ninkovi in search of period eye

Upload: johanna341529511

Post on 01-Jun-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    1/55

     

    In search of the period eye:

    Contributions from neuroscience

    MA Renaissance Studies: Dissertation

    Pale Nikoi -09

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    2/55

    2

    Contents

    Table of Figures ....................................................................................................................................... 3

    1. Introduction .................................................................................................................................... 4

    2. General Literature Review .............................................................................................................. 6

    2.1 A Note on Function ............................................................................................................... 13

    3. Contributions from Neuroscience ................................................................................................. 16

    3.1 Mirror Neurons ..................................................................................................................... 16

    Case Studies: Empathetic Responses ............................................................................................ 20

    3.2 Ambiguity .............................................................................................................................. 34

    3.3 Plasticity ................................................................................................................................ 41

    4. Conclusions ................................................................................................................................... 48

    Appendix 1 - Contemporary account of empathetic responses to paintings ....................................... 51

    Bibliography .......................................................................................................................................... 52

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    3/55

    3

    Table of Figures

    Figure 1 - Olga Rozanova, Green Stripe (1918)

    Figure 2 - Rogier van der Weyden, Deposition (c.1435)

    Figure 3 - The Goddess Parvati

    Figure 4 - Bartholomew, James, son of Alphaeus and Andrew, detail from the Last Supper  

    Figure 5 - Jesus, Thomas, James the Greater and Philip, detail from the Last Supper  

    Figure 6 - Matthew, Jude Thaddeus and Simon the Zealot, detail from the Last Supper  

    Figure 7 - Judas Iscariot, Peter and John, detail from the Last Supper  

    Figure 8 - Stefano Di Giovanni Sassetta, The Last Supper  (1423)

    Figure 9 - The Crucifixion, miniature from a 13th-century Psalter

    Figure 10 - Mary of Cleophas (?), detail from the Deposition 

    Figure 11 - Mary Magdalene, detail from the Deposition 

    Figure 12 - Eos and Kephalos (1st

     half of 5th

     century before Christ)

    Figure 13 - Niobide (1st

     half of 5th

     century before Christ)

    Figure 14 - Image of Maenad

    Figure 15 - Relief of Maenad

    Figure 16 - The 'rabbit or duck' illusion

    Figure 17 - The Necker cube illusion

    Figure 18 - Bi-stable image showing a vase or two faces

    Figure 19 - Johannes Vermeer, Girl reading a letter at an open window (c. 1657-1659)

    Figure 20 - Johannes Vermeer, The Music Lesson (c. 1662-1665)

    Figure 21 - Diagrams representing functional and anatomical changes to a neural network (Kandel

    2006, 214)

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    4/55

    4

    1.  Introduction

    One fundamental problem in art history is the difficulty of coming to terms with art produced in

    times and cultures remote from our own. How can the paintings of Rogier van der Weyden, for

    example, be fully appreciated today, when paintings in 15th

    -century Netherlands were conceived

    under very different economic conditions to those of today and with very different objectives in

    mind? I his primer in the social history of pictorial style , Painting and Experience in Fifteenth-

    Century Italy 1 (1988), Baxandall proposes several ways of bridging this gap, albeit in the context of

    15th

    -century Italian painting. Partly by being attentive to both the economic context of the

    Quattrocento and its proper language for talking about art, and partly by invoking the concept of the

    peio ee, daaall (1988, 151) aages to shape ou peeptio of Renaissance painting.

    The concept of the period eye refers to those cognitive skills that influence the way a particular

    society in a particular period perceives art. The cognitive revolution of the 20th

      century most

    certainly contributed to the formation of this idea. I believe that the neuroscientific developments of

    today have a similar potential for influencing the way art is understood. With this in mind, in this

    dissertation I aim to answer the following research question: How can neuroscience contribute to

    the appreciation of Renaissance art nowadays?

    There are three relevant sets of skill, as Baxandall (1988, 31) explains; a stok of pattes, ategoies

    and methods of inference; training in a range of representational conventions; and experience,

    drawn from the environment. Essentially, standing before a work of art, the beholder brings to it a

    combination of innate and socially-developed skills, olletiel also efee to as ogitie stle, 

    that contribute to the meaning of that work for the beholder (Baxandall 1988, 29). Essentially, this is

    a more thorough address of what Gombrich (2002a, 246) called the eholes shae, that is the

    projection of the eholes  own life and experience into the image. And, since the painter

    1 To be referred to as Painting & Experience for the remainder of this essay.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    5/55

    5

    endeavours to ath the oo eoiato of his auiees ogitie skills, the peio ee

    influences pictorial style itself (Baxandall 1988, 40).

    Ipotatl, the peio ee shapes ou poes of isiiatio. “o a etai pofessio, daaall

    (1988, 39) elaoates, leas a a to isiiate patiulal effiietl i ietifiale aeas. Fo

    example, Baxandall (1988) suggests that merchants are capable of discriminating between volumes

    of barrels, sacks or bales, and are invited to do so by painters who would place in their works

    geometric puzzles as a way of engaging their audience.

    In this way, Baxandall places visual culture within a social context. His former teacher, Gombrich, on

    the other hand, has been criticized for divorcing art from society, as a subject of study removed from

    all other aspects of human life (Langdale 1998). It is its contextualised nature that makes the period

    eye a particularly helpful instrument of art historical study, since it permits one to glean what it was

    like to experience painting in fifteenth century Italy.

    I believe that recent advances in the understanding of the human brain could enrich the concept of

    the period eye. Interdisciplinary studies have, thus far, focused on modern art. In this dissertation I

    propose to investigate the relevance of these studies for art of the Renaissance in parts of Europe

    (for the purposes of this essay this covers mainly c.13th

     to 16th

     centuries). To do this, and to provide

    the academic context for the remainder of the work, I will begin with an overview of the literature

    dealing with the application of neuroscience to art. This shall be followed by a more focused analysis

    concerning, in turn, the following three areas: mirror neurons, ambiguity, and neuroplasticity. The

    section on mirror neurons will also include a more extensive case study of empathetic response

    hih ill e ase o Leoao a Viis Last Supper   a ‘ogie a e Wees Deposition.

    Unfortunately, due to limited space, the latter two sections will focus on the theoretical aspects

    without detailed case studies, although I will venture to provide examples where appropriate. A

    concluding section will summarize the main findings in light of the literature and case studies

    provided.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    6/55

    6

    It should be noted at the outset that this dissertation will not differentiate between different types

    of beholder. Although a limitation of the work, it should not hinder the identification of certain

    trends in the analysis. It must be recognised, however, that different types of audience may have

    experienced paintings in very different ways. Any further study in this field would certainly warrant

    closer attention to discrete categories of audience, based on social class, sex, or profession, for

    example.

    2. 

    General Literature Review

    In this section I shall give an overview of the literature broadly concerned with the contributions of

    neuroscience to art history. But firstly, to set the context for the discussion to follow, it is necessary

    to define the problem in more detail.

    The problem of recreating the social and artistic experience from history is an enduring one in art

    history. The works of Heinrich Wölfflin in particular, embedded a historical awareness into art

    history as a discipline (Harrison et al. 1998, 682-683). In Renaissance und Barock  (1888), in which he

    sets about explaining the stylistic change in architecture from one period to the other, Wölfflin (1998

    [1888], 723) ites that To explain a style then can mean nothing other than to place it in its general

    histoial otet2. Wölfflis ie of the hages i stle, as Kese   (2009, 266) points out,

    epee o histoiall istit oes of isio, elate to the Weltanschauung  of the peio.

    Additionally, Wölfflin plays no small part in establishing the concept of the history of seeing in art

    history (Gombrich 2002a, 14).

    If we accept the premise then that there indeed exists a histo of seeig, the assessig past

    esposes, iee of elaiig the fo histo (Freedberg 1989, 22) seems to be a necessary

    step towards sharpening our perception of Renaissance painting. Going as far back as the

    Renaissance, however, a culture very unlike ours, the problem is exacerbated by the lack of

    2 Eie “til ekläe ka ihts Aees heisse als ih ah seie Ausuk i ie allgeeie eitgeshihte

    eieihe (Wölfflin 1888, 65)

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    7/55

    7

    documentary evidence that might otherwise offer an insight into contemporary responses to

    artworks (Baxandall 1988, 24).

    Harrison et al. (1998, 683) identify the work of Wilhelm Dilthey as one of the most thorough to

    address this problem. While some observers have deemed the problem of historicism

    insurmountable (Gombrich 2002a, 54), Dilthey maintained, as did Gombrich after him, a more

    optimistic stance that the aeful stu of at oks oul iee ispie oes histoial iagiatio

    to tase oes o otet (Harrison et al. 1998, 683, Gombrich 2002a, 54). In this way Dilthey

    hopes to eoe the appeiatio, utilizatio, a eeae of the eistig ajo fos of at

    (Dilthey 1998 [1892], 725-726).

