semantic paradoxes continued. recap the barber paradox once upon a time there was a village, and in...

82
Semantic Paradoxes Continued

Upload: jessica-juers

Post on 28-Mar-2015

219 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Semantic Paradoxes Continued

Page 2: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

RECAP

Page 3: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

The Barber Paradox

Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. • B shaved all the villagers who did not shave

themselves, • And B shaved none of the villagers who did

shave themselves.Question, did B shave B, or not?

Page 4: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Suppose B Shaved B

1. B shaved B Assumption2. B did not shave any villager X where X shaved X

Assumption3. B did not shave B 1,2 Logic

Page 5: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Suppose B Did Not Shave B

1. B did not shave B Assumption2. B shaved every villager X where X did not shave X

Assumption3. B shaved B 1,2 Logic

Page 6: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

The Law of Excluded Middle

Everything is either true or not true.

Either P or not-P, for any P.

Either B shaved B or B did not shave B, there is not third option.

Page 7: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Disjunction Elimination

A or BA implies CB implies C

Therefore, C

Page 8: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Contradiction, No Assumptions

B shaves B or B does not shave B [Law of Excluded Middle]

If B shaves B, contradiction.If B does not shave B, contradiction.

Therefore, contradiction

Page 9: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Contradictions

Whenever we are confronted with a contradiction, we need to give up something that led us into the contradiction.

Page 10: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

No Barber

In this instance, however, it makes more sense to give up our initial acquiescence to the story: We assumed that there was a village with a barber who shaved all and only the villagers who did not shave themselves.

The paradox shows us that there is no such barber, and that there cannot be.

Page 11: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Disquotation

To say P is the same thing as saying ‘P’ is true. This is the “disquotation principle”:

P = ‘P’ is true

Page 12: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Liar Sentence

L = ‘L’ is not true

Page 13: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

“‘L’ is true”

1. ‘L’ is true Assumption2. L 1, Disquotation3. ‘L’ is not true 2, Def of L

1 & 3 form a contradiction

Page 14: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

“‘L’ is not true”

1. ‘L’ is not true Assumption2. L 1, Def of L3. ‘L’ is true 2, Disquotation

1 & 3 form a contradiction

Page 15: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Contradiction

‘L’ is true or ‘L’ is not true[Law of Excluded Middle]

If ‘L’ is true, then ‘L’ is true and not true.If ‘L’ is not true, then ‘L’ is true and not true.

Therefore, ‘L’ is true and not true.

Page 16: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Solutions

1. Give up excluded middle2. Give up disjunction elimination3. Give up disquotation4. Disallow self-reference5. Accept that some contradictions are true

Page 17: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

The Liar’s Lesson?

There are lots of very complicated solutions to the liar, all of which do one of two things: abandon classical logic or abandon disquotation.

It’s clear we have to do one of these things, but neither is very satisfying, and there are no solutions to the liar that everyone likes.

Page 18: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Grelling’s Paradox

Grelling’s Paradox or the paradox of heterological terms is very similar to the liar.

To begin with, let’s consider a principle like Disquotation, which I’ll just call D2:

‘F’ applies to x = x is F

Page 19: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Autological and Heterological

The analogue of ‘L’ in Grelling’s paradox is the new term ‘heterological’ defined as follows:

x is heterological = x does not apply to x

We can also define autological, as follows:x is autological = x does apply to x

Page 20: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Question: Does ‘heterological’ apply to ‘heterological’?

Page 21: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Yes?

1. ‘H’ applies to ‘H’ Assumption2. ‘H’ is H 1 D23. ‘H’ does not apply to ‘H’ 2 Def H

Page 22: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

No?

1. ‘H’ does not apply to ‘H’ Assumption2. ‘H’ is H 1 Def H3. ‘H’ applies to ‘H’ 2 D2

Page 23: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Contradiction

Just like the liar, we’re led into a contradiction if we assume:

• D2: ‘F’ applies to x = x is F• Law of excluded middle: ‘heterological’ either

does or does not apply to itself.• A or B, if A then C, if B then C; Therefore, C

Page 24: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

RUSSELL’S PARADOX

Page 25: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Sets

There are dogs and cats and couches and mountains and countries and planets.

According to Set Theory there are also sets. The set of dogs includes all the dogs as members, and all the members of the set of dogs are dogs. Likewise for the set of mountains, and the set of planets.

Page 26: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Notation

We write out sets by putting names of their members between brackets. So the set of full professors in Lingnan philosophy is:

{Darell, Neven, Paisley}

Page 27: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Notation

We can also write the set using a condition:

{x: x is a full professor in Lingnan philosophy}

This is the same as the set {Darell, Neven, Paisley}. We might introduce a name for this set:

F = {x: x is a full professor in Lingnan philosophy}

Page 28: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Membership

The fundamental relation in set theory is membership, or “being in.”

Members of a set are in the set, and non-members are not. Mt. Everest is in {x: x is a mountain}, Michael Jordan is not in {x: x is a mountain}.

