politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

Upload: liberto-carratala

Post on 14-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    1/24

    Life politics, nature and the state: Giddenssociological theory and The Politics of ClimateChange1

    Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    Abstract

    Anthony Giddens The Politics of Climate Change represents a significant shift in

    the way in which he addresses ecological politics. In this book, he rejects the

    relevance of environmentalism and demarcates climate-change policy from life

    politics. Giddens addresses climate change in the technocratic mode of simple

    rather than reflexive modernization. However, Giddens earlier sociological

    theory provides the basis for a more reflexive understanding of climate change.

    Climate change instantiates how, in high modernity, the existential contradiction of

    the human relationship with nature returns in new form, expressed in life politicsand entangled with the structural contradictions of the capitalist state. The inter-

    linking of existential and structural contradiction is manifested in the tension

    between life politics and the capitalist nation-state. This tension is key for under-

    standing the failures so far of policy responses to climate change.

    Keywords: Climate change; Giddens; life politics; environmentalism; risk;

    ontological insecurity

    A distinctive aspect of Anthony Giddens sociological theory has been hisemphasis on the challenge posed to modern societies by ecological issues

    and by environmentalist movements as an expression of what he calls life

    politics, raising questions of lifestyle or how we should live (Giddens 1990:

    165; Giddens 1991: 9, 2146, 2213; Giddens 1994: 14; OBrien 1999: 278).

    His 2009 book, The Politics of Climate Change [hereafter Politics] follows

    from this ecological dimension of his sociological thought. However, Politics

    represents a shift in the way in which Giddens handles ecological politics. In

    this book, he rejects the relevance of environmentalism and adopts a nar-

    rowly instrumental approach focused on market-oriented policies, bracketing

    the questions of values and lifestyles raised by environmentalism and other

    Thorpe and Jacobson (Department of Sociology, University of California, San Diego) (Corresponding authors email: cthorpe@

    ucsd.edu)

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 ISSN 0007-1315 print/1468-4446 online.

    Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden,

    MA 02148, USA on behalf of the LSE. DOI: 10.1111/1468-4446.12008

    The British Journal of Sociology 2013 Volume 64 Issue 1

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    2/24

    life-political movements. This shift, we argue, represents a retreat from the

    reflexivity of high modernity that Giddens theorized in his earlier work.

    Rather, the approach to climate change in Politics reflects the characteristic

    orientation of simple modernization (Giddens 1994: 5, 42, 807): an instru-

    mental approach to nature, faith in technological progress and abstract

    systems of expertise, and the exclusion of ambivalence and uncertainty. This

    instrumental and technocratic approach might seem justified by the urgency

    of tackling climate change, but we argue that Giddens policy prescriptions

    are too narrow and limited, and that the politics of climate change must meet

    the deeper challenges of reflexivity and the existential and value-questions

    raised by environmentalism.

    The recent shift in Giddens handling of environmental issues also serves to

    highlight the fundamental tension between life politics and the key institutionsof modernity the nation-state and systematic capitalist production (Giddens

    1990: 174). The problem of whether life politics can be reconciled with these

    institutions is central to Giddens work, but is not adequately resolved. This

    tension is expressed in his notion of utopian realism (Giddens 1990: 1545;

    1994: 24950). The utopian dimensions of his thought came to the fore when

    he presented life-political movements as potential heralds of a post-modern

    order that would involve post-scarcity economics, democratization, and an

    ecological ethos (Giddens 1990: 16373). But this was tied to his notion of

    realism, expressed in his view that we remain within modernity an intensi-

    fied high modernity (Giddens 1990: 1556; 1991: 4, 2732). Giddens has

    treated realism as demanding acceptance of institutions such as the global

    market which operate in ways that can run counter to life-political values.

    Giddens Third Way was not only about moving beyond modern politics split

    between left and right; it was also an attempt to reconcile life politics with

    modern institutions of the state and capitalist production and exchange.While

    left-wing critics of the Third Way have emphasized its accommodation with

    global capitalism (e.g. Callinicos 2001), life politics potentially destabilizessuch accommodation.

    The inherent tension in Giddens utopian realism can be understood in

    relation to his central metaphor of modernity as a juggernaut (Loyal 2003:

    152). The image, in The Consequences of Modernity, implies relentless dyna-

    mism and inertia, especially associated with capitalist growth and technologi-

    cal development, suggesting that these processes cannot be held back: The

    juggernaut crushes those who resist it. Instead, one must ride the juggernaut

    (Giddens 1990: 139, 146). However, Giddens also suggested that we shouldseek to assert collective agency over technological momentum, implying

    that the juggernaut could be steer[ed] toward alternative futures (1990: 154;

    see also Craib 2011 [1992] : 77). Giddens embraced life politics as a corrective

    to productivism, or accumulation for its own sake, and to the compulsive

    character of modernity, manifested in capitalist accumulation, bureaucratic

    100 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    3/24

    organizations, and technological systems (1994: 1689, 195; 1994b: 90). Unless

    such a challenge is mounted, these forms of bureaucratic and technological

    inertia have apocalyptic implications, either in nuclear war or an ecological

    catastrophe [. . .] as disturbing in its implications (Giddens 1990: 173).

    Politics is about how to assert agency in the face of possible disaster and

    it emphasizes the need for a rapid shift in technological priorities. However,

    in contrast to Giddens earlier thought, here he presents the locus of agency

    as being political, technoscientific and business elites rather than social

    movements. He gives little attention to democratic participation and rejects

    the idea of a grassroots shift toward more ecologically sustainable lifestyles.

    Ethical questions of how we should live are shut down in favour of pragmatic

    top-down policy solutions. As he addresses climate change, Giddens detaches

    questions of risk from the existential dilemmas stressed in his earlier work.Focusing on pragmatic policy fixes, Giddens fails to draw deeply on his earlier

    analyses of the contradictions of the capitalist state, ontological insecurity,

    reflexivity, and the rise of life politics. But these analyses and concepts provide

    key insights for understanding the depth of the challenge that climate change

    poses for modern institutions.

    Drawing on Giddens earlier thought, we argue that the problem of climate

    change exposes fundamental contradictions in the relationship between the

    state and capital, which have been exacerbated by globalization processes. It

    also uncovers the basic existential contradiction of the human relationship

    with nature that Giddens argued has been repressed in modernity. In climate

    change, these different forms of contradiction are overlaid on one another,

    compounding the complexity and intractability of the problem. Risks of

    climate change need to be understood sociologically in relation to the radical

    ontological insecurity that arises from the way in which the existential con-

    tradiction has returned in a new form. Since climate change is not only a

    problem of risk, but also poses an existential dilemma, it cannot be merely

    managed at a technical and pragmatic policy level. The reflexive ethical ori-entation of life politics is essential if society is to cope with the challenge of

    climate change.

    Nature, the existential contradiction, and modernity

    The human relationship with nature is central to Giddens historical sociology.

    In this relationship, Giddens identified the fundamental contradiction thatexists in all types of society. Human beings emerge from and exist within the

    world of Being, the world of nature. And yet, the human individual is also a

    conscious, reflective agent and in that sense transcends nature as the negation

    of the inorganic (Giddens 1981: 2367). This existential contradiction is medi-

    ated by society, since it is in society that the human being acquires a second

    Life politics, nature and the state 101

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    4/24

    nature of culture, language, and social practice (Giddens 1981: 236; 1979: 161).

    The reproduction of social relationships sustains the accommodations

    between human beings and nature and the modes of control to which nature

    is made subject (Giddens 1979: 161). In this way, the existential contradiction

    acquires a social character as it is externalized in institutions and thus

    becomes translated into structural contradiction (Giddens 1979: 161).

