maguire, henry (ed) - byzantine magic

Upload: sanja-pajic

Post on 10-Feb-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    1/229

    This is an extract from:

    Byzantine Magic

    1995 Dumbarton Oaks

    Trustees for Harvard University

    Washington, D.C.

    Printed in the United States of America

    published by

    Dumbarton Oaks Research Library and Collection

    Washington, D.C.

    www.doaks.org/etexts.html

    edited by Henry Maguire

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    2/229

    ByzantineMagic

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    3/229

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    4/229

    Byzantine Magic

    Edited byHenryMaguire

    Dumbarton OaksResearch Library andCollection

    Washington,D.C.

    Distributed by Harvard University Press

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    5/229

    Copyright 1995 by DumbartonOaks

    TrusteesforHarvardUniversity,Washington, D.C.

    All rights reserved

    Printed in the UnitedStates of America

    LibraryofCongress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Byzantine magic/editedby Henry Maguire.

    p. cm.

    Papers originally delivered at a colloquium held Feb.27 28,

    1993, at DumbartonOaks, Washington, D.C.

    Includes bibliographical references andindex.

    ISBN 0-88402-230-71 . MagicByzantine EmpireHistoryCongresses. 2.MagicReligious

    aspectsChristianityHistoryCongresses. I. Maguire.Henry, 1943

    BF1593.B98 1995

    133.4309495dc2O 94-33501

    CIP

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    6/229

    Contents

    Preface vii

    Introduction

    Henry Maguire 1

    1 The Fathersofthe Church and the EvilEye

    MatthewW.Dickie 9

    2 The Archaeological Context ofMagic in the Early Byzantine Period

    James Russell 35

    3 Magic and the ChristianImage

    Henry Maguire 51

    4 Holy and Unholy Miracle Workers

    Alexander Kazhdan 73

    5 Reactions ofTwo Byzantine Intellectuals to the Theory

    and PracticeofMagic: Michael Psellos and MichaelItalikosJohn Duffy 83

    6 Balsamon onMagic: FromRoman Secular Law to

    ByzantineCanon Law

    Marie Theres Fgen 99

    7 AContribution to the Study of Palaeologan Magic

    RichardP . H.Greenfield 1 17

    8 Magic in Slavia Orthodoxa:TheWritten Tradition

    Robert Mathiesen 1 5 5

    v

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    7/229

    vi Contents

    Abbreviations 179

    Index 1 8 3

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    8/229

    Preface

    The papers in this book were originally delivered at a colloquium that took

    place atDumbarton OaksFebruary 27 28, 1993. I amgratefulto thescholars

    whoagreed to speak at the colloquium and whosubmittedtheir texts for publi-

    cation here. I would also like to thankthe members of the audience who en-

    gagedin lively and interesting discussion.In particular,I amgrateful to Stanley

    Tambiah,who contributed the perspectives of asocialanthropologist in a most

    illuminatingwayand helped us toavoid the pitfalls of Byzantine parochialism.

    Finally, thanks are due to HedySchiller,w hohelpedboth toorganizethemeet-

    ing and to prepare the manuscript for publication, and to thestaffof theDum-

    barton OaksPublications Office, who saw the bookthroughthepress.

    Henry Maguire

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    9/229

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    10/229

    Introduction

    HENRY MAGUIRE

    Inrecent years considerableattentionhas been given to magic in thesocietiesofancient Greece and Rome, lateantiquity, and the medieval West.Muchless

    attention,however, has been given to the phenomenon ofmagic in eastem

    Christendom during the medievalperiod. The papers in thisvolume, written

    by specialists in a wide range ofdisciplines, explore the parameters and sig-

    mficance ofmagic in Byzantine society from the fourth century to the empires

    fall. Theauthors address a wide variety of questions, some ofwhich arecom-

    mon to allhistorical research into magic andsome ofwhich are peculiar to the

    Byzantine context.

    The first question to which this book seeks an answer is the relative im-

    portanceofmagic inmedievalByzantium. Anyone who has looked atByzan-

    tine texts, both highbrow andlowbrow, will havebeen struck by the periodic

    mention of magical or semi-magical practices. There is,for example,thestory

    in theChronographyof Michael Psellos, discussed herebyJohn Duffy (Chap-

    ter 5), which describeshowEmpressZoe had madeforherself a private image

    of Christ that forecast the future by changingcolor. Orthere is the talein theLife of IreneofChrysobalanton, referred to by Alexander Kazhdan (Chapter

    4), about the lead idols ofa nun and her suitor with which love magic had

    been worked; these effigies were miraculously retrieved from a magician in

    Cappadocia through the agency ofSt. Anastasia and St. Basil and given to

    Irenea s shew as at prayer in the chapel ofherconvent inConstantinople. Are

    such stories to be dismissed merely as quaint footnotes to the history ofByzan-

    tium, ordo they represent something moreimportant and more fundamental,

    which historians need to understandin order to understandByzantine civiliza-

    tion as a whole?

    A second question, which crops up very often in the study of Byzantine

    culture, is the question ofcontinuity, ofsurvival and revival.To what extent

    1

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    11/229

    2 Henry Maguire

    wasmagican aspect of the classicalworld that survivedunchanged inByzan-

    tium, a part ofitsantique legacy? The problem is whether the medievalByzan-

    tines innovated in the area of the occult as they undoubtedly did in the otherarts.There isalsothe question ofthe afterlife of Byzantine magic. How fardid

    Byzantium transmit magic, along with its other leaming, to areas under its

    cultural influence, sucha s the Slavic lands?

    Related to these questions is the problem of the eastem provinces, espe-

    cially Egypt, which in late antiquity hadbeen the homelandofso muchmagi-

    cal lore and paraphernalia. What effect did the lossof the eastern provinces in

    theseventhcentury haveonthe laterpractice ofmagicin Byzantium?Wasthe

    importance of magic in the Byzantine Empire thereby reduced, or was it

    changed?

    Ifmagic didsurvivefrom lateantiquity intothe medievalperiod, there is

    the question of where and in what forms it survived.Magic neededbothpro-

    viders and consumers; accusations of magic needed both accusers andac-

    cused. The historian seeks to know what is revealed about the social context

    of magic by the Byzantine law codes, leamedliterature, the more popular

    saints lives, and material culture itself. What was the character ofmedievallegislationagainstmagic as opposed to that of the late Roman period?Did the

    medieval intellectuals of Byzantium consider magic to be merely an exercise

    in antiquarianism or a living phenomenon? What light is shed by surviving

    objects, as opposed totexts,onthe continuation or decline ofmagical practices

    andbeliefs? Does the evidence of material culture fit in with the evidence from

    thetexts?

    Finally, there is the most fundamental question, that of the Byzantine

    definitions of magic. How was sorcery defined by the church and by the secularauthorities?How did a Byzantine distinguish between supernatural phenom-

    ena that were holy andthose that were demonic,between the miracle and the

    magic trick, between the nocturnal visitations of saints and ofdemons, be-

    tweenthe pagan amulets and the portable relics from Christian shrines? In the

    realm of the visual arts, there was the question of which uses of art couldbe

    defined as orthodox and which were unacceptable. In what circumstances

    could theuse of Christianimages be termed magical?Although the authors of this book address a broad range ofquestions,

    and their conclusions are varied, certain themes emerge clearly from all of

    the contributions and can usefully be summarized here. Concerning the most

    fundamental problem, that ofdefinition, one clear conclusion is the needto

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    12/229

    Introduction 3

    make adistinction between what we might wish to callmagican external

    definitionand what the Byzantines, at any place or time in their history,

    might call magican internal definition. From anexternal viewpoint magicand miracles may looksimilar, as might pagan amulets and Christiantokens,

    but from an internalviewpoint they were very different. The modern anthro-

    pologist who attemptsan external definition of magic that will hold good for

    all societieswill have to be consistent, but, as AlexanderKazhdan shows, we

    should notexpect consistency ofthe Byzantines when they made their internal

    definitions. The distinctions between good and bad miracles were for them

    areas of ambiguity andconflict, which might have important social implica-

    tions. This meant that the psychologicalbenefits of theByzantines beliefinmiracles were mixed. With the hope for holy miracles came the dread of

    sorcery.

    Second, there can be nodoubt, in the light of the evidence presented here,

    that the Byzantines themselvesfeltthat magicw as asignificantfactor in their

    society. The richtextualmaterialdiscussed byRichard Greenfield (Chapter7 )

    demonstratesthat magicwas still flourishing,at least in the minds ofcontem-

    poraries,during the last phase of the Byzantine Empire. Magic, then, was a

    part of the Palaeologan Renaissance, but was it an unchanging legacy from

    lateantiquity? The answer to this question, as in other aspects of Byzantine

    culture, is mixed.Matthew Dickie (Chapter 1 ) describes howtheearly church

    fathers, by keeping distinct the powers ofhumanand of supernatural agencies,

    were able to combine a continued beliefin theevil eye with orthodox Chris-

    tianity. In theory,itw asthe devil who caused the harm and notjealous humans,

    although some maintained that the devilmightstill use the envious for hisevil

    purposes. Thebeliefin the powers ofenvy and the evil eyecertainly survivedthrough the Byzantine period and beyond. On the other hand, while there was

    a measure ofcontinuity, it can alsobesaidthatinmany important respects the

    Byzantinessucceeded in changing the status of magic in theirsociety.