    It is important to note that a of daaalls ieas ae foue ipliitl o epliitl o iolog

    and, in particular, psychology. Indeed his chapter on the period eye (1988) begins with a standard

    description of the mechanics of vision. Gombrich, perhaps more than any other art historian,

    promoted the use of psychology (claiming in one interview that his approach to art history was

    always biological (Onians 2007, 159)) to shed light on problems in the discipline. His influential book,

     Art and Illusion, egis ith a uote fo Ma J. Fieläes Von Kunst und Kennershaft : At eig

    a thing of the mind, it follows that any scientific study of art will be psychological. It may be other

    things as ell, ut pshologial it ill alas e. (2002a, 1).

    However, Gombrich wrote  Art and Illusion in the 1960s, and Baxandall wrote Painting & Experience 

    in the 1970s. Since then, a great deal of progress has been made in understanding of the mind3

    . The

    20th

      etu sa the aial of a e siee4  (Kandel 2006, xii). Considerable advances in

    technology have exposed the human brain to closer examination than ever before. Although still far

    from fully understanding this highly complex organ, techniques such as functional magnetic

    resonance imaging (fMRI) and positron-emission tomography (PET) scans have allowed new insights

    3 Fo the puposes of this issetatio I shall use the tes i a ai itehageal. Kael (2006,

    xii) states that oe of the piiples of the e siee is that i a ai ae   isepaale a that,sipl put, i is a set of opeatios aie out the ai.4 Elsehee efee to as euosiee, ai stuies o ai siees.  

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    8/55

    8

    into the ais inner workings. Not only does the new technology permit the observation of single

    cells, but also of neural circuits in action (Kandel 2006, 305). Indeed, by the 1990s, fMRI allowed for

    the oitoig of eual atiit i eal tie (Onians 2007, 3). The ability to investigate the brain

    directly at a neural level has allowed scientists gain greater understanding of the mind by direct

    observation, thus gradually leading away from a strict behaviourist approach to psychology. Kandel

    (2006, xii) suaises the e siee of i as a siee that uses the poe of oleula

    iolog to eaie the geat eaiig steies of life.

    Although there may well be other aspets of the e siee eleat to ‘eaissae paitig,

    owing to restrictions of space, this work will limit its scope to mirror neurons, ambiguity, and

    neuroplasticity. In the process, I will highlight how each of these complements existing art-historical

    thinking about Renaissance painting, using examples where appropriate. In order to establish a

    suitable context it will be helpful to begin with a brief overview of the more general trends in the

    literature.

    One of the most comprehensive accounts of the rapprochement of the disciplines of art history and

    neuroscience is John Oias Neuroarthistory   (2007). An important feature of this book is its title,

    indicative in itself of the rising interest of both the neuroscientific and the art-historic communities

    in the bearing of recent advances in neuroscience on understanding art production and reception.

    Furthermore, Onians himself taught a postgraduate module in At a the dai, named after the

    1999 paper by Zeki, which was the first postgraduate course in an art history department that

    applied neuroscientific principles. Freedberg, for his part, founded the Art and Neuroscience

    Project at the Italian Academy for Advanced Studies in America in 2001. This project encourages,

    aog othe thigs, iestigatio of esposes to oks of at [since] developments in the cognitive

    euosiees hae geatl illuiate the eual sustate of suh esposes.  (The Art &

    Neuroscience Project n.d.).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    9/55

    9

    An interdisciplinary approach however is not without its risks. Considerable criticism can be found of

    those advocating oelo lais a aitios of iolog a the siees of the i (Kesner

    2009, 268). One of the more high-profile cases involves Goihs espose to ‘aahaa and

    Histeis (1999) somewhat provocative article The Science of Art –   A Neurological Theory of

     Aesthetic Experience  (Onians 2007, 8). Gombrich, Kesner (2009, 268) explains, objected to the

    authos  poor application of biology to culture, based as it was on a simplistic and reductionist

    account of art. 

    Although the potential pitfalls of straddling multiple disciplines are clear, I do not believe that this

    confrontational account of the relationship between art history and brain studies is representative

    of real trends. Each discipline has much to learn from the other. Indeed, the emphasis seems to be

    very much on inter-disciplinary collaboration, as a uik glae at Oias  (2007) bibliography

    reveals, with combined efforts from the likes of Freedberg (art historian) and Gallese (neuroscientist)

    or Hobson (psychiatrist) and Wohl (art historian). Mandelbaum (1970, vii) summarises this point

    succinctly;

    The paths of art historians, psychologists, and philosophers do not normally converge,

    even when they are dealing with a common problem, since their aims and their methods

    are in most cases radically different. Yet, questions regarding the nature of

    representation in art have recently provided a common meeting ground.

    A more particular problem for the present work is that of the applicability of neuroscience to

    Renaissance painting. It has been noted (Zeki 1999, 99) that the developments in our understanding

    of the mind lend themselves more to analysing art of the 20th

      century than to previous periods

    including the Renaissance. To uesta the easos fo this, it is ipotat to appeiate )ekis

    general approach to the subject. His starting assumption is that the function of art is an extension of

    the function of the visual brain, that is to acquire knowledge about the world (Zeki 1999, 1, 8). This

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    10/55

    10

    assumption leads Zeki to extrapolate principles of art from principles of vision. As shall be shown,

    this method encounters important limitations when applied to Renaissance art.

    As a neuroscientist specialising in the human visual system, Zeki in the 1980s and 1990s contributed

    much to the discovery and investigation of functionally specialised areas of the visual brain. The level

    of specialisation turned out to be greater than scientists suspected. Not only does the modularity of

    vision mean that there ae speifi goups of ells speialise i a iffeet attiute of the isual

    see, suh as fo, olou a otio (Zeki 1999, 59), but there are specific groups sensitive to

    particular colours but not to others, to vertical lines but not horizontal ones, or to movement in a

    particular direction (Zeki 1999, 60-62).

    One can begin to understand the way in which neuroscience can help one understand how a

    painting such as Olga ‘ozaoas Green Stripe  (Figure 1) affects the viewer. A bold green vertical

    stripe on a pale background excites localised groups of cells activated by those formal features, and

    the contrast itself is reinforcing for the brain since areas of high contrast in nature are usually

    information-rich and therefore attract attention(Ramachandran and Hirstein 1999, 25). The act of

    activating particular modules of the visual system in a targeted way and then enhancing them is also

    known as isolation (Ramachandran and Hirstein 1999, 22). It is this type of rather direct connection

    between the painting as a visual stimulus and the excitation of particular brain areas that prompts

    Zeki to declare that the artist is in a sense, a neuroscientist, exploring the potentials and capacities

    of the ai (Zeki n.d.). Where the approach seems to be less effective, however, is with a painting

    such as Leoaos Last Supper  or Rogier van der Weydens Descent from the Cross (Figure 2).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    11/55

    11

    Figure 1 - Olga Rozanova, Green Stripe (1918) Figure 2 - Rogier van der Weyden, Deposition (c.1435)

    Moe ats tee toas  abstraction and simplification means that, as stimuli, modern

    paintings arouse more isolated areas of the brain and therefore more specific responses than more

    complex figurative or narrative paintings (Zeki 1999, 99). For this reason, Inner Vision (1999) contains

    many examples from Impressionism, Cubism, Suprematism, Fauvism, and Kinetic art. Although Zeki

    develops a chapter entitled A euoiologial appaisal of Veee a Mihelagelo suh

    examples are rare. It is interesting to note too, that Ramachandran typically uses Indian art, such as

    the sculpture of the Goddess Parvati in Figure 3 for example, to elucidate his laws of aesthetics, but

    these too exhibit elements of abstraction in a way that Renaissance paintings do not. Even within

    the scope of modern art, it is recognised that science has little to offer in terms of explaining works

    such as Mael Duhaps Pissoir , implying that responses to this work are primarily socially

    constructed (Ramachandran 2000).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    12/55

    12

    Figure 3 - The Goddess Parvati

    I believe that the starting proposition that the overriding function of painting is the discovery of the

    world is reductionist to the point of offering little if any insight into figurative and narrative art.

    Although Zeki may be correct on some meta-level, this is not particularly helpful to art historians.

    Cota to )ekis uifig efiitio, a useful and necessary distinction between arts produced in

    different periods must be based on function.

    According to Gombrich (1984, 20), art should be judged primarily by standards of utility. Throughout

    histo, oks of at ee osiee to hae a efiite futio (Gombrich 1984, 20). As a

    consequence, it is not against our present taste that art should be assessed, but rather against a

    easue of hethe it oks  in terms of fulfilling its intended function (Gombrich 1984, 23).

    Similarly, in his discussion of the  Aims and Limits of Iconology   (1978, 5), Gombrich emphasises

    Hishs pia of gees i estalishig the itetio of the atists a theefoe the asi leel

    of meaning of the work itself. Baxandall too highlights the importance of reconstructing the atists

    intention in order to fully appreciate a painting, although it is debatable to what extent this is really

    ever achievable (Baxandall 1989, 109).

