on action anthropology

7
On Action Anthropology Author(s): Murray L. Wax Source: Current Anthropology, Vol. 38, No. 2 (April 1997), p. 287 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/204611 . Accessed: 21/09/2013 03:46 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The University of Chicago Press and Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Current Anthropology. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Upload: murrayl

Post on 13-Dec-2016

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: On Action Anthropology

On Action AnthropologyAuthor(s): Murray L. WaxSource: Current Anthropology, Vol. 38, No. 2 (April 1997), p. 287Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of Wenner-Gren Foundation for AnthropologicalResearchStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/204611 .

Accessed: 21/09/2013 03:46

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

The University of Chicago Press and Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research are collaboratingwith JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Current Anthropology.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: On Action Anthropology

Discussion and Criticism1

the Critique of Political Economy (see Tucker 1980:2).On the Status of Methodological It has been made so often since that it has found its wayinto contemporary satire. Howard Kirk, the sociologistIndividualismin Malcolm Bradbury’s The History Man, begins one ofhis books as follows (Bradbury 1975:91):

daniel nettle The attempt to privatize life, to suppose that it isMerton College, Oxford University, Oxford OX1 4JD, within single, self-achieving individuals that lie theU.K. ([email protected]). 1 xi 96 infinite recesses of being and morality that shapeand define life, is a phenomenon of narrow histori-What we are supplying are really remarks on the cal significance. It belongs to a particular, and brief,natural history of human beings. phase in the evolution of bourgeois capitalism, andludwig wittgenstein is the derivative of peculiar, and temporary, eco-nomic arrangements. All the signs are that this con-Duran Bell (CA 36:826–30) argues that human socialviction about man will soon have passed away.behaviour and food sharing by hunter-gatherers in par-

ticular cannot be explained from the standpoint knownThe many reports of the passing away of methodologi-as methodological individualism. Quoting Kennethcal individualism have, however, all been rash; it isArrow, Bell takes this to be the pretheoretical assump-probably more firmly established now than ever. I willtion that ‘‘behaviour . . . [is] explicable in terms of indi-argue below that there are sound scientific reasons forviduals, not of other social categories’’ (p. 826). Bell crit-this.icises recent hypotheses that hunter-gatherers share

The main thrust of Bell’s attack on methodologicalmeat either in return for future advantages of variousindividualism is, however, empirical. He gives interest-kinds (Hawkes 1993, Hill and Kaplan 1993) or becauseing examples, not just from hunter-gatherer societiesthey are unable to prevent others from taking it (Blurtonbut from the ‘‘heartland of methodological individual-Jones 1987). Instead, he suggests an analysis based onism,’’ the United States of America, of how people inthe characteristics of corporate groups rather than onfact enjoy a pattern of rights and responsibilities in vir-costs and benefits accruing to individuals. My purposetue of their membership of a social group. A person feelsin this commentary is not to discuss Bell’s analysis ofobliged, and obliges others, to help or protect a strangerthis particular issue. Rather, I wish to examine the sta-because ‘‘as a socialized member of some form of corpo-tus of methodological individualism in social theory inrate group, he recognises a social responsibility to sup-general. Bell may be right that corporate groups are anport the rights of the other’’ (p. 827). Methodological in-ethnographic reality and must enter into any completedividualism thus fails because ‘‘it cannot reckon withdescription of social life. However, it is not clear thatthe ethnographic and widespread historical incidencethey have any place in explanations of social be-of resource possession and management by corporatehaviour. This is because of the fundamental fact that itgroups’’ (p. 826).is individuals rather than groups who live, die, and re-

Bell sees evolutionary ecologists such as Hawkesproduce. I draw attention to the grave danger of irrele-(1993) as imprisoned in an individualist paradigm forvance which faces any social theory which rejectscultural-ideological reasons, unable to see the corporat-methodological individualism as an explanatory para-ist reality of human social behaviour, whilst he, unfet-digm.tered, can deal with it on its own terms. It seems to meAs Bell rightly points out, methodological individual-that Bell is entirely correct that humans are fundamen-ism as a paradigm first came to prominence in econom-tally social beings who solve the material problems ofics. He suggests that it has come to have currency inexistence by forming corporate groups which act in aanthropology ‘‘in part because anthropology is primar-concerted way and hold resources collectively. Any trueily an empirical field that has left these theoretical mat-description of social life must refer to this characteristicters to others’’ and in part because of the cultural pri-of people. However, this is no reason to argue thatmacy given to individualism and economism withinmethodological individualism fails. This is because BellWestern capitalism (p. 826). This latter point seems tohas not distinguished description from explanation. Ahave its origin in a remark in Marx’s Introduction todescription of social life must refer to corporate groups.An explanation of why those corporate groups form can-not refer to the corporate groups, for that would be a1. Permission to reprint items in this section may be obtained only