    The changed position of magic can be seen in both material culture and

    writtendocuments. In the discussion of material culture,it is useful to make a

    distinction between artifacts that were marked with non-Christian devices,

    such as ring-signs and the names ofpagan deities, and those marked with

    Christian signs or images, such as crosses and portraits of the saints, In the

    case of thefirst class of objects,those with non-Christian devices, the issues

    were more clear-cut, In the case of objects of the second class, those with

    Christian devices, the issues were more ambiguous and complex. As James

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    13/229

    4 HenryMaguire

    Russellshowsfrom archaeological evidence(Chapter2), and John Duffyfrom

    literary sources, amulets of various kinds marked with essentially non-

    Christian signs were relatively widespread in the early Byzantine period.Though many churchmen certainly disapproved ofthese objects, the authori-

    ties were unable to prevent their use. St. John Chrysostom, for example, in-

    veighed against those who used charms and amulets and who made chains

    around their heads and feet withcoins ofAlexander ofMacedon. But two

    centurieslaterpeople were still wearing tunics decoratedwithrepeatedmedal-

    lions depicting Alexander as a potentrider(Chapter 3, Fig. 14). Furthermore,

    as Russell relates, one house at Anemurium yieldedapierced coinofMarcus

    Aurelius or Lucius Veins that hadbeen worn, presumably as a charm, by an

    inhabitant ofthatcity as late as the seventhcentury.But thesituationseemsto

    have changed aftericonoclasm. With some exceptions, such as the Chnoubis/

    Medusaamuletsthat were considered to help during pregnancy andin child-

    birth, the non-Christian amulets tended to disappear from the material culture

    of the latercenturies of Byzantium, to be replaced by portable crossesand

    jewelry displaying Christian images or containing relics. Theearly Byzantine

    site at Anemurium harbored a silver lamella (a thin sheet ofmetal)inscribedwith a magicalcharm (Chapter 2, Fig. 10), but we have little archaeological

    evidence ofthiskindfrom the medieval period ofByzantium. The evidenceof

    archaeology isconfirmedby the writtentexts. John Duffy showshow theatti-

    tude ofAlexanderofTralles, a doctor ofthe sixth century,contrasted with that

    ofthe eleventh-and twelfth-century intellectuals Psellos and Michael Italikos.

    AlexanderofTralles was prepared to prescribeamulets for his wealthier pa-

    tients whoobjected to the indignities of physical cures. Wemay infer thatin

    his day suchamuletswereemployed quiteopenly,and notonly by the poor, an

    inference that is supported by the archaeological record from Anemurium. Six

    centuries later, however, Michael Italikos gave only a hint that sucha cure

    might be ventured.

    Wecan conclude, then, that the types ofdevice that the church fathersof

    the fourth century had found most offensive,the amulets withsatanic charac-

    ters such as ring-signs, were purged from the overt material culture inthe later

    medieval period, to be replaced by more acceptable objects, such as crosses,relics, and intercessory iconsofthe saints. At early Byzantine Anemurium the

    number of excavated pendant crosses was smaller than that of the non-

    Christian apotropaic objects. But after iconoclasm, many ofthe functions that

    had previously been performedby profaneamuletswere performed by objects

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    14/229

    Introduction 5

    ofexplicitly Christian character. This change was encouraged by the church

    authorities themselves. As Matthew Dickieshows, in the fourth century John

    Chrysostomrecommends that infants be protected from envy by the sign ofthe cross rather than bymagical signs,while at the end ofthe Byzantineperiod

    Joseph Bryennios,in a passage cited by Richard Greenfleld, recommends the

    wearing ofthe cross or the Virgins image insteadofprofane amulets.

    The church, therefore, wassuccessfulin marginalizing thenon-Christian

    magical remedies, but itcouldnot eliminate them altogether; theapparatusof

    magic respondedto opposition by becoming more occult. People in the medi-

    evalcenturies ofByzantium wereless likely to wear amuletsofmetal or stone

    inscribed with heathen signs and symbols, but, as Richard Greenfield points

    out, m the Palaeologan period we still hear of amulets written on pieces of

    paper or parchment. They are mentioned, for example, in the proceedingsof

    trials before the patriarchal court.Itmay be surmised that these scraps werea

    safer medium for theinscribingofforbidden texts andsigns, since they could

    bemore easily manufactured and destroyedthanamuletsinmore durable ma-

    terials.Naturally, noneofthe perishable paper amulets has survived, though

    we do possess a number ofmagic books from the late Byzantine and post-Byzantine period, which are also discussed byGreenfleld.

    The question ofthe magical useofChristian images is much morecorn-

    plicated andisdealt with in more detail in Chapter 3, Magicand the Christian

    Image. In theearly period many ecclesiastical authoritieshad strong reserva-

    tions about theprivate, unofficial useofChristian signs and images, and about

    their roles in practices and beliefsystems that were not regnlated bythe church.

    Similar reservations are revealed by the passage from John Chrysostom, cited

    by Marie Theres Fgen, concerning the drunken andfoolishold womenwho

    falsely make Christian incantations, misusing the name ofGod (Chapter 6).

    Suspicions about the misuse ofChristian images by private individuals cer-

    tainly addedfuelto the arguments made by the opponentsofChristian icons.

    In this case, also, the church after iconoclasm was able to exert a muchstronger

    control, In thelatercenturiesofByzantium, boththe theory and the conditions

    ofuse ofChristianimageswere much more closely regulated, with results that

    were visible in the formsofthe images themselves. Christian icons becameless ambiguous and thus less suspect. Nevertheless, we still encounter in-

    stances of the magical use ofChristian images and symbols in the post-

    iconoclastic period, oneofthe most interesting being letter 33 ofMichael Ital-

    ikos, which isreferred to by John DuffyThis letter was written toaccompany

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    15/229

    6 Henry Maguire

    the gift of a gold coin, which MichaelItalikos claims was that of Constantine

    I. As described by Italikos, the piece was mounted to be worn as a pectoral

    and bore onone side the imprint ofConstantine, the most imperial, the mostpious, and the best ofemperors, together with Helena, andon the other side

    an image of Christ in Roman guise.The design of the piece also incorporated

    a cross, and itssurroundinginscription was in Latin characters. Italikosfurther

    described the coina s an imperial nomisma investedwithan ineffable power,

    which was effective against all evils but particularly against disease. Al-

    though we may doubt whether the coin seen by the medieval writer really

    showedConstantine and Helena, itwasclearly ancient,and it is clear that Ital-

    ikos actively believed in its supernatural powers. He said explicitly that the

    powers came notsimply from the crossbutfrom the coinitself. The letter of

    MichaelItalikos, therefore, brings us once again to that unstable border where

    Christian content shaded into magic, even while it shows us the continuity

    thatunderlies change. Constantine has replacedAlexander, but the medium of

    transmission ofpower,thecoin, remains the same.

    Turning from material culture to texts, we find that important changes

    occurred in the treatment of magic by Byzantinelegislators, as is revealed inthe paper by Marie Theres Fgen. She shows how the attacks on magic by

    secular authorities becameless harsh andless crude thanthey hadbeen in the

    imperial legislation of the fourth century;by the twelfth century the problem

    of illicit contacts with thesupernaturalw asthe province ofreligious discipline.

    Byzantine canon law, as exemplifiedby the Council in Trullo of 691/92 and

    Balsamons twelfth-centurycommentary, provided greater precision indefining

    thepractitioners of magic than had the late antique imperiallegislation, while

    thescale of punishments becameless draconian.To use her term, magic, while

    not permitted, was in a way domesticated in the medieval centuries ofBy-

    zantium. In part this change came about because magic hadbeen brought into

    a single unified system ofrelationshipsbetween human beings andthe super-

    natural.In this system therewas ultimate divinejustice,whateverthe demons

    might be allowed to get away with in the interim. Any attempts to control

    demons through magic could bring only short-term advantages;inthe end they

    would fail. So magic found a place in later Byzantine culture, but it was adefined place. In the late antique periodthere was more open-endedcompeti-

    tion between the different supernatural forces that viedfor peoples attention,

    and hence moreconflict.

    The last paper in this volume (Chapter8 ) deals with the little-explored

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    16/229

    Introduction 7

    topic of the reach of Byzantine magic intoSlavic culture.Just as Byzantium

    gaveorthodox Christianity to the Slays, so too it gavemuch that was unortho-

    dox, includingexpertise in magic. As Robert Mathiesen shows, thecontribu-tionofByzantiumto thewrittencorpusof magical or semi-magicaltexts trans-

    lated into Church Slavonic was large and varied. In addition, Byzantium

    influenced the material culture of Slavic magic,as it did the art oforthodox

    churches. The most spectacular example of this influence is the gold Medusa

    amulet fromCernigov with its inscriptions in both Greek and Slavonic. Inits

    early centuries Byzantiumhad borrowedmuch of its magical lore from the

    Near East, especially fromEgypt; in its latercenturies ittransmitted a part of

    thislegacy to theSlays.

    The authors of thisvolume are in a sense pioneerswho have entered the

    relatively uncharted territory of magic in the Byzantine middleages. Now that

    they haveprovided signposts, indicatingthe scope of magic, its forms, and its

    functioning in Byzantine society,other areas of research have come intoview.

    The most intriguing of these unexplored areas is comparative studies:how did

    magic inByzantiumdiffer from magic in western Europe during the same

    period, and why? Why were there virtually no witches in the East, but onlyfoolish old women? How does magic in the Islamic world relate to early

    Byzantine practices? What were the connections betweenthe magical learning

    ofthe Italian Renaissance and the Byzantine tradition? Such questions must

    await furtherinvestigationby the practitioners of magicalscholarship.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    17/229

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    18/229

    This is an extract from:

    Byzantine Magic

    1995 Dumbarton Oaks

    Trustees for Harvard University

    Washington, D.C.

    Printed in the United States of America

    published by

    Dumbarton Oaks Research Library and Collection

    Washington, D.C.

    www.doaks.org/etexts.html

    edited by Henry Maguire

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    19/229

    1

    TheFathers ofthe Church and the Evil Eye

    MATTHEW W . DICKIE

    The purpose of this paper is to demonstratehow difficult even the most highly

    educated and sophisticated Christians of the late fourth andearlyfifthcenturies

    found it to rid themselves of the idea that envy lends a malign power to mens

    eyes. The idea at issue is that the eyes ofenvious men are able, unaided, to

    inflict injury at adistance. This isthe beliefcalled theevil eye by speakers

    of English and other modem European languages, thoughthat significantly is

    not the way in which most men in pagan and Christian antiquitywould havereferred to it . The difficulty that suchfathers of the church asBasil, Jerome,

    and JohnChrysostomhad with freeing themselvesfromthe idea issome indi-

    cation ofhow deep-seated it must have been in the generalpopulation.