    While in Expressionism the 20th

     century saw the rise of an entire movement dedicated to exploring

    the atists ie eotioal ol a ouiatig it to a ie auiee, in the 15th

     century, as

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    13/55

    13

    Baxandall (Baxandall 1988, 3) put it, painting was still too important to be left to the painters. The

    atist i the ‘eaissae oke to a pogae poie his pato (Gombrich 1978, 6). Such

    a programme was contractual and could specify not only the subject to be painted, but also which

    colours were to be used, what quality pigment was to be used, and what figures were to be

    included, for example (Baxandall 1988, 6, 12). This therefore poses a problem for the Renaissance

    art historian wishing to explore Renaissance art from a biological perspective, since it appears that

    biology played a relatively minor role in shaping the art relative to certain other factors. This point is

    central to Freedberg also, who, in his quest for universals in The Power of Images –  Studies in the

    History and Theory of Response (1989, xx), stresses the importance of not fogettig that esposes

    are forged on the anvil of culture and in the fie of patiula histo.

    I believe this problem is not insurmountable, but it does require a more detailed look at the function

    of Renaissance paintings.

    2.1 

     A Note on Function

    Painting in the Renaissance had a fundamentally different function to art of the 20 th century. Most

    Renaissance painting was religious. This apparently trivial observation, in fact, has certain important

    consequences. There existed a tradition in Catholic thinking (Welch 2000, 137), stemming from Pope

    Gregory I at the turn of the 6th

     century, and filtering down to Thomas Aquinas in the 13th

     century. A

    contemporary of Aquinas, Johannes Balbus (John of Genoa), wrote in his Catholicon that the reason

    for images in churches was threefold;

    First , for the instruction of simple people [...] Second , so that the mystery of the

    incarnation and the examples of the Saints may be the more active in our memory

    through being presented daily to our eyes. Third , to excite feelings of devotion, these

    being aroused more effectively by things seen than by things heard. (Johannes Balbus

    cited in Baxandall 1988, 41)

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    14/55

    14

    This orthodox stance was reiterated by the Council of Trent in 1563 (Welch 2000, 165). This is not to

    suggest, however, that religious art was uniform since the time of Gregory I. Indeed, an important

    poit to ote is that Gego Is aage ol efes to the fist of the thee  parts that Balbus mentions

    above, and the other two were, therefore, added later. This development may be related to the

    important shift which occurred between the 13th

     and 16th

     etuies, hee the ste atioalit of

    scholastic theologians was gradually modified by warmth of feeling and emotion (Huyghe 1967, 19).

    St Bernard, like St Francis, encouraged their followers to contemplate God not only though the mind

    but also through the emotions. This shift resulted in a need for a physical and material

    representation.

    In Painting & Experience, Baxandall (1988, 43-47) deals with Quattrocento painting, which

    functioned very much as a collaborative creation between the artist and the audience, the former

    providing the scene as a generic foundation for the latter to build their personal mediation upon. As

    suh, the paite as a pofessioal isualize of the hol stoies (Baxandall 1988, 43). The painter,

    therefore, avoided depicting people or places in too much detail, instead complimenting the

    eholes interior vision (Baxandall 1988, 45-47). Although the centuries that followed saw a shift

    towards greater detail, partly influenced by both technological and stylistic developments in the

    north countries, the basic function of paintings in Renaissance Italy as aids to religious mediation did

    not change.

    An important piece of evidence for the role internal representations played in prayer, the book

     Zardino de Oration (1454) offers the following instructions:

    Moving slowly from episode to episode, meditate on each one, dwelling on each single

    stage and step of the story. And if at any point you feel a sensation of piety, stop: do not

    pass on as long as that sweet and devout sentiment lasts. (cited in Baxandall 1988, 46)

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    15/55

    15

    In his take on the emotive function of images, Dominican Fra Michele da Carcano draws attention to

    another important aspect of the tendency towards realism during the 15th

     century. He writes that

    with images e a be moved when they see [the Saints as if atuall peset cited in Baxandall

    1988, 41). Gombrich (2002b, 84), among others, repeatedly draws attention to the importance of

    the beholders ole as eyewitness for the development of painting in the Renaissance away from the

    pitogaphi fo of pitoial aatio toas atualis. Giotto was one of the key figures to

    stee paitig i the ietio of aati epesetatio, iflueced partly by friars whose

    sermons encouraged the faithful to visualise the events from the Bible and the lives of the Saints as

    if they were actually present (Gombrich 1984, 151-152). It became necessary not only to represent

    hat happee, as i the pitogaphi stle, ut also uiall how  it happened (Gombrich 2002b,

    21, 89, Gombrich 1976, 16). It as pehaps thus that Gego Is aage as modified in the late

    middle ages, although one can only speculate.

    The early Franciscan tract, the Little book on the meditation on the Passion of Christ divided

    according to seven hours of the day  by Pseudo-Bede, provides an invaluable glimpse into the method

    of meditation required from the faithful:

    It is necessary that when you concentrate on these things in your contemplation, you do

    so as if you were actually present at the very time when he suffered. And in grieving you

    should regard yourself as if you had our Lord suffering before your very eyes. (cited in

    Freedberg 1989, 171)

    According to Freedberg (1989, 171), the narrative in the book addresses the reader occasionally to

    euie, What the oul ou o if ou ee to see these thigs?. Desiptios of Chists suffeig

    in this, as in other treatises that followed, were very gruesome and vivid (ibid.).

    The above discussion shows that when considering art from any period, including the one under

    investigation here, from a neuroscientific perspective, the focus should be less on the direct

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    16/55

    16

    connection between the mind of the artist and that of the beholder, but rather on the intended

     function  of the art work and the mind of the beholder. By implementing an integrated approach

    which combines the analytical elements in this way, it may be possible to establish the relevance of

    neuroscience for Renaissance art. With this in mind, I will not turn to the first of the three

    developments from neuroscience to be discussed.

    3.  Contributions from Neuroscience

    The present section will focus in more detail on the three key discoveries to be considered, namely,

    mirror neurons, ambiguity, and neuroplasticity. The section on mirror neurons will also include two

    paintings Leoao a Viis Last Supper  a ‘ogie a e Wees Deposition) as case studies

    to be analysed in light of the theory. At a high level, the different parts will be organised in terms of

    an explanation of the discovery followed by an examination of its relevance for Renaissance

    painting. At the end of each section, I will pause to reflect on the contributions offered by each of

    the discoveries.

    3.1  Mirror Neurons

    there was speech in their dumbness, language in their very gesture (Shakespeare, The

    Winter's Tale Act v Scene 2 Line no 14-15)

    The observation by Rizzolatti et al. in 1996 that certain neurons in macaque monkeys fire both when

    the monkey performs an action and when it observes that action being performed by a human is

    cosiee ‘aahaa as the single most important "unreported" ... sto of the eae

    (Ramachandran n.d.). The easo fo ‘aahaas ethusias is that the haateisti

    behaviour of mirror neurons (dubbed by hi as oke see oke o euos oul e uial

    in understanding previously elusive aspects of human nature such as non-verbal communication,

    learning by imitation, the development of language, and, crucially for the present discussion,

    empathy. Oes ailit to put oeself i aothes shoes, to epathise ith thei oo, to

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    17/55

    17

    understand the intention behind their actions, could all be attributable to a large extent to mirror

    neurons.

    It must be recognised that discussion of the role of empathy in art follows in the tradition of the likes

    of Friedrich Theodor Vischer, Robert Vischer and Heinrich Wölfflin. As early as the 19th

      century,

    Fieih Vishe ote that the uosious poess hee the sujet pojets his o he

    feelings into the inanimate object must be investigated on the level of our physical and psychological

    ogaizatio (Harrison et al. 1998, 682). Ultiatel, it as Fieihs so, ‘oet Vishe, ho

    embedded empathy as a central concern in art history (Harrison, Wood and Gaiger 1998, 682). In

    1873, Robert Vischer adopted the term Einfühlung5  to esie the phsial esposes that ae

    geeate the oseatio of paitigs (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 198). Building on Robert

    Vishes ieas, Wölffli eploe the pshologial a phsial effets of patiula ahitetual

    forms on the beholder (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 198). At the turn of the 20th

      century, Aby

    Warburg wrote about the Pathosformel : the representation of inner emotional states through

    particular physical representations of figures. Bernard Berenson even approached the modern

    understanding of empathetic responses, suggesting that the movement of figures depicted in

    ‘eaissae at as epeiee the iees o usles, thee ehaig thei epeiee

    of the work itself (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 198).

    Looking back even further, Socrates is purported to have taught the need to represent not only the

    phsial i at, ut that the phsial shoul i tu eeal the the atio of the soul Tes psyches

    erga) (Gombrich 2002a, xxii). Indeed, Warburg believed that Renaissance masters learned the skill of

    achieving Pathosformel   from classical Greece (Gombrich 2002a, 20). This seems to agree with

    Paofsks theo that the Italia ‘enaissance of the 14th

     and 15th

     centuries was characterised by a

    appoheet of lassial fo a lassial otet (Panofsky 1972, 111).