    Giddens traced how state power has drawn on symbolic and religious

    resources that express attempts to handle the existential contradiction

    (Giddens 1981: 237). In pre-capitalist class-divided societies the states media-

    tion of existential contradiction underpins its mobilization of authoritative

    resources (Giddens 1981: 96, 100, 1456). When existential contradiction is

    institutionalized in the state, it is transformed into structural contradiction so

    that the state is the focus of the contradictory character of human societalorganisation (Giddens 1981: 237). With the development of the capitalist

    nation-state, however, structural contradictions lose their manifest relation-

    ship with existential contradiction. Capitalism severs contradiction from its

    foundation in existential contradiction. Or rather, existential contradiction is

    suppressed by structural contradiction, in which the state/society relation

    becomes detached from the intermingling of human social life and nature

    (Giddens 1981: 238).

    The fundamental contradiction of the capitalist state is the division between

    the political and the economic as separate spheres, arising from the capitalist

    labour contract (Giddens 1981: 128). The economic sphere is insulated from

    the force wielded by the state, but this separation means that the state relies for

    its revenue on private accumulation outside its direct control (Giddens 1981:

    17781, 20914, 229). Extraction of surplus is achieved through capitalists

    surveillance and management of the labour process (Giddens 1981: 13540).

    Class relations within the labour process (1981: 2201) are interlaced with

    technical control of the natural world: an exploitative attitude to nature [. . .] is

    associated with social exploitation, directly geared into it (Giddens 1979: 163,emphasis in original). According to Giddens, The instrumental relation to

    nature that is promoted by the rise of capitalism, fuelled by the accumulation

    process, becomes one side of the faultline of the contradictory character of the

    capitalist state (1981: 238).

    The instrumental relationship with nature that characterizes capitalist pro-

    duction also conditions quotidian life. Giddens argued that de-traditionalized

    and routinized everyday life is a specific feature of capitalist modernity. Eve-

    ryday life is shaped by the intersection of internal pacification by the state, thedull compulsion of market forces, and the reach of capitalist production in

    creating manufactured urban environments which are experienced as being

    removed from nature (Giddens 1981: 1534). Modern everyday life is thus

    smoothed of the disruptions of nature, resulting in routinized predictability

    (Giddens 1981: 173; Giddens 1991: 1356, 1649; see also Shove 2003: 13940,

    102 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    5/24

    1612). However, this routinization combines with a heightened sense of fra-

    gility of the individual in their daily life (Giddens 1981: 11, 194; 1991: 167). The

    rise of capitalism undermines pre-existing sources of ontological security,

    meaning the ability to take for granted ones experienced reality and the

    continuity of the present with established patterns and institutions (Giddens

    1981: 11, 152; 1991: 534). Modernity erodes the traditional narratives and

    practices that provided ways of handling the dilemmas that arise from the

    existential contradiction (Giddens 1981: 154). There is a deep sense of mean-

    inglessness in the wasteland of everyday life (Giddens 1981: 13).

    As a source of security, modernity substitutes for tradition the instrumental

    control of nature. Security comes to depend on trust in abstract systems of

    technology and scientific expertise (Giddens 1990: 923, 1123; Giddens 1994:

    80). The influence of these systems within everyday life, combined with thedull compulsion of economic forces, has the effect of suppressing existential

    anxieties. Giddens commented on just how far modern civilization has come

    to rely on the expansion of control, and on economic progress as a means of

    repressing basic existential dilemmas of life (Giddens 1994: 212).

    The suppression of existential dilemmas is an aspect of the way in which

    capitalist modernity subjects human life to automatic forces, as implied by the

    metaphor of the juggernaut. Automatism can be seen in the dull compulsion

    of the market and in the unquestioned pursuit of economic growth (Giddens

    1981: 11, 124). Giddens argues that under capitalism, economic relations

    become peculiarly significant [. . .] as a medium of power (Giddens 1981: 111,

    emphasis in original; see also 7, 104, 1068, 112). Within capitalism, the power

    of the dominant class derives fundamentally from its control of allocative

    resources (Giddens 1981: 210). As social power depends increasingly on

    allocative control, economic forces become the crucial levers of societal trans-

    formation (Giddens 1981: 104, 244). It is a distinctive feature of capitalism that

    economic growth becomes an imperative built into the social system. Giddens

    writes that capitalist society is associated with a chronic impetus to techno-logical innovation and economic growth unparalleled in previous history

    (Giddens 1981: 1212; see also 214).

    However, this chronic impetus also makes modernity prone to crisis.

    Giddens writes that Understanding the juggernaut-like nature of modernity

    goes a long way towards explaining why, in conditions of high modernity, crisis

    becomes normalised (1991: 184). The domination of nature, manifested in

    advancing technology, produces new threats, especially in the form of more

    devastating weapons. The threat of nuclear war has been a key theme inGiddens work (esp. Giddens 1985). At the end ofA Contemporary Critique of

    Historical Materialism, Giddens noted that the whole of humanity now lies in

    the shadow of possible destruction. This unique conjunction of the banal and

    the apocalyptic, this is the world that capitalism has fashioned (1981: 252). In

    subsequent work, Giddens increasingly dealt with risks of ecological disaster

    Life politics, nature and the state 103

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    6/24

    as an aspect of modernitys apocalyptic potential. In Beyond Left and Right,

    he argued that An ever-expanding capitalism runs up not only against envi-

    ronmental limits in terms of the earths resources, but against the limits of

    modernity (Giddens 1994: 10). Modern everyday life is evacuated of moral

    meaning and yet modernity unleashes technological forces that inspire dread.

    Such threats are rationalized within the abstract systems of modern science,

    such as formal risk assessment in which Apocalypse has become banal

    (Giddens 1991: 183). But Giddens suggested that these threats could not be

    contained within the parameters of instrumental or technical reason. Moder-

    nitys suppression of existential dilemmas reaches its limit.

    A key aspect of the reflexivity of high modernity is the re-emergence of

    existential problems suppressed by simple modernity. Giddens wrote that

    New forms of social movement mark an attempt at a collective reappropria-tion of institutionally repressed areas of life (1991: 207, see also Dickens 1999:

    101). He discussed ecological politics in this context. In Beyond Left and Right,

    he suggested:

    The ecological crisis [. . .] and the various philosophies and movements

    which have arisen in response to it, are expressions of a modernity which

    [. . .] comes up against its own limits.The practical and ethical considerations

    thus disclosed [. . .] express moral and existential dilemmas which modern

    institutions, with their driving expansionism and their impetus to control,have effectively repressed or sequestered. (Giddens 1994: 11)

    The opening up of the moral and existential question of how we should live

    is the defining feature of life politics (Giddens 1994: 90). The aspects of life

    hidden by modernity push back as ethical questions which have to be justi-

    fied, leading to the emergence of new political agendas (Giddens 1994a: 10).

    Ecological movements link concerns of everyday life (e.g. consumerism and

    waste) with challenges to systemic features of capitalism and modernity, ques-

    tioning especially the value of economic growth and the control of nature(Giddens 1991: 208). In this way ecological issues are a signal, as well as an

    expression, of the centrality of life-political problems. They pose with particu-

    lar force the questions we must face [. . .] when there are ethical dilemmas that

    mechanisms of constant economic growth either cause us to put to one side or

    make us repress (Giddens 1994: 92). Giddens thereby presented life-political

    movements, including ecology, as carriers of the reflexivity of high modernity

    (cf. McKechnie and Welsh 2002).

    The emergence of ecological politics demonstrates that modernity is nolonger able to bracket the existential contradiction rooted in human beings

    relationship to nature. A key dimension of the reflexivity of high modernity is

    that we can no longer treat the problem of nature as progressively solved

    through instrumental control. Instead, how we, as conscious agents, relate

    to nature becomes again a problem of morality and meaning as well as of

    104 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    7/24

    scientific understanding. In Beyond Left and Right, Giddens wrote, The ques-

    tion of how shall we live? is raised by any attempt to decide what to preserve

    of nature or of the past (1994: 212).

    However, the problem of nature returns in a new form in high modernity.

    Giddens has emphasized that, under conditions of modernity, nature is radi-

    cally transformed by human activity. In the sense of being a physical environ-

    ment independent of human action, nature has all but dissolved; the problems

    of environmental degradation which perturb us today come from the trans-

    formation of the natural into the social and cultural (Giddens 1994: 47). The

    environmental problems of high modernity are problems of the created envi-

    ronment and of a plastic nature moulded by human action (Giddens 1990: 60,

    127; 1994: 102).