from their authors. vicious circle. Nor can it just assume them, for then it

283

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: On Action Anthropology

284 current anthropology

would be no kind of explanation at all. It would seem, which they act are individuals, who maximise their life-time reproductive success (defined in an appropriatelythen, that explanatory theory must start from the level

of the individual. inclusive way). It is individuals who adopt different be-havioural strategies, individuals who survive and repro-The holist might simply respond to this argument by

maintaining that the individualist has no more right to duce or fail to do so. Individuals are thus actors in evo-lutionary history in a more important and concrete wayassume the individual as a point of departure than the

holist has to assume the group. However, this argument than groups. This conclusion has not been arrived at be-cause of some cultural prejudice or postulated a priori.is incorrect. There are in fact compelling scientific rea-

sons for building explanatory social theories around the Alternatives in which groups are the evolving entitiesjust do not work mathematically, except in highly re-individual, and these come not from ideology or the pri-

macy of economics but from the findings of a more fun- stricted circumstances, because selection on individu-als disrupts evolution at the level above (Williams 1966,damental discipline, evolutionary biology.

It might reasonably be said that the objective of an- Levin and Kilmer 1974, Wade 1978). Individuals whosebehaviour contributes to the fitness of their groupthropology is to explain human social behaviour and

the human social system. A major philosophical diffi- rather than their own when the two are in conflict willbe reproduced out of existence.culty with such a project is finding sound starting prin-

ciples from which to do this. In fact, there is only one Dawkins (1995) gives a striking illustration of thisfact. All living people have a continuous chain of pro-coherent candidate for a background theory on which

anthropology can be founded, and that is Darwin’s the- genitors stretching back thousands of generations to theorigin of humanity. Take the chain of progenitors of aory of evolution.

With the modern theory of evolution, we have for the !Kung San hunter-gatherer living today. Of those 30,000or more individuals, we know that not one died in in-first time ever a genuinely explanatory, general theory

of why people (and other animals) behave in the way fancy, though infant mortality has always been ex-tremely high. Not one was too nutritionally stressed tothat they do (Dennett 1995). It is genuinely explanatory

because it specifies a mechanism for the production of reproduce, though this is common. Not one failed tofind a mate. Not one forwent his or her own reproduc-behaviour (natural selection) which is powerful, can be

shown mathematically to work, and refers only to ob- tive opportunity for the sake of the band. Many individ-uals have no doubt lived whose pro-group behaviourjects whose existence we can verify directly. Further-

more, it can be used to make mathematically precise, was at considerable cost to their own welfare. However,unless there was some compensatory benefit, thistestable predictions about behaviour, and these predic-

tions are extremely successful over a wide range of phe- would have reduced their reproductive success and theywould have been gradually driven out of populations.nomena. In fact, evolution, in its modern interpreta-

tion, has made such phenomenal progress over the past They are not, therefore, the people whose kind arearound today.30 years that it is now described as the second-most-

successful scientific theory in history, after quantum By contrast, consider the fate of corporate groups overthose thousands of generations. Many of our hunter-physics (Dunbar 1995).

Now, the claim that the theory of evolution must un- gatherer’s progenitors joined groups which later split ordispersed; many progenitors subscribed to culturalderwrite social theory is not a claim that human behav-

iour is genetically determined. Neither is it a claim that norms which led to misery and were abandoned. Count-less forms of social and political organisation came andhuman societies are underlyingly similar to those of

other animals; that would be as nonsensical as the idea went. Where individuals made the right decisions andsurvived, they have kin in the world today. Whetherthat viruses and horses must be structurally similar be-

cause they are both products of evolution. All the claim corporate groups failed has negligible influence on sub-sequent human evolution except insofar as it deter-amounts to is the following: Human beings live and die

in the material world, and some of them live longer and mined the fate of individuals.2 Thus the most promisingputative explanation for any behaviour which we ob-leave more descendants than others. Differential repro-

ductive success has been shown to be a strong influence serve in the world today is that it somehow enhancedthe welfare and hence the reproductive success of theon populations even within relatively short historical

time-frames (Borgerhoff Mulder 1987, Voland 1990). individuals who started to do it. This is a deceptivelysimple statement which nonetheless is more powerfulPeople’s propensities to behave are partially heritable.