    5 A liteal taslatio i Eglish oul e feelig i.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    18/55

    18

    All this, Goih (1970, 36) suaises suitl, tes to oooate the hpothesis that e

    interpret and code the perception of our fellow creatures not so much in visual but in muscular

    terms.

    Since their discovery, the existence of mirror neurons in the human brain could only be suggested

    via fMRI scans that indicated increased activity in certain areas of the brain. Very recently, however,

    obstacles to observing individual cells within the brain were finally overcome. This allowed for the

    existence of mirror neurons in humans to be proven, and for their mechanism to be demonstrated

    (Mukamel et al. 2010). In their important article, Motion, emotion and empathy in esthetic

    experience, Freedberg and Gallese (2007) specifically focus on mirroring mechanisms and empathy,

    describing several different types of empathetic response to visual stimuli. Broadly, three key types

    of response are identified. Each shall be described in turn.

    The f ist oes the oil egageet ith gestues, oeets a itetios of othes

    (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 201). The authors offer as an example Mihelagelos Prisoners,

    explaining that esposes ofte take the form of felt activation of the muscles that appear to be

    atiate ithi the sulptue itself (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 197), thus effectively

    communicating to the beholder the sense of exertion the figure must be experiencing as it tries to

    free itself from the block of marble (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 198). 

    The seo tpe of io espose oes  the feelig of epath fo oil sesatios 

    (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 201-202). Caaaggios Incredulity of St. Thomas, for example, is shown

    to arouse iees soatoseso sste as the peeie to e touhe a poe theseles.

    Furthermore, these tactile sensations are localised in that part of the body observed to be affected

    in the painting, i this ase the thoa hee Jesus ou is situate. A i Goas Desastres de la

    Guerra, bodily empathy arises as a result of both the representation of unbalanced figures as well as

    from images of bodily harm and mutilation. The latter is seen to activate those areas of the brain

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    19/55

    19

    normally activated during the actual experience of pain as well as the ensuing shock (Freedberg and

    Gallese 2007, 198). Significantly, the experience of physical empathy often translates into emotional

    empathy  – the thi tpe of io espose (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 197). The latter point

    suggests that a beholder is capable of identifying the emotions of others by internally imitating their

    actions (Freedberg and Gallese 2007, 201-202).

    It is worthwhile introducing, at this point, a consideration of function into the discussion. In The

    Power of Images, Freedberg (1989, 1-2) offers two contemporary accounts of empathetic responses

    to paintings. The first of these, from 1584, emphasises the ability of a painting to rouse the beholder

    to a wide variety of emotions or desires, depending on what is represented in the painting (see

    Appendix 1). This aout ehoes Aletis On Painting (1970 [1435-1436]) where he wrote that we

    weep with the weeping, laugh with the laughing, a giee ith the gieig. The second account,

    from 1587, is worth restating here in full:

    [...] since the eye is the most perfect among the exterior senses, it moves the minds to

    hatred, love and fear, more than all the other senses ...; and when the beholders see

    very grave tortures present and apparently real ... they are moved to true piety, and

    thereby drawn to devotion and reverence  –  all of which are remedies and excellent

    means for their salvation. (cited in Freedberg 1989, 2)

    This account brings to the fore the tradition of empathic meditation (Freedberg 1989, 164). This

    tradition ties in firmly with the earlier discussion of function, and it is worth remembering that

    images ee a effetie a of ietig peoples attetio toas Chists suffeigs a goo

    deeds by exciting them to empathy (Freedberg 1989, 164).

    It is interesting to note that mirror neurons are an inbuilt feature of the human brain. This suggests

    that the neural mechanism underlying empathy is universal as it is shared by all humans regardless

    of when or where they lived. This is an important point, and one we shall return to, as it addresses

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    20/55

    20

    the perennial debate in art history about whether there are any aspects of human cognition that are

    universal in this sense, or whether this is always historically specific and moulded by the particular

    society or culture in question.

    In osieig the o a its laguage i th

    -century painting, Baxandall (1988) focuses on the

    highly codified and formalised movements and gestures exhibited. This method of interpretation can

    be revealing, although highly dependent on the scarce literary evidence from the time. Thus, the

    Mirror of the World from the 1520s provides a rare insight into the meaning of gestures by matching

    them to particular emotional states or particular circumstances. This approach does, however,

    overlook those more spontaneous gestures, of which the interpretation is none the less important. I

    believe that complementing the contemporary literary evidence from the period with an

    understanding of mirror neurons may help the modern audience view Renaissance art more like a

    Renaissance audience. I will now look at two specific examples of paintings where I believe

    knowledge of mirror neurons and their role can provide toas  viewer with an augmented

    experience of the works.

    Case Studies: Empathetic Responses

    The to paitigs I ill o eploe i oe etail, i ie of the isussio aoe, ae Leoaos

    Last Supper   a ‘ogies Deposition. Although the paintings are from different decades and

    locations, I believe each one can demonstrate different aspects of the empathetic response. It is the

    itetio hee to use the to ase stuies to eostate ho the popose itegate appoah,

    combining neuroscience and a consideration of function, can contribute to the appreciation of

    Renaissance art and also highlight any limitations of the approach.

    Leonardo da Vinci’s Last Supper

    The istoria will move the soul of the beholder when each man painted there clearly

    shows the movement of his own soul. [...] These movements of the soul are made

    known by movements of the body. (Alberti 1970 [1435-1436])

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    21/55

    21

    The most important consideration in painting is that the movements of the figure

    expresses its mental state, such as desire, scorn, anger, pity, and the like. (da Vinci 2008,

    168)

    Leonardo da Vinci painted the Last Supper in 1495 –1497 in what was at the time a mausoleum of

    the monastery of Santa Maria delle Grazie in Milan (Zöllner 2007, 122). The painting depicts the

    moment that Jesus tells his apostles that one of them would betray him: When Jesus had thus said,

    he was troubled in spirit, and testified, and said, Verily, verily, I say unto you, that one of you shall

    betray me. (John 13.21. The Gospel of Joh futhe eouts the isiples eatios as the looked

    one on another, doubting of whom he spake Joh .. These reactions of surprise, anger and

    questioning are captured in the group of three to the left of the painting (Saints Bartholomew,

    James, son of Alphaeus and Andrew) and another to the right of Christ (Saints Thomas, James the

    Greater and Philip).

    Figure 4 - Bartholomew, James, son of Alphaeus and

    Andrew, detail from the Last Supper  

    Figure 5 - Jesus, Thomas, James the Greater and Philip,

    detail from the Last Supper  

    The aout otiues to esie the see: Simon Peter therefore beckoned to him, that he

    should ask who it should be of whom he spake. (John 13.24). This is captured in Figure 6. Peter then

    leas i toas Jesus east a asks hi, hile Jesus ases: He it is, to whom I shall give a sop,

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    22/55

    22

    when I have dipped it. And when he had dipped the sop, he gave it to Judas Iscariot, the son of

    “io. (John 13.26). Figure 7 shows Judas and Jesus reaching for the same piece of bread.

    Figure 6 - Matthew, Jude Thaddeus and Simon the Zealot,

    detail from the Last Supper  

    Figure 7 - Judas Iscariot, Peter and John, detail from the

    Last Supper  

    The story is infused with drama. Leonardo manages to convey a sense of this through the gestures

    and attitudes of the apostles. Both James, son of Alphaeus, and James the Greater raise their hands

    in astonishment, for example, the former raising his eyebrows and the latter with mouth wide open.

    Bartholomew, meanwhile, stands up to lean across the table with great intensity, both hands on the

    table, and his powerful gaze adding to the spectacle. It is interesting to note an account of

    Leoaos fiend Luca Pacioli, who wrote that it was

    not possible to imagine the apostles more agitated upon hearing the voice of unfailing

    truth [...] In their poses and their expressions, they seem to be speaking one to another

    and this one to that with vigorous astonishment and dismay. (cited in Zöllner 2007, 122)

    Even Darwin (2006 [1872], 1430) efes to the Leoaos Last Supper  to eeplif astoishet i

    his writings on the gestures of the human body. Just as Alberti (1970 [1435-1436]) advocates the use

    of many and varied gestures in a painting to render the picture more compelling, Leonardo here

    deploys these gestures with a specific aim. The image conveys hat it ust hae ee like he

    Christ uttered those words (Gombrich 1984, 226).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    23/55

    23

    A consideration of the eholes io espose permits the art historian to place the beholder at

    the centre of the analysis. To that end, it is possile to uesta Leoaos use of epessie

    gestiulatio asie to the haates as a etho of heighteig the eholes epeiee of the

    scene. In beholding the Last Supper , in accordance with the taught meditation techniques, the

    behole ust oetate o eah of the figues i tu. A, i aoae ith Leoaos o

    intention, and thanks to the mirror system, he should feel angered with Andrew, astonished with

    James the Greater, and perhaps saddened with John. Not only does the beholder reflect

    intellectually on the parts of the story as he concentrates on each character or group of characters in

    turn (as he would have done presented with an earlier, pictographic version of the story (Figure 8)),

    but reacts empathically to each character also, based on a mirror response to each gesture, thus

    being further implicated as a witness to the scene.

