notes on sculpting the human

Upload: daniel-e-florez-munoz

Post on 03-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Notes on Sculpting the Human

    1/5

    Jean-Luc Nancy: The Being of Human Being

    or Notes on Sculpting the Human

    Association of Law, Culture and the Humanities

    Conference: Sculpting the Human: Law, Culture and BiopoliticsBirkbeck, University of London,

    22 March 2013

    Sculpting the human: Sculpt and Human: Two profound lexemes, both intimately linked with law.

    First, Sculpt: A brief etymological investigation reveals the following: Sculpt comes from the Latin

    Sculpere,which is a back formation of the word Exculpere meaning to carve or cut out.Exculpere is

    in turn linked withExculpare, which is literally to exculpate, to alleviate of guilt.

    Imagine the sculptor working on stone, exculpating it, cutting out its guilt. But for what could a stone

    be culpable? What could be its crime, fault, error or shame? Perhaps from the sculptors point of view,

    the stone is culpable of not yet being the image, shape or form that is desired, willed or deemed just

    by the sculptor. Exculpation occurs when the sculptor sculpts, chips away at the offending element.

    The sculptor, in a sense, designates culpability and manifests the law, executes an injunction, by

    cutting into the stone.

    The tapping of the sculptors chisel, its penetration into the body of the stone, is reminiscent of

    Kafkas Penal Colony. Of the condemned man, the traveller asks Does he know his sentence? No,

    says the Officer. It would be useless to give him that information. He experiences it on his own body.

    The diabolical machine metes out the sentence, its needle-like harrow, like the sculptors chisel,

    inscribing the law repeatedly onto and into his body, eventually killing him.

    Many questions arise from this: what of the status of the sculptor as artist and hence the complicity of

    poesis, the productive telos, vision, or aim of the artist, with violence? Can violence be inflicted on a

    stone? If this is taking the idea of violence too far, then what of the sculptor as jurisprudential

    metaphor, the sculptor who or that has the prudentia, foresight, vision or better still the power to en-

    vision how the subject mustbe, how it mustbecome, how it mustbe relieved of the guilt of being out

    of shape, not right, too much in a state of nature, which is to say, too natural: what of the exculpation

    of the legal subject through material inscription, the cold hard penetration of the chisel, the needle, the

  • 7/28/2019 Notes on Sculpting the Human

    2/5

    harrow into the body. By what right does the sculptor sculpt, who or what authorizes the sculptor, that

    is, who or what comes before the sculptor and hence before the law is it more law, a sovereign

    sculptor, a sculptor king, perhaps Nothing, or some combination or cross-fertilization of all these

    ideas? These are just some of the problematic questions.

    For the moment, however, I would simply like to reaffirm the association of the sculptor with law and

    hence the idea of sculpting the human with the question of legal subjectivity.

    One of the major ways in which the law sculpts the human is through the machinery of human rights.

    Costas Douzinas has drawn on the example of cubist art to describe how this operates:

    The legal person that rights and duties construct resembles a caricature of the actual human self.

    The face has been replaced by an image in the cubist style; the nose comes out of the mouth,

    eyes protrude on the sides, forehead and chin are reversed. It projects a three-dimensional object

    onto a flat canvas.

    In short, for Douzinas, human rights are a blunt tool that is used to sculpt something rather more

    inhuman than human. Certainly, the legal subject becomes a fully autonomous and responsible

    individual, the individual of classic liberalism, but nothing more than that. Douzinas therefore argues

    that human rights misrecognize or repress the recognition of the inter-subjective nature of the human

    being.

    This inter-subjective nature is far from a stable and isolated individual. It is an identity in constant

    construction through its interaction with others. In essence, the being of human being is being in

    community, which Douzinas rightly notes, is the opposite of common being or of belonging to an

    essential community. This is then, an appropriate point to in which to bring in Jean-Luc Nancy.

    In an essay of his on Human Rights that I have had the pleasure to translate for publication later this

    year, Nancy begins by explaining why the word human is, for him, problematic in terms of its

    semantic baggage, both in French and English. In English we have derivative words such as humaneand humanity, which contain within them sentimental notions of philanthropy, care and Christian

    charity. He argues that such language contains a hidden axiom of condescension. With respect to the

    word human then, Nancy writes that:

  • 7/28/2019 Notes on Sculpting the Human

    3/5

    It is for the rich, cultivated and dominant who feel benevolence, compassion and pity for the

    social misfortune of others. And for all that, philanthropists have never sought to challenge the

    social order, except in minor ways.

    It should be emphasized here that Nancy is not denouncing feelings of care for others. He is merely

    trying to bring to light how such discourses of humanity can paradoxically involve a certain

    obnoxious inhumanity. This is why, in general, he and many other thinkers have tended to speak in

    terms of subjectivity rather than humanity, where subjectivity is a more open terrain in which to think

    being in the world. For example, the title of an early book that he co-edited was Who comes after

    the Subject? rather than who comes after the human or who is post-human?

