lmcamus and his critics on capital punishment

Upload: sabik-pandit

Post on 06-Jul-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    1/12

     N EXCHANGE

    Camus and

    His

    Critics

    on Capital Punishment

    Donald

    Lazere

    A

    LARGE MAJORITY

    of the American public

    continues to favor the death penalty,

    and a 1972 Supreme Court decision virtu-

    ally abolishing capital punishment on

    constitutional grounds has gradually

    been superseded by a variety

    of

    legisla-

    tion within individual states circumvent-

    ing the Court’s constitutional objections

    and resulting in a new cycle of execu-

    tions during recent years. For this rea-

    son, Albert Camus’ classic essay against

    capital punishment, “Reflections on the

    Guillotine,”retains all of its timeliness and

    power as a challenge to Americans and

    citizens of other countries where support

    for th e death penalty remains strong.”Re

    flections” was published in France in a

    1957 bookceauthored by Arthur Koestler

    titled

    R ‘exions sur

    la

    peine cap itale,

    and

    the English version appeared in a 1960

    collection of Camus’ journalism, Resis-

    tance, Rebellion, and Death.’

    For the purpose of reconfirming the

    viability of Camus’ arguments on capital

    punishment and the larger philosophi-

    cal, political, and literary issues the es-

    say raises, I will briefly review his lines

    of argument and then evaluate two ma-

    jor at tempts in the United States to re-

    fute them, “On Camus and Capital Pun-

    ishment” by Thomas Molnar and “For

    Capital Punishment” by Walter Berns.

    This exchange retains additional con-

    temporary significance because Molnar

    and Berns represent the movement of

    intellectual conservatism that has gained

    increasing influence in th e United States

    in the past few decades, so that the

    debate provides an exemplary case of

    the nature and quality of conservative

    versus liberal ideology-though Camus

    was more inclined toward nonviolent

    anarchism and communitarian social-

    ism

    than liberalism.

    Published fifteen years after Camus’

    The Stranger,

    “Reflections” recapitulates

    severalof that novel’s images and themes

    concerning the impending execution

    of

    its narrator Meursault: the story of

    Camus’/Meursault’s father self-righ-

    teously going

    to

    watch an execution but

    coming home vomiting; the agonies of

    the condemned man in the death cell,

    the theatricality

    of

    courtroom rhetoric

    and arbitrariness of the verdict, etc.

    Camus continues beyond

    The Stranger,

    which ends before Meursault

    is

    guillo-

    tined, to describe actual executions, jux-

    taposing their barbaric reality to the

    euphemisms in which society inconsis-

    tently shrouds this purportedly exem-

    plary ritual. (Camus argues that execu-

    tions should be televised rather than

    taking place in private if society truly

    believes they

    serve

    as a deterrent to

    potential criminals.)

    After beginning with these gruesomely

    visceral physical descriptions of decapi-

    Modern ge 371

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    2/12

    tation, Camus reviews criminological

    data refuting defenses

    of

    capital punish-

    ment based on its alleged deterrent value

    and citing the high incidence of judicial

    errors and variability in verdicts from

    one time and place to another. These

    data provide the basis for arguing against

    capital punishment on the grounds of its

    irreversibility; on these grounds alone,

    Camus argues for life imprisonment with-

    out parole a s an alternative. H e goes on,

    however,

    to

    philosophical, religious, and

    political levels of argument. H e does not

    wholly reject conservative defenses of

    punishment

    as

    revenge or retribution,

    but draws the line at death, not only

    because of the dangers

    of

    erroneous

    executions but because society drags

    itself down to the level of its most irratio-

    nal members in indulging the impulse to

    bloodshed, and indeed may incite more

    of those members to murder through

    emulation than it deters.

    On the metaphysical level, Camus at-

    tacks capital punishment as blasphemy

    against Christian mercy and repentance:

    “There could be read on the sword of the

    Fribourg executioner the words: ‘Lord

    Jesus, thou art the judge.’ And, to be

    sure, whoever clings to the teaching of

    Jesus will look upon that handsome

    sword as one more outrage to the person

    of Christ.”2Moreover, he argues that t he

    religious faith undergirding earlier

    church-states can no longer justify mod-

    ern secular states’ assumption of God-

    like power over life and death.

    On the political plane, Camus argues

    as

    a

    leftist that bourgeois society breeds

    and profits from anti-social conditions

    like

    poverty and alcoholism, bu t totally

    absolves itself of responsibility for the

    criminal consequences of these condi-

    tions. (This argument has been sup-

    ported by recent studies of atrocity kill-

    ers in the United States showing nearly

    allof hem to have been poor and abused

    as children.)

    His

    argument

    is

    not that

    individuals bear no responsibility for

    crime or that society is not entitled to

    defend itself, but that as long

    as

    society

    bears the smallest fraction

    of

    responsi-

    bility, it is unwarranted in placing 100

    of

    responsibility o n criminals in execut-

    ing them; the cost of

    life

    imprisonment

    should be considered society’s minimal

    share

    of

    responsibility. Finally, and most

    compellingly, he argues that capital pun-

    ishment

    is

    the ultimate weapon of exces-

    sive state power over the individual, and

    should

    be

    abolished as a first step to-

    ward reversal of the deification of the

    state and nationalism that has led in the

    twentieth century o two world wars, the

    threat of nuclear war, totalitarianism,

    and the diminishing of individual liber-

    ties, even in democracies.