    Figure 8 - Stefano Di Giovanni Sassetta, The Last Supper  (1423) 

    There is the danger here of overstating the case. The gesticulations of the Apostles would be difficult

    to interpret to this level of meaning if the beholder was unfamiliar with the story (Gombrich 2002b,

    69). Uoutel, a othe fatos oul hae fe ito the eholes epeiee of this ual.

    There is, simultaneously however, the danger of dismissing altogether the part played by empathy

    (and by the mirror mechanism). An experiment cited by Changeux (1994, 192) provides considerable

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    24/55

    24

    insight. The neurologist Alexandre Luria, while investigating the impact of lesions of the frontal lobe

     – one of the areas where mirror neurons occur (Rizzolatti and Craighero 2004)  –  found that when

    patients were presented with a painting by Baron Klodt, the Last Spring, they were incapable of

    understanding its content. The scene depicted a ig gil sittig i a ahai hile he elel

    parents watch her sadly and her sister stands by the window in an attitude of profound sorrow

    (Luria in Changeux (1994, 192). Luias sujets, uale to establish a coherent view of the picture,

    guesse ase o the gils go that the ee lookig at a eig see. Chageu ituitiel

    suggests that the frontal cortex plas a essetial ole i iseig the etal states, affects,

    beliefs, desires and intentions of othes, whether real or represented in a painting (Changeux 1994,

    192). It may be said then, without exaggeration, that it is thanks to the mirror neuron system that

    the gestures can be interpreted at all. I believe the knowledge of the story and the understanding of

    the gestures in terms of emotional states combine in the painting and reinforce one another to

    produce a powerful holistic effect.

    Thee is a ee, hoee, fo ultual sesitiit. Goihs (2002b, 69) perceptive analysis of the

    mural reveals that in the Last Supper , Leonardo combines spontaneous and conventionalised

    gesticulation, reporting that the gestures themselves are often taken as representative of a

    Mediterranean culture. Having said that, both Gombrich (1976, 33) and Baxandall (1988, 48-49)

    emphasise the trans-cultural influence of popular preachers in the 13th century. As Baxandall (1988,

    64) points out, these ee skille isual pefoes ith a oifie age of gestiulatio ot speial

    to Ital.  It has been demonstrated, in addition, that the expression and interpretation of certain

    basic emotions (such as happiness, sadness, fear, and surprise) exhibit remarkable consistency

    across cultures (Feldman 1993, 368-369, Ekman and O'Sullivan 1991).

    It ust e ote that, all aouts, Leoaos Last Supper  was an exceptional rendition of this

    traditional theme (Zöllner 2007, Gombrich 1984, 224). It is notable precisely for the animated nature

    of the characters and the diversity of their attitudes, as the contemporary accounts demonstrate.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    25/55

    25

    Pehaps this the plaes Leoaos Last Supper  among those works that traversed the tradition of

    pictographic representation and ushered in the new, dramatic, style of painting. One reason why this

    depiction was unusual was ue to the elatie iffiult of taslatig Jesus pshologial suffeig

    into a visual representation. The isussio aoe has sho that osieig the eholes

    mirror response, the audience is brought to the fore of the analysis, and the intended experience of

    the work can be reconstructed somewhat more accurately than is possible otherwise. Furthermore,

    the analysis has shown that consideration of the mirror response only makes sense and adds value

    to the analysis if considered in conjunction with the art-historical context. As a theme, the Last

    Supper seems to have been less open to the imparting of the type of emotional intensity discussed

    above than certain other themes from the Passion. Other more physical aspects of the Passion offer

    the painter a more straightforward message to convey. The following section addresses this

    hypothesis in more detail by examining Rogier a e Wees Deposition6.

    Rogier van der Weyden’s Deposition 

    One approach to determining the meaning of medieval painting, pioneered by Panofsky in his

    influential article on the Arnolfini Portrait  (1934), is that of isguise solis. I espose to the

    ensuing pursuit of coded messages in pictures, Marrow (1986) tries to re-focus attention on two

    points that he deems more central to the task of understanding pictures. The first of these is a

    greater emphasis on the eholes espose i.e. hat oe "oes" i fot of it, o ith it  (1986,

    152)), and the second is the ole of the oks i stiulatig e states of osiousess Marrow

    uses Rogiers Deposition to elaborate on these points (Figure 2).

    “iilal to Leoaos Last Supper , Rogiers Deposition stands at the crossroads between the 13th

    -

    century pictographic tradition and the increasingly prominent dramatic representation in the 15th

     

    century. The 13th

    -century Crucifixion below (Figure 9), for example, converted scripture into image

    form in such a way as to conceptualise the key theme; the idea of compassion. This was embodied,

    6 Also known as The Descent from the Cross, or simply Descent .

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    26/55

    26

    tpiall, the Vigi o the oe ha, ho itesse he sos eath, a “t. Fais o the

    othe, ho epathise ith Chists suffeig to such a degree that he experienced the stomata

    himself (Marrow 1986, 153). The Virgin is shown, furthermore, with a sword piercing her heart, as a

    liteal epesetatio of “ieos pophe7.

    Figure 9 - The Crucifixion, miniature from a 13th-century Psalter

    The 14th

     century saw the invention of the  Andachtsbild  (the devotional image). These images were

    characterised by the gradual isolation of holy figures from recognisable settings (Marrow 1986, 153).

    Rather, artists istille the essage of Mas a Chists opassioate loe ito its oe essetial 

    elements (Marrow 1986, 153-154). This development coincides with the rise of personal meditative

    devotion in the northern countries, hat Paofsk efee to as oteplatie iesio 

    (Marrow 1986, 154). These images had the function, therefore, of stimulating the appropriate

    emotions in viewers (Marrow 1986, 155).

    7 Yea, a so shall piee though th o soul also, that the thoughts of a heats a e eeale.

    (Luke 2.35)

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    27/55

    27

    Rogiers Deposition shares some of the Andachtsbild ’s characteristics. As von Simson (1953, 9) points

    out, the see is stitl liite to the hua sphee, ithout the patiulas of akgou o

    landscapes to distract the viewer from the unfolding drama. The intended effect of the composition

    is to pusue the sigle thee of laet ito its fiest eotioal aifiatios  (von Simson 1953,

    10). Indeed, the subject of the painting can be specified as the juxtaposition of the  passio  and

    compassion (von Simson 1953, 11). This is epesete isuall Mas postue ioig that of

    Jesus. It is worth pausing here to describe briefly the historical development of this theme.

    The 12th

      and 13th

      centuries saw an increasing intimacy in the relationship between Mary and her

    dead son. The assoiatio of Mas suffeig ith that of Chists is a pat of Chistia otie that

    stems from the writings of Bernard of Clairvaux in the 12th

      century (von Simson 1953, 11). The

    association grows stronger throughout the 13th

     century, inspired partly by the increased emphasis

    laid by St. Francis and his followers on the affect. Whereas in previous times Mary was shown to

    possess a piestl igit i fae of he sos saifie, the   forming attitude now held the Virgins

    suffering in such reverence that Bonaventure was inspired to suggest that at the Crucifixion Mary

    as tasfoe ito the likeess of Chist (von Simson 1953, 12-13).

    These tendencies reached a peak in the 14th

     and 15th

     centuries, giving rise to what von Simson (1953,

    13) efes to as the age of Copassio. The Pietà as a devotional image, for example, now

    becomes second in popularity only to the Man of Sorrows (von Simson 1953, 14). Indeed, the

    Speculum humanae salvationis, published in 1324, did much to popularise the association by

    following the “ee “tatios of Chists Passio ith the “ee “oos of Mary (von Simson 1953,

    12-13). By the mid-15th

      century, then, the  passio  and compassio  are perceived as inseparable by

    writers such as Bernardine of Siena and Denis the Carthusian (von Simson 1953, 14). As von Simson

    suaises, The aste thee aopte the mariology of the most famous theologian of his time

    and country [Denis], i a iage hih popula eotios eee itelligile to eeoe. (1953,

    15).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    28/55

    28

    Although Marrow (1986, 156) criticises von Simson for over-emphasising the importance of liturgical

    and doctrinal content of the painting, both authors do, in fact, insist on the primacy of the

    eholes espose. Von Simson (1953, 16) eplais that it is though estalishig the o of

    siilitue  between the beholder and Jesus that the artist brings the doctrine to life. Indeed,

    unlocking the meaning of Rogiers Deposition  lies on the level of human experience or, in other

    os, the otie ha to e lie to eoe effetie (von Simson 1953, 15).