    I shallalso try to show that thesechurch fathers, who do attackbeliefin

    theevil eye,address only oneaspectof a much larger constellation ofbeliefs.

    They leave unquestioned the assumption that thereare envious supernatural

    forces out there eager todestroyprosperity, virtue, and beauty. Theirfailure to

    deal with this largerissue is a further indication ofjusthow much a part ofmens mental make-up must have been the conviction that life was beset by

    unseen envious forces. We see evidenceofthat fear in themany amulets that

    survive from thisperiod. It is important to bear in mind that the fear reflected

    in theseobjects is notdirected specifically at the evil eyeas thefathers of the

    church construe it but at a much widerspectrum ofdangers. In the case of

    Basil and JohnChrysostom, and perhaps to a lesser extent Jerome, thereis a

    further factor that has affected their thinking aboutthe evil eye: theinfluence

    of pagan philosophy has made them concentrate theirattention on aseverely

    restricted conception of theevil eye to theexclusion of other related beliefs.

    The fathers of the church have no reservations about condemning all

    forms ofmagic-working, in which categorythey certainly included the casting

    9

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    20/229

    10 Matthew W. Dickie

    of theevil eye.1 Althoughthey are unanimous andconsistent in theircondem-

    nation ofmagic-working, they waveron the question of whether there isany-

    thing to i t .2 Theycondemn magicians as frauds andcharlatans, but sometimes

    speak of them as though they posed a real threat. They haveno doubt that

    magic is the devils work, but they are not at all certain whetherthe demonic

    forces magicians enlist toaid themdo in fact afford any real help or only create

    theillusion ofchange.3

    Theattitude ofthefathers of the church to magic reflects in partthehostil-

    ity of the Roman civil authorities to magic as a socially disruptive force, in

    part the skepticism found in educated pagancircles about the possibility of a

    mans being able to set aside the laws ofnature, and in part the feeling thatendowing men with more than human abilities is contrary to Christian doc-

    tinne.4Scripture has asurprisingly small part toplay in shapingChristian atti-

    tudes towardmagic.5 How little support the church fathers can find in it for

    their condemnation of magic is apparent in Jeromes palpable delight in his

    commentaryon Galatians at Pauls mentioning sorcery pharmakeia immedi-

    1 Formagicin the NewTestament:DavidE. Aune, Magicin Early Christianity,

    ANRW 11.23.2 (Berlin-New York, 1980) , 1 5 07 57 ; for th e views ofthe ante-Nicenefatherson magic: FrancisC. R . Thee, Julius Africanus and theEarly Christian View of

    Magic (Tlbingen, 1984), 316 448; forOrigen, Chrysostom, and Augustine: N.Brox,

    Magie und Aberglauben an den Anfangen des Christentums, Thierer theologische

    Zeitschrift83 (1974), 15780.2 Ramsay MacMullens assertion (Enemies of the Roman Order [Cambridge,

    Mass., 1964], 3 23 24 note 25) that if the Church thunderedagainst magicbeliefs, thatwasbecause they werewicked, notuntrue, is too extreme andunnuancedandtakes no

    account of the verydifferent positions different fathersadopted.3 On the tendency todeny that humans can perform sorcery andto blame every-

    thing on thedemonic, seePeterBrown,Sorcery, Demons andtheRise ofChristianity,

    in Witchcraft, ConfessionsandAccusations, ed. Mary Douglas(London, 1970), 32.

    4 OnRoman legislation against magic appealed toby Augustinein support ofhisthesis that magic is pernicious and notonly condemnedby Christians, seeDe civitate

    dei, 8.19; in general on Roman legislationon magic, seeMacMullen, Enemies, 12427;

    on thejudicial prosecutionin the 4th century A.D. ofthose who had resortto magic, see

    A.Barb, TheSurvival ofMagicA rts, in The Conflict between Paganism andChris-

    tianity in theFourth Century, ed. A . Momigliano(Oxford, 1963), 10014; John Mat-thews, The RomanEmpire ofAmmianus (London, 1989), 21726.

    5 Magic condemned: Deuteronomy18:1112; Galatians5:20;Didache, 2.2;Aris-

    teides, Apologia, 8.2, 13.8; Justin,Apologia, 1.14.2; Pseudo-Phocylides, 149 ; Oracula

    Sibyllina, 283 85.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    21/229

    Fathers of the Church and the Evil Eye 1 1

    ately afteridolatry amongst the deeds of the flesh (Gal. 5:18): heremarksthat

    we are not to imagine that magical spells and the maleficent artsarenot forbid-

    den in the New Testament;they are forbidden amongstthe deeds of the flesh.The explanation he gives for their being put in thiscategory isthat because of

    the magical arts unfortunate people often fall in loveand become the objects

    oflove.6 The church fathers may havefound condemnations of magichardto

    comeby . Theyare evenless well-placed when it comes to adducing scriptural

    authority for their contention that magicians andsorcerers are impostors and

    charlatans. They are firmly convinced that men cannot alter the course of

    nature but cannotfind chapter andverse tosupport that view.

    The attitude of the fathers of thechurch to theevil eye is a profoundlyambiguous one: they are notpreparedto accept that the eyes ofenvious men

    can on their owninflict harm, but they are willing to concede either that the

    virtuous and the fortunate do have something to fear fromenvious forces or

    that asupernatural forcemay use theeyes ofthe envious tocause harm. This

    is their consideredposition when their mind is fully focused on theissue and

    its implications. When their mind is on somethingelse, they speak of theeyes

    of the envious doingharnn. In essence theycontinue to believe inthe evil eye,

    but qualify the expression of theirbeliefto make it philosophically and theo-logically respectable.

    The position that they take on the evil eye owes a good deal more to

    presuppositions aboutthe nature of man and his capabilities that the church

    fathers share with educated pagans than it does to the authority of the scrip-

    tures. What a church father found incredible about the evil eye was exactly

    whatan educated pagan would have foundincredible. What thefathers leave

    unquestioned is exactly what a paganwould have left unquestioned. They

    share very much the same blind spots. Not only do paganpresuppositions

    shape the attitude of the fathers of the church to the evil eye, but pagan

    philosophical discussion has deeply affected the way in which such fathers

    as Basil and John Chrysostom conceive of it. The limited view that they

    take of the issue is a holdover from learned pagan discussion. The termsof

    debate that Basil and John Chrysostom felt bound by here had been laid

    6 Commentarius in epistulam ad Galatas, PL 26, col. 443: etne forsitanvene-

    ficia, et maleficae artesnon viderentur inNovo prohibitaeT estamento, ipsaequoqueinter carnis opera nominantur. quia saepe magicis artibus, et amare miseris evenit et

    amari.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    22/229

    12 Matthew W. Dickie

    down long before by pagan philosophers. This has meant that one belief

    has been singled out from a largercomplex of beliefs of which it was part

    and discussed in isolation from them. The evil eye, as I shall try to show,is a somewhat artificial construct. Ancient criticism of it is interesting as

    much for what is said about it as for what is not said about the larger body

    of beliefs to which it belongs.

    We must step back for a moment to look more closely atwhat it is that

    weare talking about when we speak of the evil eye in classical antiquity and

    the late Romanworld. Michael Herzfeld has with some reason proposed that

    the termevil e y e should not be used in cross-cultural comparisons, on theground that the term is frequently employed to refer to beliefs that have little

    incommon with each other, althoughhe does think that it has a proper applica-

    tion.7 There are problems with the notion of the evil eye, even within aculture.

    In the case of classical antiquity and ofthelate Romanworld,the term evil eye

    as such is hardly used at all and then only under theinfluence of certainscrip-

    tural passages of uncertainimport.8 The terms mostoften used are,by Greek

    speakers, p hthonosand baskania and,by speakers of Latin, invidia andfasci-

    natio orfascinus. What men fearedunder these headingswas not a single ob-ject with a secure and fixed identity but a complex of objects with shifting

    identities, and identities that coalesce. Very often what they fearedwill have

    been inchoate and will have lacked any realidentity.9The more or less constant

    factor inthis constellation offears wasfear ofenvy: men wereafraid lest their

    good fortune would drawenvy on theirheads. They might fear itwould come

    from their fellow men,demons, thegods, fortune, thefates, and a malign su-

    pernatural powerthey calledsimplyp hthonos or invidia. Their fear will very

    often havehad no clear focus to it and will havebeenno more thananundiffer-entiated sense ofapprehension.Theexplanationsthey gavefor themisfortunes

    that befell them will have beenequallyfluid,and they will sometimeshave put

    down the catastrophe to acombination of forces, for example, envious demons

    7 The Horns of the Mediterraneanist Dilemma, American Ethnologist 1 1

    (1984), 448 50; Closure as Cure: Tropesin theExploration ofBodilyan dSocialDis-

    order, CurrentAnthropology 27 (1986), 108 note 3.8 Itis found in Gregory of Nyssa, Oratiofunebris in Meletium, PG 46,col. 856

    and inJohn Chrysostom, Commentarius in epistulam 1 adCorinthios, PG 61, col. 106.9 1do not, for instance, share Peter Browns confidence (Witchcraft, 32) that the

    identityofthe force apostrophized asInvide on Christian amulets wasalways andun-

    failinglythought to be the devil.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    23/229

    Fathers of the Church and the EvilE ye 13

    working through envious human beings; or again they will have assigned no

    more secure an identity to the cause of their misfortune than that phthonos or

    invidiahad struckthem down.To substantiatethesecontentionsadequatelywould take too much space.

    Two passages, one fromPlatosPhaedo(95b56)and the other from Libanius

    correspondence(Ep. 140 3.1 2), will have to suffice to illustrate respectively

    the undifferentiated nature of fear of baskania and the identification of

    baskania with fortune. When Socrates in Platos Phaedo tells Cebes not to

    speak too boldly, afterCebes has expressed hisconfidence that Socrates will

    have nodifficulty in dealing with thenext topic to be discussed, lest some

    baskania upsetthediscussion they areabout to have,0there does notseemtobe anygoodreason to assign aprecisesource to thethreat. It seems unlikely

    thatit is supposedto emanatefrom any ofthosepresentin Socrates deathcell.