    This transformation of nature introduces a new kind of ontologicalinsecurity. While modern science and technology allowed greater control over

    natural hazards such as disease, flood, and pests, new kinds of unpredictability

    emerge in high modernity. In Modernity and Self-Identity, Giddens pointed to

    global warming as an example of this new unpredictability arising not from

    brute nature but from the unintended consequences of industrial society. We

    today face high-consequence risks [. . .] about which precise risk assessment is

    virtually impossible (Giddens 1991: 137; cf. Beck 1995, 2009). We are less

    assured of the ability to control nature through science and technology, and

    unpredictability now arises from our very transformations of the natural

    world. These transformations, in turn, diminish our ability to treat nature

    as a source of ontological security. Giddens quoted environmentalist Bill

    McKibbens lament that the new transformed nature offers none of the con-

    solations of the retreat from the human world, a sense of permanence, or even

    of eternity (McKibben quoted in Giddens 1991: 137). The murkiness of the

    boundaries between the human and the natural is a key dimension of the

    radical ontological insecurity of high modernity.

    Giddens has criticized what he perceives as the fundamentalist tendency inenvironmentalism to retreat from this insecurity toward a romantic conception

    of natural harmony (1994: 11, 48). He argued that nature cannot any longer be

    defended in the natural way. Instead, a contemporary environmentalism must

    recognize that nature is no longer separate from human action (Giddens 1994:

    2056).The point, as Giddens put it in The Nation-State and Violence, should be

    not so much to rescue nature as to explore possibilities of changing human

    relationships themselves (1985: 341).

    Despite his criticisms of environmentalism, Giddens also argued for thepositive potential of the reflexivity that emerges from the environmentalist

    challenge to modernity. When environmentalists highlight problems of risk

    and deep ecologists lament lost natural harmonies, they experience these

    aspects of modernity as failures, and so questions of the modern relationship

    with nature return first of all under a negative sign . But Giddens suggested

    Life politics, nature and the state 105

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    8/24

    that each, when viewed positively, discloses moral considerations relevant to

    the question how shall we live? in a world of lost traditions and socialized

    nature. While pollution and environmental degradation represent modernity

    under a negative sign, the positive potential of high modernity is for renewed

    protection of the non-human world (Giddens 1994: 207). Giddens critique of

    what he saw as backward-looking tendencies in environmentalism was there-

    fore combined with his determination to pursue the positive ways in which

    environmentalism opens up the question of the human relationship with the

    non-human world, bringing back questions of meaning and morality, and

    calling for the assertion of conscious agency over and against the automatism

    of modernitys juggernaut.

    Life politics and the Third Way

    Giddens social and political theorizing has been influenced by environmen-

    talists call for a new value-orientation. Giddens suggested that one reason

    why existing Marxist and socialist thought needed to be revised is that this

    tradition has incorporated a Promethean approach to nature (1981: 60;

    Giddens 1994: 53; cf. Foster 1999: 372). The traditional left has remained

    mired in the productivism of simple modernity (Giddens 1994: 1756). A new

    approach is required for what Giddens has called the potential emergence of

    a post-scarcity order, defined as a condition in which economic growth can no

    longer be regarded as necessarily good, but must be evaluated ethically in

    terms of its effect on the quality of life (Giddens 1990: 1657; Giddens 1994:

    163). Giddens emphasized that scarcity is relative to socially defined needs

    and to the demands of specific life-styles. Therefore, moving toward a post-

    scarcity condition has less to do with reaching an absolute level of material

    abundance and more to do with alterations in modes of social life (Giddens

    1990: 166). The re-evaluation of our wants and needs called for by life politicsis an important part of this. Life politics points us [. . .] beyond circumstances

    in which economic criteria define the life circumstances of human beings

    (Giddens 1990: 165). This shift would involve a new ethical orientation toward

    nature. Giddens conjectured that An overall system of planetary care might be

    created, which would have as its aim the preservation of the ecological well-

    being of the world as a whole (1990: 170).

    Giddens theoretical work in the 1990s drew inspiration from the ways in

    which life politics called modernitys economic compulsiveness into question.Life politics could be expressed in lifestyle decisions that limit, or actively go

    against, maximizing economic returns (Giddens 1994: 102, emphasis in

    original). Giddens endorsed the need for change within everyday life. He

    wrote that A clear part of increased ecological concern is the recognition that

    reversing the degradation of the environment depends upon adopting new

    106 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    9/24

    lifestyle patterns. He suggested that Widespread changes in lifestyle, coupled

    with a de-emphasis on continual economic accumulation, will almost certainly

    be necessary if the ecological risks we now face are to be minimised (Giddens

    1991: 2212). A post-scarcity condition also demands the humanising of

    technology so as to introduce moral issues into the now largely instrumen-

    tal relation between human beings and the created environment (Giddens

    1990: 170). Against standard discourses of modernization that assume a

    single path of development targeted toward a high-production and high-

    consumption economic model, Giddens advocated alternative development

    taking into account non-material values as sources of happiness and self-

    respect (1994: 1638). The global cosmopolitanism emerging from reflexive

    modernization includes an attitude of respect towards non-human agencies

    and beings (Giddens 1994: 253).While Giddens criticized the way in which the value of economic growth has

    been taken for granted, he held back from asserting that post-scarcity order

    would mean an end to growth. Growth would be no longer of overriding

    importance (1994: 101). But a post-scarcity economy is not necessarily a

    no-growth economy (Giddens 1994: 178). He suggested that industrial pro-

    duction and the market could be deprived of their compulsive character and

    shaped by values expressed in life-political movements (Giddens 1990: 165).

    Giddens presented his utopian realism as shaping, but not operating

    against structural trajectories of the capitalist economy and the global market.

    Utopian realist politics seeks to realize life-political values, but in a way that

    corresponds to observable trends (Giddens 1994: 101). This problem of

    meshing life-political value-considerations with realism concerning what are

    taken to be objective economic and social trends remains the fundamental

    tension in Giddens Third Way project (Finlayson 2003: 12531). Giddens

    Third Way attempts to reconcile life politics both with the global market and

    the political structures of the nation-state. This attempt, however, necessarily

    collides with the structural contradictions of the capitalist state, contradictionsthat intensify under conditions of economic globalization. These contradic-

    tions have crucial implications for whether ecological issues can be adequately

    addressed within the framework of the Third Way.

    Giddens emphasized the nation-state as the crucible of power in modern

    societies (1981: 147, 189). But the capitalist nation-state is also dependent on

    processes of the accumulation of private capital that are outside its control.

    The contradictory position of the state in relation to capital is also a contra-

    diction between private appropriation and socialised production .Although capital is under private ownership, the unified or socialised

    character of capitalism produces much higher levels of societal integration

    (Giddens 1981: 238). Giddens observed that The capitalist state maintains a

    monopoly of political and military power within its own bounds, but the world

    system which it initiates is fundamentally influenced by capitalistic processes

    Life politics, nature and the state 107

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    10/24

    operating on a world scale (1981: 197). Increasing global social integration,

    driven by capitalism as a world system, is not matched at the political level,

    where power remains strongly tied to the nation-state (Giddens 1981: 202). So

    the contradictory relationship between the state and private accumulation

    becomes exacerbated as private capital is increasingly mobile on a global scale

    (Latham 2001: 31). Giddens writing on globalization can be understood as

    implying that the structural contradictions of the capitalist state increasingly

    take spatio-temporal form.

    In The Third Way, Giddens argued that globalization pulls away from the

    nation-state, especially weakening the states capacity for economic interven-

    tion (1998: 31; Loyal 2003: 155). At the same time, globalization pushes down

    below the level of the nation-state (Giddens 1998: 31). Giddens argued that

    globalization acts as a spur for de-traditionalization, individualization, andintensified social reflexivity (1994: 42, see also 801, 1101).Together, globali-

    zation and life politics call into question routinized domains of everyday life

    and produce pressures for grassroots democratization as a means for express-

    ing the heightened reflexivity of local and global life today (Giddens 1994:

    120). Globalization does not overturn the position of the nation-state as a

    crucible of power, but it does mean that the nation-state now stands in a

    contradictory relationship with social integration globally and increasing

    pressure for democratization locally.