    Marrow (1986) claims that the iees espose  is not only inspired towards the appropriate

    response by contemplating Christ and the Virgin, but in the sees witnesses, and not least the

    Virgin herself, these responses are actually exemplified   (Marrow 1986, 155). This, according to

    Marrow (1986, 155), represents a shift in emphasis unique to the Renaissance, away from the

    traditional subject matter, that is the story or idea depicted, and towards the beholder. In some

    sese, Ma i ‘ogies Deposition  is an aspirational representation of the beholder. In summary

    then, Marrow (1986, 157) argues that works such as Rogiers Deposition 

    surpassed the symbolic images of compassion of the thirteenth century, and the

     Andachtsbilder  of the fourteenth, both of which espoused compassion only conceptually

    or by inference, by visualizing and thus explicitly extolling diverse forms of emotional

    response to traditional Christian subjects.

    Subsequently, Maos (1986, 163) argument turns to establishing the relationship between artistic

    stimuli and consciousness itself. At a high level, he explains that the new method of representation

    required a different engagement from the viewer. In particular, the meaning of the work now

    depended to a much greater degree on the viewer experiencing the appropriate emotional

    response. An important change, therefore, from Middle Ages was characterised by a work of art no

    loge eig efiale eel hat is epesete ut its eaig eig vested also in effects

    hih ae oetl ultiate i the ehole (Marrow 1986, 169).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    29/55

    29

    Although I agee ith the ke ieas i oth Maos (1986) and Simsons (1953) analyses, I do not

    think that these fully address the question of the beholders espose to the ok i uestio.

    Mao oest uite eplai why   the image of Mary should affect the viewer in the first place.

    Although her image certainly functions as a reminder that hers is the appropriate emotional

    response that the beholder should aspire to, I would like to suggest that this works in combination

    with the mirror response aroused by the image. The image of Mary involves the viewer in a direct

    bodily engagement with the painting. As methods of engaging the iees osiousess, Mao

    (1986) cites instances of artists using mirrors that face the viewer or outwardly gazes from

    protagonists. I think that the evocation of the different types of mirror response could be added to

    this list of tools that the artist can deploy to achieve his aim. The recognition and understanding of

    this tool seems critical, therefore, to recreating the intended 15th

    -century experience of the painting.

    Practical experiments investigating the viewer response to different paintings are not within scope

    of this essay. One might only hypothesise here that results of such tests on the effects of ‘ogies 

    Deposition  would reveal the different characters in the painting to arouse different mirror

    responses. Aside from Christ and Mary, already discussed, one would expect viewers to empathise

    with the distressed woman on the left of the panel (Figure 10) (perhaps Mary of Cleophas, Marys

    sister), symptomatic of an emotional   mirror response. Viewers may also feel unbalanced, as they

    hae ee sho to o fae ith Goas Desastres de la Guerra (see Section 3.1), by the sight of

    Mary Magdalene, tiste as she stas at Chists feet (Figure 11).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    30/55

    30

    Figure 10 - Mary of Cleophas (?), detail from the

    Deposition 

    Figure 11 - Mary Magdalene, detail from the Deposition 

    What may be referred to as the mechanics of a painting - that is its composition, colours, and other

    formal aspects - are largely discernible. If the stated hypotheses are correct, however, this would

    cast fresh light onto the mechanics of the beholders espose, all the more important if this is the

    true (or at least other significant) subject of the painting. Again, I would argue that the power of the

    painting is derived from the successful integration of the narrative, the formal aspects of the

    painting, and the manipulation of the audience participation by the evocation of empathetic

    response. Thus, if indeed the otie ha to e lie to eoe effetie (von Simson 1953, 15), it

    is now possible to see the important roles played by the artist, the painting, and the audience in

    bringing it to life.

    To eiteate, pesete ith ‘ogies Deposition the modern viewer is faced with the usual problem

    of bridging his time and culture and that of Rogier and his audience in order to appreciate the

    painting more fully. As von Simson (1953, 15) poits out, The etet to hih the age as oe

    oteplatio of these eets supasses oe uestaig. An awareness of mirror responses

    can perhaps reveal an overlap between the modern viewer and the 15th

    -century viewers espose.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    31/55

    31

    As ith Leoaos Last Supper , the analysis demonstrates how the investigation into mirror

    responses could be combined with an appreciation of the iconography to contribute to recreating

    the original intended experience of the work.

    Perhaps the new light shed on this work ca also help aess Maos (1986) concern with the

    relationship between the consciousness of the audience and the artwork. While the inversion of the

    subject matter described above is certainly significant, it may not be as unique as Marrow suggests

    (1986). He writes that, Nee efoe [...] had the situations of the observed in art and its observer

    ee so epliitl eese. (Marrow 1986, 165). It a e appopiate hee to eall Paofsks

    theory about the rapprochement of classical form and classial otet, a to suggest that ‘ogies

    Deposition i fat otais eleets of Waugs Pathosformel . What I would like to suggest here is

    that ‘ogies Deposition adopts not only classical forms, but classical aims too, in order to achieve

    the highly emotive effect described above, albeit in a different context, namely a Christian one.

    Examples of possible classical forms prefiguring images of the dead Christ are shown in the figures

    below. Figure 12 is reminiscent of images of the Pietà, while Figure 13 of the deposition itself.

    Figure 12 - Eos and Kephalos (1st

     half of 5th

     century before

    Christ)

    Figure 13 - Niobide (1st

     half of 5th

     century before Christ)

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    32/55

    32

    Parallels between the characters in these mythological scenes and Jesus and Mary are not the only

    ones that can be drawn. Indeed, Warburg exemplified his concept of Pathosformel  with reference to

    the Maenads as the types borrowed in Renaissance scenes of the Crucifixion to depict the mourning

    women at the foot of the cross (Wind 1937). Indeed,  Figure 15 offers a striking comparison with

    Ma Magalee i ‘ogies Deposition.

    Figure 14 - Image of Maenad Figure 15 - Relief of Maenad

    What is more, I believe it is the universality of the mirror system mechanism that permits certain

    forms to be reused in different contexts while maintaining particular effects. If this is true, it would

    be testable experimentally, and would be supported i f toas iees were shown to exhibit the

    predicted esposes. This a also patl eplai h soe paitigs, suh as ‘ogies Deposition,

    receive as much attention today as they do despite the cultural and temporal distance. This point

    shall be developed further in Section 3.3. 

    To conclude, with reference to the research question stated in Section 1, the discussion and analyses

    above have gone some way to answering how neuroscience can contribute to the appreciation of

    Renaissance art nowadays. Crucially, the analyses of the case studies are demonstrative of an

    integrative approach to understanding art works. Zeki (1999, 28-29) argues that what is important

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    33/55

    33

    for a general appreciation of a work of art can be gained through a direct experience of it thanks to

    the universality of perception. The rest, he claims, should be left to the connoisseurs. I do not think

    that a strict distinction between these different kinds of knowledge about a painting is a helpful one.

    I believe it is precisely the marriage of these different elements that can add the most value to

    toas  appreciation of the works. I believe that the analysis here has shown that any universal

    aspects of brain mechanisms, in this case empathetic response, cannot be isolated from the rest of

    iconography and can only be truly helpful in revealing the meaning of paintings when integrated

    with iconographic and other art-historical knowledge.

    This approach has revealed several specific insights into Renaissance art. Whilst lending valuable

    suppot to daaalls  ideas about how gestures and movements in paintings were read by a

    contemporary audience, the consideration of mirror responses has allowed for further

    reconstruction of the intended experience of these works. In particular, it has allowed for the

    consideration of the effect of the less codified and formalised gestures that Baxandall (1988)

    explores in Painting & Experience. A key to this is the emphasis given in the analysis to the

    eholes esponse itself. This seems particularly relevant given the increasing consideration in the

    peio gie to the eholes affetie ioleet i the oks. Highlighting these aspects in the

    analysis, it has also been possible to suggest broader implications for the persistence of certain

    evocative forms (Pathosformel  a thei elatio to the eholes osiousess. This section has

    also elaborated on some key themes of the discussion. Namely, it has explored the roles of nature

    and nurture in the production and consumption or art works, as well as the corresponding status of

    the universal versus the historical in art history. These themes shall be explored further in the

    following Sections.

    In spite of the limitations of )ekis appoah  discussed above, he does nevertheless make some

    significant contributions, not least through the study of ambiguity to which I shall now turn.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    34/55

    34

    3.2 

     Ambiguity

    Ambiguity  – rabbit or duck  – is clearly the key to the whole problem of image reading.

    (Gombrich 2002a, 198)

    Goihs uhaateistiall hisial oet oes itoue a oetheless ipotat thee

    to the present discussion. Ambiguity can be understood at various levels of complexity. Simple

    perceptual ambiguity, at one end of the scale, is well exemplified by such bi-stable illusions as the

    rabbit/duck illusion (Figure 16) or the Necker cube illusion (Figure 17). In both cases, the stimulus on

    the page is constant while the brain switches between two alternative views (between a rabbit and a

    duck in the former and between two alternative perspectives on the cube in the latter). These

    illusions present the brain with too little information to be able to resolve the ambiguity. As a result

    the ai sithes etee to euall plausile itepetatios, although at a given time, only

    oe itepetatio is possile (Zeki 2004, 183).