    I1

    Thomas Molnar’s “OnCamus and Capi-

    tal Punishment” appeared in the sum-

    mer

    1958

    issue of

    Modern Age.

    Walter

    Berns’s “For Capital Punishment” was

    published in the April 1979

    Harper’s,

    at

    that time predominantly neoconserv-

    ative in its politics; the essay was repub-

    lished the same year in Berns’s bookFor

    Capital Punishment: Crime and the Mo

    rality

    of

    the D eath P e n ~ l t y . ~

    erns, a po-

    litical scientist, was and still is a resident

    scholar at t he American Enterprise Insti-

    tute in Washington. In my view, Molnar’s

    article, although appearing only a year

    after Camus,’ presents a more informed

    account than Berns’s later one of Camus’

    philosophy and its basic points of opposi-

    tion to conservative thought. Neverthe-

    less,

    will make the case tha t both

    es-

    says misrepresent Camus’ ideas to t he

    point

    of

    attackinga straw man and evad-

    ing the central issues Camus addresses.

    Before summarizing Molnar’s and

    Berns’s arguments, it

    is

    necessary to

    note that neither critic addresses all of

    Camus’s main lines of argument, includ-

    ing the issues of judicial error and vari-

    ability-an omission that presents prob-

    lems for the moral position they defend,

    3

    72

    Fall 996

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    3/12

    which assumes a high degree of recti-

    tude in the judiciary system. Both do

    raise the traditional conservative argu-

    ment for deterrence , only t o acknowl-

    edge its weakness as a defense

    of

    capital

    punishment; they reject it not

    so

    much

    because empirical evidence does not

    support it (which neither denies), but

    because any empirical argument, as

    Molnar says, “enters into the game

    of

    pragmatism and statistic^, ^

    as

    opposed

    to the moral dimensions they both em-

    phasize.

    Molnar begins his essay with the

    case

    of an elderly, white New Yorkshopkeeper

    who, having been held up twice, finally

    shot to death athird blackrobber,whose

    gun, as it turned out, was a toy. Molnar

    defends t h e shopkeeper’s action against

    predictable liberal criticisms, moving

    from this individual execution of justice

    to the death penalty. In both cases,

    Molnar asserts, man has a

    “moral

    duty

    to

    react with indignation when his com-

    mon sense, uncorrupted by psychologi-

    cal and sociological sophistication,

    tells

    him that evil

    is

    evil, hat every action is

    projected against the walls

    of

    the social

    order and of the divine order, and rever-

    berates from there.”j

    Molnar opposes this definition of jus-

    tice to the alleged moral relativism of

    modern liberals, including Camus. After

    a fairminded summary of Camus’ vari-

    ous

    works expressing his social and

    metaphysical skepticism, particularly

    regarding the frailties of legal justice

    and “the role of the judge who assumes

    divine prerogatives in an agnostic soci-

    ety,” Molnar charges that “Camus’ idea

    of

    justice

    is

    tinged with sentimentality,

    and it fails to distinguish between a gen-

    eralized and hazy

    guilt-feeling

    made fas h-

    ionable by the novels of Dostoevsky and

    Kafka) and the moral and legal concept

    of individual responsibility.”6 Molnar

    continues:

    reply to Camus that responsibility ought

    to be kept l imited if we want it to have a

    meaning It is human nature to feel in-

    terested in, concerned

    with,

    and, hence,

    responsible for

    a

    relatively

    small number

    of people and issues. This is contrary to

    the prevailing liberal, humanitarian phi-

    losophy

    which

    wants to impress upon us

    a universal concern for all mankind, and

    responsibility for events distant from

    US,

    outside of our possible sphere

    of

    influ-

    ence and effectiveness. The m a n w h o

    would adopt this attitude [is] obliviousto

    its abstract and artificial nature ...’

    Molnar goes on to reply to Camus’

    arguments about the impossibility of

    definitively delineating between the

    individual’s and society’s responsibility

    for crime;equating Camus with the kind

    of liberals who “say or imply tha t man is

    good, but ‘society’ corrupts him .... We

    know these Rousseauistic laments, but

    we may be surprised t o find them under

    Camus’ pen.”8

    In spite of Molnar’s generally well-

    informed view

    of

    modern moral philoso-

    phy and Camus’ thought in general, he

    misrepresents “Reflections on th e Guil-

    lotine” on three major points: Camus’

    alleged denial

    of

    the responsibility of

    criminals and the legitimacy of punish-

    ing them, his displacement

    of

    responsi-

    bility for crime onto society, and the

    abstrac t nature

    of

    his position. To begin

    with Molnar’s charge tha t Camus has a

    romantically sentimental attitude toward

    criminals and exonerates them of all

    responsibility, Camus could not be more

    clear in his opposition to such attitudes:

    There

    is no question

    of

    giving in to some

    conventional set of sentimental pictures

    and calling to mind Victor Hugo’s good

    convicts. The age

    of

    enlightenment, as

    people say, wanted to suppress the death

    penalty on the grounds that man was

    naturally good.

    Of

    course he is

    not

    (he

    is

    worse or better). After twenty years of

    our magnificent history we are well aware

    of this.

    But precisely because

    he

    is not

    absolutely good, no one among us can

    Modern

    ge

    3

    7

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    4/12

    pose as an absolute judge and pronounce

    the definitive elimination of the worst

    among the guilty, because no one

    of u s

    can

    lay claim to absolute innocence.Capi-

    tal judgment upsets the only indisput-

    able human solidarity-our solidarity

    against death-and it can be legitimized

    only

    by

    a

    truth or

    a principle that is

    superior to man?

