the visions that appear in his dreams are least lawless(571d6572b1).

    Remarkably, Plato relies on the Greek religious idiom of incubation (enteringthe liminal dream-state) and divination (apprehending the future andthe past) toevoke the intuitive dimension of what he here blandly calls reason, which is infact the organ of visionary perception. It would seem to be a rough descriptionof Platonic concentration of awareness and meditation which are similar to

    yogicpratyhra and dhyna (180). These are the goals of the emotional andpsychological training which comprise the theme of the impressive survey inchapter 25 of the Ethics of Imperturbability throughout the Greek and Indiantraditions (597641).10

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    14/20

    14 / John Bussanich

    McEvilley justly remarks that Socratesbecame the primary saint of the

    ethics of imperturbability in later Greek philosophy (599), though he seemsreluctant to acknowledge that Platos portrait of Socrates as impervious toextremes of weather and to pains and pleasures and to his uncanny states ofabsorption provide just the sort of evidence we need to connect Socratesconcrete behavior with his own comparison of the theoretical account of the sixsteps of the ladder of love in the Symposium with the stages of samdhi inPatajali.Socrates is anotherwiseman in thetradition going backto Parmenides,Pythagoras, and Empedocles. But rather than asserting his own divinity as hispredecessors had doneand his Neoplatonic successors like Plotinus andIamblichus didPlatos Socrates denies that he is wise: like a midwife heassists at the birth of wisdom in others.11 Nevertheless, he offers guidance tobecome like God so far as is possible, the aim of the virtuous person whobecomes just and pure, with understanding (Theaeteus 176b13).12 Though itis generally ignored by Platonic scholarship, the famous parable of the Cavehints at the intervention of the Platonic guru in the life of the cave-dweller in theascent to the sun: when one of them was freed and suddenly compelled to standup, turn his head, walk, and look up toward the light (515c5); if someonecompelled him to look at the light itself (515d8); and if someone dragged himaway from there by force, up the rough, steep path, and didnt let him go until hehad dragged him into the sunlight (515e5). Interpreting passages like these notas mystical experience but as emotionally overwrought descriptions of ordinaryreasoning processes is a distortion as McEvilley justly remarks (187). I wouldadd that the teacher who drags the disciple does more than engage the student

    dialectically.

    NEOPLATONISM AND VEDNTA

    McEvilleys comparison of Neoplatonic and Vedntic mystical metaphysics isimpressive but condensed. He sketches a few parallels between Tantra andtheurgy (586) and between Plotinus spiritual exercises and Indo-Tibetan medi-tation techniques (58890), but he focuses more on doctrinal metaphysics thanmystical experience or the divinization theme. Yet Plotinus Enneads alonecomprise more evidence for the practice of meditation and the awakening of

    the higher aspect of mind than all the Greek philosophers before him takentogether. He is clear about the importance of experience: whoever has seen,knows what I am saying (6.9.9). Plotinian metaphysics is heavily indebted toPlato and Aristotle, but much of his writing offers strikingly original accounts of

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    15/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 15

    the immediate apprehension of transcendent realities. Once again McEvilley is

    preoccupied with establishing the Indian origins of Neoplatonic metaphysics toovercome what he sees as unjustified scholarly skepticism. His judgment thatPlotinus was philosophizing in an Indianized tradition (550) because he isdependent on Plato and the Presocratics is dubious if my claim is true that theprimary sources of Greek religious philosophy are local and experiential. Healso seems unaware that many Neoplatonic scholars are familiar with Asianwisdom traditions and are sympathetic with the comparative approach heemploys (see Bussanich 1997; Findlay 1967; Shaw 1995; Wallis 1976).