    Noragainis there any warrant for supposing thatit is meant to come from the

    gods, despite thefact thatSocrates immediatelyproceedsto say that thematter

    will be thegods concern(95b7). Furthermore, wehave absolutelyno reason

    to suppose that there is in what Socrates says anyimplied reference to the

    haranful gaze ofsome being. Libanius, on theother hand, declares he knew

    that whenthree young men were praised a baskania would castits gazeon

    them, butgoeson to say that phthonerosdaimon couldnotabidewhatwas said

    aboutthem. baskania in this case does have abaneful gaze,but it is not

    the baskania of anyhuman beingthat is at issue; ifanything, it is that of

    envious fortune.

    In pagan antiquity what is singled outfor rejection is only one smallfacet

    ofthe constellation of beliefs that arise out of the deep-seated conviction that

    good fortune will attract the hostility of envious supernatural forces. Menfound it impossible to accept only that other human beings could, without

    physical contact, do harm from afar, not that other non-human beings and

    forces might out ofenvy do damage, either by casting hate-filled eyes orby

    some other means. This is not to say there would not have been those who

    would not have rejected the whole complex of ideas out ofhandin theory,

    this is what a Stoic or Epicurean would have doneonly that while a man

    10 m e mega lege m e tis em in baskania peritrepse to n logon ton mellontaesesthai

    1 1 ein o ti baskaniatis opsetai tous sous uieis e pephuken oran ekeinetousepainomenous ... oukenegken oun phthonerosdaimon ton peri auton dogon

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    24/229

    14 MatthewW. Dickie

    mighthave difficulty accepting that the interventionofanother human being

    could alternatures course,he would have had a good deal less difficulty with

    the ideathat theinterventionofan envious force or being, if it were other than

    human,was capable ofinterrupting the normal pattern ofevents.

    Some educated men in pagan antiquity, at least fromthe first century of

    ourera,and probably from a much earlierdate, evidently foundthe idea that

    the eyes of envious mencould cast a harmful spell somethingof an embar-

    rassment.Grattius, apoet writingunderAugustus, speaksin his Cynegeticaof

    fear of the maligneye as a false fearbelonging to an earlierage.7 Persius, the

    Roman satirist of the time ofNero, characterizes thegrandmother and aunt

    who take an infantboy from his cradle todaub saliva on his forehead and lips,

    so as to negatethe effectofeyesthatburn,as fearful ofthe divine.13 In speak-

    ing ofeyesthat burn, Persius is referring tothe scorching and withering effect

    that the evil eye was imagined topossess. We should not assume too readily

    that Grattius and Persiushave only theeyesof humanbeings in mind, but we

    may fairly infer that, in speaking respectivelyoffalse fear(falsus metus)and

    fear of thedivine (metuensdivum), they are referring to the stateof mind that

    in Greekwould be labeled deisidaimonia,14 that is, the preternatural fear ofthedivine and demonic. Incategorizing the fear in theseterms and attributing

    it to an earlier eraandto women, they distance themselves from it. Plutarch,

    in his account of a conversation after a banquet at which thesubject of the

    envious eye (baskanos op h tha lm os and those men able to harm with it isbrought up, says most ofthose present completely belittled and ridiculed the

    idea(Quaestionesconvivales, 680c).15 Finally,inHeliodorusnovel theAethio-

    pica, when an Egyptian priest suggeststhat his hostsdaughter has drawnan

    enviouseye on herself, the host, a priest of DelphianApollo,smilesat theirony

    12 quid, priscas artes inventaque simplicis aevi, /si referam? non illametus so-

    lacia falsi /tam longam traxere fidem (400402); ac sic offectus oculique venenamaligni /vicittutela p ax impetrata deorum (4 06 7 ) .

    13 ecce ania aut metuens dinum matertera cunis /exemit puerum frontemqueatque uda labella/ infamidigito et lustralibus salivis /expiat, urentisoculos inhibere

    perita (2.3134).

    14 Phrases of the formmetuens divum, as the commentatorson Persius point out,normallyrefer to a proper respect for thegods (Ovid,Fasti,6.25960,Metamorphoses,

    1.323; Livy, 22.3.4) and not to superstitious fear. Itis unlikely, however, thatPersius

    has simple piety in mind and not thesuperstitiousfear characteristic ofwomen.15 oi m e n alloi pantapasinex ep h lau r izo n t O pragma kaikategelon

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    25/229

    Fathers of the Church andtheEvilE ye 15

    ofhis guestssubscribing to abeliefto whichthe masses gavetheir allegiance

    (3.7.2). 1 6

    It would be foolishto make too much of these expressions of disdain anddraw theconclusion that the educated classesin theRomanEmpire were either

    contemptuous of beliefin the evileye andviewed fear of it as apathological

    condition or were embarrassed about admitting to theirown belief. Theydo

    nonetheless constitute evidencethat thebeliefencounteredsome resistance.7

    We should also becautious about placing toomuch weight on thelonely posi-

    tion that Plutarch implies heoccupied in believing inthe evil eye: he gives us

    to believe that, at least at the beginning ofthe dinner partys conversation on

    theevil eye,onlyhe and hishost, Mestrius Florus, wereprepared to defend thebelief. We may suspect that the isolation of Mestrius and Plutarch does not

    necessarily reflect any reality, butis adeviceintended to highlight the intellec-

    tual tourde force that Plutarch performs in explaining how it is possible for

    theenvious tocause damage at adistance.

    No doubttherewere many reasonsfor an educated man to want to dis-

    tance himself from giving open adherence to the belief, but one prominent

    factorinfluencing his conduct may well have been concern lest he seemed to

    belong to the number of thosewho were filledwith credulous and awe-struck

    amazementin the face of themiraculous andwonderful. Thereis,not surpris-

    ingly, a tendency to assign the evil eye to the realm of themiraculous andthe

    wonderfulbecause it represents a departure from the normal course of nature

    andprecisely because there seemed to be no way to explain how one man,

    without being in direct physical contact with another, could harm him. Thus

    Apollonius Rhodius in his Argonautica, after describing Medeas bewitching

    thebronze giant Taloswith theevil eye, apostrophizes Zeus in shaken wonderthat it should be possible for death to come on someone without his being

    struck or fallingsickandthat amanshould be able to harmsomeonefrom afar

    (4.l673~75).18 Stories about the evil eye seem tohavebeen one ofthe staples

    16 gelasas oun eironikon kaisu galr, eipen,oso podus ochlos einaitinabaraskaniran episteusan

    17 MacMullen, Enemies, 121, again goes too far in maintaining of the 2nd and

    3rd centuries that As time went on, all doubters disappeared. A universal darknessprevailed. He restates the same view,dismissingbrowns reservations (Witchcraft, 22)in Paganism in the Roman Empire (New Haven-London,1981), 7 1 74 .

    19 Zeu pater em eg ad i imoi eni haresithambosaetai /ei d e m enousoisi tupesitem ouno n olethros /antiaei kai diitisapoprothen a lm m e chaleptei

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    26/229

    16 Matthew W. Dickie

    of the branch ofliterature that from the Hellenistic Ageon catered to thepub-

    lics taste forwonders, paradoxography.19 This taste for the miraculous was to

    some extent made disreputable by the assaults of two philosophical schools,the Epicureans and the Stoics. The Stoics,about whom we are better informed

    here, hadno time for wonders and simply denied the possibility of their exis-

    tence.20 Much of the impetus for their attack isattributable to their eagerness

    to counter the disconcerting effect that awe-struck fear might haveon amans

    mental equilibrium. It will beno coincidence thenthat the philosophical stand-

    point of Persius and ofthose at Plutarchsdinner party who attackbeliefin the

    evil eye is a Stoicone.31

    From an intellectual point of view, the difficulty educated pagans hadwith the evil eye, whenthey put theirminds to the issue, was that itwas hard

    to seehow theeyes could harm without apparent physical contact. There were

    three responses to this difficulty: (1) probably the mostcommon, to ignore it;

    (2) to see in it an insuperable obstacle to the beliefs being true; and (3) to

    arguethat there was in factphysical contact between theeyes and whatthey

    restedon. Thus Plutarchs explanation of theevil eye isthat there is a physical

    emanation from the eyes ofthe envious person which enters the eyes of the

    envied party to cause bodily and psychic upset (Quaest. conviv., 680f~681a,

    68le f). Plutarch here is deeply indebted to the presocratic philosopher De-

    mocritus, who had used his theory ofatomic particles toaccount forthecapac-

    ity the eyes of the envious had to harm (DK 68 A 77 =Plutarch, Quaest.

    conviv., 682f 683a). What is notable aboutall of the the theories devised in

    19 Pliny the Elder attributes to two Hellenistic paradoxographers, Isigonus and

    Nymphodorus, stories about people who hadthe power to fascinate(Historia naturalis,7.16). On the literary form, see A. Giannini, Studi sulla paradossografia greca I,

    RendIstLomb97 (1963), 246 66; idem, Studi sulla paradossografiagrecaII, Acme 1 7(1964),9 9 1 4 0 .

    20 Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, ed. J. non Arnim, 4 nols. (Leipzig, 190524),

    III, 642;cfibid., I,239 (Zeno); Epictetus, 1 .29.3. Strabo (1.3.21) treats Democritusa sth e precursor ofthose philosophers (i.e., the Stoics)w ho try to inculcatea resistancetoastonishment (athaumastia). O n Democritus an d th e Stoics, see R. Gauthier and J.Jolif, LEthique a Nicomaque, 2nd ed. (Louvain-Paris, 1970), on Aristotle, Nicoma-

    cheanEthics, 1 125a2. Lucian couples Democritus with Epicurus and Metrodorus asmen resolute in their determination not to be awed by miracles (Alexander, 17).