    The key word here

    is

    “absolute.” Like-

    wise for Camus’ view of punishment:

    “The instinct of preservation

    of

    societ-

    ies, and hence of individuals, requires

    hat individual responsibility be pos-

    tulated and accepted without dreaming

    of an absolute indulgence that would

    amount t o the death of all society. But

    the same reasoning must lead us to con-

    clude that there never exists any total

    responsibility or, consequently, any ab-

    solute punishment or reward .... The

    death penalty, which really neither pro-

    vides an example nor assures distribu-

    tive justice, simply usurps an exorbitant

    privilege b y claiming to punish an al-

    ways relative culpability by a definitive

    and irreparable punishment.”I0 And,

    “Compassion, of course, can in this in-

    stance be but an awareness of a common

    suffering and not a frivolous indulgence

    paying

    no

    attention to the sufferings and

    rights of the victim. Compassion does

    not exclude punishment, but it suspends

    the final condemnation.”” And finally,

    “We should admit at one and th e same

    time our hope and our ignorance, we

    should refuse absolute law and the ir-

    reparable judgment. We know enough to

    say that this or that major criminal de-

    serves hard labor for life. But we don’t

    know enough t o decree that h e be shorn

    of his future.”l2

    In response to Camus’ citation of t he

    high incidence of slum housing and alco-

    holism in France as factors contributing

    to crime, Molnar claims, “Now Camus

    may be hoist by his own statistical pe-

    tard,”I3 since France has a lower crime

    rate than other countries with better

    housing and

    less alcoholism. Camus

    never a ttempts, however, to make such

    a reductive correlation between social

    conditions and crime in one country or

    another; his point

    is

    thatany society tha t

    fosters, and allows profiteering from,

    poverty and vice bears a minimal share

    of

    responsibility for the criminal conse-

    quences.

    So

    Camus’ case rests not on a denial of

    individual responsibility or punishment,

    but only

    o n

    drawing the line at carrying

    them to the point of death; in ignoring

    this essential distinction, Molnar misses

    Camus’ entire point. Ignoring the dis-

    tinction likewise misleads Molnar into

    an analogy between capital punishment

    and a mother slapping her child for dis-

    regarding her instructions:

    Beyond the mother’s mmediateresponse,

    avenging, in some way, the injury against

    a visible (or invisible) order, there

    is

    of

    course, the further and inseparable in-

    tention of “teaching the child a lesson.”

    But again,

    this

    does

    not

    amount exactly

    to discouraging

    him

    from repeating the

    same thing; it merely informs him that

    each time

    he

    commits act A, he takes risk

    R that punishment P

    might

    follow. The

    legal systems of civilized nations express

    the same idea.

    Thus the law does not

    punish

    only

    in

    order to set an exampleand prevent other

    misdeeds,

    but

    also because

    our

    innate

    concept of justice, reinforced by tradi-

    tion, demands an immediate reaction

    against crime

    and

    apenalty possibly equal

    to the amount of suffering

    or

    damage

    caused.I4

    Whether Molnar

    is

    arguing here for

    deterrence or retaliation, the analogy

    of

    slapping the child, for whatever pur-

    pose, is surely incommensurate with

    teaching someone a lesson by killing

    him. And the notion of “a penalty possi-

    bly equal to the amount

    of

    suffering”

    could b e said t o enter into the game of

    pragmatism that Molnar eschews, since

    it involves what Camus calls a casuistry

    374 Fall 996

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    5/12

    of bloodshed attempting to measure

    what degree of imposed suffering justi-

    fies execution-murder in various de-

    grees, kidnapping, rape, adultery,

    etc

    and possibly leading

    to

    justification for

    crucifixion, drawing and quartering, or

    keeping killers alive to torture them daily.

    Molnar makes another dubious anal-

    ogy in criticizing Camus’ “cheap rheto-

    ric” in his gruesome descriptions

    of

    a

    decapitation, intended to expose the

    hypocritical euphemisms in which ex-

    ecutions are shrouded. “After all,”

    Molnar comments, “few people could

    bear witnessing even a minor surgical

    intervention, let alone a major

    operation.’’’15t is generally agreed, how-

    ever, that the gore of an operation

    is

    justified by its salutary effects, whereas

    the salutary effects of executions, on

    society

    if

    not on the patient, are exactly

    what abolitionists dispute. Molnar fur-

    ther ignores the point of Camus’ use of

    emotional appeal-that many people

    who approve of capital punishment in

    the abstract would not do

    so

    if they

    understood its flesh-and-blood reality.

    Molnar’s penchant for analogies that

    distract from the visceral specifics of an

    individual’s death

    is

    only one sign of

    precisely the abstract modes of thought

    Camus’ essay and the rest of his works

    are addressed against. When defenders

    of

    capital punishment dismiss cases

    where innocent people may have been

    executed, on the grounds that such cases

    are “exceptional,” Camus remarks that

    all of “our lives are exceptional, too.”16

    Molnar, accusing Camus and other liber-

    als of abstract moralizing is anomalous

    in an essay filled with phrases l ike,

    “[Camus]simply fails to see that it is not

    the judge-in-person, but the representa-

    tive

    of

    the law who sits in th e chair, and

    that th e law-expression of the social

    order-possesses certain definite, al-

    though imperfectly mirrored, attributes

    of the divine order.’’l7 Such phrases in-

    evitably bring to mind one of Camus’ most

    powerful criticisms of the abstractions

    of

    legal justice, the passage in The Stranger

    where Meursault, having been condemned

    to death for a murder committed in a

    moment

    of

    sun-blindness, muses:

    Try as

    1

    might, couldn’t stomach this

    brutal certitude. For really,when onecame

    to think about it, there was a dispropor-

    tion between the judgment on which it

    was based and the unalterable sequence

    of events starting from the moment when

    that judgment was delivered. The fact

    that the verdict was read out at eight p.m.

    rather than at five, the fact that it might

    have been quitedifferent, that it was given

    by men who change their underclothes,

    and was credited to

    so

    vague an entity as

    the “French people”-for that matter, why

    not to the Chinese or the German

    people?-all these facts seemed to de-

    prive the court’s decision of much of its

    gravity.’*

    Criticizing Camus, along with other

    existentialists

    l ike

    Sartre and Malraux

    who assert the factitiousness of society’s

    claim to power over individual lives and

    deaths, Molnar says, “Never for a mo-

    ment do they seriously consider theview

    that the defects of institutions and of

    society as a whole have their roots in

    human nature, or as the Christian and

    Jewish religions put it, in original sin;

    that we are not justified to transfer man’s

    own failings

    to

    the community and its

    defective organi~ation.”’~amus does

    indeed consider such views, for more

    than a minute, and thoroughly refutes

    them. H e argues that modern societies

    are essentially secular or ecumenical,

    and therefore have no right to legislate

    on the basis

    of

    the

    beliefs

    of specific

    religions. Particularly in legislating mat-

    ters of life or death, they cannot legiti-

    mately assume the existence of a God or

    an afterlife in which the errors of human

    justice might

    be

    redeemed. How can a

    society

    l ike

    the United States, for ex-

    ample, whose present gods are the pur-

    suit of wealth and consumption of com-

    Modem

    ge

    37

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    6/12

    modities, rock music stars and protes-

    sional athletes, suddenly lay claim to

    being the steward of divine order when

    it comes to executions?

    In Molnar’s statement about original

    sin cited above, the phrase after the

    semicolon seems

    a

    o sequitur Even

    if

    one accepts Molnar’s belief in original

    sin (as Camus does not), the logical con-

    sequence of that doctrine, as Camus

    suggests, would seem to be that the

    postlapsarian state

    of

    all societies as

    well as individuals should be a warrant

    against the assumption that any such

    fallen society should have the godlike

    power to judge who shall

    live

    and who

    shall die. Thus Camus does not attempt,

    as Molnar claims, to “transfer man’s own

    failings to th e community,” but only to

    assert (an assertion that would seem to

    be equally valid for either believers or

    agnostics), “There is a solidarity

    of

    all

    men in error and aberration. Must that

    solidarity operate for the tribunal and

    ine Camus’bemused reaction to Molnar’s

    reference to “imperfectly mirrored at-

    tributes of the divine order.” Which soci-

    ety is nearly enough perfect to mirror

    divinity, and which isn’t? Nazi Germany?

    Communist Russia? The United States?

    One would think that Molnar, as an

    Hungarian survivor of Nazism and Com-

    munism, should be as skeptical

    as

    Camus

    of the claims to omnipotence by modern

    states, including Nazi Germany, which

    claimed the religious mandate,

    ott

    mit

    Uns specially in exterminating politi-

    cal “criminals.” Molnar claims that

    Camus’ arguments against capital pun-

    ishment (which Molnar sees as a plea for

    mercy toward victims

    of

    political perse-

    cution during the Algerian War, at its

    height in 1957 , “may serve, in the eyes

    of a nondiscriminating public opinion,

    the much more dubious cause of exoner-

    ating common criminals, murderers, and

    Gestapo-torturers.”2’This last claim ig-

    nores Camus’ record as a leading

    Resis-

    be denied the accused?”20One can

    imag-

    tance journalist and his extensive post-

    war deliberations on moral dilemmas

    such as executing Nazi war criminals in

    “Reflections on the Guillotine” and else-

    where, including his account

    of

    his

    change

    of

    att itude from favoring capital

    punishment a s the result of a debate

    with the Catholic author Franqois

    Mauriac, who argued persuasively

    against executing Nazi collaborators in

    France following World War 11

    Molnar glosses over Camus’ central

    argument that fascist and communist

    totalitarianism arose largely out of the

    modern deification

    of

    state power and

    ideological absolutism epitomized in the

    death penalty:

    Those who cause the most blood to flow

    are the same ones who believe they have

    right, logic, and history [and, he might

    have added, God]

    on

    their side Blood-

    thirsty laws, it has been said, make blood-

    thirsty customs. But any society eventu-

    ally reaches a stateof ignominy in which,

    despite every disorder, the customs never

    manage to beas bloodthirstyas thelaws....