Page 29: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Set Theoretic Rules

Reduction:a is in {x: COND(x)}Therefore, COND(a)

Abstraction:COND(a)

Therefore, a is in {x: COND(x)}

Page 30: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Examples

Reduction: Mt. Everest is in {x: x is a mountain}Therefore, Mt. Everest is a mountain.

Abstraction: Mt. Everest is a mountain.Therefore, Mt. Everest is in {x: x is a mountain}

Page 31: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Self-Membered Sets

It’s possible that some sets are members of themselves. Let S = {x: x is a set}. Since S is a set, S is in {x: x is a set} (by abstraction), and thus S is in S (by Def of S).

Or consider H = {x: Michael hates x}. Maybe I even hate the set of things I hate. So H is in H.

Page 32: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Russell’s Paradox Set

Most sets are non-self-membered. The set of mountains is not a mountain; the set of planets is not a planet; and so on. Define:

R = {x: x is not in x}

Page 33: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Is R in R?

1. R is in R Yes?2. R is in {x: x is not in x} 1, Def of R3. R is not in R 2, Reduction

4. R is not in R No?5. R is in {x: x is not in x} 4, Abstraction6. R is in R 5, Def of R

Page 34: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Historical Importance

Russell’s paradox was what caused Frege to stop doing mathematics and do philosophy of language instead.

Page 35: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Comparison with the Liar

Russell thought that his paradox was of a kind with the liar, and that any solution to one should be a solution to the other.

Basically, he saw both as arising from a sort of vicious circularity.

Page 36: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Comparison with the Liar

If this is right the semantic paradoxes may not be properly “semantic” at all, but arise from a structural feature that many non-semantic things (like sets) also have.

Page 37: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

The von Neumann Heirarchy

Page 38: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

CURRY’S PARADOX

Page 39: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Haskell Brooks Curry

• Mathematician who worked on combinatory logic.

• Has three computer languages named after him: Haskell, Brooks, and Curry.

• Devised a semantic paradox.

Page 40: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Conditional Proof

Suppose you want to prove a conditional (“if-then”) statement.

For example, suppose you want to show that if the accuser is telling the truth, then the accused should go to jail.

Page 41: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

The Accusation

Michael kicked me.

Page 42: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Assuming for the Sake of Argument

First, you would assume for the sake of argument that the accuser is telling the truth. Assume that Michael did in fact kick the puppy.

(Even though of course he’s innocent.)

Page 43: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Conditional Proof

Then you would use that assumption to show that Michael belonged in jail.

You would argue that since kicking puppies violates article 2, section 6, paragraph 3 of the criminal code, Michael belongs in jail.

Page 44: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Conditional Proof

Finally, you would stop assuming that Michael did actually kick the puppy and conclude:

If the accuser is telling the truth, then Michael belongs in jail.

Page 45: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Modus Ponens

There’s one other rule of logic that involves conditionals. This rule is used when we already know a conditional is true:

Premise: if A, then BPremise: A

Conclusion: B

Page 46: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Curry’s Paradox

Define the Curry sentence C as follows:

C = If C is true, then Michael is God.

Page 47: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proving C

To prove C we do a conditional proof:

C = If ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God.

Page 48: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proving C

To prove C we do a conditional proof:

C = If ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God.

Assume this.

Page 49: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proving C

To prove C we do a conditional proof:

C = If ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God.

Prove this.

Page 50: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proving C

To prove C we do a conditional proof:

C = If ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God.

Throw out assumption and conclude this.

Page 51: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proof of C

1. ‘C’ is true Assumption2. C 1, Disquotation3. ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God

2, Definition of C4. Michael is God 1, 3, Modus Ponens

Page 52: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proof of C

1. ‘C’ is true Assumption2. C 1, Disquotation3. ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God

2, Definition of C4. Michael is God 1, 3, Modus Ponens5. If ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God

1, 4 Cond. Proof

Page 53: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

No Paradox Yet

Now we have proven C. This in itself should not bother us.

We are not committed to saying Michael is God, only that if ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God.

Page 54: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Proof that Michael is God

1. If ‘C’ is true, then Michael is God.Previous Proof

2. C 1, Definition of C3. ‘C’ is true 2, Disquotation4. Michael is God 1, 3, Modus Ponens

Page 55: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Set Theory Version

Curry’s Paradox also comes in a set theoretic flavor. The paradoxical set is this one:

M = {x: if x is in x, then Michael is God}

Page 56: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Requirements

Curry’s Paradox leads to contradiction (or absurdity, or anything you like) and all it requires is:• Self-reference• Disquotation• Conditional Proof• Modus Ponens

Page 57: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Important Feature

Curry’s Paradox uses different logical rules (modus ponens, conditional proof) than the liar paradox (excluded middle, disjunction elimination).

This suggests that it’s probably not the logic, but instead self-reference and/ or disquotation that is the problem.

Page 58: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Important Feature

Recall that paraconsistent logics can avoid the Liar Paradox by assuming that some sentences can be both true and false while avoiding explosion.

Even with such an assumption, however, Curry’s Paradox still works, and leads to explosion, since you can prove anything with it.