    21 H. Dorrie, DerKonigskult des Antiochos von Kommagene im Lichteneuer

    Inschrziten-Funde, AbhGott,phil.-hist.Kl., 3rd ser.6 0 (Gottingen, 1964), 110, identifies

    the scoffers position as Stoic.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    27/229

    Fathers of the Church and the EvilEye 17

    pagan antiquityandthey are all reallyvariations on Plutarchs adaptation of

    Democritusto make sense of the ability of the envious to inflict harm

    through their eyes is that they assume the harm must be done through someform ofphysical contact.

    22

    ThatPlutarchs theory should have found its wayinto two collections of

    physical and medical conundrums, one ascribed to Aristotle ([Arist.], Probi.

    ined. 3.52 [BussemakerIV.3331 and the other to Alexander of Aphrodisias

    ([Alex. Aphrod.] Probl. 2.53 [J. L. Ideler, Physici etmedici Graeci minores

    1.67 68]), is a fair indication that there wasan audience for it and that Plutarch

    somewhat misrepresents his position in suggesting itwas a lonely andembat-

    tled one. Many educated men will have been only too happy to embrace anexplanationthat conferred respectabilityon a beliefto whichthey might other-

    wisehave been embarrassed to admit. Many othersapparently feltno embar-

    rassment atall aboutthe belief. Pliny theElder, despite the robust skepticism

    hedisplays about certain aspects of magic, is one such:23 there is no hint that

    hewithholds his intellectual assent from what he has to say aboutfascinatio.24

    Aelian,a product of the Second Sophistic who wasborn in Praeneste butwrites

    in Greek, is another: hehappily recounts themeasures that animals and birds

    take to protect themselvesagainst theeyesof theenvious.35

    In sum, in pagan antiquity one small facet of a much larger complex of

    beliefs, whose core was the feeling that good fortune was vulnerable to the

    assaults ofenvious supernaturalforces, was singledout for rejection or expla-

    nation. It is important to bear this in mind whenweturn to what those fathers

    of the churchwho do address theissue ofbaskania orfascinatio haveto sayabout it . Those church fathers who show no sign ofhaving readany of the

    philosophicaldiscussions of thetopic, although they take a somewhat largerview ofbaskania, cannot accept that one human being can harm another

    throughbaskania, but do not question the existence ofan envious supernatu-

    ralforce. The church fathers whose thinking does betraytheinfluenceofpagan

    22 Heliodorus, Aethiopica, 3 .7 .2 8 .2 ; [Aristotle], Problemata inedita, 3 .52

    (bussemakerIV.333); [AlexanderofAphrodisias],Problemata, 2 .5 3 (J .L .Ideler,Phys-ici etmedici graeciminores, 1 .67 68 ) .

    23 O n Plinys disbeliefinmagic,seeMaryBeagon, Roman Nature: The ThoughtofPliny theElder(Oxford, 1992),92 123 , an assessmentthat doesnot quite bring outPlinysblind spots.

    24 Historia naturalis, 7 . 1 6 18 ; 13.40; 19.50; 28.22, 35, 101; 37.145, 164.25 De naturaanimalium, 1.35; 11.18.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    28/229

    18 MatthewW Dickie

    philosophical discussionshow in theverylimitedview they takeofbaskania

    and in theircriticism ofbeliefin it their indebtedness, naturally unacknowl-

    edged,to pagan thinkingonthe subject.What they attackisthebeliefthatmenin theirenvy are ablethrough theireyesalone to hurt other human beings; the

    basisof their criticismisthata merepart ofthe body could not dothis onits own.

    The Fathers of the Church

    Nowhere is the limiting influence of pagan discussion more evidentthan in

    Basils discussion of the evil eye in his homily on envy. After arguing that theenvious do themselvesmuch more harm than they do those at whomthey direct

    theirenvy, he turns to an apparentcounter-example to his thesis, namely, the

    beliefheld by some that envious men through thesole agency of theireyescan

    inflictharmon others.20 He goes on togive afuller versionof this belief:Bod-

    ies ingood condition, eventhose that are at the very apogee of physical form

    and youth, waste away when exposed to fascination and lose all of their sub-

    stance, inasmuch as a deadlyeffiux emanates from envious eyes to ruin and

    kill.27 Having spelled out what the belief is, Basil dismisses it as a vulgarstory introduced by old women into the womens quarters.28 Then, changing

    histacksomewhat, he makes what is in effect a concession:whendemons who

    have a hatred of what is fair come across men withpropensities akin to their

    own, they employ these propensities to further their own purposes, which

    meansthat they pressthe eyes of the envious into service to secure their own

    ends.29Basil concludes this part of thehomily byasking us whether we are not

    afraid ofmaking ourselvesa servant of a deadly demon and the enemy ofGod

    who isgood and free of all envy.

    26 De invidia, PG 3 1 , c o l . 3 8 0 : tous de h a th on erou s tines oiontai kai d i oph

    thalmon monon t e n blaben epiballein.27 oste ta euektikasomata kai ek tes kata ten elikirana km eseis tenak-

    ran Oran uperanthesanta, ekesthaipar autOn katabaskainomena, kaiolon a-throos sunanaireisthai ton ogkon oionreumatostinos olethriou ek tOn phthoneronoph t h a lm on aporreontos, kai lumainomenou kai dirahatheirontos.

    28 toutonegode touton en tO n logona p o p e m p o m ai osdemode kai te gunaikonitidipareisachthenta up o graidion

    29 de ekeino dep h e m i , oti oi misokaloi oraimones,epeidan oikeiaseautoiseur-osi proaireseis pantoiosautraispros t O id io n apokechrentaibo u l em a oste kaitois O h a th a lm o is tOnbaskanoneis uperesianchresthaitou idiou thelematos.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    29/229

    Fathers of theChurch and the EvilE ye 19

    Thebeliefthat Basil rejects as vulgar and an old wives tale, at least in

    the form that he presents it, is no such thing, but a leamedinterpretation of

    baskania that he gets from Plutarch, probablydirectly. Basil read Plutarch;the homily De invidiaowes a debt toPlutarchsDe invidia etodio.

    30 Since the

    theory ofbaskania that herejects is basically thesame as Plutarchs, and the

    description of the effect of baskacania on bodies in their prime comes from

    Plutarchs explanation of why good-looking young men in their prime may

    fascinatethemselves ifthey see their image reflected inwater, the chances are

    that hehas taken it directly from that author.31

    Why Basil shoulddismiss Plutarchsexplanation ofbaskania as an old

    wives tale is something of a puzzle. In calling it an old wives tale, he of

    course wishes to suggest that it is a superstitiousbeliefof the sort that only

    credulous old women would believe.32 Itseems unlikely, however, that it had

    30 Basilsdebt particularly to Plutarchs De tranquillitate vitaehas been demon-

    strated by M. Pohlenz, Philosophische Nachklange in altchristlichen Predigten,

    ZWTh 48 (1905), 72 95 . See also R. Hirzel, Plutarch (Leipzig, 1912), 8485; K.Ziegler,RE21(1951), cdl. 311; D. Russell, Plutarch (London, 1973), 144 45. Case

    for debt toPlutarchs Deinvid. etod. in basils De invidia:enviouswill never admit toenvy: Deinvid., PG 31, col. 373 =Mor., 537e; misfortune of the enviedputs astop toenvy: Deinvid., PG 3 1 , col. 373 = Mor., 5 3 8 b c ; doinggood to the envious does notstop theirenvy but exacerbates it:De invid.,PG 31 , cols.3 7 6 77 =Mor, 538 c d .

    5 Cf. Quaest. conviv. 682e: sphaleron gar e e p akron euexia katatO n Ippokraten, kai te a sOmataproelthontam ec h ri tesaacr rasak m es O u c h esteken.

    32 For oldwives talesa s an exp ression ofcontempt: Plato, Gorgias,527a, Res-

    publica, 350e,Theaetetus, 176b; Herodas, 1.74; 1 Timothy 4:6;Lucian, Philopseudes,9; Philostratus, Vita Apollonii, 5.14; Porphyry , DeAbstinentia, 4.16;Julian, Oratio 5 ,

    161 b; Cicero, De naturadeorum, 3.12; Tibullus, 1.3.85;Horace, Sermones, 2 .6 .7 6 7 7 ;Apuleius,Apologia, 25,Metamorphoses, 4.27;see also Headlamon Herod.1.74; non-sensical talk characteristicofold women: JohnChrysostom, InMatthaeum, PG 57,col.30,In epistulam ad Romanos,PG 60, col.414 ,In epistulam 2 ad Thessalonicenses,PG62, col. 470 ; on the superstitiousness ofwomen in general: bionfr . 30 Kindstrand =Plutarch,De superstitione, 168d;Polybius, 12.24.5;Strabo,7.3.4; on th e superstitious-ness ofold women: Plutarch, Nonposse suavitervivere secundumEpicurum, 1 I05b;Cleomedes, De motu circulari corporumcaelestium, 208 Ziegler; basil, Homilia inhexameron, 6.11, PG 2 9 ,col. 145; Gregory ofNyssa, InEunomium, PG 45, col.296 ;

    John Chrysostom,InMatthaeum, PG 57, col.353;Cicero,De domosua, 105,ND, 1.55,2.5, 70 , 3.92, 96, Dedivinatione, 1.7, 2.19, 125, 141, Orationes tusculanae, 1.48, 92;Servius, in Aeneidem, 8.187;Minucius Felix,Octavius, 13.5; Lactantius,Divinaeinsti-tutiones, 1.17.3, 5.2.7; Firmicus Materuus, De erroreprofanorum, 17.4; on women andold women in particularbeing expertin warding offor taking offth e evil eye: Theocri-