    How can European society of the mid-

    century survive unless it decides to de-

    fend individuals by every means against

    the State’s oppression? Forbidding a

    man’s execution would amount to pro

    claiming publicly that society and the

    State are not absolute values, that noth-

    ing authorizes them to legislate defini-

    tively

    or

    to bring about the irreparable.22

    Molnar’s position against Camus de-

    rives from

    a

    classic conservatism justi-

    fying state power in the tradition of Euro-

    pean church-states and the divine right

    of kings. But such a position seems anach-

    ronistic not only in light of twentieth-

    century totalitarianism but also of the

    degeneration of democratic sta tes into

    corporate plutocracy, corrupt parties,

    and bureaucratic ineptitude. The main-

    stream

    of

    conservative ideology, at least

    in the United States, has been libertarian

    and othe r varieties of anti-statism. The

    fact that Molnar himself cites Friedrich

    37

    Fall 996

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    7/12

    Hayek

    as

    an authority makes it all the

    more puzzling that he fails to acknowl-

    edge what would seem to be the strong

    appeal in Camus’ arguments for anti-

    statist conservatives. From my own

    so

    cialdemocrat ic viewpoint, this appears

    to be one of countless contradictions

    between absolutistic, judicial-moral stat-

    ism and economic laissez-faire in con-

    temporary conservatives (other than

    lib-

    ertarians), whether the intellectual

    variety of Molnar and Modern

    Age

    or the

    vulgar variety of Nixon-Reagan-Bush

    Republicanism-though, to be sure, left-

    ists

    can be accused

    of

    the reverse

    set

    of

    self-contradictions.

    Walter Berns’s “For Capital Punishment”

    follows many

    of

    the same lines of argu-

    ment as Molnar; Berns falls into the same

    misrepresentations or misunderstand-

    ings

    of

    Camus’ “Reflections” and is even

    more fallacious in his reasoning, adding

    some flights of literary fancy to confuse

    things. H e begins by explaining that he

    has come around to rejecting the con-

    ventional liberal wisdom that capital

    punishment represents an unjustifiable

    principle of revenge against criminals,

    and now believes “we punish criminals

    principally in order to pay them back,

    and we execute the worst of them out of

    mora l neces~ i ty .”~~

    e

    reiterates this

    point several times over, and yet, like

    Molnar, he never explains how accept-

    ing the principle of punishment logically

    dictates capitalpunishment, as opposed,

    say,to life imprisonment without parole

    as advocated by Camus.

    Berns cites as authority for the prin-

    ciple of retribution Simon Wiesenthal’s

    writings about his motives for bringing

    Nazi war criminals to justice, but he

    presents no supporting quotations from

    Wiesenthal. The fact is that in

    Wiesenthal’s memoirs and interviews

    with Joseph Wechsberg he advocates

    neither retaliation nor execution:

    “ am not motivated by a sense of re-

    venge.’Iz4

    [Wiesenthal] was approached by several

    groups who wanted to create gangs that

    would capture and kill their former tor-

    mentors; he opposed this idea violently.

    The Jews must not fight the Nazis with the

    Nazis’ depraved methods, he said.25

    Wiesenthal knew that the Nazi crimes

    could never be ‘avenged.’ Obviously,

    strict accountability for the crimes was

    impossible The important thing was to

    prevent the commission of mass murder

    in the future.26

    Wiesenthal explained that the Jews have

    always had

    a

    high regard for the sanctity

    of human life and didn’t think that murder

    would expiate murder.27

    About Camus, Berns claims, “The most

    powerful attack on capital punishment

    was written by a man, Albert Camus,

    who denied the legitimacy

    of

    anger and

    moral indignation by denying the very

    possibility of

    a

    moral community in our

    time. The anger expressed in our world,

    he said, is nothing but hypocrisy.”28This

    grotesque distortion of Camus’ ideas is

    based, not on “Reflections” but on The

    Stranger,

    a

    novel which Berns views as

    expressing unequivocally thesame ideas

    as Camus’ essay published fifteen years

    later. To be sure, the novel and essay

    express some

    of

    the same ideas, but

    Berns either d oes not know or chooses

    to ignore that Camus ViewedTheStranger

    as a very limited and even anomalous

    part

    of

    his total work-a study

    of

    one

    distinctive character ,his distinctive sen-

    sibility and reactions to an accidental

    series

    of

    events pulling him into crime

    and punishment. Others of Camus’s

    works, including “Reflections,”explictly

    or implicitly repudiated the nihilistic

    implications of his early novel.

    Berns

    is

    especially equivocal in using

    TheStrangerto gloss th e following quotes

    from “Reflections”:

    Modern ge 3

    77

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    8/12

    “Our civilization has lost the only values

    that, in a certain way,

    can

    justify that

    penalty

    [

    the existenceof] a truth or prin-

    ciple that is superior to man.” [Berns’

    ellipsis and brackets.] There is n o basis

    for friendship and

    no

    moral law; there-

    fore, n o one, not even a murderer, can

    violate the terms of friendship or break

    that law; a n d there is no basis for the

    anger that we express when someone

    breaks that law. The only thing we share

    as men,

    t h e

    only thing that connects us

    one to another, is a “solidarity against

    death,”

    and a

    judgment of capital

    punish-

    ment “upsets” that solidarity. The pur-

    pose

    of

    human life is to stay alive.29

    The preceding words may

    be

    an accu-

    rate enough account of The Stranger, but

    surely not of “Reflections” or of Camus’

    work as a whole. (Even The Stranger

    does not imply that staying alive at an y

    cost is all-important; Meursault could

    avoid execution by lying about the cir-

    cumstances of th e murder he commit-

    ted, but he refuses to.) On the contrary,

    friendship and fraternal solidarity are

    among the most positivevalues through-

    out Camus. He sees this precious soli-

    darity constantly menaced both by th e

    absurdity of life’s physical constraints

    and t he absurdity of society’s arbitrary

    conventions-preeminently the power

    of the s ta te to suppress individual lives

    through war and capital punishment. By

    temperament a solitary individual and

    political anarchist, Camus nevertheless

    emphasized the paradox that t he meta-

    physical and social isolation of each in-

    dividual creates

    a

    bond between her or

    him and everyother individual;as he put

    it in Lyrical and Critical Essays, “Soli-

    tudes unite those society

    separate^. ^'