    These contradictions impact the legitimacy of the nation-state since liberal

    democracy, based on an electoral party system, operating at the level of the

    nation-state, is not well equipped to meet the demands of a reflexive citizenry

    (Giddens 1994: 10). In The Third Way, Giddens called for a democratizing of

    democracy (1998: 77) in order to develop political forms that could overcome

    the contradictory relationship between the nation-state and globalization.

    Life politics and individualization require that authority [. . .] be recast on an

    active or participatory basis (Giddens 1998: 66). Giddens asserted that these

    new conditions required a double democratization: upward in the sense ofextending democracy to the level of supra-national institutions and downward

    in the sense of new forms of grassroots participation (1998: 717, 1467,

    quoting 72).

    As it pulls away and pushes down, globalization opens up a spatio-temporal

    dimension in the structural contradictions of the capitalist state. These struc-

    tural contradictions come to be combined with existential contradiction as the

    states ability to repress existential dilemmas is weakened under conditions of

    reflexive modernization. Renewed value-questions of how we should livecannot be handled by modernitys technocracies, bureaucracies and repre-

    sentative politics, and require new forms of dialogic democracy. Giddens

    argued in The Third Way that Experts cannot be relied upon [. . .] to know

    what is good for us and therefore that Characterizing risk [. . .] cannot just be

    left to experts (Giddens 1998: 59, 76).

    108 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    11/24

    Globalization creates pressures for grassroots democratization and awakens

    life-political concerns. But the demands of life-political movements such as

    environmentalism often conflict with the more economistic interests of the

    capitalist nation-state, with its dependency on private accumulation within a

    global market.This opens up the tension in Giddens utopian realism, begging

    the question of how to reconcile life-political values with economic and power-

    political interests. In his Fabian pamphlet, extracted in Giddens The Global

    Third Way Debate, Fabian Society director Michael Jacobs suggested that the

    key problem with environmentalism is that it is Driven by its values rather

    than by analysis of the world as it is (2001: 317; Jacobs 1999). Too frequently,

    environmentalists make utopian proposals that seem to ignore the trends of

    the modern world (Jacobs 2001: 318). A Third Way approach to ecological

    problems would aim at environmental modernisation, leveraging theknowledge-economy to solve ecological problems through technological inno-

    vation (Jacobs 2001: 32932, quoting 329). Bill Jordan has argued that Jacobs

    essay exemplifies the way in which Third Way thinkers and politicians have

    tried to reconcile ecological concerns with acceptance of the global market:

    the Green agenda was dismissed as backward-looking and unsuited to a

    globalised world, which required ecological policies to be integrated into an

    advanced technological response to all the challenges of an integrated world

    economy (Jordan 2010: 71).

    Jacobs essay prefigures the approach that Giddens adopts in his climate

    change book. In line with his conception of the nation-state as modernitys

    crucible of power, Giddens emphasizes that climate change must be analysed

    in relation to the power-political interests of nation-states, and that viable

    solutions to climate change will be those that nation-states can recognize as

    being in their interests. Solutions, he argues, will depend a great deal upon

    governmentand the state (Giddens 2009: 91 emphasis in original). Following

    from his insistence that Third way politics should take a positive attitude

    towards globalization (Giddens 1998: 64), Giddens also attempts to develop apolitics of climate change compatible with the global market. He does so,

    however, by largely abandoning his earlier engagement with life politics and by

    denying the relevance of environmentalism as a value-perspective. This indi-

    cates a breakdown of the attempt to reconcile life politics with the nation-state

    and global capitalism within a Third Way framework. Giddens abandons the

    utopian dimensions of his thought in favour of a power-political realist

    approach to climate change.

    Giddenss paradox and life politics

    Giddens rejection of the relevance of life politics for addressing climate

    change derives justification from what he calls Giddenss paradox: since the

    Life politics, nature and the state 109

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    12/24

    dangers posed by global warming arent tangible [. . .] many will sit on their

    hands and do nothing [. . .] about them. Yet waiting until they become visible

    and acute [. . .] will, by definition, be too late (2009: 2). This is both a problem

    of free-riding and of individuals discounting future harms in favour of imme-

    diate benefits (Giddens 2009: 23, 1012). Despite awareness of climate

    change, people are generally not spurred to take individual action to mitigate

    their own contribution to the problem. People drive Sport Utility Vehicles

    even in the knowledge that they are contributing to global crisis. Giddens sees

    little chance of the exhortations of environmentalists changing this. He writes

    that he is quite hostile to attempts to urge people to change their consump-

    tion patterns and daily habits in order to reduce their individual carbon

    footprint. [S]uch endeavours, he argues, are based upon a quite unrealistic

    assumption that everyone is willing and able to live like the small minority ofpositive greens (Giddens 2009: 106).

    These statements demarcate the politics of climate change from the ques-

    tion of how should we live? and the possibility of transforming everyday

    life as expressed by life politics. Instead, Giddens presents individual choice

    responding to market signals which governments can influence by providing

    positive financial incentives for adopting more environmentally-friendly prod-

    ucts (Giddens 2009: 1067). While governments may edit choice, Giddens

    accepts the market as the primary mediator of choices in everyday life and, in

    line with this, sees no possibility of a break within everyday life from moder-

    nitys instrumental relationship with nature. Giddens identifies the call for

    people to reduce their consumption with the environmental movements

    demand that we help save the planet. He argues that this expresses romantic

    values that are irrelevant to addressing global warming:We must also disavow

    any remaining forms of mystical reverence for nature, [. . .] tackling global

    warming has nothing to do with saving the earth, which will survive whatever

    we do (Giddens 2009: 6, 56).

    Similarly to Jacobs critique of environmentalism as value-driven (Jacobs2001: 317), Giddens presents environmentalism as antithetical to modernity

    and he argues that green ideas are amenable to reactionary politics (2009:

    512). He demarcates climate change from green issues, arguing that the fact

    that climate change can be known and defined only through science distin-

    guishes it from the types of problems that environmentalists more typically

    address (Giddens 2009: 55). Yet, many of the environmental movements

    claims depend on science (Yearley 1991; Tesh 2000; Egan 2007). Whether the

    questions are the effects of agricultural chemicals, radiation from nuclear-power plants, or an oil spills effects on marine life, environmental politics is

    always deeply interwoven with science. In this way, environmentalism exem-

    plifies the reflexive character of life-political movements. The value-oriented

    challenges of life-political movements combine with the way in which abstract

    systems of expertise call into question previously taken-for-granted features of

    110 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    13/24

    everyday life (Giddens 1990, 1991, 1994). In Politics, however, Giddens insists

    on a rigid demarcation between a scientific view of climate change and the

    value-orientation of saving the earth.

    As well as indicting environmentalism as mystical and anti-scientific,

    Giddens sees similar anti-modernist sensibilities in environmentalist opposi-

    tion to capitalist development. He maintains that the green movement is not

    helpful to the task of integrating environmental concerns into our established

    political institutions especially due to its history of hostile emotions toward

    industrial capitalism and markets (2009: 6, 53). Giddens earlier highlighted the

    tension between nation-state politics and life-political expressions of a reflex-

    ive citizenry (1994: 10), but in Politics he rejects the environmental movement

    because it is not well adapted to existing nation-state forms. In these ways,

    Giddens defends the institutional forms of modernity against the value-oriented challenges posed by life politics.

    Climate risk, technology, and the ensuring state

    The demarcation of climate change from value-considerations informs

    Giddens treatment of risk. Giddens has previously emphasized that risk is not

    merely negative but is also an energizing principle linked to the cultural,

    economic, and technological dynamism of modernity (1998: 63). However, as

    discussed above, Giddens also treated risk as expressing ontological insecurity

    and as opening up value-questions suppressed in modernity. Precisely for

    this reason, the characterization of risk could not be left to experts alone. In

    contrast, the way in which Giddens applies the concept of risk in Politics

    suggests a more narrowly economistic conception of weighing costs and

    benefits.