    Chapter 22, which is continuous with chapter 5 on Platos monism, is veryinformative about Neoplatonic and Vedntic views of the metaphysical structureof reality. Generally, McEvilley suggests that the hypotheses of PlatosParmenides, which provide the superstructure for Neoplatonic metaphysics,represent contracted and expanded aspects of the One and thus are analogousto nirgu~a and sagu~a Brahman (164). Specifically, he argues that PlatosOne (he has in mind, I think, the second hypothesis of the Parmenides),Demiurge, and Indefinite Dyad (the passive, material principle) correspond topu ru a , vara, and prakti (or Upaniadic ka), respectively. McEvilleyadeptly traces the close similarities between Platos cosmic theism, with itsactive creator-god crafting progressively differentiated levels of manifestedreality, and the qualified nondualism of the Viidvaita Vednta. The distinc-tion in the cosmic divinity of the Timaeus (the Demiurge) between world-souland its cosmic body is like the Viidvaita idea that god is the worlds souland the cosmos is his body (164). Platonic and Viidvaita ontology construe

    the relation between the real and the phenomenal in a similar vein: Platoexplains the relation between transcendence and immanence as the interdepend-ence of sameness/being/unity with difference/nonbeing/multiplicity as do theViidvaitins, who in their concept ofBhedbheda assert that difference andnondifference are mutually entailing. Both also subsume the archaic pantheon ofmythological divinities on the level beneath that of the supreme cosmic divinity.(Neoplatonists follow this pattern.)

    Despite the cogency of his analysis of Platos metaphysics, its doctrinalapproach has the perhaps unintended effect of revealing the unsystematic char-acter of Platos philosophy by drawing analogies with practically every schoolof Indian thought, orthodox and heterodox. Sometimes McEvilley links ideasthat are dissimilar or he draws analogies imprecisely. For example, his compari-

    son of Platos theory of explanation through universals with Sarvstavdindharma-theory (167) seems to work on the level of intellectual training, but heneglects to mention that Plato has a realist theory of universals whereas theBuddhists are nominalists. In the case of orthodox schools he mixes and matches

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    16/20

    16 / John Bussanich

    Skhyan and Vedntic ideas rather freely. In his comparison of Platos One

    to Skhyanpurua and the Dyad toprakti , he does not address the difficultiesthat the One is not a self in any obvious way and prakti is not just a materialprinciple of differentiation. In fact, it includes buddhi, which would seem to besimilar to Platonic nous if anything; and the latter is a transcendent, activeprinciple, closely related to the Demiurge and thus comparable to vara and notprakti. These issues remain unresolved perhaps owing to McEvilleys lack ofclarity on important differences between Skhyan and Vedntic metaphysics.

    A similar pattern of insightful, broad cross-traditional comparisons combinedwith occasional missteps is evident in McEvilleys excellent discussion ofPlotinus. Insofar as the Many appear to be transformations of the One and sincetranscendent principles contain immanent effects, Plotinus metaphysics (andthe Neoplatonists in general) approximates Vedntic parinamavda andsatkryavda (553). Moreover, since all the Neoplatonists are extreme realistshe is right to doubt that the strongest forms of the my-doctrine, for example,akaras, correspond to the Neoplatonic attitude towards appearances. Theshadows on the wall of Platos cave and the flickering insubstantiality ofsensible particulars are not, it seems to me, the right ingredients for a radicaldoctrine of illusion. However, theres a bit more room for illusionism inPlotinus metaphysics. The productive power (dynamis) of the higher principlesis similar to the divine creative power of akti (554); on the other hand, thetheme of deceptive divine play does not fit well anywhere in the spectrum ofPlatonic theology, one of whose main principles is the truthfulness andunequivocal goodness of the gods.

    On the so-called positive and negative theologies in Plotinus, McEvilleyarticulates well the use of what he calls bipolar contradictions in both theEnneads and in the Upaniads, Brahmastras, and Viidvaita Bhedbheda.Thus, of the One Plotinus says it is none of existing things, yet it is all(VI.7.32) and it is both present and absent (V.5.9), and in the Upaniads themany is a part ofbrahman, yetbrahman has no parts (a Upaniad2.3.43,2.1.26) (556). However, all the Vedntic schools are, I think, more emphatic-cally monistic than Plotinus metaphysics. This point is supported by the factthat neither Plotinus nor any of the later Neoplatonists explicitly identifies thesoul with the One as, for example, in the Vedntic Brahman = tman identity.Plotinus does not even quite express the milder form of the paradox: the indi-vidual self is differentfrom Brahman but at the same time not different (a

    Upaniad2.3.43). The differences between the two traditions are not simply oreven primarily terminological, but I think it is revealing that Vedntins can drawa distinction between tman andjvtman which is unavailable to Platonists.And they readily conceive of Brahman as the Supreme Self. On this point