The fact that the mechanisms by which propensities are and important than many anthropologists acknowl-edge.inherited involve cultural learning more than genetic

transmission is not particularly important: replication Bell’s comments about anthropology’s failure to de-velop theory of its own seem to advocate that each dis-with variation is all that is required by the theory of

evolution. Thus, all the conditions for natural selection cipline should pull itself up by its own boot-straps, de-riving theories inductively through close attention toto operate are fulfilled in human societies, and so hu-

man beings fall within the scope of the theory of evolu-tion. 2. Soltis, Boyd, and Richerson (1995) give the most generous treat-

Though the ultimate actors in evolutionary theory ment possible to cultural group selection as a factor in social evolu-tion and still conclude that its influence is slight at best.are genes (Dawkins 1989), the replicating vehicles by

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: On Action Anthropology

Volume 38, Number 2, April 1997 285

the phenomena it studies. Now, the observation and ca- under what conditions human social behaviour canevolve and be maintained, and when the models do nottegorisation of structures and correlations in the world

are certainly part of the knowledge-gathering process. fit the data they should be iteratively refined until theydo. Although I cannot speak for evolutionary ecologistsHowever, if we stop at that stage forever we are left

with what Gale (1979) calls ‘‘cookbook science’’: a set of like Hawkes and Hill and Kaplan, it seems to me thatthat is what they are doing: far from denying the exis-empirical generalisations which refer only to constructs

within the discourse. Only if we go on to show why tence of corporate groups, they are trying to explainhow they could have emerged in the first place.those regularities and structures exist, by showing how

they arise from something which is both more basic and Adoption of the individualistic paradigm is not accep-tance of a neoliberal prognosis for society, as Bell maybetter understood, can we achieve real ‘‘explanatory sci-

ence.’’ If there is one type of ball which, when released fear (Tucker 1980). On the contrary, one of the majorfindings of behavioural biology has been just how muchfrom the leaning tower of Pisa, flies upward rather than

dropping, we do not develop a separate discipline, the animals may benefit from cooperating with each otherwhen the right conditions are created, leading to thephysics of rising balls, which explains the behaviour of

these objects using whatever assumptions are needed. emergence of coordination amongst atomised individu-als. Evolution can thus be a metaphor for socialistOnce we have catalogued rising balls on their own

terms, we must go on to seek a explanation in terms thought just as much as for neoliberalism (Kropotkin1972). The ultimate motive force behind socialist pro-of the background theory (gravitation) of why just those

objects under just those conditions rise (for example, be- grams has always been the enhanced freedom and self-realisation that they can deliver, through collective ac-cause they contain helium, whose mass is less than that

of the surrounding air). Only then has explanation been tion, to the individual. This is clear in Marx’s Theoriesof Surplus Value. Like Hobbes before him, Marx (quotedachieved. Sadly, the distinction between description

and explanation is not properly made in ‘‘interpretive’’ in Bottomore 1991: 256) recognised the class of prob-lems known as the prisoner’s dilemma, which is treatedsocial science traditions; one even finds the strange

claim that ‘‘to identify a piece of behaviour . . . is some- as central to social theory by modern evolutionists (Ax-elrod and Hamilton 1984, Maynard Smith and Szath-times to explain it’’ (Lukes 1968:125) passing without

comment. mary 1995); to be better off in the long run, everyonehas to be persuaded to take lower payoffs in the shortThe social sciences have been dogged by the assump-

tion by various groups of practitioners that their para- run: ‘‘Although at first the development of the humanspecies takes place at the cost of the majority of humandigms need only be internally consistent, not answer-

able to our understanding of life in general. This individuals . . . . in the end it breaks through this contra-diction and coincides with the development of the indi-assumption is convenient for social scientists, as it frees

them to a large extent from accountability to the rest of vidual; the higher development of the individual is onlyachieved through a historical process in which individ-the community, but it is far from justified. A successful