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    30/229

    20 Matthew WDickie

    become part of the fabric of popularculture. A possible but only partial solu-

    tion to the problem may lie in the conventions governing the way in which

    Christians refer to theviews ofpaganphilosophers. TheCappadocian fathersand John Chrysostom are in the habit of speaking in an extremely dismissive

    fashion of pagan philosophers when the views of these philosophers are in

    conflict with what they take to be Christian doctrine.35 We find Gregory

    ofNazianzus speaking of a certain theory as even more outlandish and old

    womanlike thanthe atoms of the Epicureans.54 It is hard at the sametime not

    tobelievethatthe contempt expressed bythe Cappadocianfathers is something

    of a pose designed to reassure their hearers and readersthat, despite their edu-

    cation in the paganclassics, they hadno truck with the ideas ofp agans.35Despitehisdismissal ofPlutarchs theory, Basil has more incommon with

    Plutarch than perhaps hewould want toadmit: he toobelieves that theeyes of

    theenvious may cause hurt, but instead ofhavingrecourse to atomic theory to

    tus, 6.3940, 7.12627; H eliod., Aethiop., 4.5.3; Persius, 2.31 34; Ps. Acro, in HoratiiEpodem, 8 .1 8 ; Augustine, Confessiones, 1.7.11; old women as magic-workers: Plu-

    tarch, Desuperstit., 166a; Lucian, Philopseudes, 9 , Dialogimeretricum, 4.1, 3, 5; JohnChrysostom, Adilluminandos catecheses, PG 49 , col. 240 , In epistulam 2 ad Corin-thios, PG 61 , col. 106, Inepistulam adColossenses, PG 62, cols. 3 5 8 59 ; Athanasius,Fragmentum de amuletis,PG 2, col. 1320 ; Tibullus, 1 . 8 . 17 18 ; Horace, Sermones, 1 . 8 ;Propertius, 2.4.15; Ovid,Amores, 1 . 8 ; Petronius, Satyricon, 1 3 1 .

    33 Cf. Gregory ofNazianzus, Contra lulianumimperatorem, 2 , PG 3 5 , col.717,AdversusEunomianos, 1 0 , PG 36, col. 2 4 , Carmina moralia, 10 (de virtute), PG 37,col.695 ; John Chrysostom,AdpopulumAntiochenum,PG 49, col. 175,In ActaAposto-lorum, PG 60, col.47.

    3 4 Gregory of Nazianzus, De theologia, 10 , PG 36, col. 36: O kai tOnEpikoureion atomonatopoteron tekai graodesteron.

    35 Foran echoinbasil(Ep. 1 1 ) ofa letterofEpicurus (ft. 138Usener) suggestive

    ofa certain sympathy and understanding for that philosopher: P . Von der Mlhl, basil-iusu ndder letzteBriefEpikurs, MusHelv12(1955),4 7 49 ;WSchmid,RAC5 (1962),s.v. Epikur, col. 783; on basils attitude toward Greekliterature and his use ofGreekphilosophy to bolster his arguments: N. G.W ilson,SaintBasilon the ValueofGreek

    Literature (London, 1975) ,9 13 ; on the view that Basilsattacks on Greekphilosophyand science in the Hexamerondo not reflect basils ownposition but the officialvoice

    of the church: E. Amand deMendieta, The Official Attitude ofbasilofCaesarea asaChristian Bishoptowards GreekPhilosophy andScience, in The Orthodox Churchesand the West,D. baker, ed., Studies in Church History 1 3 (1976),2 5 4 9 ; the cleannessof this division questioned: M. Naldini, Basilio di Cesarea, Sulla Genesi (Milan,1990) , xxivxxv.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    31/229

    Fathers of the Church and the EvilE ye 21

    explainhow that couldbe,he appeals to thenotion ofenvious demons using

    envious human beings as the instruments of their will. Basil does not spell out

    his reasons forrejecting the idea that theenvious can harm through theireyesalone, but fromthe emphasisthatheplaceson its beingdonethrough the eyes

    alone we may surmise that neither he nor his audience could imagine harm

    beingdone without directphysical contact. The same pattern of reasoning,a s

    we haveseen, liesbehindpagan rejectionofbaskania.

    From ourvantage point it seems obvious that the same objection should

    apply to the theory that demons may, through the eyes of the envious, effect

    harm.ForBasil, on the other hand, bringingthe demonic or the divineinto the

    explanation puts the explanationon a plane that excuses the further exercise of

    the critical faculty. Basils rationality, like that of most men, extends as faras

    it can be made to coincide with deeply held beliefs,fears, and interests, but no

    further. His reservations about the envious having the power to inflict harm

    through theireyesturn out to be verylimited.38He is notprepared todenythat

    the eyesoftheenvious maybe dangerous, ifdemons use them, let alone that

    theremay beenvious demonic anddiabolical forcesout thereintent on destroy-

    ing what is fair andgood.

    When John Chrysostom attacksthe notion of the evil eye as incoherent,

    what he too attacks under that heading isPlutarchsconception ofthe evil eye.

    His attack comes in his commentaryon apassage inPauls Letter to theGala-

    tians that is somethingof a touchstone ofthesensitivity ofthosewho comment

    on it to the implications of beliefin theevil eye for Christian doctrine. The

    problemwith thepassage and another in theGospel ofMatthew is that they

    might be taken toshow that Paul and Jesus respectively subscribed tobeliefin

    the evil eye. The passage in Matthew (20:15)the parable in which the lordof the vineyard asks those who complain to him that those who have only

    worked from the eleventh hourhavereceivedasmucha s theywho haveworked

    all day,whether theireyeis notevilbecause he isgood3 7 isless ofan embar-

    rassment thanthatin Galatians. It is notparticularly plausibleto suppose that

    in it Jesushas theevil eye in mind. Nonetheless, the possibility that Jesus might

    be thought to lend his authority to the notion makesChrysostom take pains to

    36 Similarly CharlesStewart,Demons andthe Devil:MoralImagination in Mod-

    em GreekCulture (Princeton, 1991), 290 note 16. See also RichardP . H. Greenfleld,Traditions ofBeliefin Late Byzantine Demonology(Amsterdam, 1988), 112.

    37 e o o p h th al m os souponerosestin,O ti ego agathos eimi;

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    32/229

    22 Matthew W Dickie

    ensure that his readers understand the passage correctly. Pauls words inGala-

    tians (3:1) incalling the Galatians foolish and asking who has put an envious

    spellon them are less easilydiscounted.38

    In Chrysostoms view, Galatians 3:1 is a rebuke aimed at the Galatians,

    couched not in the harshest waypossible,but madeless severeby the sugges-

    tion,in ebakanen, that theGalatians conduct has been sufficientlymeritor-

    ious to have drawnenvy ontheir heads; what has happened is that the Galatians

    have suffered theassault of a demon fiercelyhostileto theirsuccess.39 Chryso-

    stom now proceeds to give a justification for his interpretation ofebaasacanen

    as a reference to a demonic assault and not to fascinationby thehumaneye:40

    he argues that when we hear ofphthonosin thispassage and in the Gospels ofophthalmosponeros meaning envy, then we are not to suppose that the cast

    of the eye harms those seeing it , for the eye could not be bad, being only a

    bodily part.41 There then follows an extremely tortured explanation of how

    Christ came to useo p h th al m os poneros ofenvy,the gist ofwhich is that,a s the

    eye is a passive receptor through whichthe vision of what is seen flows into

    the soul,there can be nothing bad about theway in which it sees,the badness

    being confinedto the reception of what is seen by soulsendowed with a bad-

    ness that gives rise toenvy.42BythisChrysostom may meanthat while theeyes

    of theenvious are not bad in the sensethat they can do harm, they are bad in

    38

    oanoetoiGalatai,tis umas ebaskanen;39 John Chrysostom, In epistulam ad Galatas commentarius, PG 61 , col. 648:

    ouk amoironegkomion tenep iplexinth eis . toutogar deiknuntos estin,O ti p h t ho n ouaxia epratton proteron, kai daimonos epereia t O gignomenon en , sphodron kata

    teseuemerias auton pneusantos.40 B. K otting, RAC,s . v . Boserblick,col.479 , is misleading here in paraphrasing

    th eintent ofChrysostoms position to be that the danger of theevil eyecomes not fromthe eye itself but from moral distortion in theheartofth e enviousm anand inattributingthesame view to Jeromeon Gal. 3:1.

    41 John Chrysostom, Inep. ad Gal.comm.,col. 648: Otan de p h t h o n o n akousesentautha, kai en t o Euaggelio O p h th a lm O n ponerOnto auto delounta,m e touto no-m ise s, O tie tOn O p h tha lm O n bole tous orontas blaptein pephuken O ph thalm O s garoukan eie poneros, autoto m elo s .

    42 Ibid.: all entauthao Christosouto t O n p h t h o n o n legei. O p h th a lm O n m en gar toaplosoran tes endon diestrammenes ginetaignomes epeide gar dia tes aistheseostauteseis t e n p su ch e n umen eisreiton oromenone theoria, kai osepipoluen plouto malista O p h t h ono s tiktetai o de ploutosa p o ophthalmon oratai kaisi dunasteiai kai aidoruphoriai dia t ou t o poneron O p h t h a lm O n ekalesen,o u tO norenta, alla tonmeta b araskanias OrOntaap oteskatapsuchen ponerias.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    33/229

    Fathers of the Church and the EvilEye 23

    the sense that envydistortsthevision andcauses it to put an evil construction

    on what is seen.43

    Chrysostoms position on Galatians3:1 is, accordingly, that the verse re-

    fers to ademonic assault on the Galatiansmotivated by envy and not to somehuman beings having cast an evil eye on them. The argument presented in

    support ofthis conclusion isan attack not only on the popularbeliefthatthe

    eyes of the envious can harm but also on those such as Plutarch, who try to

    providea reasoned defense ofi t. Thereare two indications that this is what he

    isdoing: (1) an element of the propositionthat he bids us not believe(i.e., that

    theeyes of the person hurt have to catch the cast of the eyes of the envious

    party for harm to be done) is a feature of most ancient explanations of the

    evil eye, including that ofPlutarch,but, in popularbelief, is not presumably

    considered a necessary factor since therenot only are humans and animals

    bewitched but also trees and crops; (2) Chrysostom is emphatic that the eye

    itself does nothing but acts as the passive instrument through which what is

    seen flowsinto the soul; thisview of visual perception stands in marked con-

    trast to the theory of vision underlying Plutarchs explanation of the evil eye,

    in which somethingflowsout of the eyesto impinge on the objectperceived.45

    I am unable to demonstrate thatChrysostom knewthe Quaestionesconvi-vales, but, like Basil,he knew PlutarchsDetranquillitate animi, as M. Pohlenz

    showed long ago. A strong case can also be made for Chrysostomshaving

    drawnon theDeinvidia etodioin his homily De invidia.46The points in com-

    mon here betweenChrysostom and Plutarch are not the same asthose between

    Basil and Plutarch, a fair indication that Chrysostom, though hemay haveread

    Basil, is not dependent on him in thismatter.47

    43 Cf. JohnChrysostom, DeChristi divinitate, PG 48,col. 808: oigar tenp h t h o-nountonOphthalmoiu g i e s ouden blepousi.