    That being said, there are no shortage of examples of his use of the French word homme meaning

    man, being translated more neutrally as human. And he readily admits that the French language,

    like the word man in English, does not so readily distinguish between the human species and male

    gender. Even the word subjectivity retains a degree of ambiguity: For example, in an interview for

    the book Derrida wonders whether we could ask what rather than who comes after the subject. He

    goes on to suggest that the question beginning with what relates to something other than the subject,

    a pre-subjectivity, something inhuman that calls the human being to responsibility. Hence Derrida

    can say it is perhaps more worthy of humanity to maintain a certain inhumanity, which is to say the

    rigor of a certain inhumanity.

    This idea of alterity or radical otherness is a familiar trope and has been articulated in many different

    ways. Some will disagree with me when I say that I think Nancy also articulates a form of radical

    alterity.

    One way is in his thinking of subjectivity as communal being, being that is both singular and plural.

    For me, alterity comes in here at the border between singularities, the borders that constitute the

    intersection of the infinite with the finite, or what he calls the infinite lack of infinite separation

    between us. Our singularity is constituted in a sense by all others as well as the difference between all

    others. We would not be humans if there were no stones, he says. Which means we have the

    minerality of the stone in our bones, we share this quality with them as well as being radically

    different from them. This is what constitutes the infinite singularity of each finite being.

    Another way is through his conception of freedom, a freedom that is strictly speaking not conceived,

    that is to say, not confined to the limit of thinking. Rather, being is surprised and seized by freedom.

  • 7/28/2019 Notes on Sculpting the Human

    4/5

    This is not the freedom at the level of the individual, in the sense of either the classic freedom of the

    individual or individual choice, but rather at the level of what in the individual is not individual, the

    operation of the law of freedom is the possibility of being addressed by the other, from out of the

    alterity of the other.

    Returning to his essay on Human Rights, Nancy notes that the Universal Declaration of Human

    Rights affirms freedom of speech and belief and freedom from fear and want, and we can now

    understand why he would consider such a recital a rather insufficient account of what it means to be

    free. For Nancy, the freedoms articulated in human rights discourse do not exhaust the possibilities of

    human freedom. We can and do deserve much more.

    Because we deserve much more, he notes the schism between legal rights and non-legal rights (or

    what has been called natural right) is not one that can be neatly comprehended as a binary distinction.

    The foundations of positive law are anything but solid, whether we consider it in terms Schmitts

    sovereign exception or in terms of the fiction of Kelsens basic norm. Nancy reaffirms here what he

    has argued extensively elsewhere, namely the absence of foundation of right in general, an absence

    that is not temporary or contingent but constitutive and even constituent of right. For Nancy, right is

    linked to the institution that cannot be instituted, namely justice, in very much the same sense as

    Derridas well-known exposition in the Force of Law.

    If legal rights can only reflect a caricature of the human self, a two-dimensional misrepresentation,

    then to render justice to person X undeconstructable justice as Derrida would have said would

    be to give to X what he or she truly deserves. And what X deserves, according to Nancy, is the

    infinite recognition of his or her singularity. That is to say, not merely the recognition of her right to

    free speech, to freedom of assembly, to access to water or a roof over her head etc., but infinitely

    more than this. Rights in this sense remain a horizon of impossibility, one that is literally beyond

    humanity, but still, Nancy argues, a necessary horizon.

    The integrity and certainty of the legal subject is therefore compromised in two directions. First at the

    point of legal foundation, which is constituted by a radical absence or an empty place in which one

    can think either in terms of a sovereign power that determines who is and isnt human, or in which

    one can think in terms of a formal presuppositions of normative necessity, in other words, legal

    fictions. At the other end, there is the impossibility of full recognition of the subject, the singular

    being whose sense can never be subject to completion.

  • 7/28/2019 Notes on Sculpting the Human

    5/5

    If we apply this to the metaphor of the sculptor, one might be tempted to speak of the possibility of a

    Leviathan sculptor, the theologico-political sculptor or the sculptor as God or the spectral sculptor,

    the sculptor that is judged, in any case, to have always failed to do justice if not to be deliberately

    unjust. This, though, is where arguably the metaphor breaks down in relation to the

    undeconstructability of justice. That it is undeconstructable means no person or thing can claim

    justice for itself, no sculptor can produce, mould or manufacture it as such, for justice is itself

    unjustifiable. On this, I shall leave you with Nancys own words:

    This justice rests on the unfound-able certainty that it is just that thatexists. On the certainty,

    therefore, that it is just that the world exists even though nothing can justify its existence.

    Unjustifiable justice, far from founding any kind of rights as extensive as these may be

    opens up instead an infinite perspective that exceeds all possibility of right This perspective

    must remain present beyond the horizon of right; for without an appeal or a sign towards it,right can only fall back into its inevitable fragility, whether of impotence, arbitrariness,

    relativity or rigidity. The greatest merit of human rights is to bring out all these difficulties

    and all of these exigencies.

    Gilbert Leung