    Figure 16 - The 'rabbit or duck' illusion Figure 17 - The Necker cube illusion

    To understand this phenomenon at a neural level, it is necessary to distinguish, in the first place,

    etee oia oes a essetial oes. As etioe i Section 1, the brain is subject to a

    high degree of functional specification. In the human visual system, some groups of cells are

    responsible solely for detecting motion, whilst others react only to certain colours, and others

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    35/55

    35

    respond to orientation (i.e. vertical or horizontal forms). A neural node describes one collective of

    suh speialise ells. A oe is sai to e essetial if its atiatio esults i the osious

    perception of the attribute that that node is responsible for, without further processing by the brain.

    To account for the register of discrete attributes due to the activity of essential nodes, Zeki (2004)

    has oie the te 'ioosiousess. Oe pat of the isual sste i the ai es ponsible for

    olou peeptio, ae V, is a goo eaple of a essetial oe. Atiit theei esults i the

    osious peeptio of olou ithout the ee fo futhe poessig   (Zeki 2004, 177). Essential

    nodes can, therefore, be thought of as perceptual sites in the brain that function simultaneously as

    processing sites. Intervention from a higher  cognitive area such as learning or memory (also

    efee to as the top-o ifluee  is not required to process and interpret the stimulus.

    Consequently, the illusions discussed above imply that each essential node, and therefore each

    microconsciousness, can have multiple states, with each state resulting in a different interpretation

    of the stimulus (i.e. rabbit or duck). Zeki (ibid.) conjectures that these states must be determined by

    the strengthening of one set of cells within the node at the expense of another.

    These ambiguous images demonstrate another key principle of perception. At least since Plato, a

    psychological hypothesis has existed that human perception is concerned with the extraction of

    stable universals (the essential) from the ever-changing world around us (Gombrich et al. 1970, 3).

    This particular role of the human visual system is upheld oe stuies i this fiel. The ol

    kolege that is oth auiig, ites Zeki (1999, 5), is kolege aout the euig a

    haateisti popeties of the ol. As suh, under normal circumstances (for the above illusions

    are contrived), the ai is a aiguit-esolig ahie pa eellee (Kandel 2006, 297),

    processing, as it does, incomplete and changing inputs to create a logiall oheet output.  It

    should be noted, furthermore, that as an incentive for the brain to discover hidden objects (an

    important skill in nature), the brain has evolved to enjoy the exercise (Ramachandran 2000).

    Following from this evidence, ambiguity can be defined as an unstable state characterised by a

    certainty of several logically coherent interpretations – a plurality of truths (Zeki 1999, 25).

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    36/55

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    37/55

    37

    recognition. Experiments, however, also indicate that the fronto-parietal cortex (involved in higher

    cognitive function) is engaged as the brain switches between one percept (i.e. interpretation) and

    the other (Zeki 2004, 186).

    Figure 18 - Bi-stable image showing a vase or two faces

    This has led Zeki (1999, 29) to speculate that highly complex ambiguous images such as the paintings

    of Vermeer, while subject to the same principles as simpler ambiguous images, engage many more

    areas of the brain, including its memory. The brain is still tasked with attributing meaning to the

    image by establishing the most likely state (or situation in the ase of Veees paitigs  that

    befits the visual clues. Typically, however, Vermeer does not provide sufficient clues to allow for the

    determination of just one stable state, inviting more questions than offering answers. Aside from

    physical aspects, like colour and form, ambiguity can thus apply equally to less tangible aspects of art

    (1999, 22). Zeki terms this notion situatioal osta. What is written in the note the woman in

    Figure 19 is reading? What is the relationship between the man and woman in Figure 20?  The

    paintings themselves do not provide the answers to these questions. Hence, according to Zeki (1999,

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    38/55

    38

    24-25), the pshologial poe of Veees oks oes fo  thei ailit to geeate

    aiguit.

    Figure 19 - Johannes Vermeer, Girl reading a letter at

    an open window (c. 1657-1659)

    Figure 20 - Johannes Vermeer, The Music Lesson (c.

    1662-1665)

    As a practical example, I would now like to consider the role of ambiguity as discussed above with

    speial efeee to Velázuezs Las Meninas. This large format (318cm × 276cm) group portrait

    depicts the King and Queen of Spain, their daughter, Velazquez himself, the court dwarfs, a

    chaperone, a guard, and an attendant. Art historians, philosophers, and indeed other artists have

    produced voluminous analyses attempting to decipher this highly complex painting.

    The painting contains three focal points: the Ifata Magaita, Velazuezs self -portrait, and the

    reflection of the royal couple. Velázquez is one of five characters that look out at the viewer from

    the painting. These gazes have the effect of implicating the viewer in the scene, effectively rendering

    them a fourth focal point of the painting. This is enhanced by both the mirror where the beholder

    might expect to see himself , a the paites o attitue as he stas efoe his aas. Perhaps

    he is pausing to study his subject, before adding another brush-stroke. Thus the spectator becomes

    that subject.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    39/55

    39

    But the subject of the canvas that Velázquez so tantalizingly obscures from view could equally be the

    king and queen or the Infanta Margarita or even the whole scene from the point of view of the

    couple  – i.e. Las Meninas itself. Although previous studies have attempted to decipher this enigma

    with certainty, I believe it is precisely the ambiguity between this multitude of certainties that lends

    the painting its dynamic. It is thanks to this that Each focal point involves us in a new set of

    elatios (Clark 1960, 36). Foucault (2004, 5) also acknowledges the complex relationships between

    the different roles, writing: No gaze is stale ... sujet a ojet, the spetato a the oel, 

    eese thei oles to ifiit. As with the simple illusions seen at the beginning of this section, the

    compositional balance of Las Meninas  means that at any one time the viewer is capable of

    contemplating only one of these focal points as the subject matter, and the instability of each

    perpetuates the iees interaction with the painting.

    In the case of Las Meninas, the ultimate purpose of this illusionistic game is open to speculation.

    One might argue that it addresses concerns particular to the 17th

    -century Spanish empire on the one

    hand, and those of Velazquez in improving his social standing on the other. Considering first the

    latter, the painting in which Velazquez had included his self-portrait was originally entitled The

    Family  (Levey 1971, 147, Portus 2004, 171), thus indicating the aspirational nature of his inclusion in

    the group. With espet to the foe, i “pai paites ee ot eepte fo the atisas ta – 

    the alcabala sales tax imposed on manufactured goods  – until 1677 (Shiner 2001, 67, Taggard 1996,

    80). In both Florence and Rome, however, it was already recognised as a liberal art. Velázquez may

    thus be making an appeal to his audience to reconsider both the intellectual underpinnings of his

    art, and his own social status as an artist. Seen in this way, the ambiguity may function as a powerful

    hetoial tool that poses the uestio athe tha offeig a ases  since these, ultimately,

    must come from the audience. In this case, then, an understanding of ambiguity does help explain

    how  the painting works, but, for lack of material evidence, one can only speculate as to the aims of

    the painter, or why  he chose to paint the work the way that he did.

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    40/55

    40

    The importance of ambiguity in art has been highlighted by art historians and neuroscientists alike,

    both otig its ailit to egage ith the eholes iagiatio (Gombrich 1984, 228, Zeki 2004,

    189). “oethig, )eki (2004, 189) quotes Schopenhaue, iee the ultiate thig, ust e left

    oe fo the i to o. Whilst )eki (1999, 26) lais that aiguit is a haateisti of all geat

    at, Quatee (1998, 121) in the early 19th

      etu, stipulates that It is the fitious a the

    incomplete in every art, and these alone, which constitute art, and become moreover the sources of

    the pleasue of iitatio. Cota to )ekis alue jugeet, Q uatremère rather introduces a

    principle; that all   art can only ever be incomplete, and the beholder is inevitably   absorbed in the

    exercise of bridging the gap between it and reality. Whilst there is a danger here of abstracting the

    problem to a point where it no longer bears any relevance to the task at hand, I aim to show how

    these theories have, in fact, very concrete implications for understanding Renaissance painting.

    It is important to note first, that the exercise above in using ambiguity to explain Renaissance

    painting is limited. Las Meninas stands out in Renaissance painting, if not in the history of art, as an

    exceptional painting. The ability to shed more light on such a unique painting, as welcome as it is,

    does not necessarily help improve the art historias uestaig of a peio o a stle i at

    history.

    I think it may be possible, nonetheless, to broaden the relevance of ambiguity for Renaissance art,

    again, by considering the proper context. A paradox of realism during the Renaissance, Gombrich

    (1984, 228) explains, was that by attempting to replicate nature in portraits, the sitters depicted

    actually came across as lifeless. In an effort to make his characters seem less rigid, Botticelli depicted

    the movement of hair and garments. Leoaos Mona Lisa o the othe ha, use the atists o

    ietio of sfumato to puposefull istot aeas aou the oes of the sujets outh a

    eyes. The overall effect of using the technique in this way is to introduce an element of uncertainty

    aout the sittes oo: He epessio alas sees just to elue us (Gombrich 1984, 228). An

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    41/55

    41

    important element of the painting is thus left to the eholes iagiatio, a it is this iagiatie

    engagement borne out of built-in ambiguity that brings the Mona Lisa to life for the beholder.