    Giddens explains that he side[s] with those who are optimistic about

    humanitys ability to deal with the problems of climate change in the sensethat risk and opportunity belong together; from the biggest risks can also flow

    the greatest opportunities (2009: 228). A cost-benefit model of risk is evident

    in Giddens rejection of the precautionary principle in favour of what he calls

    the percentage principle according to which there is always a balance of risks

    and opportunities to be considered (2009: 72, see also 57). Giddens acknowl-

    edges that Risks associated with climate change [. . .] shade so far over into

    uncertainty that they often cannot be calculated with any precision (2009:

    174). But if climate risks are highly uncertain, it becomes problematic to argue,as Giddens does, that one can balance risk with opportunity through market

    means such as assurance bonds and polluter pays mechanisms that entail the

    ability to assign monetary value (2009: 678; cf. Beck 2009: 1389). 2 Uncer-

    tainty has, instead, been a motivation for institutionalizing the precautionary

    principle which seeks to avoid environmental damage by careful forward

    Life politics, nature and the state 111

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    14/24

    planning and places the burden of proof on those implementing potentially

    harmful activities (ORiordan and Jordan 1995: 193; see also Raffensperger

    and Tickner 1999: 89; Wynne 1992).

    The precautionary principle is, on Giddens view, closely linked with envi-

    ronmentalisms conservationist attitude [. . .] towards nature (Giddens 2009:

    57, see also 53). His opposition to conservationism derives from his longstand-

    ing view that modernity has brought nature to an end. The value of staying

    close to nature or conservation, he argues has no direct relevance to climate

    change (Giddens 2009: 55). The desire to protect animal species from extinc-

    tion might [. . .] be a worthy one, he writes, but its only connection to climate

    change is if extinction threatens the ecosystems that help reduce emissions

    (Giddens 2009: 55).3 Conservationist and environmentalist calls to reduce

    consumption represent, for Giddens, an attempt to turn back history to asimpler world. Instead, he asserts there can be no overall going back the

    very expansion of human power that has created such deep problems is the

    only means of resolving them (2009: 228).

    Giddens looks for a solution to climate change compatible with his view

    that the juggernaut of modernity cannot be stopped and must be ridden. He

    finds this approach in ecological modernization theory (EMT), which envis-

    ages sustainability arising from a combination of economic development,

    technological innovation, and institutional reform (Dryzek 2005: 16779).

    This represents a marked departure from his more cautious treatment of

    EMT in The Third Way. There, he remarked that EMT did not adequately

    acknowledge the conflict between environmental protection and economic

    development (Giddens 1998: 58). Yet, in Politics, he endorses EMT as an

    approach through which environmental issues could best be dealt with by

    being normalized by drawing them into the existing framework of social

    economic institutions, rather than contesting those institutions as many

    greens chose to do (2009: 70). He also praises EMTs emphasis [. . .] on the

    role of science and technology in generating solutions to environmental dif-ficulties (Giddens 2009: 70). This description of EMT parallels Giddens own

    arguments for addressing climate change through a surge of technological

    innovation (2009: 11).

    Giddens expresses enthusiasm for technologies such as nuclear power and

    low fuel-consumption hypercars which would allow future economic growth

    to be decoupled from contributing to climate change (2009: 133, 1401). In

    this way, his argument aligns with the position of Jacobs and EMT that new

    technologies enable the dematerialisation of economic activity (Jacobs2001: 322; cf. York and Rosa 2003). A key way in which Giddens sees tech-

    nology as assisting with tackling climate change is through increases in

    energy efficiency. He asserts that greater energy efficiency ipso facto reduces

    emissions (Giddens 2009: 107). The idea that energy efficiency allows the

    dematerialization of growth enables Giddens to avoid extending his critique

    112 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    15/24

    of productivism (or what he calls in Politics the fetish of growth) to an

    endorsement of environmentalists calls for a no-growth society (Giddens

    2009: 9, 54).

    As discussed above, Giddens has been concerned to overcome the automa-

    tism of capitalisms growth-imperative, arguing that we are moving toward a

    post-scarcity society. In Politics he states that we cannot assume that growth

    is an unalloyed benefit and argues that GDP is not necessarily an adequate

    measure of wellbeing. His view is not that economic growth has to stop, but

    that it should not be pursued irrespective of its wider consequences and that

    we should adopt other measures such as the Sustainable Society Index (2009:

    656, 71).But he views growth as essential for developing countries even if this

    process involves a significant growth in greenhouse gas emissions (2009: 72).

    Developing countries should therefore have a licence to pollute (2009: 64).The notion of alternative development put forward in Beyond Left and Right

    is absent in Politics, which instead asserts a development imperative (2009: 9,

    64, 72). Giddens looks to Contraction and convergence whereby devel-

    oped countries reduce their emissions first, and radically, with poorer countries

    following suit as they become richer [. . .] Developing nations can increase

    their emissions for a period in order to permit growth, after which they must

    begin to reduce them. The two groups will then progressively converge (2009:

    645). Since Giddens rules out calling for significant lifestyle changes, it is

    crucial for his case that the reductions in emissions are made possible by new

    technologies. So he seems to take as a normative model the existing material

    living standards and consumption patterns of developed nations. Although he

    follows his earlier critique of productivism in the sense of rejecting a view of

    growth as an unproblematic good, an element of productivism remains in the

    view that a certain level of production must be achieved before environmental

    goals can be prioritized.

    For the spur toward technological energy-efficiency and green technology,

    Giddens looks to a combination of market signals and state action to incen-tivize consumers and businesses to reduce emissions (2009: 106). He argues

    that competition will create increased efficiency whenever [a] good is

    exchanged, but the state will have to ensure that externalized costs are

    brought into the marketplace (2009: 5). Carbon taxes are one method for

    regulating industry emissions that Giddens advocates (2009: 12, 14955). Such

    measures would be a component of what Giddens calls a return to planning.

    However, he emphasizes the difference between this and older socialist or

    social-democratic models. The kind of active state intervention that Giddenscalls for is in line with his earlier conception of the social investment state in

    The Third Way (2009: 5, 67, 69, 946; 1998: 99128). It is planning not in place

    of the market, but for the market, using incentives and penalties as means of

    editing choice, and operating as acatalyst and facilitator of action (2009: 91,

    109). The ensuring state facilitates, but also regulates, risk-taking in the

    Life politics, nature and the state 113

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    16/24

    market (2009: 916; see also Giddens 1998: 100). Giddens suggests that,

    through taxes, regulations, and incentives, states can promote a shift from

    energy-intensive practices toward efficiency and renewable energy (Giddens

    2009: 8, 923).

    Giddens conceptualizes the ensuring state as having a primarily cooperative

    relationship with private business and he expresses optimism about the pos-

    sibility of new forms of mutual action and collaboration between businesses,

    NGOs and citizens.While he acknowledges that Powerful interests often stand

    in the way of reform and recognizes the power of business in avoiding emis-

    sion reduction targets and in lobbying against climate change action, Giddens

    remains optimistic about the business communitys willingness to cooperate in

    climate-change mitigation efforts (2009: 11, 93, 11920). He expresses disap-

    proval of the easy demonizing of the industry lobbies, and of big businessmore generally, that pervades much of the environmental literature and is

    critical of the left for using climate change as an opportunity to renew the case

    against markets (2009: 49, 120). There are, he argues, significant examples of

    businesses voluntarily moving toward more ecologically sustainable practices.

    A new generation of business leaders, he writes, is arising which not only

    acknowledges the perils of climate change, but is active in the vanguard of

    reaction to it (2009: 121).