    This bond in turn should lead individu-

    als

    to unite in struggling against social

    forces encroaching on individual liberty,

    and for the establishment

    of

    social con-

    ditions and political policies maximizing

    that liberty. Hence Camus’ own lifelong

    political commitments, including risk-

    ing his life in the Resistance, and his

    writings (such as The Plague, The Rebel,

    and The Just

    Assassins)

    delineating situ-

    ations where sacrificing one’s life

    takes

    moral precedence over staying alive at

    any cost-details that Berns inexcus-

    ably ignores. Finally, in “Reflections”

    Camus makes it clear that murderers

    must be deplored and punished for u p

    setting our “solidarity against death,”

    but that by executing them societydrags

    itself down to the same level a nd -e ve n

    worse-institutionalizes their personal

    failure t o sanctify life.

    Berns’ literary penchant leads him

    even farther astray when he compares

    The Stranger unfavorably with Macbeth,

    prefacing his praise of t he latter with an

    endorsement by Abraham Lincoln,

    “‘NothingequalsMac6efh I t is wonder-

    ful.’

    Macbeth is wonderful because, to

    say nothing more here,

    it

    teaches us the

    awesomeness

    of

    the commandment

    ‘Thou shalt not Berns, however,

    does say more:

    Canwe imagine aworld that does not take

    its revenge

    on

    the man who kills Macduff’s

    wife and children? (Can we imagine the

    play in which Macbeth does not die?) Can

    we imagine a people that does not

    hate

    murderers? (Can

    w e

    imagine a world

    where Meursault is an outsider only be-

    cause he does not

    pretend

    to be outraged

    by murder?) Shakespeare’s

    poetry

    could

    not have been written out of the moral

    sense that the death penalty’s opponents

    insist we ought

    to

    have. Indeed, the issue

    of capital punishment can be said

    to

    turn

    o n whether Shakespeare’s or Camus’ is

    the more telling account of murder

    In Macbefh he majesty of the moral law is

    demonstrated to us... In a similar fash-

    ion,

    the punishments imposed

    by

    the 1e-

    gal order remind us of the reign of

    the

    moral order;

    not

    only do they remind

    u s

    of it,

    but by

    enforcing its prescriptions,

    they enhance the dignity

    of

    the legal or-

    der in the eyes of moral men, in the eyes

    of

    those decent citizens who cry out for

    ”gods who will avenge in ju~t ice. ”~~

    378

    Fall 996

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    9/12

    Now, even if we grant it to Berns that

    Macbeth

    presents a more cathartic a p

    peal to our sense of justice than The

    Stranger,

    we must also note the ways he

    has stacked the deck in this comparison.

    To begin with, Macbeth is a butcherous

    political tyrant, whereas Meursault is an

    ordinary man who stumbles inadvert-

    ently into committing a single act of

    manslaughter. (Granted, he fails to ex-

    press remorse or compassion for his

    victim, and in this respect, the book’s

    morality is indeed open to being criti-

    cized, as Camus himself later acknowl-

    edged.)

    A

    much fairer and more obvious

    point of comparison could have been

    made with two of Camus’ plays, Caligula,

    in which a Macbeth-like tyrant is like-

    wise struck down by his oppressed sub-

    jects, or The Jus t Assassins n which a

    Russian revolutionary of 1905 voluntar-

    ily gives up his

    life

    as compensation for

    his assassination of the Grand Duke.

    Berns’s comparison cavalierly disre-

    gards several major differences in the

    teleological and aesthet ic beliefs of

    Shakespeare’s time versus Camus’. Mod-

    ernliteraryrealism and naturalism, from

    which The Stranger derives, were pre-

    cisely reactions against earlier ages of

    belief in “gods who will avenge injus-

    tice.” We may still thrill today to the

    poetic justice in Macbeth, but we know

    that in real

    life,

    Macbeth would be just as

    likely to kill Macduff as the reverse.

    Berns’s appeal t o “the reign of the moral

    order,” ike Molnar’s, seems quite plain-

    tive in a wholly pragmatic, materialistic

    modern moral order engineered largely

    by and in the interests of the multina-

    tional corporations, their governmental

    agents, and assorted lobbyists, law firms,

    and public relations agents who are cur-

    rently defined as conservatives.

    nd

    that

    “awesome” legal or de r invoked by

    Berns-administered in America largely

    through patronage and disabled ever

    further through Reaganomic budget

    cuts-is the same one denounced as

    “big government” by Berns’s supply-side

    economist colleagues at the American

    Enterprise Institute.

    On a more mundane level, in Macbeth

    justiceis administeredneither bythegods

    nor by the state,but by Macduff. Is Berns

    advocating that we deal with criminals by

    giving them over to hand-tehand com-

    bat, perhaps with the survivors of their

    victims? Vigilante justice may seem a p

    pealingin oursafeaesthetic distance from

    the Shakespearean stage (or from the

    films of a Charles Bronson and a Clint

    Eastwood), but is Berns, or Molnar, really

    prepared to turn over today’s legal pro-

    cess toanyonewho declares himself judge,

    jury, and executioner? Berns’s and

    Molnar’s unqualified appeals to anger and

    moral indignation against criminals disre-

    gard an elementary point agreed on by

    most political philosophers in modern

    constitutional democracies; as Camus

    puts

    it

    in “Reflections,” f murder is in the

    nature of man, the law is not intended to

    imitate or reproduce that nature. It is

    intended to correct it. Now, retaliation

    does no more than ratify and confer the

    status of alaw on apure impulse of nature.