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    17/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 17

    McEvilley bends and twists Plotinus ideas to fit Vedntic orthodoxy. First, to

    support his claim that something close to the Vedntic brahmtman formulaappears in the Enneads he quotes passages like VI.5.12 (564) which mention thesoul becoming the All. But here the all refers to intelligible reality, not theOne. Indeed, for Plotinus, and arguably for Plato as well, the true self is nousor intellect, not the One. In the Greek idiom the ultimate goal is beyondtheself. Second, McEvilley does not present a convincing defense of his claims thatthe One is a self and that apprehension of the One in Plotinus represents theattainment of ultimate self-knowledge. For Plotinus self-knowledge is perfectedon the noetic level, where there is a perfect fit between thought and being (cf.especially V.3 and V.5). McEvilley implies that this highest knowledge issimilar to Vedntic par vidy (560). But union with the One is a hyper-onticstate that is explicitly said to be beyond thought and knowledge, as he notes(561), so no type ofvidy quite fits. I note, finally, that McEvilley agrees withthe received view on which soul never achieves ultimate union with the One butis eternally condemned to transmigration and reincarnation (567n29; cf. contraBussanich 1994). Oddly enough, here McEvilley misses an opportunity torecognize that on this point Plotinus is very close to the Advaita Vednta viewthat the liberated soul attains identity with the absolute.

    The fact that this review contains many criticisms, requests for expansion ofkey points, and occasional clarifications signals my admiration and gratitude forMcEvilleys achievement. No other book offers so much illumination on thestriking parallels between ancient Greek and Indian philosophy.

    Notes

    1. He also notes in passing (121) the importance of Wests comparison of theUpaniadic Path of Five Fires and the Paths of Gods and Fathers in hispathbreaking Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient (1971: see especially6200, 17300).

    2. For example, in his most recent book, which McEvilley was not able toconsult, Burkert stresses the difficulties of identifying specific borrowings, since

    among Iranian, Egyptian, and Pythagorean elements, the intermingling ofsimilar motifs and tendencies is too dense, and the determining contacts go

    back too far as against the extant Greek texts, so that a neat sorting out ofitems and ways of transfer becomes impossible (2004: 113).

    On Egyptian religion the works of Assmann (2001) and Hornung (1996) are

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    18/20

    18 / John Bussanich

    fundamental.

    3. McEvilley acknowledges his indebtedness to West for this comparison,though he does not mention the extensive earlier scholarship cited by West.

    4. Kingsley 1995 and 2003 demonstrate in massive detail how these twosides of Empedocles thought are interrelated. He shows how the supposedlyscientific aspect of his thought, prominent in his poem On Nature, aims atteaching his pupil Pausanias the inner workings of the realm of nature so that hecan make us of this magical esoteric lore to achieve enlightenment, the subjectof his other poem Purifications.

    5. See Kingsley (1995: 79132) for the Orphic-Pythagorean sources of thePhaedo myth and their combined impact on the later Neoplatonic commen-tators.

    6. On Socrates religious experience, see Bussanich (2005).7. Grinshpon (2003: 36) cites Hermann Oldenbergs view that the characters

    and their interchanges amount to only clumsy sketches of everyday life. Thetendency to depersonalize the Upaniads is evident even in Halbfass India andEurope, which contains no references to its great spiritual heroes such asUddlaka ru~i or Yjavalkya.

    8. See, for example, Sulabhs Refutation of King Janaka in Mahbhrata12.308 with Fitzgeralds study (2002). The literary approach to Plato is nowalmost a mass movement. For recent outstanding examples of the genre, seeBlondell (2002), Kahn (1996).

    9. In this respect they are similar to the Medieval scholastics.10. The discussion of Hellenistic moral psychology is impressive (see further

    on this topic, Knuuttila 2004; Sorabji 2000).11. I never express my own views about anything, because there is nowisdom in me.God compels me to attend the travail of others, but has forbid-den me to procreate. So that I am not in any sense a wise man; I cannot claim asthe child of my own soul any discovery worth the name of wisdom. But withthose who associate with me it is different. At first some of them may give theimpression of being ignorant and stupid; but as time goes on and our associationcontinues, all whom the god permits are seen to make progress.and yet it isclear that this is not due to anything they have learned from me; it is that theydiscover within themselves a multitude of beautiful things, which they bringforth into the light. But it is I, with gods help, who deliver them of thisoffspring (Theaeteus 150cd).