    There is room, however, for scepticism about the depth of such voluntary

    shifts in corporate practices, and Giddens himself acknowledges the problem

    of greenwash (2009: 121). Companies often claim to be reducing emissions

    based on a measure of carbon intensity, while increasing their total energy

    consumption and emissions. Environmental journalist Fred Pearce writes, The

    problem is that the atmosphere doesnt recognise this increased efficiency. All

    it does is respond to the extra carbon dioxide in the air by raising tempera-

    tures (Pearce 2009). Giddens points to Wal-Marts commitment to reduce its

    emissions (2009: 121). Yet, critics point out that Wal-Marts business model is

    highly import-dependent, producing significant emissions from long-distancecontainer-shipping, and that its big box stores increase car travel by customers

    (Anderson 2007, Anderson and Waskow 2007: 178; Mitchell 2011). In such

    cases, while there may be improvements in efficiency, the business model is

    fundamentally carbon-intensive.

    Corporate interests have also been influential within the political field,

    actively working against progress on climate-change policy. In the USA, oil

    and gas interests spent over $154 million on lobbying in 2009, including efforts

    against climate-change legislation (Mulkern 2010). In California, climate-change mitigation legislation (Assembly Bill 32) was enacted in 2006, and

    Giddens praises it an example of regional climate-change action (2009: 127,

    200). However, in 2010, prior to the laws implementation, oil companies and

    other corporate entities spent millions of dollars supporting a referendum

    initiative to suspend the law by requiring stringent economic conditions for its

    114 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    17/24

    activation (Roosevelt 2010).4 While this referendum ultimately failed at the

    polls, it constituted a concerted effort by corporate interests against climate-

    change policies.

    Giddens politics of climate change centre on international negotiations

    between nation-states, cooperation between states and business, and to some

    extent the role of NGOs in spurring states and businesses into taking action

    (2009: 5). The key to solving the climate change problem, for Giddens, is the

    convergence of interests: in the political sphere, the alignment of climate

    goals with other political goals, such as energy security, and in the economic

    sphere, alignment of climate action with competitive advantage (2009: 89).

    While Giddens recognizes that global summits meant to set targets for emis-

    sions have largely failed to achieve concrete results (Giddens 2009: 4, 18692,

    202; Giddens and Rees 2010), he does not propose truly distinct alternatives tothis model. For example, he criticizes the G-8 countries for not making

    progress on emissions-reduction goals, yet he calls for establishing a body

    representing the major polluters which would set an example of convergence

    by showing how emission reductions could be coupled with economic advan-

    tage (2009: 2212). The core of Giddens approach to climate change is the

    notion that the state can shape economic incentives, thereby promoting the

    convergence of social interests and stimulating technological advances such as

    in energy efficiency.

    Conclusion: life politics and climate change

    Giddens emphasis on technological solutions to climate change is an escape

    from the unresolved dilemma of how to reconcile his critique of productivism

    with his view that we must ride modernitys juggernaut: the central tension in

    his utopian realism. In A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism,

    Giddens argued that capitalism exhibits an unprecedented chronic impetus toboth technological innovation and economic expansion (Giddens 1981: 121).

    In Politics Giddens looks to innovation, especially improvements in energy

    efficiency, to reduce the climatic disruption that accompanies economic

    growth. But the Jevons paradox indicates that, by lowering costs, improved

    technological efficiency can itself facilitate the expansion of production,

    increasing overall resource-use and emissions (Foster 2009: 124; York and

    Rosa 2003: 280; Polimeni et al. 2009; Clark and York 2005: 411; Gould, Pellow,

    and Schnaiberg 2008: 44). Given capitalisms chronic impetus to growth, thebenefits of efficiency are likely to be swallowed up by the ongoing expansion

    of production. If technological efficiency is no panacea, then there is no solu-

    tion internal to capitalist modernitys dynamism. The response that is required

    is not just the application of modernitys science and innovation to modernitys

    risks, but a more fully ethical reflexivity, calling into question our modern ways

    Life politics, nature and the state 115

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    18/24

    of living and thinking (see also McKechnie and Welsh 2002).This is the kind of

    broad ethical reflexivity that Giddens has argued is characteristic of life

    politics.

    However, Politics operates with a highly restrictive value-frame that mar-

    ginalizes life politics in favour of instrumental and technocratic approaches.

    Giddens adopts an economistic approach to conceptualizing climate risk as a

    set of costs and benefits and to understanding political action in terms of

    instrumentally rational action motivated by economic incentives. He suggests

    that if these incentives can be structured properly, currently divergent interests

    will tend to converge. Giddens explicitly rejects the salience of an approach

    that calls on individuals to change their worldview and mode of everyday

    living. He presents environmentalists call for an ethical reorientation in atti-

    tudes as irrelevant to the problem of climate change. This is in contrast to theview expressed in a recent joint report by the Climate Outreach and Informa-

    tion Network, the Campaign to Protect Rural England, Friends of the Earth,

    Oxfam, and the World Wildlife Fund. This report, titled Common Cause: The

    Case for Working with our Cultural Values, stresses the importance of deep

    value-frames in motivating political action (Crompton 2010). The report

    argues that treating climate change as primarily an economic problem, as in

    the Stern Review on the Economics of Climate Change, may undermine the

    compelling moral arguments for action (Crompton 2010: 51, emphasis in

    original).

    Ingolfur Blhdorn similarly criticizes policy agendas relying on technologi-

    cal fixes and incremental reform. He writes:

    As these techno-managerial approaches reinforce rather than challenge the

    underlying values and logic governing advanced modern societies [. . .] they

    may actually themselves accelerate the depletion of the cultural resources

    on which sustainability vitally depends. (Blhdorn 2009: 4)

    Politics instantiates such cultural depletion, since a major thrust of this book

    is toward discrediting the environmentalist valuation of nature for its own

    sake. Instead, the values that Giddens puts forward in Politics are those that

    mesh with the instrumentalist orientation of capitalist culture. He argues that

    with risk comes opportunity and that tackling climate change can be a

    positive-sum game since it will create economic opportunities. Giddens

    response to climate change mirrors what Jordan has argued is the broader

    tendency of the Third Way to base policy on a utilitarian rational-actormodel of society as composed of individuals organized through market

    incentives and contractual regulation (Jordan 2010: esp. 3, 4362). Politics

    reinforces an instrumental frame of rational self-interest congruent both

    with market individualism and with the pursuit of national self-interest by

    states.

    116 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    19/24

    Politics participates in what Giddens previously referred to as modernitys

    suppression of existential dilemmas. The value question of how should we

    live? is suppressed in the book, as Giddens rejects the relevance of change in

    everyday modes of living and instead prioritizes elite action (by policymakers

    and enlightened corporate leaders), asserts an imperative of economic devel-

    opment, and calls for More of the same in the sense of the pursuit of scientific

    and technological development (2009: 6, 93). Politics therefore responds to

    climate change in the technical-instrumental mode of simple modernization,

    abandoning the insights of high-modern reflexivity. This reflexivity has to do

    not only with the way abstract systems of expertise impinge on everyday life,

    but also the flooding back of repressed existential concerns, and their expres-

    sion in life politics.

    Environmentalisms reconsideration of the human relationship with thebroader living world manifests modernitys inability to keep existential dilem-

    mas and associated value-questions at bay. The contradiction basic to human

    existence of being both in nature and transcending it is no longer effectively

    suppressed in the pursuit of economic growth and scientific-technical advance

    and mediated through the structures of the state. A key dimension of high-

    modern reflexivity is that it has become apparent that the instrumental

    control of nature through science and technology produces new hazards and

    uncertainties. This occurs in a context of the wasteland of everyday life with

    few patterned ways of mediating existential problems (Giddens 1981: 13). For

    this reason, the re-emergence of these suppressed dilemmas calls modern

    everyday life into question, presenting life-style as a value problem.

    Giddens insists that there is no going back either to tradition or nature.