Page 59: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

THE PARADOX OF THE HEAP

Page 60: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Sorites

1. 1 grain of sand is not a heap.2. For all numbers n: if n grains of sand are not

a heap, then n + 1 grains of sand are not a heap.

3. Therefore, 200 trillion grains of sand are not a heap.

Page 61: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

The Other Way

1. 200 trillion grains of sand makes a heap.2. For all numbers n: if n + 1 grains of sand

make a heap, then n grains of sand make a heap.

3. Therefore 1 grain of sand makes a heap.

Page 62: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Paradox

Neither of these sorites arguments results in a contradiction… until you add in the obvious fact that the conclusion of each is false.

Page 63: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Borderline Cases

The paradox seems to arise whenever we have a term that admits of borderline cases.

There are some people that I don’t know whether they’re rich out of uncertainty: because I don’t know how much money they have. These are not borderline cases.

Page 64: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Borderline Cases

The paradox seems to arise whenever we have a term that admits of borderline cases.

But there are other people that I don’t know whether they are rich even though I know exactly how much money they have. These are borderline cases.

Page 65: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Borderline Cases

Most of our ordinary language admits of borderline cases:

Big, tall, short, rich, fast, slow, smart, dumb, funny, long, flat, narrow…

Also: mountain, car, tree, horse…

Page 66: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

What To Do?

Neither of these sorites arguments results in a contradiction… until you add in the obvious fact that the conclusion of each is false.

To deny the conclusion, we need to deny either premise 1 or premise 2 or logic.

Page 67: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Denying Premise 1

In the first argument, premise 1 is:

1 grain of sand is not a heap.

In the second it’s:

200 trillion grains of sand is a heap.

Page 68: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Denying Premise 2

Premise 2 (Argument 1) says: For all numbers n: if n grains of sand are not a heap, then n + 1 grains of sand are not a heap.

The negation of this is: There exists a number n such that: n grains of sand are not a heap, but n + 1 grains of sand are a heap.

Page 69: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Denying Premise 2

Premise 2 (Argument 2) says: For all numbers n: if n + 1 grains of sand make a heap, then n grains of sand make a heap.

The negation of this is: There is a number n such that: n + 1 grains of sand make a heap, but n grains of sand do not make a heap.

Page 70: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

No Sharp Boundaries

Premise 2 in both cases asserts No Sharp Boundaries. It’s never true that one grain of sand makes the difference between a heap and not a heap.

Page 71: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

No Sharp Boundaries

• One hair doesn’t make the difference between being bald and not bald.

• One micrometer doesn’t make the difference between being tall and not tall.

• $0.10HKD does not make the difference between being rich and not rich.

• One nanosecond does not make the difference between being old and not old.

Page 72: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Solutions

1. Accept Sharp Boundaries.2. Introduce more truth-values.

Page 73: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Epistemicism

One solution is to claim that there ARE sharp boundaries, but we can never know where they are.

Acquiring $0.10 can make someone go from not rich to rich, but we can’t ever know when this happens.

Page 74: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Epistemicism

Basic problem: What determines the boundary if not how we use the words?

What determines how we use the words if not what we (can) know?

Page 75: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Epistemicism

Further problem: the epistemicist says we can’t know where the Sharp Boundary is, but that it exists. However, he has to admit that we can:• Guess where the Sharp Boundary is.• Wonder where the Sharp Boundary is.• Fear that we are crossing the Sharp Boundary

(e.g. for getting old).But all these seem silly!

Page 76: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Many-Valued Logics

Another solution is to introduce a new truth-value: True, False, and Undefined.

There’s No Sharp Boundaries, because there’s no point at which adding one hair moves someone from truly bald to falsely bald.

Page 77: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Many-Valued Logics

More hairs →tttttttttttttttttttttttuuuuuuuuuuufffffffffffffffffff

Page 78: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Higher-Order Vagueness

The problem is that now there are sharp boundaries between being truly bald and undefinedly bald, and between being undefinedly bald, and falsely bald.

Intuitively, adding one hair to a truly bald person can’t make them undefinedly bald.

Page 79: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Many-Valued Logics

More hairs →tttttttttttttttttttttttuuuuuuuuuuufffffffffffffffffff

Two sharp boundaries!

Page 80: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Fuzzy Logic

Instead, we might try having infinitely many truth-values: 1 is fully true, 0 is fully false, and any number in between is less than fully true.

More hairs →1 1 1 1 1 1 .99 .98 .98 .97… .12 .11 .1 .1 0 0 0 0 0

Page 81: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Fuzzy Logic

A fuzzy logician has to explain how to calculate the truth-values of complex expressions from the truth values of their parts. Common rules:• The truth-value of “~P” is 1 minus the truth-

value of P• The truth-value of “P & Q” is the lowest of the

truth-values of P and Q.• The truth-value of “P or Q” is the highest of the

truth values of P and Q.

Page 82: Semantic Paradoxes Continued. RECAP The Barber Paradox Once upon a time there was a village, and in this village lived a barber named B. B shaved all

Problems

“P & ~P” should always be fully false: 0.

But if P = 0.5, then “P & ~P” = 0.5