theory of the social system of one species must show uals are sacrificed.’’A credible body of anthropological theory would be ofhow that system arose from the general principles

which govern the social systems of all species (and or- great value because it might suggest how differentmodes of social organisation can evolve and be adaptiveganic life more generally). I do not claim that this is

easy. Examples of ‘‘ultrasociality’’ such as Bell’s are in- under certain conditions. However, an anthropologicaltheory which writes its own ground-rules, incommen-deed very difficult to explain in terms of concrete bene-

fits accruing to selfish individuals. In fact, the emer- surate with those of natural history, will convince onlythose who are already initiates, and anthropology willgence of collectivities has always been a central

problem of social theory (see, for example, Hobbes’s face a slow retreat before the advance of more realisticdisciplines such as history, economics, sociobiology,[1909(1651)] Leviathan), and it is only recently, with the

intellectual tools made available by neo-Darwinism, and evolutionary psychology. This would be greatly tothe detriment of our understanding of society, as nothat theoreticians have begun to examine possible

mechanisms by which this may occur (Boyd and Richer- other discipline brings such a breadth of context and ex-perience to bear on the subject as anthropology.son 1989, 1992; Binmore and Samuelson 1994; Knight,

Power, and Watts 1995; Nettle and Dunbar 1997). Methodological individualism stemmed from eco-nomics. Perhaps we can also borrow some lessons aboutIn sum, although the cohesion and power of human

corporate groups do seem to be at odds with the as- what to do with it. The critiques of economics by theso-called behavioural economists are very much likesumption that those groups are made up of atomised in-

dividuals seeking selfish gain, we should not simply that which Bell employs in anthropology: they pointout numerous instances in which actual human behav-abandon the overall explanatory program and found our

own theory on ad hoc principles. If every subdiscipline iour fails to correspond to the model of the rational,utility-maximising individual provided by the theory.did that, the sciences would, to borrow a metaphor from

Eric Wolf (1982), be left like the Danae sisters of Greek However, rejecting the theoretical framework outrightin favour of a loose systemisation of empirical knowl-mythology, each one of whom was consigned forever to

pour water into her own separate bottomless container. edge just leads to a fruitless ‘‘balkanization’’ of the dis-cipline (Schlicht 1990, Hermann-Pillath 1994), whilstAnthropological theory should seek to show how and

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: On Action Anthropology

286 current anthropology

lukes, s. 1968. Methodological individualism reconsidered.failing to offer any new core ideas. Theorists and field-British Journal of Sociology 19:119–29.workers should instead cooperate in seeking higher-

maynard smith, j. , and e. szathmary. 1995. The ma-level theories or expansions of theory which can ac- jor transitions in evolution. Oxford: W. H. Freeman.count for the data. I thus return Bell’s metaphor to him nettle, d. , and r. i. m. dunbar. 1997. Social markers

and the evolution of reciprocal exchange. current anthropol-(p. 830): he and Hawkes are ‘‘separated by a plate ofogy 38:93–99.glass much like the separation between visitors and

schl icht, e. 1990. Rationality, bounded or not, and institu-prisoners at the county jail.’’ Rather than seeing tional analysis. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Eco-Hawkes as the prisoner—of her ideologically imposed nomics 146:703–19.

soltis, j. , r. boyd, and p. j. r icherson. 1995. Canindividualist paradigm—I see Bell as the prisoner, of agroup-functional behaviours evolve by cultural group selec-kind of disciplinary parochialism. If we want to explaintion? An empirical test. current anthropology 36:473–94.the rich data which anthropologists collect and see an-

tucker, d. f. b. 1980. Marxism and individualism. Oxford:thropology develop as an enriching part of the intellec- Basil Blackwell.tual mainstream rather than a marginal and eccentric voland, e. 1990. Differential reproductive success within the

Krummhorn population (Germany, 18th and 19th centuries).activity, we should think carefully about abandoningBehavioural Ecology and Sociobiology 26:65–72.methodological individualism.

wade, m. j. 1978. A critical review of group-selection models.Quarterly Review of Biology 53:101–14.

williams, g. c. 1966. Adaptation and natural selection: Acritique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton:References Cited Princeton University Press.