    Nature has ended in the sense that it can no longer be taken for granted. But

    this does not provide grounds for suggesting that nature has ceased altogether

    to be a meaningful category (Dickens 1999: 1024). Giddens recognition that

    capitalist accumulation [. . .] is not self-sustaining in terms of resources and

    reference to environmental limits in terms of the earths resources suggestthat it is still possible to speak of natural resources as an external condition for

    human economic activity (1990: 165; 1994: 10). And his discussion of problems

    of deciding what to preserve implies that it does still make sense to think of

    natural ecosystems as an evolved inheritance to be conserved rather than a

    product of human activity (Giddens 1994: 212). Problems of pollution are not

    just problems of our created environment but of how what we create interacts

    with features of the physical and biological world that human beings have not

    created and do not control. For example, in the case of global warming, humanstransform nature by burning fossil fuels, but do not create or control the heat

    absorption characteristics of carbon dioxide or the interactions between the

    Earths atmosphere and oceans. Climate change therefore represents a

    complex interaction between nature and technologized second nature. The

    effects of climate change on weather patterns (producing floods, droughts, and

    Life politics, nature and the state 117

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    20/24

    storms) exemplify how nature returns in a way in which what is natural and

    what is unnatural is problematic. This lack of distinctness of the boundary

    between the human and non-human nature is a key dimension of the onto-

    logical insecurity of high modernity.

    While some forms of environmentalism, notably deep ecology, do try to

    derive values from pure nature, this is just one part of the more complex way

    in which ecological politics foregrounds and contests problems of how to value

    nature, and how to decide what to preserve. Giddens wrote that nineteenth-

    century romanticism gave rise to Antecedent forms of todays green move-

    ments (1990: 161). But environmentalism has developed beyond these origins.

    Contemporary environmentalism operates not only with romantic value-

    repertoires, but also with scientific knowledge-claims which it mobilizes even

    while contesting technocratic authority (Yearley 1991; Fischer 2000; Egan2007; Tesh 2000). Environmentalist movements challenge the demarcation of

    risk debates within the boundaries of technical knowledge, and insist on the

    moral and aesthetic value-dimensions of these issues (McKechnie and Welsh

    2002; Wynne 2002). In doing so, these movements carry an awareness that

    environmental issues are not just about better management of pollution, but

    are also existential troubles that require ethical reflection concerning the place

    of human beings in relation to the physical and biological world of nature (see

    also Jordan 2010: 823).

    Modern ecological problems such as climate change re-open the existential

    contradiction under conditions in which this is no longer adequately mediated

    by social institutions but becomes a pressing source of ontological insecurity,

    calling forth new modes of reflexivity. While the existential contradiction

    appears in new form, it continues to be related in complex ways with structural

    contradictions of the state. Action on climate change is mired in the structural

    contradictions of the capitalist state. One can see in climate change the con-

    tradiction between socialized production and private appropriation, especially

    in the sense in which productions externalities are socialized in the form ofpollution while profit is privately appropriated.The dependence of the state on

    private accumulation is a significant obstacle to international agreement as

    states are unwilling to agree to climate regulation that could adversely affect

    the competitiveness of their national economies (see also Jordan 2010: 1423).

    Giddens sociological theory provides a conceptual framework for under-

    standing the social dimensions of climate change as a problem in which the

    suppressed existential dilemma of the human relationship with nature returns

    and is made manifest, but is also deeply entangled with contradictions of thecapitalist state. Existential dilemmas that return in high modernity are

    expressed in life politics. However, this opens up a new contradiction between

    this form of politics and the forms of participation institutionalized in the

    nation-state. Giddens proposals for democratizing democracy were in recog-

    nition of the need for new institutionalized forms of participation enabling the

    118 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    21/24

    expression of life politics. However, life-political questioning of values at the

    level of everyday life largely goes without institutional articulation, falling

    between the structures of the state and the market. Giddens approach to the

    politics of climate change is symptomatic of this gap, as he abandons the

    life-political component of the Third Way in favour of a technocratic and

    managerial approach in which the key actors are businesses, politicians and

    officials.

    In Politics, citizens are relegated to a role in support of policymaking.

    Giddens writes that, while generating widespread political support from citi-

    zens is necessary, for better or worse, the state retains many of the powers that

    have to be invoked if a serious impact on global warming is to be made

    (Giddens 2009: 91). The problem with this state-centered conception of politics

    is that it fails to express and articulate the active stance towards the conditionsof their existence that Giddens has argued is characteristic of a society of high

    reflexivity (Giddens 1994: 87).

    The significance of environmentalism, as a life-political movement, is pre-

    cisely the way it calls into question conditions of existence taken for granted

    in modernity. The challenge environmentalism poses is to re-evaluate our

    everyday practices and social and economic organization in light both of a

    scientific understanding of environmental harms and of an ethical reformula-

    tion of the place of humanity in the natural world. The lack of integration of

    environmentalism into orthodox politics stems from the contradiction

    between the dominant structures of the capitalist state and the forms of

    reflexivity carried by life-political movements. This contradiction between life

    politics and the capitalist state is key for understanding the failures so far of

    policy responses to climate change.

    (Date accepted: November 2012)

    Notes

    1. The authors would like to thank Jenni-

    fer Nations for her input at an early stage of

    this work, and Ingmar Lippert for comments

    on an earlier draft. We are also very grateful

    to this journals anonymous referees for

    their enormously helpful feedback.

    2. The notion of balancing risk and

    opportunity is, in general, problematic whenapplied to environmental problems. When

    one makes a monetary investment in a

    venture, potential losses are finite (limited to

    the amount invested), while the oppor-

    tunities may be virtually infinite. With the

    environment, this calculation is reversed:

    potential losses are infinite and they may be

    irreversible as in the case of extinction.

    There may also be a long time-delay before

    environmental harms become fully evident

    and chains of causality are often extremely

    complex.

    3. The connection between conservationand efforts to mitigate climate change is, in

    fact, highly significant, since emissions from

    deforestation make up 17 to 20 per cent of

    annual global greenhouse gas emissions

    (Secretariat of the Convention on Biological

    Life politics, nature and the state 119

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    22/24

    Diversity and Deutsche Gesellschaft fr

    Internationale Zusammenarbeit 2011: 11).

    The United Nations Global Biodiversity Out-

    look Reportargues,The linked challenges of

    biodiversity loss and climate change must beaddressed by policy-makers with equal prior-

    ity and in close co-ordination, if the most

    severe impacts of each are to be avoided

    (Secretariat of the Convention on Biological

    Diversity 2010: 11).

    4. The measure, Proposition 23, would

    have suspended implementation of the

    emission controls until unemployment

    drops to 5.5 percent or less for [a] full

    year http://www.voterguide.sos.ca.gov/

    propositions/23/ (Accessed May 5, 2011).

    See also Campaign Finance: Yes on 23,California Jobs Initiative, a Coalition of

    Taxpayers, Employers, Food Producers,

    Energy, Transportation and Forestry Com-

    panies, Cal-Access, http://cal-access.ss.ca.

    gov/Campaign/Committees/Detail.aspx?id=

    1323890&session=2009&view=general

    (Accessed June 14, 2012).

    Bibliography

    Anderson, S. 2007 Wal-Marts New Green-

    washing Report, AlterNet, 20 November

    2007, [online] Available at: http://www.

    alternet.org/environment/68352/

    Anderson, S. and Waskow, D. 2007 Global

    Warming in S. Anderson (ed.) Wal-Marts

    Sustainability Initiative: A Civil Society Cri-

    tique, ed. [online] Available at: http://www.ips-dc.org/reports/wal-marts_sustainability_

    initiative_a_civil_society_critique

    Beck, U. 1995 Ecological Politics in an Age

    of Risk, Cambridge: Polity.

    Beck, U. 2009 World at Risk, Cambridge:

    Polity.

    Blhdorn, I. 2009 Locked Into the Politics

    of Unsustainability, Eurozine, 30 October

    30 2009, [online] Available at: http://www.

    eurozine.com/articles/2009-10-30-bluhdorn-en.html

    Callinicos, A. 2001 Against the Third Way:

    An Anti-Capitalist Critique, Cambridge:

    Polity Press.

    Clark, B. and York, R. 2005 Carbon

    Metabolism: Global Capitalism, Climate

    Change, and the Biospheric Rift, Theory

    and Society 34: 391428.

    Craib, I. 2011 [1992] Anthony Giddens,

    London: Routledge.Crompton, T. 2010 Common Cause: The

    Case for Working with our Cultural Values,

    London: WWF-UK.

