plato´s political cuisine. commensality, food and politics ... · pdf filea cozinha...

36
Ágora. Estudos Clássicos em Debate 17 (2015) 123158 — ISSN: 08745498 Plato´s political cuisine. Commensality, food and politics in the Platonic thought A cozinha política de Platão. Comensalidade, comida e política no pensamento platónico FERNANDO NOTARIO 1 (Labex RESMED — Université Paris Sorbonne — France) Abstract: This paper addresses the question of the sociological and political background of food, cuisine and commensality in Plato´s philosophy. It argues that the importance of these elements in Plato´s political thought is related to the increasingly complex gastronomic developments in fourth century Greek world. In the first place, it will analyse the general trends concerning Platonic perceptions on fourth century´s food habits and cookery. In the second place, it will study the role food and eating habits have in the Platonic utopias of the Republic, Critias and Laws. These two compared analyses will demonstrate how the utopian diets and eating habits are key elements in the construction and stabilisation of these imaginary communities. Keywords: Plato; Utopias; Food; Commensality; Politics; Banqueting. 1. Introduction In later years, there have been an increasing number of interesting works concerning ancient Greek gastronomy and food habits 2 . One of the most interesting trends is the exceptional development of cookery and gastronomy in the late classical period, roughly corresponding with the fourth century BC 3 . The emergence of the firsts Greek cookbooks, the professionalization of the cooking activity and the integration of gastronomic connoisseurship in the general trends of social recognition are some of the elements that help to this cultural development 4 . This process is coincident with the consolidation of dietetics as one of the most relevant Text received on 10/25/2014 and accepted on 01/20/2015. 1 [email protected]. 2 Detailed bibliography can be found in MURRAY (2003); NOTARIO (2011); SCHMITT PANTEL (2012). 3 DALBY (1996): 113129. In a more general way: OLSON;SENS (2000). 4 BERTHIAUME (1982) 7178. Greek cookbooks: WILKINS;HILL (1996). Concerning the concept of social recognition in ancient Greece: DUPLOUY (2006).

Upload: nguyenphuc

Post on 05-Feb-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • gora.EstudosClssicosemDebate17(2015)123158ISSN:08745498

    Platospoliticalcuisine.Commensality,foodandpoliticsinthePlatonicthought

    AcozinhapolticadePlato.Comensalidade,comidaepolticanopensamentoplatnico

    FERNANDONOTARIO1(LabexRESMEDUniversitParisSorbonneFrance)

    Abstract:Thispaperaddressesthequestionofthesociologicalandpoliticalbackgroundoffood,cuisineandcommensalityinPlatosphilosophy.Itarguesthattheimportanceofthese elements in Platos political thought is related to the increasingly complexgastronomic developments in fourth century Greekworld. In the first place, itwillanalyse the general trends concerning Platonic perceptions on fourth centurys foodhabitsandcookery.Inthesecondplace,itwillstudytherolefoodandeatinghabitshavein thePlatonicutopiasof theRepublic,CritiasandLaws.These twocomparedanalyseswill demonstrate how the utopian diets and eating habits are key elements in theconstructionandstabilisationoftheseimaginarycommunities.

    Keywords:Plato;Utopias;Food;Commensality;Politics;Banqueting.

    1.Introduction

    In later years, there have been an increasing number of interestingworksconcerningancientGreekgastronomyand foodhabits2.Oneof themost interesting trends is the exceptional development of cookery andgastronomy in the late classical period, roughly correspondingwith thefourth century BC3. The emergence of the firsts Greek cookbooks, theprofessionalization of the cooking activity and the integration ofgastronomicconnoisseurshipinthegeneraltrendsofsocialrecognitionaresomeoftheelementsthathelptothisculturaldevelopment4.Thisprocessiscoincidentwith the consolidationofdietetics asone of themost relevant

    Textreceivedon10/25/2014andacceptedon01/20/2015.1fnotariopacheco@gmail.com.2DetailedbibliographycanbefoundinMURRAY(2003);NOTARIO(2011);SCHMITT

    PANTEL(2012).3DALBY(1996):113129.Inamoregeneralway:OLSON;SENS(2000).4BERTHIAUME (1982)7178.Greek cookbooks:WILKINS;HILL (1996).Concerning

    theconceptofsocialrecognitioninancientGreece:DUPLOUY(2006).

  • 124

    FernandoNotario

    gora.EstudosClssicosemDebate17(2015)

    branches in ancientGreekmedicine,which, besides some earlierworks,isalsoroughlysituatedinthefourthcenturyBC5.