wittgenstein, l. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Oxford:axelrod, r. , and w. hamilton. 1984. The evolution of co-Basil Blackwell.operation. New York: Basic Books.

wolf, e. 1982. Europe and the people without history. Berke-bell, d. 1995. On the nature of sharing: Beyond the range ofley: University of California Press.methodological individualism. current anthropology 36:

826–30.b inmore, k. , and l. samuelson. 1994. An economist’s

perspective on the evolution of norms. Journal of Institutionaland Theoretical Economics 150:112–13. On Anthropologyblurton jones, n. 1987. Tolerated theft: Suggestions aboutthe ecology and evolution of sharing, hoarding, and scrounging. and the InternetSocial Science Information 26:31–54.

borgerhoff mulder, m. 1987. On cultural and reproduc-tive success: Kipsigis evidence. American Anthropologist 89:617–34. joyce l. ogburnbottomore, t. 1991. 2d edition. A dictionary of Marxist

Old Dominion University Library, Norfolk, Va.thought. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.boyd, r. , and p. j. r icherson. 1989. The evolution of in- 23539-0256, U.S.A. 10 x 96

direct reciprocity. Social Networks 11:213–36.———. 1992. Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or The Internet as a topic has taken over our professional

anything else) in sizeable groups. Ethology and Sociobiologylives as much as the Internet as a reality. Its application13:171–95.to anthropology deserves a timely and thorough explo-bradbury, m. 1975. The history man. London: Secker and

Warburg. ration. The article on it by Brian Schwimmer (CA 37:dawkins, r. 1989. 2d edition. The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford 561–68) is dated December 1995, and in the absence of

University Press. information on how recently the research was con-———. 1995. River out of Eden. London: Weidenfeld and Nich-ducted it is difficult to determine the accuracy and com-olson.

dennett, d. 1995. Darwin’s dangerous idea. Harmondsworth: pleteness of the information that is presented. It is un-Penguin. clear, furthermore, whether Schwimmer worked from

dunbar, r. i. m. 1995. The trouble with science. London: printed resources (which are not cited) or searched theFaber and Faber.

Internet directly. If the latter, it would be helpful togale, g. 1979. Theory of science. Toronto: McGraw-Hill.know whether he used a web-search engine or exam-hawkes, k. 1993. Why hunter-gatherers work: An ancient ver-

sion of the problem of public goods. current anthropology ined Internet sites that select and point to other sites.34:341–51. He criticizes the American Anthropological Associa-

hermann-p illath, c. 1994. Evolutionary rationality, ‘‘Homo tion and the Human Relations Area Files for not takingEconomicus,’’ and the foundations of the social order. Journaladvantage of the Internet, but he does not say whetherof Social and Evolutionary Systems 17:41–69.

h ill, k. , and h. kaplan. 1993. On why male foragers hunt he surveyed organizations or institutions as to their in-and share food. current anthropology 34:701–6. tentions to do so. From personal communication with

hobbes, t. 1909 (1651). Leviathan. Oxford: Oxford University a staff member at the HRAF I have learned that this or-Press.

ganization was never consulted about its plans.knight, c. , c. power, and i. watts. 1995. The humanSchwimmer provides no Internet addresses or rele-symbolic revolution: A Darwinian account. Cambridge Archeo-

logical Journal 5:75–114. vant citations and often does not give the full names ofkropotk in, p. 1972. Mutual aid: A factor of evolution. Lon- the resources he lists. Though they are subject to

don: Penguin. change, addresses are essential for accessing resourceslevin, b. r. , and w. l. k ilmer. 1974. Interdemic selectionaccurately and easily. The references cited are very fewand the evolution of altruism: A computer simulation study.

Evolution 28:527–45. and do not include published (print) articles on anthro-

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: On Action Anthropology

Volume 38, Number 2, April 1997 287

pology resources on the Internet1 or electronically pub- cial databases. Searching may seem to be free to individ-uals who have access through their local libraries, butlished materials.2 If he could not list every relevant In-

ternet resource, he could have cited sources that do the libraries are incurring a cost for providing that ac-cess.include such information. He mentions the value of

electronic publishing, but he does not cite any of the Resources on the Internet are growing and changingevery day. A recent initiative is the development of theliterature on this topic to support his arguments.