    While Gombrich associates this heightening of the psychological power of painting with Leonardo

    and his important invention of distorting outlines of forms, I believe that an important parallel exists

    in earlier painting, namely the religious paintings of the 15th

     century. As discussed in Section 2.1, the

    eligious paitig fo this peio as tpiall itee to opleet the eholes iteal

    vision of a particular scene. Another way of looking at it, in light of the above discussion, is that the

    paite i fat uilt aiguit ito the pitue i oe to peit the iiiuals iagiatio to

    create its own version, and become witness to the events. Thus, not by obscuring forms as Leonardo

    did, but rather by the omission of specific descriptive detail, artists left open the possibility of many

    variations of the scene, engaging the eholes i as he ties to fi his. I this a, the gap

    between painting and reality becomes instrumental in the function of the painting.

    In this section I have shown how recent developments in understanding the neurology of ambiguity

    to oo )ekis (2004) phase a illuiate seeigl ople oks suh as Mihelagelos

    Rondanini Pietà a Velazuezs Las Meninas. Crucially, however, again by considering the problem

    in context and in terms of the function of the works, it has been possible to add another layer of

    uestaig to daaalls (1988) explanation of 15th

    -century religious paintings.

    3.3 

    Plasticity

    It seems there is nothing to exceed the plasticity of man, except, of course, the plasticity

    of woman. (Gombrich et al. 1970, 11)

    The last of the major developments in neuroscience that I wish to discuss is neuroplasticity. In

    Painting & Experience, there are two aspects of his social history of pictorial style that Baxandall

    does not dedicate much attention to. Firstly, whilst addressing in detail the impact that the period

    eye has on style, Baxandall (1988) only hints at the potential reciprocity of this relationship, that is,

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    42/55

    42

    the influence that art could have on the period eye.  And secondly, although Baxandall (1988)

    suggests that experience of art is influenced by both innate and conditioned factors, Painting &

    Experience  focuses mainly on the latter. It has been pointed out (Onians 2007, 179-180) that,

    ultimately, he gives little consideration to the passive structuring of the brain, concentrating instead

    on formal training. I think that neuroplasticity, the concept that the neural networks comprising the

    brain are malleable, offers fresh insight into the relationship between experience and the brain, and

    into the broader but related relationship between society and art.

    Since the 1960s, evidence has been growing in support of the idea that, contrary to previous belief,

    the human brain does not become ha-ie during childhood and adolescence, but continues to

    change in several important ways throughout adulthood (Doidge 2007, xviii). Although much

    research is being done to determine exactly the extent of the mutability of the human brain (Rakic

    2002, 614), already the discovery that brain neural circuits are not permanent or necessarily

    function-speifi, is eee soe as oe of the ost ipotat isoeies of the tetieth

    etu (Doidge 2007, xix).

    The neural network can change in response to experience in several different ways (Kandel 2006,

    204). Firstly, synaptic connections between neurons can be made weaker or stronger. Weaker

    connections can be observed when a particular stimulus is repeated over time resulting in a

    decreased psychological response, a process known as habituation. Alternately, the synaptic

    connection can be strengthened (diagram on left of Figure 21) by other types of learning such as

    sensitisation or classical conditioning. Sensitisation is the occurrence of a synaptic amplification as a

    result of repeated stimulation, while classical conditioning is an associative type of learning where a

    behavioural response is elicited by a previously unrelated stimulus through repeated exposure to the

    stimulus in synchronisation with a stimulus that normally does evoke the response (famously studied

    by Ivan Pavlov on dogs). I the oaest tes, Kael (2006, 171) explains, these observations

    suggeste that the flo of ifoatio i the aious eual iuits of the ain could be modified

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    43/55

    43

    by learning. Even more astonishingly, experiments have demonstrated that learning can also cause

    the atual ue of sapses i the ais etok to hage (Kandel 2006, 213). New

    connections are established aitie plastiit as a result of learning (diagram on right of  Figure

    21), and existing connections abandoned sutatie plastiit when they are not used (Doidge

    2007, 298).

    Figure 21 - Diagrams representing functional and anatomical changes to a neural network (Kandel 2006, 214)

    The etet of the ais plastiit has ee eostate i aati fashio ueous

    practical experiments. Ramachandran and Blakeslee (Ramachandran and Blakeslee 2005, 59)

    describe several methods of quickly altering a pesos o-image, giving them the impression that

    parts of their body have either changed shape or become disembodied. This, the authors explain,

    eostates that the ight ki of seso stiulatio a opletel alte oes appaetl

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    44/55

    44

    certain knowledge developed over a lifetime in just a few seconds (Ramachandran and Blakeslee

    2005, 59).

    Thus the brain was shown to be undergoing constant change as a direct result of experience,

    pefetig its iuits so it as ette suite to the task at ha. (Doidge 2007, xviii-xix). It is

    important to note that the changes described show a tendency towards greater efficiency. It has

    been reported that, under some circumstances, healthy working parts of the brain would

    compensate for parts that were not working, either due to genetic mutation or damage caused by

    accidents, physically extending their influence in the brain (Doidge 2007, xviii-xix).

    Another experiment described by Ramachandran (2000), involving the conditioning of rats to

    distinguish a rectangle from a square, reveals a feature of neuroplasticity particularly pertinent to

    the present discussion. Conditioning the rats by feeding them cheese every time they are presented

    with the rectangle but not the square leads the rats to exhibit a preference for the rectangle by

    moving towards it. Once the rats are then presented with the original rectangle and another,

    skinnier and longer, rectangle, they exhibit preference for the new rectangle even though this is not

    what they were taught to associate with food. As Ramachandran (2000) explains, what the rats

    leae as a ule: etagulait. I othe os, the geate the aspet atio of the shape, the

    geate is the ats pefeee fo it. This is efee to as the peak shift effet a oth at histoias 

    (Gombrich et al. 1970) and neuroscientists (Ramachandran and Hirstein 1999) have explained the

    power of caricature in these terms, as well as its bearing on art more generally. What is more, the

    effect can be cumulative, evoking a stronger response every time the stimulus is presented.

    These discoveries certainly bear importance for the nature/nurture debate. Although DNA

    eteies hih euos ae ale to oet ith hih othe euos, uilt ito the ais

    neural network is the  potential   for a multitude of behaviours. Which particular circuits are then

    favoured over others, and therefore which particular responses and behaviours are

    generated/produced is down to experience (Kandel 2006, 202). This radical new view of the human

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    45/55

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    46/55

    46

    emphasis placed on colour (colorito) and drawing (disegno) in Venetian and in Florentine painting

    respectively during the Renaissance. This states that visual preferences developed in each city

    according to the influence of their distinct environments on the populatios ais  (University of

    East Anglia 2006). Alternatively, it may be possible to re-examine the question of what impact the

    accurate presentation of perspective on the canvas may have had on the public of the 14th

     and 15th

     

    centuries. Doidge (2007, 299-300), explains that perceptual learning occurs as the ais ailit to

    discriminate between visual stimuli becomes greater, or when the brain learns a new way of

    perceiving altogether, resulting in structural changes to the brain. This seems to support the theory

    that Aletis On Painting (1970 [1435-1436]) was not only an instructive manual on how to execute

    the e etho of painting, but also crucially an instructive manual, dedicated originally to the

    Duke of Mantua, on how to  look  at these paintings (Maniura 2010). Aletis ai i this teatise

    Spencer (1970) explains, is one of making the new humanist art of Florence understandable and

    desirable for a larger group of artists and patrons.  (my emphasis). It seems appropriate to recall

    Maos (1986, 163) concern with the alternative state of consciousness demanded of the beholder

    by Renaissance art. Although further research would be required to test these ideas, it is significant

    in itself that such questions should be reopened for consideration by developments in brain studies.

    The ais popesit to hage i espose to epeiee has le soe (Changeux 1994, 193) to

    oi the te etal Daiis. Plastiit is competitive, Doige (2007, 298) writes, and Kandel 

    (2006, 202) discusses plasticity in terms of the selection  of preferred connections from a set of

    existing connections. Given that the selection process is based on the actual use of synapses and

    neural pathways, I wonder whether in fact Lamarckian evolution is not a better analogy. In any case,

    the relevance for art is the same, as summarised by Gombrich (cited in Changeux 1994, 189 : In art

    history, the word evolution  is a good deal more than a metaphor aig that form adapts to

    function through a process of mutation and selection, and then of survival of the fittest forms. 

  • 8/9/2019 Ninkovi in Search of Period Eye

    47/55

    47

    duilig o Dakis (2009, 192) idea that memes are the replicators of culture, just as genes are

    the replicators of life (in the biological sense), Changeux (1994, 196) suggests that paintings can be

    seen as a sthesis of ees. It should be noted that here too the term is more than a metaphor.

    Mees ae actually realized physically, Huphes  (cited in Dawkins 2009, 1