    Dickens, P. 1999 Life Politics, the Environ-

    ment and the Limits of Sociology in M.

    OBrien, S. Penna and C. Hays (eds) Theo-

    rising Modernity: Reflexivity, Environment

    and Identity in Giddens Social Theory,

    London: Longman.

    Dryzek, J.S. 2005 The Politics of the Earth:

    Environmental Discourses, Second Edition,

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Egan, M. 2007 Barry Commoner and theScience of Survival:The Remaking of Ameri-

    can Environmentalism, Cambridge, MA:

    MIT Press.

    Finlayson, A. 2003 Making Sense of New

    Labour, London: Lawrence and Wishart.

    Fischer, F. 2000 Citizens, Experts and the

    Environment: The Politics of Local Knowl-

    edge, Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Foster, J.B., 1999 Marxs Theory of the

    Metabolic Rift: Classical Foundationsfor Environmental Sociology, American

    Journal of Sociology 105(2): 366405.

    Foster, J.B. 2009 The Ecological Revolution:

    Making Peace with the Planet, New York:

    Monthly Review Press.

    Giddens, A. 1979 Central Problems in Social

    Theory: Action, Structure and Contradiction

    in Social Analysis, London: MacMillan.

    Giddens, A. 1981 A Contemporary Critique

    of Historical Materialism, Vol. 1: Power,Property and the State, London: MacMillan.

    Giddens, A. 1985 The Nation-State and Vio-

    lence: Volume Two of a Contemporary Cri-

    tique of Historical Materialism, Cambridge:

    Polity Press.

    120 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013 British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    23/24

    Giddens, A. 1990 The Consequences of

    Modernity, Stanford: Stanford University

    Press.

    Giddens, A. 1991 Modernity and Self-

    Identity, Stanford: Stanford UniversityPress.

    Giddens, A. 1994 Beyond Left and Right,

    Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Giddens, A. 1994a Industrialization, Eco-

    logy, and the Development of Life Politics

    in W.V. DAntonio, M. Sasaki and Y.

    Yonebayashi (eds) Ecology, Society & the

    Quality of Social Life, New Brunswick, NJ:

    Transaction Publishers.

    Giddens, A. 1994b Living in a Post-Traditional Society in U. Beck, A. Giddens

    and S. Lash, Reflexive Modernization: Poli-

    tics, Tradition and Aesthetics in the Modern

    Social Order, Stanford: Stanford University

    Press.

    Giddens, A. 1998 The Third Way, Cam-

    bridge: Polity.

    Giddens, A. (ed.) 2001 The Global Third

    Way Debate, Cambridge: Polity.

    Giddens, A. 2009 The Politics of ClimateChange, Cambridge: Polity.

    Giddens, A. and Rees, M. 2010 Open Letter

    on Climate Change, The Huffington Post22

    September 2010,[online] Available at: http://

    www.huffingtonpost.com/anthony-giddens/

    open-letter-on-climate-ch_b_734676.html

    Gould, K.A., Pellow, D.N. and Schnaiberg,

    A. 2008 The Treadmill of Production: Injus-

    tice and Unsustainability in the Global

    Economy, London: Paradigm Publishers.Jacobs, M. 1999 Environmental Modernisa-

    tion:The New Labour Agenda, London: The

    Fabian Society.

    Jacobs, M. 2001 The Environment, Moder-

    nity and the Third Way in A. Giddens (ed.)

    The Global Third Way Debate, Cambridge:

    Polity.

    Jordan, B. 2010 Why the Third Way Failed:

    Economics, Morality and the Origins of the

    Big Society, London: The Policy Press.Latham, M. 2001 The Third Way: An

    Outline in A. Giddens (ed.) The Global

    Third Way Debate, Cambridge: Polity.

    Loyal, S. 2003 The Sociology of Anthony

    Giddens, London: Pluto.

    McKechnie, R. and Welsh, I. 2002 When the

    Global Meets the Local: Critical Reflections

    on Reflexive Modernization in R.E. Dunlap

    et al. (eds) SociologicalTheory and the Envi-

    ronment: Classical Foundations, Contem-porary Insights, Lanham, MD: Rowan &

    Littlefield.

    Mitchell, S. 2011 Can You Say Sprawl?

    Walmarts Biggest Climate Impact Goes

    Ignored, Grist, November 29, [online]

    Available at: http://www.grist.org/business-

    technology/2011-11-29-can-you-say-sprawl-

    walmarts-biggest-climate-impact-goes-

    ignored

    Mulkern, A.C. 2010 Oil and Gas InterestsSet Spending Record for Lobbying in 2009,

    The New York Times, 2 February, [online]

    Available at: http://www.nytimes.com/

    gwire/2010/02/02/02greenwire-oil-and-gas-

    interests-set-spending-record-for-l-1504.

    html

    OBrien, M. 1999 Theorising Modernity:

    Reflexivity, Identity and Environment in

    Giddens Social Theory in M. OBrien, S.

    Penna and C. Hays (eds) Theorising Moder-nity: Reflexivity, Environment and Identity in

    Giddens Social Theory, London: Longman.

    OBrien, M., Penna, S. and Hay, C. (eds)

    1999 Theorising Modernity: Reflexivity, Envi-

    ronment and Identity in Giddens Social

    Theory, London: Longman.

    ORiordan, T. and Jordan, A. 1995 The Pre-

    cautionary Principle in Contemporary Envi-

    ronmental Politics, Environmental Values

    4(3): 191212.Pearce, F. 2009 Greenwash: Tesco and its

    Bizarre Carbon Accountancy, The Guard-

    ian 15 January 2009, [online] Available

    at: http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/

    2009/jan/15/greenwash-tesco

    Polimeni, J.M., Mayumi, K., Giampietro, M.

    and Alcott, B. 2009 The Myth of Resource

    Efficiency: The Jevons Paradox, London,

    UK: Earthscan Publishing.

    Raffensperger, C. and Tickner, J. 1999Introduction:To Foresee and to Forestall in

    C. Raffensperger and J. Tickner (eds) Pro-

    tecting Public Health & the Environment:

    Implementing the Precautionary Principle,

    Washington, D.C.: Island Press.

    Life politics, nature and the state 121

    London School of Economics and Political Science 2013British Journal of Sociology 64(1)

  • 7/30/2019 politica vitales, naturaleza y estado en giddens.pdf

    24/24

    Roosevelt, M. 2010 Bid to Suspend Califor-

    nias Global Warming Law Qualifies for

    November Ballot, Los Angeles Times June

    23, 2010, [online] Available at: http://articles.

    latimes.com/2010/jun/23/local/la-me-climate-initiative-20100623

    Secretariat of the Convention on Biological

    Diversity 2010 Global Biodiversity Outlook

    3, Montreal: Secretariat of the Convention

    on Biological Diversity.

    Secretariat of the Convention on Biologi-

    cal Diversity and Deutsche Gesellschaft

    fr Internationale Zusammenarbeit 2011

    Biodiversity and Livelihoods: REDD-plus

    Benefits, Montreal: Secretariat of the Con-vention on Biological Diversity.

    Shove, E. 2003 Comfort, Cleanliness and

    Convenience: The Social Organization of

    Normality, Oxford: Berg.

    Tesh, S. 2000 Uncertain Hazards: Environ-

    mental Activists and Scientific Proof, Ithaca:

    Cornell University Press.

    Wynne, B. 1992 Uncertainty and Environ-

    mental Learning: Reconceiving Science andPolicy in the Preventive Paradigm, Global

    Environmental Change 2(2): 11127.

    Wynne, B. 2002 Risk and Environment

    as Legitimatory Discourses of Technology:

    Reflexivity Inside Out? Current Sociology

    50(3): 45977.

    Yearley, S. 1991 The Green Case: A Sociol-

    ogy of Environmental Issues, Arguments and

    Politics, London: HarperCollins Academic.

    York, R. and Rosa, E.A. 2003 Key Chal-lenges to Ecological ModernizationTheory,

    Organization & Environment 16(3): 27388.

    122 Charles Thorpe and Brynna Jacobson