    44 Cf. Ap. Rhod., Arg., 4.1669 70 (dependenton Democritus): echthodopoisin /

    O m m as i chadkeioio Talo emegeren opopas; [Alex. Aphrod.], Probl., 2 .53 : osperiodes tis kai phthoropoios aktis exeisinap o tes kores auton kai au tee eisiousadia tenO p hth alm O n toup h th on ou m eno u trepseite e n p s u c h e n kai t e n p h us in.

    45 Quaest. conviv., 681a:polukinetos gar e O p s i s ousameta pneumatosaugenaphientos purode thaumastentinadiaspeirei dunamin, Oste podIakaip aschein kai

    poieind i autes ton anthropon.46 Pohlenz, Nachklange, 9194.47 The case forChrysostomsindebtedness in theDe invid. (PG63, cols.67782)

    to Plutarchs De invid. et od. rests on the presence in both of the following topics:

    animals do not envy each otherand, though they may go to war with eachother, the

    hatredis provoked by a cause: John Chrys., De invid., PG 63, col. 677 = Plut., De

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    34/229

    24 MatthewW Dickie

    Itturns out then that Basil andChrysostomtake verymuch the sameline

    in interpreting theevileye andareboth concernedto reject not only popular

    beliefbut also therationalization of thebeliefdevised by Plutarch. It is notsurprisingthat there should be a measure of agreementon this point between

    Chrysostom and his older contemporary,Basil. ThatChrysostomshould resort

    to detailed philosophical argument to support his rejection, and Basil should

    not,reflectsthe differing requirements of a popular address and aleamed com-

    mentary.Finally, bothChrysostom and Basil present aunifiedvoice in seeing

    baskania as a form ofenvious demonic assault.Jeromes commentaryon Galatianswas probablywrittenalong with com-

    mentarieson three otherPauline epistles inA .D . 387/88.It was composed in ahasty fashionand draws on the work of earliercommentators.

    48 Jerome takes

    a somewhat different approach to Galatians3:1 fromChrysostom: he argues

    that Paul uses the language ofthepeople in this matter, but notbecause Paul

    supposes there is such a thing asfascinus in its vulgaracceptance.49 He goes

    on to adduce two passagesfrom theSeptuagintin whichthe terms baskania

    andbaskanos are used,50and to conclude that they teach us that a man may

    be tortured in his envyby anothers good luck orthat aman who is in posses-

    sionofsomegoodmay be harmed byanothers fascinatinghim, that is, envying

    him. Of this latterbelief,Jerome says thatfascinus issupposed particularly to

    harm infants,the young, and those whosestepis notyetfirm.51 Asan example

    of thebeliefhe cites averse from Vergils Third Eclogue, ascribing it not to

    Vergil by name but toa certain pagan: nescioquis tenerosoculusmihi fascinat

    agnos(103). Whether thebeliefis true ornot, hewill leave to Godto see,he

    says.Jerome makes himself seem more open-minded on thisissue than in fact

    invid. etod.,537b-c; misfortunes of enviedput an end toenvy: John Chrys.,De invid.,PG 63, col. 677 =Plut., De invid. etod., 5 3 8 b ;thereason for enmities disappears:JohnChrys.,De invid.,PG6 3, col.6 78 = Plut., Deinvid. etod., 538c.

    48 See J. N. D. Kelly, Jerome (London, 1975), 145.49 Jerome, Comm. in Gal., PL 26, cols. 3 7 2 7 3 : quod autem sequitur: Qui vos

    fascinavit, digne Paulo (qui etsi imperitus est sermone, non tamen scientia) debemus

    exponere, non quo scierit essefascinum, qui vulgo putaturnocere; sed usus sermone

    sit trivii, et ut in ceteris, ita et in hoc quoque loco, verbum quotidianae sermoci-nationisassump serit.

    50 Sirach 18:18.2;SapientiaSalomonis 4:12.5 Jerome, ibid.: dicitur fascinus proprieinfantibus nocere, et aetati parvulae, et

    his qui necdumfirms vestigio figantgradum.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    35/229

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    36/229

    26 MatthewW Dickie

    whichhe drew may have explained theirposition more fully. Jeromes com-

    mentary does nonetheless providean indication thatChrysostom hadpredeces-

    sors in rejecting thepossibilityofreading Galatians 3:1 literally and in inter-preting instances of fascination as demonic rather than human assaults.

    The tradition of interpretationthat wefind inChrysostom and Jeromewas

    by no means universal. The two early Latin commentaries on Galatians, that

    of Marius Victorinusand that of the writer given the name Ambrosiaster by

    Erasmus, bothexplain whatebaskanen means, buthave nothing to say either

    about whether Paul subscribes tothe beliefthat men can fascinate or whether

    there is anything tothe belief.55 Victorinus, infact, writes in such a way as to

    suggest that he accepts the belief.56 Augustine in his commentary quotes theverse buthas nothing tosay about it(Expositio in Galatas, PL35, col. 2116).

    Ifexpressions ofdisbeliefinthe evil eyewere only to befound inBasil,

    Chrysostom,and Jerome, wemight beinclined to suppose that the evileyewas

    a matter oflimited and local concern andthat itwas an issue only inthe minds

    of those who had read Plutarch or had in some way been influenced by him.

    Thereis,however, evidenceof a morewidespread concern with fascination in

    Christian circles in both the East andWest.

    Two generations or more beforeBasil, the North African father Tertullian,

    a convert toChristianity from paganism, had already in effect rejected what he

    calledfascinus inits pagan understanding. The language he employs suggests

    the position he adopts was already one that had some standing among Chris-

    tians, In the Devirginibus velandis, a tract denouncing the action of a group

    ofyoung Carthaginian womenwho haddecidedto remain unmarried and who

    had been persuaded to stand in church with their heads uncovered and their

    faces unveiled,57 he maintains that among the benefits a virgin acquires fromveiling herself from theeyes ofothers is thatshe protects herself against scan-

    dalous talk, suspicion, whispering, emulation, and envy itself.38 Mention of

    envy leads Tertullian togo ontosaythat there isalso somethingfearedamong

    55 MariusVictorinus:In epistulamPauli ad Galatas liberI , PL 8,cols. 1 1 6 6 6 7 ;Ambrosiaster: PL 17, col. 372.

    56 Victorinus, ibid.: non papiuntur fascinum, nisi qui in bono aliquo pollent, et

    patiuntura malignis etinv id i s .57 On the circumstances that gaverise tothis tract, see Peterbrown, The Body

    andSociety(New York, 1988) ,8 0 .50 Tertullian, De virginibus velandis, 15, PL 2 , col. 959: confugit ad velamen

    capitis, quasi ad galeam, quasi ad clypeum, qu i bonum suumprotegatadversus ictus

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    37/229

    Fathers of the Church and the Evil Eye 27

    pagans, to which they give the name offascinus; it is the unhappy outcome of

    too great praise andglory.39 This, Tertullian says,Christians sometimes inter-

    pretby thedevil andsometimesby God; inthe one case a s a hatred of what is

    good and in the other as ajudgmenton arrogance that raises up the humble

    and lays low those who have got above themselves.60A piousvirgin, he con-

    cludes, will therefore fear, underthe heading offascinus, the envious temper

    of the Adversary and the censorious eye ofGod.61 That is to say, a virgin will

    veil herself sothat her beauty may not incurthe envious eye of the devil and

    sothat the pride she takes in herbeautymay not drawGodswrathon herhead.

    How many Christians interpretedfascinus inquite thisway we cannot say,

    and we may suspect that Tertullian is recommending rather than reporting awidely accepted interpretation of the notion. That said, it does nonetheless

    soundas though he is appealing to a recognized position. He does not explain

    in any detail what the nature of thefascinusfeared by paganswas.62 Hisinsis-

    tence that it is to be understooda s Godspunishment of pride or the envyof

    the devil would seem to indicate that he is taking issue withan understanding

    of the termthat attributed special powers to human beings.On the other hand,

    his definitionoffascinusastheunhappy outcomeof toogreatpraise andglory

    doessuggest not onlythat he is thinking ofmen casting the evil eye but also

    of their fascinatingby praising.63He has, accordingly, in mind a conceptionof

    tentationum, adversus iacula scandalorum, adversus suspiciones, et susurros,et aemula-tionem, ipsum quoque livorem

    59 Ibid.: Dam estaliquid etiamapud ethnicos metuendum, quod fascinumvocant,infelicioremlaudiset gloriae enormioris eventum.

    69

    Ibid.: hoc nosinterdumdiabolo interpretamur: ipsius est enim, boni odium,interdumDes deputamus: illius estenim superbiae iudicium, extollentis humiles, etdeprimentiselatos.

    61 Ibid.: timebititaqu e virgo sanctior, velin nomine fascini, hinc adversarium,inde Deum: illius linidum ingenium, huiuscenssrium lumen.