    We have all known that impulse, often to

    our shame, and we know its power, for it

    comes down to us from the primitive

    Once again in this passage, as through-

    out his essay, Camus

    is

    not categorically

    opposing the impulse to retaliation, but

    he is emphasizing the need for limiting

    that principle at the point where it be-

    comes morally and socially

    d6rnesur6

    or

    counterproductive, as in the example he

    gives of Arab countries cutting off the

    hands of robbers. Neither Molnar nor

    Berns really comes to terms with Camus,

    because their absolutistic arguments

    assume tha t his are equally absolutistic

    (or absolutely relativistic), without ever

    recognizing that t he core

    of

    his philoso-

    phy in “Reflections”and elsewhere is its

    classical opposition of measure and lim-

    its to both absolutism and relativism.

    Modem Age

    3

    79

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    10/12

    1. Resistance, Rebellion, and Death, translated by

    Justin O’Brien New York, 1960).

    2.

    Ibid., 171.3. For

    Capital Punishment: Crime and the Morality of the

    Death Penalty New York, 1979). 4. “On Camus and

    Capital Punishment,” 301.5.

    Ibid.

    99. 6. Ibid., 300.

    7 . d em . 8 Ibid., 302. 9 “Reflections on th e Guillo-

    tine,”

    222 .

    IO

    Ib id ., 210.11. Ibid. , 217.12.Ibid., 230.13.

    “CamusandCapitalPunishment ”302.14.Ibid. 01-

    302.15.Ibid.,304-305.16. “Reflectionson the Guillo-

    tine,” 212.17.“Camusandcapital Punishment,”301.

    18. The Stranger, translated by Stuart Gilbert [New

    York, 1946), 137-138.19.“Camus andcapi tal Punish-

    ment,”305 .20 . “Reflections on the Guillotine,”217.

    21 . “Camus and Capital Punishment,” 299 .22 .

    “Re-

    flections on the Guillotine,”227-228.23.“For Capital

    Punishment,”15 .24 . The MurderersAm ong Us: The

    Simon Wiesenthal Memoirs, ed. and with introduc-

    toryprofile by Joseph Wechsberg NewYork, 1 9 6 9 ,

    8.25.Ibid . .9.26.Idem. 27. Ibid.. 261 .28.“ForCapital

    Punishment,”16.29. Ibid., 17.30. Lyrical an d Critical

    Essays, trans. by Ellen Conroy Kennedy New York,

    1968), 12.31.“For Capital Punishment,” 17.32. Idem .

    33. “Reflections on the Guillotine.”198.

    A

    Reply

    to

    “Camus

    and

    His Critics on Capital Pun ishment”

    IN THE INTERVENING

    YEARS thirty-eight, to be

    exact, an entire generation, the issue

    discussed inModemAge Summer 1958)

    has remained as valid and alive

    as

    it was

    then-and so will it remain as long

    as

    there are communities with a sense of

    identity, on the one hand, and breakers

    of law, on the other. History s not an

    evolutionary science; the problems tha t

    the passage of time raises are, while

    different in style and anecdotal illustra-

    tion, identical across civilizational peri-

    ods. Crime invites punishment, and irre-

    versible crime invites what the French

    call

    le chBtiment supreme.

    Albert Camus, and in his wake Profes-

    sor Donald Lazere, discuss the issue

    from the wrong angle. Although in Camus’

    time Western opinion had not yet plunged

    into the mire of a tear-jerking humani-

    tarianism, his American commentator’s

    thesis benefits by the currently raging

    universal hypocrisy: capital punishment

    s

    declared an absolute evil. But the

    butchering of innocents in abortion clin-

    ics has become a woman’s right; Pol

    Pot’s massacres ar e said t o be redeemed

    by pure intentions; and for certain Meth-

    odist churches every illegal immigrant

    is

    Jesus Christ in person. No wonder we

    are confused. This confusion s also at

    th e root of the Camus/Lazere thesis. The

    matter in question is not whether, as

    Camus claims, a human being can

    be

    an

    “absolute judge” because he

    s

    “abso-

    lutely innocent”; nor

    is

    it an issue of

    “human solidarity against death” ill-fit-

    ting Camusian phrases quoted by

    Lazere).At issue isa society’s anation’s,

    a

    state’s, a tribe’s) duty to restore a

    certain moral balance when it is su-

    premely upset. It is necessary to restore

    th is equilibrium against external aggres-

    sion when the community

    s

    attacked in

    its vital identity and interests-the case

    of Bosnia serves as a classic example-

    and to restore it internally when in the

    protected domestic area a

    life

    is taken.

    So far, then, the justification of just wars

    and capital punishment.

    The difficulty of arguing against

    Camus/Lazere

    s

    that they absolutize

    man, not to say divinize him, aided as

    they are in this endeavor by the contem-

    porary humanitarian verbiage. Thus they

    come to decide the issue of capital pun-

    ishment according to two opposing a p

    plications of the same standard: the vic-

    38

    all 1996

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    11/12

    tim of assassination no longer benefits

    by his sacrednessas a person, yet Camus

    insists on the continued sacredness

    of

    the assassin. Former ages knew nothing

    of

    this strange and obscene phenom-

    enon; they sentenced a sacrilegious per-

    son to death, whether he killed a person

    or de-sacralized a holy object. The no-

    tion still survives in the re-sacralization

    of churches after the misuse of their

    premises, for example, by communist

    regimes which used churches for stables,

    athletic clubs, or atheistic exhibits.