    Thenew sociocultural interest in foodand cookery,both, from thegastronomicandthedieteticpointofview,introducedinterestingquestionsregardingfoodpreparationandconsumptionthatwouldinfluencecontemporaryandlaterphilosophicalinquiry6.Beyondtheviewsofsomephilosophicalandreligioussects,since the later fifthcentury,cookeryandeatingbecamecriticalmattersregardingethicalandmoralissues,suchasphysicaldesire, guilt or indulgence7. Fourth century philosophers used food as awayofthinkingaboutthenatureofsocialrelationships,thevirtuesandimperfections of contemporary political ideologies, and the acceptance orrejectionofthesharedhabitsconcerningcookingandeating.

    Besidesanarguablysharedbackground rooted in thepersonal relationshipswith Socrates, the existence or, at least, the terms inwhich theSocratic circle can be defined, remains a problematic topic.As severalscholars have pointed out, in the case of admitting its existence, thefragmentationof thiscirclemusthavebeenanearlyphenomenon.This isprovedintheemergenceofrivalphilosophicalschools,eachoneinterestedintheappropriationofconflictingmemoriesconcerningSocrates,hispersonalityandlegacy8.Theliterarygenreofthelogoisokratikoi,theSocraticdialogue,conveys thearticulationof thediverging imagesofSocrates.At thesame time, however, gives them a particular shape in accordancewith,orcontrasting with, the writers philosophical, ethical and ideologicalprinciples9. Inspiteof these fragmentationandcolliding interests, there islittledoubtthatatleasttherewasanunderlyingSocraticexperiencethatthe

    5CRAIK(1995);NUTTON(2004)115127.6Ingeneral:WILKINS;HILL(2006)185210;AUBERGER(2010)211216.Concerning

    foodandphilosophy:TELFER(1996);ONFRAY(1990a;1999b);KORSMEYERS(2002);KAPLAN(2012).

    7Concerningthediscoursesaboutfoodofsomeofthesesects,suchasOrphicorPythagoreans:DETIENNE(1970;1977);SEAFORD(1981);BEER(2010)2853.

    8MONTUORI(1988)724;MORRISON(2011)xiiixv.DORION(2011).9Arist.Rh.3,1417a1720;Po.1447b113;F72Rose.VEGETTI(2006);DANZIG(2010)

    69113;DORION(2011)79.

  • Platospoliticalcuisine.Commensality,foodandpoliticsinthePlatonicthought 125

    gora.EstudosClssicosemDebate17(2015)

    scholarsusuallyhaveascribedtothemoral,dialecticandethicalhorizons10.It is regarding these overlapping areas that the philosophical attitudestowards food and eating in the Socraticphilosophical schools achieve itsfullsignification.

    Asinotherareasofintellectualinquiry,nevertheless,thedifferencesbetween the Socratic students are also evident in theway they conformtheirphilosophyoffood.Xenophonpresentsacoherentframeforfoodconsumption inmoral,ethicalandpolitical terms,andotherSocraticssuchasAntisthenesoAristippusdevelopedasignificantpartoftheirmoral,ethicaland even ontologicalpropositionsusing food as a conceptual tool11.Thispaperaims toanalyse, in the firstplace, thewayPlatodealtwithcontemporarygastronomicdevelopments and its impact in the sociocultural recognition patterns of the Greek social elites. The contrast and even realoppositionbetweencookeryanddieteticsisoneofthemajortrendsinPlatonicthinkingconcerningfood.However,theanalysisoffoodandeatinginthePlatonicutopian textsclearlyshowsus thathealthcanberegardedassecondaryor,rather,justacomplementaryaspectofthem.Thepoliticalandsociologicalbackgroundof food ismoredecisive than themedicalone inPlatonicthought.

    2.ThebackgroundoffoodandcookeryinPlato

    Itcanbehardlyarguedthateatinganddrinkingareamongthemostprominent topics in Platonic studies.Although the relationship betweenPlatoandwinedrinkinghasreceivedsomescholarlyattention,thecontextsof cooking and eating have remained in a relative academic obscurity12.Nevertheless,classicalscholarshavelittletoblameonthisapparentneglect.ThedisdainwithwhichPlato regards contemporarygastronomy ismate

    10WOLFF(1997);GOURINAT(2001);DRING(2011).11Concerningthepolitical,moralandethicalusesoffoodasthebackgroundfor

    theevergeticactioninXenophonsworks:AZOULAY(2004);NOTARIO(2013).ConcerningAristippus, food and pleasure: TRAINA (1991); OKEEFE (2002); HOURCADE (2008).ConcerningAntisthenes,cynicalattitudestowardsfoodandothercynicalhabits:NAVIA(1996)3780;(2001).