    62 Thee,JuliusAfricanus, 403 note 3,thinks thatTertulliansposition is ambigu-ous and that herefersto the evil eye in a sort of ad hominem argument, as a paganidea which at least served to reinforce his ideas about virgins wearing vei1s. RobinLane Foxs (Pagans and Christians [Harmondsworth, 1986], 370) paraphrase of

    the intent of the passage is also somewhatmisleading: Tertullian drew attention tothe continuing risks of the pagans evil eye as a counter to the virgins self-congratulation?

    63 There is an instance offascinareused meaning to fascinate by praising inTertulliansaccount ofM arcions attackon Lukesversion of th e nativity ofJesus: ta-

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    38/229

    28 Matthew W Dickie

    fascinusrather wider thanthat withwhich Basil, JohnChrysostom,and Jerome

    wereto takeissue. Furthermore, his interpretation ofit differs somewhatfrom

    theirs. What he does have in common with them is that he would deny thatthere is anything tofascinus as it was understood by pagans. He would also

    agree with themin imputing at least some instancesof fascinus to thedevil.

    There is then already inTertullian the germ ofthe doctrineon fascination by

    the evil eye that we find in later authors.

    Tertullian givesus some impression of what a preacher not influencedby

    pagan philosophical discussion of the topic mightsayto hisflockabout fasci-

    nation by theevil eye and in what sort of contextthe issue would arise. Some

    furtherlight on these points is shedbya homily attributed to Eusebius ofAlex-

    andriaon the observance ofthe Sabbath (SennoVII.:DeNeomeniis etSabbatis

    etdenonobservandisavium vocibus, PG86.1, cols. 35457).64 Thesermon is

    an attackonthose Christians who giveas their reason for performing some act

    of charitythat it is the Sabbath or thefirstday of a new month or a birthday, or

    againwhosaythat Easter iscoming and thatthey are watching the birds. Such

    conduct, Eusebius declares, ischaracteristic of Jews, not Christians. He goes

    on to criticize a number of other practices that takeplace on theseoccasions:not givingfireto a neighbor after sunset, paying attention to the cries of birds,

    and treatingmens utterancesa s prophetic.65 He summarizes the intent of this

    section of his argument by declaring that Christians ought not to spend their

    timeon such days paying close attention tothe cries of birds, to what day and

    hour it is,and to being ontheir guard against men(paraterein anthropous

    WhatEusebius now goes on to attackare men who, instead of blaming

    thedevil for whathas gone wrong, when Satan destroys some fine workthey

    have made, assert that so-and-so as he went past fascinated it.66 This leadsEusebius toexclaim at thewayin which men ascribe barasacania to their fellow

    men when the devil has fromthe beginning beenenvious and is at war with

    ceat et anus il l a (sc. Anna, Luke 2 :36 38 ) , nefascinet puerum (Decame Christi,

    PL 2, col. 800) .64 I am deeply indebted to DirkK rausmlller forpo inting outth e homily tom e. 1

    fear that, butfor him, Iwould never have comeacrossit .65

    alloi phulassontat p h o n a s orneon, kai acledonismous anthropon.66o deina anthropos paragonebaskanen. Forth e evil eye being cast by one

    passing b y , cf . the exorcism from early 19th-century Cretequotedin Curt Wachsmuth,Das alte Griechenlandim Neuen (bonn, 1864) ,6 0 61 : kai perasasoi aggeloi k iarchaggeloikaiphtharmisasi ten.

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    39/229

    Fathers of the Church and the EvilEye 29

    mankind. Eusebius proceeds to explain how the devil contrives to get men to

    blame theirillsonthe bassacania of their fellows: ifhe should see a man doing

    good work in hisfield, heconceives envy of him andstrives to break him; butsince he is invisible,he contrivesto havethe responsibilityascribed to others

    who are without guilt; again when he sees a fine ox exerting itselfpulling a

    cart and people admiring it and praising i t, hecauses it tocollapse; its master

    does notblame the devilbut a man who is without guilt. A furtherexclamation

    at the power of the devil follows: how the devil is always able, wheneverhe

    wantstodoill, to get one ofthose persons whom men are on their guardagainst

    (O nmellousin paraphulattesthai to bepresent; thus a man goingon a jour-

    ney away from home, from which he will return withouthavingaccomplishedhis goal, will say that he met so-and-so as he left and that was thereason

    for his failure. Eusebius ends the homily with the observation that wehave a

    phylacteryagainst thebaskacanis of thedevil in the form of thecross.

    The connecting threadthat ties Eusebiusdenunciation ofJudaizing prac-

    tices to his criticism of those men who blame their misfortunes on the

    bassacaniaof theirfellows rather thanthe devil is that these men are guilty of

    being on their watch against theirfellows. It is possible that a similar under-lying connection in thought is to be discerned in John Chrysostom: in two

    homilies helumps together with the observance of the cries ofbirds and the

    utterances ofmen theuse ofincantations andamulets,to which in one casehe

    adds engaging in magic-working (In epistulam 1 ad Corinthios, PG 61, col.

    38; Inepistulam] ad Timotheum, PG 62, col. 552).To Chrysostoms way of

    thinking these practices were clearlyallof a piece. It isworth mentioningthat

    healso attackspaying attention to the cries ofbirds and theutterances ofmen

    kledonismoi kai oionismoi on the sameground as doesEusebius, namely,that theChristians who do this are guilty of Judaizing(Comm. in ep. ad Gal.,

    PG 61, col. 623).Whatever the connecting thread may be that ties these prac-

    tices together for Chrysostom, we can at least beconfidentthat attention to the

    cries ofbirds and to mens utterances was in the eyes of Chrysostom very

    closely connected with engaging in such magical practices as wearing amulets

    anduttering incantations.

    Eusebius, accordingly, provides us with another context in which a con-

    gregation might be urged to put aside the beliefthat their fellow men could

    fascinate them, either by their looks or by theirpraise: denunciation of such

    Judaizing practicesa s attending tobirds cries and to the utterances of menas

    thoughthey were fraught with significance. For Eusebius the same mistaken

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    40/229

    30 MatthewW Dickie

    view oftheworld is to be seen infinding significance in the calls ofbirds as is

    apparentin thinkingthat men can harm by their looks or praise.Eusebiusdoes

    not say why he thinks this is awrong-headedpoint ofview.Heevidently imag-ines itsufficientfor the purpose of asermontodenounce itas a piece oftrick-

    ery on the part of the devil. LikeTertullian, Eusebius takes a larger view of

    what men mean by baskania thando Basil and John Chrysostom: he deals

    with both acts of fascination done through theeyesand fascinatingbypraising.

    He certainlystill continues to believein a form of fascination in attributing the

    misfortunes thatmen blameon theirfellows to theenvyof the devil. He adds,

    however,a twist tothat thesis,not found elsewhere:the devildeliberately tricks

    men into thinking that the ills they suffer are to be attributed to the envious

    gaze of a passerby or someones admiringpraise.

    Conclusions

    We would go rather further thanthe evidence warrants were we to suggestthat

    all ofthe prominent men in the upper reaches ofthehierarchy of the church inboth East andWest were agreed that humanbeings did not havethe capacity

    to fascinate others,whether by casting their envious eyeson them orby prais-

    ing them. So far as we can see, this was not anissue that troubledeveryone

    equally. Thecommentaries on Galatians3:1 thatmakeno mention of theissue

    are an indication that noteverybody wassensitive to the problem.On the other

    hand, the testimony ofTertullian and Eusebius isproofthat it wasnot only very

    highly educated Christians, such as Basil and JohnChrysostom, who found the

    idea that one man could harm anotherwith hisenviousgaze incredible. It looksrather as if there was, in the hierarchy of the church from at least the end

    of the third century A.D., a widely shared hostility to beliefin baskania and

    fascinatio, to which Basil and John Chrysostom subscribe, though their con-

    ception ofbaskania has beeninfluencedby Plutarch and what they takeissue

    with is his explanation ofit.

    A ll ofthe fathers ofthe church whodo attackbeliefin the evil eye take it

    for grantedthat Christians do havereason to fear asupernatural force, enviousof good fortune; prosperity, beauty, and virtue. They naturally identify that

    force withthe devil. Two ofthem, Basil andJerome, go further and maintain

    orsuggest that thedevil orhisdemons usemens enviouseyes to accomplish

    their own envious purposes. Otherssuch as Tertullian, John Chrysostom, and

  • 7/22/2019 Maguire, Henry (Ed) - Byzantine Magic

    41/229

    Fathers of the Church and the Evil Eye 31

    Eusebius excludethe action of human intermediaries and putdown the reverses

    that the fortunate suffer to the direct action of the devil. Only Eusebius puts

    forward theview that thedevil deliberately contrives to make hisenvious as-saults on the fortunate when there are men around on whose envious gaze or

    praise thecatastrophe can be blamed.

    For most ordinary Christians it was probably a matter only of academic

    interest whether the harm theirneighbors envious eye inflicted on them was

    his ownunaided doing or whether he was the instrument of thedevil and his

    demons. The author of a Christian magical papyrus of the sixth century A.D.,

    intended to protect a house andthose dwelling in it fromall ill and from fasci-

    nation by the spirits of the air andthe human eye, clearly remained unaffectedand is in fact, with that concernfor differentiation characteristic of late antique

    magic, anxious to distinguish between fascination by the spirits ofthe air and

    fascinationby thehuman eye, so that he might the better be able to counter

    them (PGMP 9).67 Nor again does the author ofan inscriptionfrom Igazin

    Syria that dates to the middle ofthe fifth century A .D. betray any awareness

    that he contravenes Christian doctrine when, after calling on theTrinity and

    God to drive phthonosfar off, he declares that because Christs handrelievespain, he will not fear the plans of the demon who wreaks ill nor the hate-filled

    andunlawfuleye of man (IGLSyr l599.6~7).68

    Even JohnChrysostom when his guard is down speaks as if the eyes of

    envious mencanharm. In his commentary on 1 Corinthians, in a discussion of

    what apotropaic devices a Christian may use without allowing himself to be

    entrappedby the devil, he roundly condemns the practice followedby nurses