    12. More clearly than Plato, but in tune with Parmenides and Empedocles, theNeoplatonists promote divinization as an ideal capable of realization. Compari-son of this theme with moka andjvanmukti in Indian traditions would have fitwell into McEvilleys project.

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    19/20

    The Roots of Plantonism and Vednta / 19

    References Cited

    Assmann, Jan. 2001 [0000]. The Search for God in Ancient Egypt(trans. DavidLorton). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Blondell, Ruby. 2002. The Play of Character in Platos Dialogues. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    Burkert, Walter. 2004. Babylon, Memphis, Persepolis: Eastern Contexts ofGreek Culture. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Bussanich, John. 1994. Mystical Elements in the Thought of Plotinus(Appendix to II.36.1).Aufstieg und Niedergang der rmischen Welt2.36.7:530030.

    Bussanich, John. 1997. Plotinian Mysticism in Theoretical and ComparativePerspective.American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71, 00: 33965.

    Bussanich, John. 2005. Socrates and Religious Experience. In RachanaKamtekar and Sara Ahbel-Rappe, eds., The Blackwell Companion to Socrates,0000. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Clooney, Francis. 1993. Theology After Vednta: An Experiment inComparative Theology. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Coomaraswamy, Ananda K. 0000. A New Approach to the Vedas. City:Publisher.

    Coomaraswamy, Ananda K. 1977. Coomaraswamy: Selected Papers. Volume 2:Metaphysics (ed. Roger Lipsey). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Coomaraswamy, Ananda K. 2002. Perception of the Veda (ed. Vidya NivasMisra). New Delhi: Manohar.

    Cooper, John M. ed. 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hackett.Danilou, Alain. 1982 [0000]. va and Dionysos (trans. K. F. Hurry). TheHague: East-West Publications.

    Findlay, J. N. 1967. The Transcendence of the Cave. London: George Allen &Unwin.

    Fitzgerald, James L. 2002. Nun Befuddles King, Shows Karmayoga Does NotWork: Sulabhs Refutation of King Janaka at MBh 12.308. Journal ofIndian Philosophy 30, 6: 64177.

    Grinshpon, Yohanan. 2003. Crisis and Knowledge: The Upanishadic Experi-ence and Storytelling. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.

    Halbfass, Wilhelm. 1988 [1981]. India and Europe: An Essay in Under-standing. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Hornung, Erik. 1996 [0000]. Conceptions of God in Ancient Egypt: The One andthe Many (trans. John Baines). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Kahn, Charles H. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Useof a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • 7/27/2019 John Buccanich on Thomas McEvilley Platonism_Vedanta

    20/20

    20 / John Bussanich

    Kingsley, Peter. 1990. The Greek Origin of the Sixth-Century Dating of

    Zoroaster. Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies 53, 2:24565.

    Kingsley, Peter. 1995. Ancient Philosophy, Mystery and Magic: Empedoclesand Pythagorean Tradition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Kingsley, Peter. 1999. In the Dark Places of Wisdom. Inverness: Golden SufiCenter.

    Kingsley, Peter. 2003.Reality. Inverness: Golden Sufi Center.Knuuttila, Simo. 2004. Emotions in Ancient and Medieval Philosophy. Oxford:

    Oxford University Press.Parker, Robert. 1995. Early Orphism.In Anton Powell, ed., The Greek World,

    483510. London: Routledge.Schibli, Hermann S. 1990. Pherekydes of Syros. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Shaw, Gregory. 1995. Theurgy and the Soul: The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus.

    University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Sorabji, Richard. 2000. Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation to

    Christian Temptation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Wallis, Richard T. 1976. NOUS as Experience. In R. Baine Harris, ed., The

    Significance of Neoplatonism, 12154. Albany: State University of New YorkPress.

    West, M. L. 1971. Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

    JOHN BUSSANICH is Professor of at the University of NewMexico. < >