    The transfer of th e victim’s sacred-

    ness

    as

    a person to the murderer-the

    Camusian logic-protects th e la tter

    against the former’s fate. According to

    this view, the judge

    is

    not permitted to

    impose capital punishment to de-

    sacralize the criminal); the judge, that is,

    the society which he represents, and the

    killer become equal parties. More: as a

    spokesman for “institutionalized vio-

    lence,” the judge

    is

    regarded

    as a

    greater

    criminal than the taker

    of

    life. In this

    perspective, the modern one, light sen-

    tencing becomes a branch of socia l

    therapy administered by the udge/thera-

    pist to the assassin/patient.

    Let us note, however, that society

    is

    neither achurch nor a hospital. The task

    of these two institutions s to help save

    souls and to help cure bodies. Society

    s

    a

    network of reciprocal actions wherein

    those who break the rules must pay the

    penalty; but society also participates in

    the moral order, and is ennobled in pro-

    portion as it defends that order. Thus

    capital punishment

    is

    not merely a de-

    terrent against the highest law-break-

    ing, it

    is

    more importantly a restorative

    act of the moral order. It is a misplaced

    argument to say that sentencing one to

    life

    imprisonment or hard labor would

    be an adequate alternative. citizen not

    only fears the killer, he

    s

    also aware that

    society’s moral identity and integrity

    suffer when the supreme crime is not

    irrevocably compensated for.

    What does it mean, then, that “com-

    passion does not exclude punishment,

    but it suspends the final condemnation”?

    Either society punishes according to the

    gravity and monstrosity of the crime, or

    it hides behind judicial agnosticism,

    claiming it does not know how to distin-

    guish between one crime and another.

    With this step, however, society muti-

    lates itself, cutting off one of its func-

    tions. Judicial agnosticism, by the way,

    is

    again manifest when the courts pre-

    tend ignorance as to whether a foetus is

    alive or not a t conception.

    There

    s

    no question that Camus was

    an eminently decent individual, “a good

    man,” and that his plea against capital

    punishment was motivated by a sense

    of-here misplaced-charity.

    I

    still re-

    tain a letter from him, dated October

    1952

    in which he severely criticizes Jean-

    Pau Sa r t r

    e’s

    “merc 1es

    s

    rigor

    s

    m”

    jans6nisrne impitoyable)

    and asks for

    th e recognition

    of

    “immediately obvious

    values” in our life. Yet, as also seen in his

    novel,

    TheStranger,

    Camus confuses pri-

    vatevir tues and public imperatives; thus

    he justified in advance the demagogues

    who use the first when t he criminal

    be-

    longs to their own camp, and the second

    when he

    s

    an adversary. This was illus-

    trated by Simone de Beauvoir when she

    not only wanted t o pardon the common-

    law criminal his misdeeds are bour-

    geois society’s responsibility), but also

    called for the destruction of the political

    opponent.

    While in our time the concept

    of

    pun-

    ishment yields to that of therapy, we

    should not be surprised that criminol-

    ogy and the practice of tribunals also

    undergo vast changes. The foundation

    of law used to be God and nature, both

    demoted by modern philosophy. To

    make a long legal story short, let us

    observe that in the Kantian-Fichtean

    universe, underlined both by the French

    Revolution and, less blatantly, by the

    American Revolution, the foundation of

    Modern

    ge

    38

  • 8/17/2019 lmCamus and His Critics on Capital Punishment

    12/12

    law became man himself. Building on the

    Kantian precedent, Hans Kelsen in this

    century eliminated natural law, arguing

    that it is based on fictional norms, and

    that positive law alone

    s

    valid because

    it is founded on ad-hocsociological cur-

    rents and interests. In this view, Soviet

    law was as valid because internally co-

    herent) as any other legal system

    founded on circumstances and prece-

    dents.

    In recent years, however, the concept

    of man as the subject of law has been

    changing. Human rights have become

    exclusive

    of all

    others: family, nation,

    God. But more was to come. The horizon

    of human rights is no longer circum-

    scribed bythe individual’s concretesitu-

    ation-his membership in a nation, a

    religion, a class, a profession-since the

    human person himself is held to

    be

    inde-

    terminate and tending to transcend all

    limits. In present legal thinking, man’s

    humanity consists in his capacity to tear

    himself out

    of

    any definition. Denying

    him his right to turn into anything to

    choose his lifestyle or his sexual orienta-

    tion) s condemning him to remain what

    he is and forbidding him to become what

    his potentialityand choices suggest. The

    unjust law is the one which confines the

    individual within a nation, a race, a sex,

    or a social function. In contrast , just law

    assigns no limits to free growth.

    We find in this recent evolution the

    influence of philosophy from Kant to

    Nietzsche to Sartre: the human being

    builds himself independently of other

    factors tradition, law, moral norms) and

    chooses an existence which should by

    no means rigidify as a destiny. There

    s

    no human nature, no divine guidance, no

    social limitation. Man

    s

    free, and as

    noted earlier, auto-divinized. Obviously

    the law is subordinate to him, and he

    owes it nothing. It is not murder but

    capital punishment that has become the

    absolute criminal act.

    Thomas Molnar