    12WineandPlato:BOYANC(1951);BELFIORE(1986)ROLAND(1990);NOL(2002);HOLOWCHACK(2003).

  • 126

    FernandoNotario

    gora.EstudosClssicosemDebate17(2015)

    rialised in a profound silence concerning food in banqueting contexts,something that ismostly apparent inhis Symposium13.Thedetailed focusPlatohas towards the realmof sociabilityanddrinkinghabits in this textcontrastswithhisobliviousattitudetowardsfood14.Thebriefdescriptionatthe beginning of the dining soon gives way to a portrait of Socrateseccentric behaviour15. After the libation and hymn singing, the guestsstarted todrink16.There isnt any furthermention to the foods thatwerecookedandeatenby theguests,a feature that,asLucianaRomeriargues,will be sharedwith other philosophical banquets17.Only those banquetsthatareconsciouslyconstructedasantiphilosophical,suchasAthenaeusDeipnosophistae or Lucians Symposium, indulge in the description of thefoodconsumedinthem18.

    As faras thePlatonicSocrates isconcerned,banqueting is justacontext forphilosophicaldebate,without any interest in the food served, andwhilehe iscertainly someone thatenjoyshumancompany,he isa solitaryeater.WhenhemakeshisentranceinAgathonsdiningroom,heeatsalone,in a somewhat differentiatedway regarding the other guests19. Later on,whenAlcibiadesremembersthecampaigntoPotidaea,hesaysthatSocratesalreadyhadthehabitofstandingalonethinkingwhiletheothermembersofthemilitary contingent dined together20.Nevertheless, Socrates loneliness

    13Concerning food inPlatosSymposium, theanalysisofLucianaROMERI (2000);

    (2002) 61103 remains of great interest. As JohnWILKINS (2000) 412 argues, if thematerialworldisthemilieuforpopularempowerment,Platossilenceconcerningfoodcouldbeseenasanothermarkofhiselitistbackground,philosophicalconceptsaside.

    14Forexample,concerningthehostreception:Pl.Smp.174de.Instructionsfortheslavesservingthebanquet:Pl.Smp.175b.ThereceptionofAlcibiadesasanunexpectedguest:Pl.Smp.213ab.Concerningsocialmanners:NADEAU(2010).

    15Pl.Smp.175ce.16Pl.Smp.176a.17ROMERI(2002)7079;X.Smp.1,811.Theparallelsilenceconcerningfoodisbut

    oneofthesignsoftheearlyconstitutionofthegeneraltrendsoftheliterarygenreofthephilosophicalbanquets:DUPONT(1977);NIGHTINGALE(1995).Cf.D.L.2,57;3,34.

    18ROMERI(2000)256271;(2002)191ff.19Pl.Smp.176a.20Pl.Smp.220cd.

  • Platospoliticalcuisine.Commensality,foodandpoliticsinthePlatonicthought 127

    gora.EstudosClssicosemDebate17(2015)

    doesnot correspond to the culturalpatterns of the solitary eaters in otherculturaldepictions of thisphenomenon inGreek culture.He is neither anincorrigiblegluttonnoranantisocialthug:forhim,food isonlyabiologicalnecessity.Whenitispleasurable,itisonlybecauseofitscontrapositiontothepainscreatedbyfamineandstarvation,notbecauseofitsinherentnature21.

    InaccordancewiththeidealimageofSocrates,thewisemanshouldbeable to raise some formofphilosophicalandbehavioural firewall thatisolateshim from theentireconceptualnetwork thatconnectseatingwithpleasure,andgluttonywith thepleasurable life22.Unlikeother intellectualproposals,suchastheCynicschool,Platoarguesthattheidealphilosophershouldnotdistancehimselffrom thedominantculturallyacceptedgastronomicbackground,althoughheshouldregardrefinedcookeryasahollowknowledge23. Thus, in Theaetetus Plato excludes gastronomic connoisseurshipfromthesetofskillsthatconformsthephilosophersmechanismsforsocialandintellectualrecognition24.

    Plato furtherexplores thecomplexrelationshipbetweenpleasure, thenewgastronomictrendsandpleasureinhisGorgias25.Thefirstglanceoftheimportancethatcook