Most of the attention of the article is given to re- Smithsonian Electronic Editions, which will provide ac-cess to digitized versions of Bureau of American Ethnol-sources for cultural and general anthropology. At the

time the article was written, many relevant and good ogy reports (http://www.sil.si.edu/elecedns.htm).To provide context and strength to his arguments,sites existed, particularly for archaeology (which

Schwimmer does note as being active) and for Native Schwimmer could have discussed whether other disci-plines are taking better advantage of the Internet andAmerican studies.3 One extremely important electronic

resource, available at the time the article was written, is what anthropologists could learn from them. He doesnot cover what existing anthropology resources on theomitted; Anthropological Literature, published by the

Tozzer Library at Harvard University, has been avail- Internet are particularly good or useful and could serveas examples for further developments.able as an online database over the Internet through the

Citadel service of the Research Libraries Group (RLG). The overall approach of the article seems to be thatof an opinion piece. As a status report, it is dated. Per-This resource is one of the few online bibliographic da-

tabases devoted exclusively to anthropology.4 Other haps it was intended as a wake-up call. A clarion callmay indeed be needed, but more supporting documenta-great resources available on the Internet are library cata-

logs. These include the extensive library catalogs of tion and in-depth discussion would have served thetopic better and would have contributed more signifi-Harvard, Yale, UC-Berkeley, and Northwestern and the

RLG (RLIN) and OCLC databases, which contain the cantly to researching and taking advantage of the powerof the Internet.collective records of libraries around the world.

One could rightly criticize Internet resources for be-ing primarily text-based and for not taking advantage of References Citedthe new software that supports sophisticated databases

cohen williams, anita, and jul ia a. hendon. 1995.and interactive teaching. This should change as theInternet resources for anthropology. College and Research Li-scholarly community gains more experience in usingbraries News 56(2):87–90, 113.this kind of software. Much of the information on the okerson, ann, l isabeth king, diane kovacs, and

Internet is free, but there is a charge for using commer- the directory team. Editors. 1995. 5th edition. Direc-tory of electronic journals, newsletters, and academic discus-sion lists. Washington, D.C.: Association of Research Libraries.

1. Cohen Williams and Hendon (1995) provides a short descriptionand addresses for many major resources on the Internet, includinglistservs. Okerson et al. (1995) is a major reference work on elec-tronic resources and is available in both print and diskette editions. On Action AnthropologyIt provides information on electronic serials and discussion listsavailable on the Internet, including lists and titles of scholarly in-terest.

murray l. wax2. Lists compiled by individuals on anthropology resources haveDepartment of Anthropology, Washington University,been published on various listservs and are available in listserv ar-

chives (although they are dated). Many of the web sites Schwimmer St. Louis, Mo. 63130, U.S.A. 13 viii 96lists maintain extensive and current links to anthropology websites and include information on listservs, gophers, and other In- Some bibliographic addenda to my comment on Solternet resources. Extensive links and lists are often maintained by

Tax’s ‘‘action anthropology’’ (CA 37:S45–47): Those in-university anthropology departments, museums, and libraries.Some good examples include http://dizzy.library.arizona.edu/ terested in the Tama Project should note the reviewusers/jlcox/first.html and http://www.usc.edu/dept/v-lib/ ‘‘Tama: An American Conflict’’ by Elizabeth Hoyt as-anthropology.html. sisted by Eleanor M. Shepherd (mimeo., Iowa State Uni-3. See in particular the extensive web site maintained by Lisa Mit-

versity, 1964). Those interested in the summer Work-ten, University of Pittsburgh (http://www.info.pitt.edu/,lmitten/shops on American Indian Affairs, conducted for Indianindians/html).

4. RLG has recently added FRANCIS, the online version of Bulletin college students and largely staffed by graduates of theSignaletique, to its list of databases. The Citadel Service of RLG University of Chicago Department of Anthropologyalso provides access to databases on Latin American materials and (Robert K. Thomas, Richard Pope, et al.), might consultmany other subjects related to anthropology. Similar services pro-

the reports by Rosalie H. Wax on the 1959 and 1960duced by other organizations and publishers provide access overthe Internet to other subject databases which are useful to anthro- workshops and on the history of the workshops to thosepologists. dates (mimeo, Newberry Library).

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: On Action Anthropology

This content downloaded from 130.209.6.50 on Sat, 21 Sep 2013 03:46:22 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions