spoudaios and teleology in the poetics

Upload: luciana-gallegos

Post on 02-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    1/19

    merican Philological ssociation

    and Teleology in the PoeticsAuthor(s): George F. HeldSource: Transactions of the American Philological Association (1974-), Vol. 114 (1984), pp. 159-176Published by: The Johns Hopkins University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/284145.

    Accessed: 08/09/2014 23:09

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    American Philological Associationand The Johns Hopkins University Pressare collaborating with JSTOR to

    digitize, preserve and extend access to Transactions of the American Philological Association (1974-).

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhuphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/284145?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/284145?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    2/19

    Transactions

    f

    theAmerican

    hilological

    ssociation

    14

    1984)159-176

    IHOYz?AIOI

    AND

    TELEOLOGY

    IN

    THE

    POETICS

    GEORGE F. HELD

    Universityf Missouri

    "Thoughthe Greeks

    reated

    tragedy,

    . .

    they

    never

    developed

    a

    theory

    f

    thetragicwhich, eachingbeyondthephenomenon fdrama,might ouch

    on

    man's

    spiritual ttitudetowards

    the world

    as

    a whole."'

    Though

    the

    Greeks did

    develop

    theories f

    tragedy,

    hey

    did

    not,

    n

    Lesky's opinion,

    develop any

    whichevinces

    "conception

    f the

    tragic

    n the

    modern,

    more

    philosophical

    ense."2

    mplicit

    n

    these statements s

    Lesky's acceptance

    of

    Kommerell's conclusions

    bout

    Aristotle's

    iew

    of

    tragedy,

    .g.,

    that

    tragedy

    or

    Aristotle

    s

    ust

    tage tragedy

    "die

    angefuhrte

    rag6die")3

    nd

    that Aristotle n the Poetics

    (unlike Horace

    in

    the Ars

    Poetica)

    is not

    concerned to informpoetshow theyare to conceive ("angreifen")what

    they

    create.4Kommerell

    concludes fromthe

    manner

    n

    which

    Aristotle

    defines

    ragedy

    hat

    he

    does not

    think f

    tragedy

    s a

    thing

    n

    itself;

    t

    is

    merely

    a

    basis

    ("Anlage") for the

    production

    f a

    particular

    ffect, .e.,

    catharsis,

    and,

    as

    such, is

    merely a

    formless

    potentiality,which is

    conceivable

    only

    in

    relation

    to

    its effect.5 he

    art of the

    tragedian

    is,

    therefore, or Aristotle

    to use

    Kommerell'sown

    examples)

    like eyesight

    rather

    hanthe art

    of

    building.6 n both

    there s

    a passingfrom

    otentiality

    to

    actuality,but whereas in

    the latter

    this

    process produces

    not

    merely

    building tself, ut concrete ndividualbuildings, n the formerwhat is

    produced is

    merely an

    effect,

    ight itself.

    Aristotle,

    e asserts,

    has no

    general

    aesthetic

    oncept or

    quality n

    mind to

    which he

    would

    relate all

    1

    Albin

    Lesky, Greek

    Tragedy,

    transl.

    H.

    A. Frankfort

    London

    1967)

    4.

    Quotations of

    Greek

    texts

    herein will be

    taken from

    he

    Oxford

    Classical

    Texts unless

    otherwisenoted.

    I

    wishto

    thank

    he TAPA

    referee or

    his

    helpful

    riticisms

    nd

    especiallymy

    dissertation

    directors,D. J.Mastronarde nd M. Griffith,ortheirhelpful criticisms nd theiropen-

    mindedness n

    allowing me in

    my

    dissertation o

    broach

    the

    speculative

    subject

    discussed

    herein.

    2

    Lesky

    (above, note

    1)

    6.

    3

    Max

    Kommerell,

    essing

    und

    Aristoteles

    Frankfort

    957) 58.

    4

    Kommerell

    above,

    note3)

    55.

    5

    See

    Kommerell

    above,

    note 3) 58-60.

    6

    Kommerell

    above, note

    3)

    60.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    3/19

    160

    George

    F.

    Held

    particular

    xamples

    of tragedy.

    His

    approach throughout

    he

    Poetics is

    historical nd descriptive, is

    sole purpose

    Beobachtetes

    u erklaren."8

    Kommerell's nd Lesky'sconclusions bout Aristotle's iewof tragedy

    have gone unchallenged

    n the scholarly

    iterature;

    nd at least some

    of

    themhave sufficiently

    ained

    acceptance to reappear

    n the works f other

    scholars

    as if

    established

    fact. Golden,

    for

    example, posits

    without

    argument hat

    Aristotle id

    not distinguish

    etween tragedy

    nd comedy

    "on

    the

    basisof any essential

    ualityof the action

    tself."9

    hisview is

    also

    held

    by Schuetrumpf.10

    esky's

    opinions re

    also implicitly

    ndorsed

    by

    Else,

    who

    holds

    that

    "Aristotle

    hought he pathos

    the

    basic, ndispensable

    'part'

    of the tragic plot,""1

    nd

    Jones,who concludes

    that"what Aristotle

    finds ssentiallyragic" s changeof fortune.'2 o theory f tragedywhich

    makes

    pathos

    or change

    of fortune he

    onlyessential

    lement

    n

    tragedy

    can be said

    to be "philosophical"

    r to "touch on

    man's spiritual

    ttitude

    towardsthe world

    as a whole."

    Yet there s

    considerable

    vidence

    that

    Kommerell

    nd Lesky

    have overstated

    heir ase-and

    notmerely ecause

    the Poetics

    is

    too

    informal

    nd provisional

    document

    for the strict-

    constructionisteading

    f

    t

    n which hey

    ndulge.

    My

    subsequentpresentation

    f this

    vidence

    falls

    ntotwo

    main

    parts.

    In the firstdiscussAristotle's efinitionfcomedy.Kommerell nd Lesky

    base their onclusions

    bout

    Aristotle'smodes

    of thought

    n

    regard

    to art

    solely upon

    the

    manner of his

    definition

    f

    tragedy. They

    completely

    ignore

    his definition

    f

    comedy

    n

    which

    Aristotle

    emonstrates

    he

    very

    modes of thought

    f which

    they

    ssert

    him

    to

    be

    incapable.

    In

    the

    second

    part

    I

    argue

    that

    o--rov8aZos9,

    avAXos

    nd

    yEXoios

    are

    for

    Aristotle

    teleological

    erms

    nd that

    hisusage

    of them

    n

    the

    definitions

    f

    tragedy

    and comedy

    s evidence

    thathe

    means todistinguish

    etween

    ragedy

    nd

    comedy

    longteleological

    ines.

    Tragedy

    s

    an imitation f an action

    which

    is significantlyelldirected owardman'sproper nd, happiness; omedy

    is

    an imitationof

    an

    action

    of the

    opposite

    sort.

    This is

    not

    the

    only

    distinction

    hich

    Aristotle ould

    draw between

    he

    actions f

    tragedy

    nd

    comedy-and

    for

    hatreason s

    not

    nearly

    s

    paradoxical

    s it

    may

    seem.

    t

    is,

    moreover,

    distinction

    hich

    s

    obviously philosophical"

    n

    nature,

    nd

    just

    s obviously

    an apply

    to actions

    ff

    s well

    as

    on the

    tage.

    7

    Cf. Kommerell

    above,

    note 3)

    55:

    "Ebenso

    ist eine

    Begrundung

    der

    Kunst

    aus

    der

    Kunstheraus, lso aus einen asthetischWertbegriff,em Aristoteles anz fremd" nd 133:

    "ist der

    Mythos

    ein

    solcher

    uberlieferter

    usammenhang

    des

    Geschehens

    nicht

    in einer

    ganz bestimmten

    ualitat."

    8

    Kommerell

    above,

    note

    3) 54.

    9

    L.

    Golden,

    "Is Tragedy

    the Imitation

    f a

    Serious

    Action'?,"

    GRBS

    6 (1965)

    284.

    10

    See

    Eckart

    Schuetrumpf,

    ie Bedeutung

    des

    Wortes

    'Oovs

    n der

    Poetik

    des

    Aris-

    toteles,

    Zetemata

    49

    (Munich

    1970) 63-64 and

    78.

    11

    Gerald

    F. Else,

    Aristotle's

    Poetics:

    the

    Argument Cambridge,

    Mass.

    1957)

    229.

    12

    John

    Jones,

    On

    Aristotle

    nd

    Greek Tragedy

    New

    York

    1968)

    16.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    4/19

    Y7Tov8aLos9

    nd

    Teleology

    n

    the Poetics

    161

    * * *

    Lesky does not

    tell

    us

    whether he

    Greeks,

    who

    created

    comedy

    as

    well as tragedy, ver developed a theory f the comic "which, reaching

    beyond

    the

    phenomenon

    of

    drama, might

    touch on man's

    spiritual

    tti-

    tude towardsthe world

    as

    a

    whole,"

    but

    this,

    t can

    be

    shown

    from

    the

    manner

    of

    Aristotle's

    efinition

    f

    comedy,

    he would be

    wrong

    to

    deny.

    That

    definition

    s

    "less

    complete

    than the definition

    f

    tragedy

    at

    the

    beginning

    of

    the next

    chapter,

    but is

    parallel

    as far as it

    goes."'13

    he

    definition

    f

    comedy

    is

    indeed

    parallel

    to

    the

    definition

    f

    tragedy

    but

    less

    complete

    than it in two

    respects:

    1)

    the elements

    which

    belong

    to

    both tragedyand comedy primarily s art forms, .e., completeness,

    length, ype

    of

    language,

    manner of

    presentation:

    hough

    mentioned

    n

    the definition f

    tragedy, hey

    are omitted

    from

    the

    definition

    f

    com-

    edy;

    apart

    from the

    word

    ,utpn,qos,

    herefore,

    here is

    nothing

    n the

    definition

    f

    comedy

    which

    ties it to "the

    phenomenon

    of

    drama";

    and

    (2) the effect n a

    spectator.Aristotle

    oes not define

    omedy n terms f

    its

    effecthere,

    and

    there s

    no

    evidence that he did

    so in the

    supposed

    lost

    second book of the

    Poetics: "If

    he

    actually defined

    comedy

    in

    terms

    of its

    effect,

    t is

    strange

    hatno

    intelligible,

    learly-marked

    estige f his

    definition as come down to us."'14 ut Aristotle's efinitionfcomedy is

    also

    more

    complete

    than his

    definition

    f

    tragedy

    n

    one very

    mportant

    respect:

    t

    contains n

    explicit

    definition

    f

    a universal

    bstract oncept,

    TO

    yEAoLov, which is

    "das spezifisch

    Komische,"'15

    he essential quality

    which

    belongs to all

    comedy,

    stage and otherwise.'6

    hat

    r0

    yEXoZoV

    is

    indeed a universal

    oncept, nd

    not imited

    n reference o

    "the phenom-

    enon

    of drama,"

    would

    seem

    likely from

    he fact,which no

    one denies,

    that

    Aristotle ntends

    his

    definition f To

    yEXOLov as

    a rebuttal

    o Plato's

    conclusions about its nature in Philebus

    48A-5OB.17

    Plato had argued

    13

    G. M.

    A.

    Grube, Aristotle:On

    Poetry

    nd

    Style

    New

    York

    1958) 10, note

    1.

    14

    Lane Cooper,

    An

    Aristotelianheory

    f

    ComedyNew

    York

    1969) 64.

    15

    Johannes

    Vahlen,

    Beitrage

    zu

    Aristoteles'

    Poetik,

    Neudruck bes.

    v. H.

    Schone

    (Leipzig-Berlin

    1914)

    16.

    16

    Elder

    Olson, The

    Theory of

    Comedy

    (Bloomington,

    ndiana

    1975) 51,

    asserts

    that

    Aristotle's

    tatement bout

    TO

    yEAo?ov,

    hough t

    "has

    nvariably een

    treated

    s a

    definition,"

    cannot

    be

    one

    because

    "Aristotle

    would

    never

    have

    permitted definition

    with a

    negative

    differentia,

    or a

    negative

    term is

    always

    ambiguous

    and

    hence can

    state the nature of

    nothing."Negativedifferentia otwithstanding,viewAristotle'statement s a definition.

    The

    reason

    for

    he

    negative

    differentias that

    Aristotle

    wishes

    pointedly

    o deny what

    Plato

    asserts:

    n intrinsic

    onnection

    etween

    omedy

    and

    evil

    which

    causesharm.

    17

    Cf. Edward Poste's

    commenton

    Phlb.

    49c2

    in The

    Philebus

    of

    Plato

    (Oxford

    1960)

    ad

    loc.:

    'Aristotle's

    efinition f the

    Ridiculous

    seems

    to have

    been

    suggested

    by this

    passage."

    Plato in

    this

    passage

    is

    primarily

    oncernedto

    demonstrate hat

    ome

    forms f

    pleasure are

    mixed with

    pain,

    and

    discusses

    the

    nature

    of

    comedy

    only

    incidentally to

    this

    purpose-because the

    pleasure

    derived

    from

    t,

    he

    believes, s of

    this

    ype.

    His

    treatment

    f

    the

    subject,

    accordingly, s

    cursory

    nd

    tendentious, is

    reasoning

    nd

    psychology,n my

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    5/19

    162 George F. Held

    that the subject matter f

    comedy (ra

    yEXoLa)

    is self-ignorancea'yvota)

    in one's friends

    LktAo)

    who are weak and without power to do one

    harm, self-ignorancewith regard to the extent of their wealth, beauty

    and virtue,

    speciallywisdom.'8And since ignorance s a form f evil, as

    Plato explicitlypoints out

    in

    the dialogue (49D9: Ov'Kov3v

    r7v

    ayvotav

    EL7TO,UEV

    OTLt

    KaKoV

    7raLv;)

    it is a

    formof evil

    (KaKov)

    which he asserts s

    the

    subject

    matter

    of

    comedy and

    the

    proper object of comic laughter.

    That Plato's

    remarks n

    the Philebus are

    directedat comedy as a univer-

    sal phenomenon

    nd not merely t stage comedy is obvious frommuch

    else in his

    discussion,

    ut

    especially fromthe followingwords 502-3):

    Ev

    TpaywioLaLS

  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    6/19

    -7rov8aLOs

    nd

    Teleology

    n

    the

    Poetics

    163

    imitation

    s

    not

    ust

    forms

    f

    self-ignorance

    r

    people

    afflicted

    ith

    them

    (cavXoTE'pWV

    is

    probably

    masculine),

    but almost

    all

    forms

    of evil

    and

    thoseafflictedwiththem.The onlykind of evil or evil personwhichhe

    would

    exclude is the most

    extreme

    kind-complete vice

    or

    wholly

    vicious persons.

    The reason

    he gives for their xclusion

    makes

    clear how

    he

    would

    define the

    comic more

    narrowly

    han Plato.

    To

    yEAoZov,

    e

    says,

    consists f that which

    is

    faulty

    or

    ugly

    but does not

    cause

    pain

    or

    harm. For

    Aristotle,

    hen,

    vil which causes

    pain

    or

    harm to

    anyone

    not

    just

    potentially

    o

    oneself, s in Plato's

    theory)

    s not

    comic.

    But,

    plainly,

    it

    is not

    onlywholly vicious

    persons nd extreme

    vice which

    cause

    pain

    or harm.

    Arguably ll,

    and

    certainly

    most,

    forms f

    vice,

    faults nd

    ugli-

    ness, physicalor ethical, cause at least some pain or harm,physicalor

    ethical, either to those who

    have

    them

    or to others.

    And

    just

    as

    plainly,

    the

    misfortunes,

    vils,

    and

    vices

    of

    stage

    comedy

    are

    therein

    epresented

    as

    causing

    a

    good deal of

    pain

    or

    harm

    to the

    comic

    characters.

    Aristotle's

    efinition f

    ro

    yEOoLov, herefore,

    f

    taken

    as

    an

    attempt

    "Beobachtetes u

    erklaren," ither

    n

    the sense of

    defining

    he particular

    essence of

    stage

    comedy

    or

    its

    appropriate

    subject

    matter, must

    be

    deemed a

    sorry

    failure,20

    nd

    contradicts he

    implicationsof

    what

    he

    himselfhas said in 49A31-32. To thisit may be objected that the evil

    actions

    represented

    n

    stage

    comedy only

    seem

    to

    but do not

    reallycause

    pain

    or

    harm.

    This,

    however,

    s

    true also of

    actions on

    the

    tragic stage.

    Admittedly, much

    greater degree

    of

    verisimilitude

    ertainsgenerally

    to the

    actions,

    nd

    so

    also

    to

    the

    pain and

    suffering,

    f

    stage

    tragedy

    han

    of

    stage

    comedy.

    But

    althoughthe

    difference n

    verisimilitude

    etween

    the two

    genres

    is

    relative, not

    absolute, Aristotle's

    xclusion from the

    comic of that

    which

    causes

    pain

    or

    harm is

    stated

    n

    absolute,not

    rela-

    tive

    terms.

    And

    if he

    had

    the

    suggested dea in

    mind,

    he

    ought to have

    stated texplicitly, ot eft tforus to infer.

    His definition f

    ro

    yEXoiozV,

    owever, makes

    quite

    good sense if

    taken

    as

    directed

    at

    the

    comic

    in

    a

    universal,

    hough

    omewhat

    refined,

    sense.

    "Deaths,

    beatings,etc."

    are in

    real life

    as well as on

    the

    comic

    stage sometimes

    bjects

    of

    laughter, ut the

    theorist s

    under no

    obliga-

    tion to

    make the

    comic coextensive

    with

    the

    laughable.

    Aristotle,s also

    Plato,

    did

    not

    think t

    was. His

    definition

    s, as it

    were, a

    "persuasive

    20

    Some mightexplain Aristotle's xclusion of pain and harmfromcomedy by arguing

    that

    he has in

    mind

    not

    rowdyOld

    Comedy,

    but

    the

    much more

    innocuous

    Middle

    and

    New.

    But

    this is

    a

    lame

    argument:

    Middle

    and New

    Comedy

    undoubtedly

    ncluded

    incidents

    involving

    pain

    and/or

    harm,

    as, for

    example,

    Knemon's

    fall

    into a

    well in

    Menander's

    Dyscolus.

    And,

    as

    Cooper

    (above, note

    14) 18-41

    has

    shown,

    there

    s

    no rea-

    son to

    believe,

    as

    some

    have, that

    Aristotle

    iscounted he

    importance

    f

    Aristophanes, he

    leading

    representative

    f

    Old

    Comedy. It

    is,

    therefore,

    most

    unlikely

    that he

    would

    not

    have

    expected his

    theory

    f

    comedy

    to

    apply

    to

    Aristophanes'

    lays

    as

    well

    as those

    of his

    successors.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    7/19

    164

    George

    F. Held

    definition":2'

    t includes

    withinthe comic only

    what we ought

    to laugh

    at, not all

    at which we sometimes

    do. Olson on

    this point, as on many

    others, as gotten o the bottom f Aristotle'smeaning.22 is distinctions

    between comic, malevolent, nd scornful

    aughter

    re implicit n Aris-

    totle'sdefinition

    f comedy. The things

    t which

    the latter wo are typi-

    cally

    directedhe excludes from the

    comic. His

    definition f the comic

    encompasseswhat

    takes place on

    the comic stage, for there

    nothing

    really painfulor harmful

    ccurs,but

    it is not directed,first nd

    foremost,

    at the

    "phenomenon

    f

    drama."

    To yEAoi2ov is frequently

    ranslated nto English

    as "the ludicrous,"

    but

    it

    is

    much more

    appropriately

    endered

    "the comic." "The laugh-

    able" would of coursebe the most iteraltranslation, ut is less prefera-

    ble

    for several reasons: ro

    y6\oZov,

    as

    I have

    shown,

    s

    not

    in

    fact, as

    Aristotle

    efines

    t,

    coextensivewith

    the

    laughable; "laughable"

    is not as

    commonly

    used

    in

    ordinaryEnglish

    as

    was

    yEXoZosg

    n

    Greek;

    and "the

    laughable"

    s

    simply

    not the

    standard riticalterm

    n

    English

    for

    expres-

    sing

    the essence

    of

    comedy.

    Aristotle's hoice

    of

    yEXoios

    to

    refer

    o

    the

    essence

    of comedy

    is

    itselfnot

    without

    ignificance

    hough

    in this, of

    course,

    he was strongly nfluenced

    by

    Plato's

    use of

    the

    word

    in

    the

    Philebus. Anotheradjective,

    KWMLKO ,23

    was also available to him and

    might

    have

    performed

    this same

    function,

    but it

    normally

    meant

    "comic"

    only

    n a narrow

    ense, .e.,

    "of

    or

    relating

    o

    stage

    comedy."

    As

    Else

    remarks, 'Comic'

    would be

    a

    good

    term but seems to

    have been

    still

    o

    closely

    associated

    with theatrical

    roduction

    n

    Aristotle's

    ay

    .

    that

    it

    lacked the

    necessary cope

    to

    designate

    the

    object

    of

    comedy

    as

    such."24LEXoLOS, however,

    n

    common

    usage

    already possessed

    he

    neces-

    sary scope,

    which

    K&)MLKO

    might

    have obtained

    solely

    with

    the

    aid of a

    definition.

    ristotle's

    reference

    or

    yAoZoso

    over

    KWMLK9os

    to refer o

    the

    essenceof comedy is, therefore,n itself o some extent ndicativeof his

    recognition

    hat comedy

    as a whole

    is more universal

    han

    stage comedy

    and

    of

    his intention

    o relate his definition

    f

    stage

    comedy

    to

    thisbroad-

    er,

    more universal

    henomenon.

    The

    scope

    of the

    Greek

    adjective

    TpayLKoS'

    was

    significantlyreater

    than

    that

    of

    KWIALKOS.

    It

    frequently

    meant "of

    or

    relating

    o

    stage trag-

    edy,"

    but

    could

    also mean "solemn"

    or

    "exalted,"

    and

    even

    on occasion

    might

    be used

    in a sense dentical

    withthatof

    the

    English

    "tragic";

    Aris-

    totle n factseemsso to use it once in the Poetics,whenhe singlesout

    21

    "Persuasive

    definition"s

    a term

    which was coined

    by

    C. L. Stevenson,

    Persuasive

    Definitions,"

    Mind (1938)

    331f.

    Its meaning

    hould be obvious

    frommy own usage

    of it.

    22

    Olson (above,

    note

    19) 161.

    23

    KwI,UwpKOs,

    f course,

    was also available

    to Aristotle, s

    also

    rpay biuo

    in

    place

    of

    7pay

    KoLS', but since

    these

    other words are

    mere cognates

    of

    KxwpKoS

    and

    rpaytov

    and

    Aristotle ever

    uses either

    one of them,

    my discussion

    will ignore

    them.

    24

    Else (above,

    note 11) 186.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    8/19

    17rovbadov

    nd

    Teleology n

    the Poetics

    165

    Euripides as "most

    tragic"

    TpayLKcwTaTos,:

    53A29)

    of the

    tragedians.

    n

    any

    case, therecan be

    no

    doubt

    that,

    f

    Aristotle ad

    attempted

    o

    define

    the tragic,he would have employedno adjectiveotherthan

    TpayLKos

    to

    form

    the articular

    noun

    to serve

    as his

    definiendum.

    This

    obviously

    he

    has

    failed

    to do. He

    has,

    however,

    done,

    as it

    were,

    the

    next

    best

    thing:

    to

    include in his definition f

    tragedy

    he

    adjective

    o7rovbdLos,

    hich

    in

    both

    Aristotle

    nd other

    writers

    s

    frequently

    n

    antonym

    to

    the

    key

    word,

    yEXotos-,hich

    he

    had

    just

    used

    to denote the essence of

    comedy.

    17rovbdatos

    oes not denote

    the

    essential

    quality

    of

    tragedy, .e., the

    tragic, he whole essence

    of

    tragedy,

    ut it does

    denote an

    essential

    ual-

    ityof

    tragedy, .e., a

    part

    of its

    essence.

    7rovbados-

    s not

    identical in

    functionwithyEXoLoswhichdenotes the whole essence of comedy,not

    just a

    part,

    but its

    inclusion

    n

    the

    definition f

    tragedy

    s

    highly

    ignifi-

    cant. In

    view of Aristotle's

    sage of its

    antonym

    o define the

    essence

    of

    comedy,

    it indicates an

    attemptby

    him

    to

    distinguish

    etween

    tragedy

    and

    comedy

    in

    terms f

    contrasting,

    ssential

    ualities. His

    assertion hat

    the

    7rpats

    itself f

    tragedy

    ught to be

    rovbata,

    moreover,

    would seem

    to

    indicate a desire to

    distinguish etween

    tragedy

    nd

    comedy

    in

    terms

    of

    essential qualities

    belonging

    to the

    actions

    themselves of

    each. At

    least it does ifwe understandhisdefinition f comedyto implythat the

    7rpaets-

    f

    comedy

    ought

    to

    be

    yEA\oa.

    Cooper

    does so

    understand

    t,25

    and

    it seems

    only

    natural to

    do so.

    In view of

    these

    considerations,

    Aristotle's

    ailure o

    define he

    tragic

    does not

    seem so

    significant.

    t

    may

    be

    just an

    oversight-and

    perhaps

    due

    partly

    to

    the

    knowledge

    that a

    definition f TO

    TpayLKov

    might,

    without

    too much

    ingenuity,be

    ex-

    tracted

    fromhis definition

    f

    TpayobLa:

    EO'TV

    O?Vv

    rpayq8thla

    Ml1tls

    7Tpa'Ewss

    a71ovbaLas-

    KaL

    TreELas-

    f/yeOos-

    VX'frs,

    271VoOv y

    XWpEs

    KaOTO TcUV elIJWV V TOLS'/OptSt,

    bpwvTrwv

    KaL

    01

    a'JtayyeXtas-,

    bt'

    E'Aeov

    KaL

    fr0/3ov

    repaLvovoa

    T7/V

    T7O

    TOLOVTo)WV

    7raOrq1.a'Tv

    KaOapcTLv.

    49B24-28)

    If

    we

    eliminate from

    his

    definition

    f

    tragedy those

    elements

    which

    belong to

    tragedy

    exclusivelyor

    primarily

    s an

    art form,

    we

    are left

    with

    two

    elementswhich

    we may

    be

    sure

    Aristotle

    would have

    included

    in

    a

    definitionof

    TO

    TpayLKov:

    (1)

    the

    ethical-physical26

    lement,

    To

    r7rovdtZov;and

    (2) pathos.27

    The

    former

    infer

    naturally

    from the

    words

    7rpacfEws-

    ovba'as; the

    latter

    from he

    words

    EAXov Kat

    xo,0ov.

    So

    conceived, his definition f the tragicwould be explicitly arallel to his

    definition

    f the

    comic, which

    consistsof

    two

    similar

    elements:

    1) an

    25

    See

    Cooper

    (above,

    note 14)

    179.

    26

    17rovbaiov,

    ike

    #aiXov

    and

    yeXoios, an

    have

    a

    physical as

    well as an

    ethical

    sense.

    Cf.

    EN

    1098A9.

    27

    Cf.

    Else's

    remark

    bout the

    importanceof

    pathos

    in

    Aristotle's

    onception of

    tragedy

    (see

    above,

    page 160).

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    9/19

    166 George F. Held

    ethical-physical lement,denoted by the words

    'Aa&pIIria

    TL

    KaL

    aLoG-XO;

    and (2) a negative element, the absence of pathos, as indicated by the

    words

    avw'vvov Ka'L

    ov

    40ap-LKdOV.

    Whereas the comic forAristotle s

    that

    which

    is

    ugly or defective but does not cause pain or

    harm, the

    tragic, surmise,he would defineas that which s

    a-7rov8ados9

    ut causes

    or, as may be inferred romPo.

    53B21

    and

    54A4-9,

    at least threatens o

    cause, pain or harm.

    The reader

    may

    surmise

    omewhatdifferently,ut,

    whetheror not

    he accepts this admittedly uite hypotheticalAristotelian efinition f

    the tragic, t should be clear fromthe preceding that a strong ase can

    be made

    against

    Kommerell's nd

    Lesky's conclusions oncerningAris-

    totle'smode of thought bout tragedy nd art in the Poetics. It should

    now be evident that Aristotle ould conceive of art as possessing defin-

    able essence and

    as

    existing

    n

    its

    own

    right part from

    ts

    effect, hat he

    did

    conceive

    of

    comedy

    in

    this

    way

    and

    very likely

    could also

    have

    thought

    f

    tragedy

    n

    the same manner

    and, lastly,

    hat

    he

    did distin-

    guish

    between

    tragedy

    nd

    comedy

    "on

    the

    basis

    of

    [an]

    essential

    uality

    of action itself." n what follows, will

    no

    longer

    be

    concerned to argue

    these

    points,

    but rathernext to

    establish

    hat

    o7rova&Los9

    and

    yEXoios

    in

    thePoeticsare teleological erms.

    * * *

    7wovbaLosg

    s

    employed

    on

    three ccasions

    n

    the Poetics

    n

    conjunction

    with he word

    4l,u71s0

    or ts

    cognate

    yL1f'o1LaL.

    No

    one

    today

    doubts

    hat

    on

    two of these occasions

    48A2

    and

    49B10),

    where

    t is

    applied

    to

    the men

    imitated n tragedy,

    --rov8aLos9

    enotes an ethical

    udgment

    bout

    them,

    even if some insist hat

    more

    than

    ust

    an ethical

    udgment

    s

    involved.28

    But on thethird ccasion, n thedefinitionftragedy

    49B24),

    where tis

    applied to

    the action

    of

    tragedy tself,

    cholars

    have tended

    to view it

    rather s an aesthetic

    erm,meaning

    "serious."

    They

    have

    done so

    despite

    theirrecognition

    hat

    the term

    hould

    be

    used

    univocally hroughout

    he

    work.29 ardie

    seems

    to

    have

    been the first

    o

    argue

    that t

    s so

    used,30

    nd

    his ideas have been

    revived

    by

    Grube

    and

    Golden.

    All three scholars

    support heir positionby citing49B38-50A2,

    where Aristotle

    nly

    a few

    sentences

    fter he definition

    f

    tragedy

    sserts hat

    ctions

    re of a

    certain

    sort n account

    of

    the

    thought

    nd

    character

    f those

    who

    perform

    hem:

    83Lay

    ap

    TOV'TWV KatL

    rTsa

    Tpace4st

    Evai 4aEv 7TOLas' TLvas.31

    Grube also cites

    28

    A. Gudeman, Aristoteles

    HEPI

    HIOHTIKHX (Berlin-Leipzig

    1934) 270,

    held that

    -rov-

    baiosv

    n the Poetics

    s

    always

    used

    in an aesthetic ense. t means "tauglich

    ur

    die

    Tragodie."

    29

    Cf. S.

    H.

    Butcher,

    Aristotle'sTheory of Poetry

    and

    Fine

    Art

    (New

    York

    1951) 234-

    35,

    and Vahlen (above,

    note 15)

    267-68.

    30

    R.

    P.

    Hardie,

    "The Poetics of Aristotle,"

    Mind

    4

    (1895) 357.

    31

    Cf. Hardie (above,

    note 30)

    358,

    Grube (above,

    note 13)

    xxi,and Golden (above,

    note

    9)

    284-85.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    10/19

  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    11/19

    168 George

    F.

    Held

    possess n and of themselves he same qualities

    as belong to that charac-

    ter? Golden simply gnores

    he passages cited by Grube where Aristotle

    does seem to distinguish etween genreson thebasis of essential ualities

    of the actions themselves.

    He also ignores the fact that, though

    "a

    person'scharacter s

    stamped on his deeds," his deeds are also stamped

    on his character: There

    can be no doubt . . that in Aristotle's thical

    theory ction and action

    alone shapes character."35he radical disjunc-

    tion between action and character mplicit in

    Golden's view of their

    relationship

    n

    the Poetics

    is foreign o Aristotle's

    hought: he emphasis

    in Aristotles on the interrelationshipetween

    the two. Jones, herefore,

    goes much too

    far

    in

    asserting hat

    "it

    needs to be said

    that

    the plot-

    character dichotomy s radically false to Aristotle's nderstanding f

    Tragedy, hatcharacter,

    ike colour,mustbe denied

    even the mostprim-

    itive autonomy";36ut

    the autonomywhich Aristotle rants o action and

    character n the

    Ethics is not so great as to permit mere metaphorical

    relationship etweenthem n the Poetics.

    Let us consider

    more closely the passage

    which, f any, explains the

    presenceof

    a7rovat'a9S

    in the definition f tragedy:

    E7rEL

    7rpa$EwS'

    ecTTL

    PLI/.L?70S,

    7rpaTTETaL 8E

    V7TO

    TLVWV

    7rpaTTovTwv,

    ovs

    avayK7/

    rTOLOVs

    rtvas

    ELvat

    KaTa

    Te

    TO ?70oS'

    KaL

    r77v

    Ltavotav

    bLa

    \~ ~~~~aeL

    '

    a' qe7sova,s, -ra

    ,

    v.e a..t

    yap

    TovTrV KaL

    ras,

    7rp4ELs

    ELVaL4fEv 7roLasTLvas,

    V

    4V

    ZvZ'

    bVO

    TrV

    7rpafEwv

    e1vaL, oLavotav

    Kat

    t'7os,]

    KaL

    Kara

    ravTasv

    Ka

    TvyxavovO-L

    Kaca

    7rorvyxavovctL

    7TavTes))....

    (49B36-50A2)

    Aristotle ddresses

    himself

    pecifically

    o

    the

    question

    of

    why

    actions

    are

    of a

    certain

    quality,

    nd

    asserts hat

    they

    are so

    because

    of

    the

    6oso

    nd

    bIaivota which

    cause them. From the

    proximity

    f this

    passage

    to

    the

    definition

    f

    tragedy,

    and

    the

    repetition

    n it of the

    words

    pln/SO-ts

    ,rpace4sc romthat definition

    s well as the obvious

    purport

    f

    the

    pas-

    sage

    as

    a

    whole,

    would conclude

    not

    only

    that herein

    ies

    the

    explana-

    tion for rovba'aS

    in

    the

    definition f

    tragedy,

    ut that

    this

    passage

    was

    specifically

    ntendedby

    Aristotle

    o

    provide

    n

    explanation

    or

    t.

    As Else

    says

    n

    commenting

    n this

    passage:37

    In

    short,

    Aristotle

    means

    by

    7rpaTEw

    he

    7rpaEwv

    7rovbalav

    Kat

    reXEL'as,

    fthe

    efinition:

    e s

    thinking,

    ot f ll

    action',

    ut

    pecifi-

    cally

    f

    he

    ragic

    ctionwithts

    ompleteness

    nd ts eriousness.

    ...

    The reference

    o thedrama s

    also

    mplicit

    n

    elva'

    .ba,.lEv

    which-certainlyot y ccident-reappearselow

    A6).

    Else, however, hough

    he has much to

    say

    about

    the

    passage

    as a

    whole,

    does not

    specifically

    onclude,

    as

    I think

    one

    should,

    that

    this

    passage

    35

    Else (above,

    note 11) 71.

    Cf. EN

    1105A26-B12.

    36

    Jones above,

    note

    12) 31.

    37

    Else

    (above,

    note 11) 241.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    12/19

    ?Irovbatos,

    and Teleology

    n the Poetics

    169

    affords n

    explanation

    for the

    presence

    of

    a-rovbalas-

    n the definition

    f

    tragedy.

    The genuineness f the sentence

    rEbVKV

    . . .

    'Oos has been widely

    impugned.

    Vahlen

    and

    Gomperz believe

    it to

    be

    out

    of

    place

    because Kat

    iaTa

    TavTav

    ought

    to follow

    immediately

    after

    rota'S

    Ttvas38

    Else

    agrees,

    concludes

    that t is an

    interpolation,39

    nd

    asserts,

    moreover,

    hat

    "it

    is

    a crude

    and

    misleadingparaphrase"

    of

    the

    preceding

    entence.40n

    that

    entence

    blta

    s

    constructed

    with the

    genitive,

    not the

    accusative,

    nd

    denotes

    mere

    instrumentality,

    ot

    causality.

    The

    subsequent sentence,

    therefore,

    ntroduces somewhat

    different

    dea,

    to which

    Else

    objects

    as

    follows:

    The

    doctrine s

    in

    fact

    not

    really

    Aristotelian. he

    two causes

    of

    action, accordingto Aristotle E.N.

    6.2.1139A31;

    De An. 3.10.433A10-

    30),

    are

    mind or reason

    (Xo\yos,LacoLa,

    or

    vovs;

    but the

    vov3s

    an be

    mere magination,

    vrTaTLa) and desire

    "p4tvs).

    It

    is true

    of course that

    character

    ends

    by shaping

    one's

    desires."'4'Schuetrumpf

    grees

    that

    7rEfqVKEV...

    'OoS may

    be

    out

    of

    place

    for

    the reason

    given

    by

    Vahlen

    and

    Gomperz,

    but

    argues against Else

    that there s no

    conflict

    etween

    this

    sentence and

    the

    preceding

    one

    and that

    its

    meaning s sufficiently

    Aristotelian. e

    points

    out

    that vov3s,

    hich

    Else holds to be one of the

    causes of action, tselfnecessarily nvolvesan

    'OLK'

    '`tvS

    and in the pas-

    sage

    from

    he

    Ethics cited

    by Else (1139A31) is

    in

    factreplaced by 'OLK'

    i'es

    in the

    very

    next

    sentence,

    so that even this

    passage shows

    the

    involvement

    f

    'Oo0S

    n

    causing action. But he also points

    out that it is

    clear from other

    passages

    in

    the

    Ethics that it is 7rpoaLpEo-Ls

    hich for

    Aristotle

    s

    ultimately

    the

    cause of action, and holds

    that

    Z7osv

    nd

    bLa'VoLa

    are the

    constituent

    lements

    of

    7rpoaL'pEo-Ls-nd in

    the passage

    from the Poetics

    function ogethervirtually s does

    7rpoaLpEo-Ls

    n the

    Ethics:42

    Haufig,

    wenn

    auch mit

    wechselnden

    Begriffen, ringt

    uch

    sonst

    Aristotelesum

    Ausdruck, ass Charakter nd Denken das

    Handeln

    bestimmen.43

    it

    diesen

    beiden Begriffen mschreibt r, wie oben

    gezeigt wurde, die

    beiden Bestandteile der

    7rpoaLpeo-Lvs

    ie

    7rpoalpfELT

    is

    nach

    EN44

    die

    Bewegungsursache

    er

    Handlungen.

    38

    See Vahlen

    (above, note

    15) 20-21 and

    Theodor

    Gomperz,Zu

    Aristoteles'Poetik, Ein

    Beitrag

    zur

    Kritik

    und

    Erklarung

    der Kapitel I-VI

    (Vienna

    1888) 29-31.

    39

    D.

    W.

    Lucas,

    Aristotle:Poetics

    (Oxford 1968) ad

    loc., also

    believes

    the

    passage to be

    an interpolation.

    40

    Else

    (above, note

    11) 240.

    41

    Else

    (above, note

    11) 240,

    note 70.

    42

    Schuetrumpf

    above, note

    10) 84-85.

    43

    Cf.

    EN

    1144A6:

    E7rL

    O

    EpyoV

    a7TOTEAELTaL

    KaTa

    T77V

    pOVP7LV

    Kal T1PV

    7)OLK47V

    pET47V

    and Pol.

    1323B32f.The

    passages cited in this

    note

    and the next

    are taken

    directlyfrom

    Schuetrumpf's

    wn

    notes.

    See

    Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note

    10) 84,

    notes6 and 7.

    44

    Cf.

    EN

    1138A31:

    rpa4Ews

    kv

    o'v

    apXn'

    7rpoalpEfOL

    b'0Ev X7

    KLV7)oLT

    &aAA'

    Ov'

    Oi

    EVEKa).f.

    also

    EN

    1139A33

    andMetaph.

    1065A32.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    13/19

    170

    George

    F. Held

    Schon as

    passt urPoetik, o a

    dOog

    nd

    LtavoLa

    gemeinsamls die

    UrsachenawTta)

    derHandlungen

    ezeichnet

    ind....

    So istdiese

    Vorstellung

    anz mEinklang it

    erEthik es

    Aristoteles.

    I agree with

    Schuetrumpf's

    onclusions bout

    this

    passage as far as

    they go,

    but believe

    that they do not

    go far

    enough, for he fails to

    see

    that this passage explains

    the reason

    for

    ff7rovbaLaS

    in

    the definition f

    tragedy.

    n fact,although

    he writes

    chapterentitled

    Die Bedeutung

    von

    a6osL,

    L

    rov3aZoS,

    4avAos

    in

    der

    Poetik,"45 e says

    nothingt all

    about

    ff7rovbaLaS

    in

    the

    definition f tragedy,

    for which

    he has been

    justly

    criticizedby Rees.46

    infer from

    thispassage that

    the

    -rpa^6s9

    f

    tragedy

    s

    ff7rovbaLa

    ot merely because

    it is

    performedby characters

    who are

    ff7rovbaLoL

    ith respect o their

    Oq

    and bLaVoLaut because it is

    a product

    of and

    is

    caused by the o-7rovbaia

    rO'6 and

    bLaVoLa of these

    characters.47 he

    reader may perhaps

    question

    whether t is possible

    to

    attribute

    o the

    O'q

    nd bLaVoLa

    of

    the tragic

    characters he sort

    of unity

    which

    the preceding statement

    eems

    to imply they

    possess.

    Clearly,

    their

    (6q

    and bLacVoLa are not of

    a

    piece, but

    ultimately

    here should be

    no

    more

    difficulty

    n

    attributing

    n

    over-allunity

    o the?'6i7and bLa'oLa

    of

    these characters

    han to their ctions.

    f

    Aristotle's

    se of the

    singular

    -rpa^

    e

    in the definition f tragedy o refer o the various actionswhich

    comprise

    a

    tragicplot

    is

    conceptually

    ntelligible,

    hen this

    explanation

    of

    how this

    -rpaLs

    comes

    to

    be o-rovia

    a

    is also

    conceptually

    ntelligible.

    This explanation

    f

    o-rovbaasa

    does

    not

    of

    course

    entail thatthe

    action of

    tragedy

    must

    be good

    in the sense

    of

    actually producing

    a

    good

    result-although

    that is

    what

    happens

    in

    some tragedies,

    e.g.,

    the

    Oresteia,

    and is

    generally

    he

    rule

    in

    epic

    which

    s also

    an

    imitation

    f

    a

    7rp4LsL

    -7rovbaLa.

    1pa6eEws

    7rovbaL'aS

    in

    the definition f

    tragedy

    ntails

    no

    more,

    nd no

    less,

    than

    that

    "the

    action

    of the

    play

    as

    a whole

    should

    be a 'good' one (i.e., it should portray ffortso bringabout a 'good'

    result)."48 r,

    to

    put

    it

    another

    way,

    it entails that

    at least some

    of the

    actions

    of

    which the

    plot

    consists hould

    be

    o-7rov8aLaL

    in

    the

    sense

    of

    being

    a

    product

    of

    the

    o-7rovbaia

    7'j6)

    and

    bLafoLa

    of the

    characters.

    But

    tragedy

    s not

    merely

    n imitation

    f actionsof

    or

    by ff71ov8aZoL,

    or

    not

    all

    actions of

    or

    by crrovtaLot

    do

    in

    fact

    emanate

    fromtheir

    r0ovbaia

    #'dq

    nd bLacVoLa.

    A

    o-rov8aZoS9

    may purposely

    ct

    out

    of

    character:

    he

    may,

    for

    example,

    for comic

    effect,

    mitate

    a

    aviAos9.

    Many

    things

    which

    o-7rovtaLot

    rdinarily o, moreover, re not especiallyrelated to

    their

    character.

    Such actions

    are

    not what

    Aristotle has

    in

    mind.

    45

    Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note 10)

    52-63.

    46

    B. R.

    Rees, CR

    23 (1973)

    52.

    47

    Of course,

    not

    everything

    hat happens

    in

    a

    play

    is a product

    of the

    7'0-q

    nd

    bLavota

    of the

    characters;

    ome

    things

    naturally

    ccur through

    hance or are

    caused

    by

    natural

    or

    supernatural

    orces.

    48

    Humphrey

    House,

    Aristotle'sPoetics

    (London

    1956) 84.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    14/19

    X.rov8aLos0nd

    Teleology

    n

    the Poetics

    171

    Y7-rovbaLas

    t

    the

    very east

    entails

    that ome of

    the actions

    performed

    y

    the

    o-7rovbaZoL

    e thosecharacteristic f

    them,

    those

    which

    dentify

    hem

    as

    o--rov8a^oL.

    The reason

    for

    the

    presence

    of

    o-rovbalaS

    in

    the definitionof

    tragedy will

    assume hereafter o be

    that

    ustgiven.

    I

    have

    left

    oT7rov-

    baLos0ntranslated nd will

    continueto do

    so since there s no

    satisfactory

    English

    equivalent.

    In

    what follows

    will be

    concerned

    only

    with

    its

    meaning,not its

    translation.

    chuetrumpf

    holds

    that

    o-rov8aZoS9

    n

    the

    Poetics is

    an

    ethical term

    expressing

    judgment

    about

    those

    qualities

    and

    virtues

    which

    belong

    to

    '6oso n

    the

    Ethics,

    i.e.,

    moral,

    not intellec-

    tual,

    qualities

    and virtues.

    believe

    that

    on the

    contrary

    7ov8aLos9

    n

    thePoetics, as also frequentlyn theEthics,expresses judgmentwhich

    encompasses he

    intellectual s well as

    moral

    sphere. will

    present

    elow

    the

    reasons for

    my

    opinion. But

    Schuetrumpf

    s

    right

    o

    reject

    the view

    of

    Gudeman that

    o-7rov8aLos9

    n

    the

    Poetics

    is

    an

    aesthetic

    term,49

    nd

    right lso,

    I

    believe, to

    dispute Else's

    assertion

    hat

    "Aristotle's ntithesis

    a-rov8aZo0-.aviAos9

    s

    not

    merely

    moral,

    n

    any

    narrow

    ense

    of

    the word.

    Political,

    ocial,

    and

    aesthetic

    lements

    re

    in

    it from he

    beginning,

    nd

    it

    need

    not

    surprise

    us

    if

    they emerge

    more

    clearly

    later on."50

    Schuetrumpfholds,on the contrary, hat only withthe words

    T(J^

    EV

    MEyaA\7,

    o

    OVTCOV

    Kal

    EVTvXLca

    (53A10)

    does

    Aristotle

    ndicate

    that

    the

    characters

    should be

    from the

    upper class

    and

    argues that

    Aristotle

    would not

    have

    included

    this

    statement

    f

    his

    previous

    tatements

    bout

    the

    tragic characters

    had

    contained a

    "Feststellung

    uber die

    ausseren

    Verhaltnisse es

    Helden."'5'

    His

    disagreement

    with

    Else on this

    point has

    been

    roundly

    criticized

    by Rees.52

    Radical

    disagreement n

    this

    point

    can

    perhaps be

    quelled

    if

    scholars will

    allow

    a

    distinction

    etween the

    denotation

    and

    connotation

    f

    these

    words.

    17rov8aLos9

    nd

    faviXos9,

    n

    my opinion, denote, as Schuetrumpfnsists, nly an ethical judgment

    about

    those to

    whom

    they

    are

    applied;

    but they

    may, I

    would

    allow,

    even

    in

    the

    hands of

    Aristotle,

    have

    social,

    political,

    and

    aesthetic

    connotations s

    well.

    That

    these

    connotations

    play

    much of

    a role in

    Aristotle's

    sage

    of

    them

    n the

    Poetics,

    however,

    do

    not

    believe.

    It

    is stated n

    Cat.

    10B6-10 that

    a-wovbaLos0

    s

    the

    adjective

    for

    pE T-:

    EVLOTE

    8e

    Ka'L

    Ovo/aTos

    KXELMEVOV

    V

    XEYETaL

    7rapWVV14W TO KaT

    avTrJv

    7ToLOv

    AEyO/.LEVov,

    Lov

    ar7o

    Ti?/

    apTS

    O

    (T7rov8aLoS

    TQ) yap

    apET?/V

    EXEWV

    0rovba&ov A'yETaL,

    &A\

    ov 7rapwvvMws

    ar7o T77

    apET?/S.

    49

    Schuetrumpf

    above, note

    10)

    52-55; cf.

    above,

    note

    28.

    50

    Else

    (above, note

    11) 78.

    51

    Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note

    10) 58.

    52

    Rees

    (above,

    note

    46) 51.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    15/19

    172

    George F. Held

    Schuetrumpf

    s aware of

    the

    interrelationship

    f

    these words. He quotes

    thispassage from he Categories

    and

    another o the same effect

    rom he

    Magna Moralia (1181A28:

    TO

    8

    cT7rovbaLov

    ElvaL

    4EcTL

    TO

    TaS

    apETasq

    VXELV)53nd states

    without qualification

    that

    -"r7rov8azosv

    und

    oaiXos

    waren ... die apEr

    ) und

    KaKla zugehorigen Adjektive."54

    He

    seems

    unaware, however,of

    the potential

    conflict etween this statement

    nd

    othersby

    him which restrict

    he udgment xpressed

    by fo7rovbaZoS'

    to the

    moral sphere. f

    ff7rov8aLos9

    s

    the adjective

    for

    pErT?,

    one would

    expect

    that t would express udgments

    bout

    any kind of

    apET7/,

    intellectual

    s

    well as moral.

    Schuetrumpf's

    onclusions

    about

    how

    a

    7rov8aLos9

    s used in the

    Poetics are based on his belief that 6oso n the Poetics has the same

    meaning

    as in the Ethics where it

    includes moral

    but not intellectual

    qualities55

    nd,moreparticularly, is

    belief

    that

    t

    has

    such

    a meaning

    n

    48A1-5 where the

    men imitated n tragedy re said to

    be

    o-7rovbaZoL

    ith

    respect

    to

    their

    jq.56

    I

    disagree

    with him

    and

    believe

    that

    q6oso

    n the

    Poetics generally

    has

    the same sense as

    in Rh.

    1

    and

    2 where

    it

    includes

    intellectual

    as

    well as moral

    qualities.57

    n a

    forthcoming

    rticle

    in

    Hermes

    I give all

    the reasons

    why.

    Here

    I will

    give

    just

    one: its

    usage

    in

    48A1-5. The meaningsof

    '6OSo

    and

    o--rov8aLos9

    here are interwined.

    HGoso

    n that passage

    should include intellectual qualities

    because

    i

    rzov8a

    os'

    there,

    n

    the basis

    of its

    usage

    elsewhere

    n

    Aristotle, ught

    to

    express judgment

    which

    spans

    the intellectual

    s

    well

    as moral

    spheres.

    Though a-wov3aLos'

    s used

    by

    Aristotle t least

    once

    as a

    purely

    moral

    term,58

    t

    carries

    a

    broader

    meaning

    when

    contrasted

    xplicitly

    r

    im-

    plicitly

    with

    OaviAos

    or

    yEAoLoS.

    This

    is

    clear from

    he discussion

    f con-

    templation

    t the end of

    the

    Ethics

    1175B25-79A33).

    There

    -7Tov8aLos9

    and

    its

    cognates

    occur

    at least eleven

    times,59

    ot

    always

    in direct

    applicationto those who contemplate, ut always in wayswhich imply

    that

    they

    are

    among

    the ff7rovbaZoL

    because

    of their ntellectual

    uperi-

    ority.

    To

    say

    that

    the

    judgment

    expressed by

    ff7rovtaLOS

    encompasses

    both moral

    and

    intellectual

    qualities,

    however,

    is

    not to

    delineate

    its

    precise

    meaning.

    I submit

    that

    o-7rov8aLos9

    nd

    its

    antonyms

    are

    for

    Aristotle,

    t

    least

    when contrasted

    explicitly

    or

    implicitly

    with

    each

    other,

    teleological

    terms, .e.,

    they denote

    respectively

    good

    and

    bad

    53

    Schuetrumpfabove,note 10) 49, note 1.

    54

    Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note 10)

    51.

    55

    Cf.

    Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note

    10)

    52-53.

    56 Cf.

    Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note

    10)

    47-52.

    57

    On the

    usage

    of

    'Oo0

    in Rh.

    1

    and 2, see Schuetrumpf

    above,

    note 10)

    83, note

    2.

    58

    Cf.

    Rh.

    1378A16

    where

    7rov6atosq

    s used

    together

    with

    opOdvq.os,

    to form the

    moral-intellectual

    ntithesis.

    Bonitz'

    Index Aristotelicus

    istsseveral

    instanceswhere

    it is

    used synonomously

    ith

    E7TLLK7'.

    59

    IXoAij

    (Vermehren)

    ather

    han

    o-7rovbij

    hould probably

    be read

    at 1177A19.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    16/19

    ,rrov8a^tos

    nd Teleology

    n the Poetics 173

    relationship

    etween

    a

    thing,

    nimate

    or

    inanimate,

    nd

    its

    proper

    end

    (and

    form).The

    following

    passage (EN

    1176B35-77A6)

    from

    the

    discus-

    sion of contemplationwill illustrate the teleological connotationsof

    crT7rovIaLos,

    nd its cognates:

    ov

    T27

    EAos

    '1

    ava7ravrTLs

    yLvEat

    yap EvEKa

    T7S1

    EVEpyELasX

    OKE O O

    EvoaL,.Lv

    8'o0 KaT apET7V lVal-

    OVTOS Of

    ,AETa

    (T7rov8?J;,

    A'A

    OVK

    ev 7raLo3aL.

    E37ATu

    TE

    A

    TyoAev

    ra rovbaLa

    TrV

    yEXOLWV

    KatlAcTa

    7ratLLa%

    Kat

    TOV

    ,E/3ATLOVOT

    aft

    Kat

    lAoptOV Kat

    avOpc7rov

    aT7rov8aloTopav

    TrV

    evepyeLav

    7/

    E

    TOV

    ATlOVOT

    Kp

    ELTTWV

    Kal

    ETatLAoVLKWT

    pa

    77n.

    Aristotle posits a direct

    and

    proportional

    relationship

    between the

    o-7rovb

    cf.

    -7rovbaLoTepav)

    of an activitynd theexcellence f the

    part

    of us

    which it

    employs and also

    between the

    a-7rovb

    of

    an

    activity

    nd

    the

    happiness

    which it is

    capable

    of

    producing.

    Contemplation,

    e

    con-

    cludes,

    s

    the most

    o7rovba'a

    of

    activities nd the one

    most

    productive

    f

    happinessbecause it

    employs

    only thebest

    part of

    us,

    vo3s.60

    he

    happy

    life is

    the

    one that is lived

    HuEra

    ov7r07s.

    It is,

    therefore, nly by

    manifesting

    7mvb

    and

    by

    engaging

    n

    o-7rovIa^LaL

    7Tpa6ELv

    and E'vfpyELaL

    that

    we

    can

    obtain our

    end,

    happiness.

    The

    teleological

    connotations f

    r-7rov8a&os

    nd its cognates hould be apparent.

    Another

    mportant

    passage for

    illustrating he

    teleological

    connota-

    tionsof

    o-7rovIaZos-

    s

    1097A15-98A20.

    There Aristotle

    sserts hat all men

    desire the

    good, i.e., that forwhich

    all

    else is done

    (1097A18).

    Happiness,

    therefore,must

    be the

    good,

    for

    we

    choose

    all

    else for

    the sake of it

    (1097B1-6).

    Happiness, however, an

    be

    obtained only by

    performinghe

    specificwork

    ,Epyov) roperto man's

    nature. This

    work

    s

    an

    activity n

    accordance

    with reason

    and virtue. t

    is the

    o-7rov8aZos

    ho

    performs

    his

    workwell

    (cEv).Neither

    4aviAos- oryE,oZos-s used in the passage,but we

    may

    nfer

    rom he

    many

    passageswhere hese

    words

    re used as

    antonyms

    to

    o-7rov8aZoL

    hat t is the

    4aVAoL

    and

    yEO^LOL

    who do not

    perform

    man's

    workwell and

    whose

    actions,

    herefore,re

    notwell directed

    t man's

    end,

    happiness.

    This,

    I

    submit,

    s

    the

    fundamental

    distinction

    etweenAris-

    totle's

    -7rov8aZot

    nd

    OaviAoL,

    the

    distinction hich s

    operative n

    Po.

    48A1-5.

    60

    EN

    1177B27-78A9.

    Aristotle t

    one

    point

    1178B27-28) even

    identifies

    appiness

    with

    contemplation; nd on thisbasishe denies thatanimalscan be happy.This identifications

    most

    problematic:

    how can it

    be

    reconciled

    with

    what else

    Aristotle ays

    about

    happiness?

    This

    question and

    the

    general

    nature

    of

    Aristotle's

    onception of

    happiness

    have been the

    subject of

    much

    recent

    discussion. ee R.

    Kraut,"Two

    Conceptions

    of

    Happiness,"

    PhR

    88

    (1979)

    167-97; W. F.

    R.

    Hardie,

    "Aristotle

    n the

    Best

    Life for

    Man,"

    Philosophy 4

    (1979)

    35-50, esp.

    36;

    Klaus

    Jacobi,

    Aristoteles'

    infuhrung es

    Begriffs

    evdbato.lda' im

    I.

    Buch

    der

    'Nikomachischen

    Ethik,"'

    Philosophisches

    Jahrbuch

    86

    (1979)

    300-325;

    J.

    L.

    Ackrill,

    Aristotle

    on

    'Eudaimonia,' (London

    1975); Stephen

    R.

    L. Clark,

    Aristotle'sMan

    (Oxford

    1975); John

    M.

    Cooper, Reason and

    Human

    Good in

    Aristotle

    Boston

    1975).

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    17/19

    174

    George F. Held

    I

    conclude,

    therefore, hat

    when Aristotle ays that the action

    of

    tragedy s o7rovbaLa, he means

    that it should possess

    the same qualities

    whichbelong o the

    7rov8zaoL,

    it shouldbe in accordancewith t least

    some of the virtues,

    moral nd intellectual, ossessed

    y the

    7rov8aLoL,

    and

    it should be to

    some significantxtentwell directed

    at the end proper

    to

    man's nature,

    happiness.We may, therefore, e

    specific bout the

    "'good'

    result" t which ffortsn tragedy

    re to be made (see

    above, page 170): it s

    the good result f happiness.As

    Olson observes,

    Tragedy exhibits ife as

    directed o important nds; comedyas eithernot

    directed o such

    ends,or

    unlikely

    o

    achieve

    them."

    1

    Once

    again Olson has gotten o the

    heart of

    Aristotle'smeaning;but "important

    nds" may be

    reduced to one, ourfinal

    end, happiness.Tragedy mitates n action which s, comedy one which s

    not,well directed

    t happiness.Tragedy xhibits o

    us characterswho

    have,

    comedy characters

    who have not,

    the wherewithal o be happy and

    who

    demonstrate

    hisby whattheydo

    in the play tself.

    Such

    characters,

    f

    course,

    may fall nto misfortune-for

    variety

    f

    reasons:moral flaws n themselves,

    onestmistakes,

    hance, the enmity f

    the gods, etc. And

    if

    theydo, they

    naturally ose

    whateverhappiness hey

    may have.

    Tragedy,moreover,

    ypically resents

    hem

    n

    the very

    ct of

    falling ntomisfortune;nd Aristotlelearly houghtt appropriate or t to

    do

    so,

    as

    is

    evident

    from

    his discussion

    f

    the

    tragic

    plot

    n

    chapters

    13 and

    14. My

    views

    about

    his

    conception

    f

    tragedy

    need

    to

    be reconciled

    with

    thesefacts nd can be.

    It

    should

    first e notedthathappiness

    orAristotle

    s

    not identical

    with good fortune.

    Happiness

    for

    hinm

    s

    a

    technical

    and

    prescriptive erm.Virtue

    nd knowledge re preconditions

    or

    happiness,

    though

    not for

    good

    fortune.

    Happiness

    nvolves

    pleasure,

    but

    not

    ust

    any

    kind,only

    thosepleasures onsequent

    o and consistent

    ith

    he

    possession

    of

    virtue

    nd

    knowledge cf.

    EN

    1177A23-B1). However, hough

    happiness

    and goodfortune re not dentical, reedom rommisfortunesnaturally

    precondition

    for

    happiness.

    This

    is

    a truism

    which Aristotle

    nowhere

    bothers o

    express,

    hough

    t

    is

    implied

    n his comment

    hat

    the man who

    contemplates

    s the

    happiest

    f

    men

    because,

    among

    other

    hings,

    e

    is the

    most like

    the gods

    and

    they

    are

    most

    ikely

    to look after omeone

    like

    themselves

    EN

    1179A23-33).

    The

    fact that

    happiness depends

    upon

    freedom rom

    misfortune,oupled

    withthe other

    factsmentioned

    bove.

    requires ome

    modification

    f my

    tatement hat

    ragedy

    mitates

    n action

    well directed t happiness: hetragic ction is well directed t happiness

    only

    to some extent

    nd in

    certain

    respects;

    o

    some

    extent

    nd

    in

    certain

    respects t is poorly

    o directed.

    t

    is

    well directed

    n

    respect

    o

    the effects

    upon

    it of theo-rov8aZa

    ~Or,

    and

    btaVota

    of the

    tragic haracters,

    ut it

    is

    poorly

    o

    directed

    n

    respect

    to

    the effects

    pon

    it of the

    moral

    flawsof

    these ame

    characters,

    heirhonest

    mistakes,

    hance, angrygods,

    tc.

    That

    61

    Olson (above, note 16) 3-5.

    This content downloaded from 163.178.101.228 on Mon, 8 Sep 2014 23:09:53 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    18/19

    1?rov8aios9

    and

    Teleology

    n

    thePoetics

    175

    it is

    poorlydirected

    t

    happiness

    may

    seem the more salientfact

    about

    it,

    but

    for

    Aristotle t is essential hat the

    tragic

    action

    possess

    both

    types

    of

    direction.This is evident fromhis definitionf tragedywhere thewords

    7rpaEws-

    o-irov8aias,

    xplicitly

    ttribute

    o it the

    one

    direction,

    while

    the

    words

    \fov

    Ka'L

    0,8ov

    implicitly

    ttribute o

    t

    theother.

    Ev8aqLoVLa, herefore,

    falls within the

    province

    of

    tragedy,

    and

    outside that of

    comedy.

    nterestingly,

    ristotle

    makes

    a statement o

    that

    effect n the

    Poetics,

    though

    the text of

    this statement s

    somewhat

    corrupt. give itstext

    s

    printed

    n

    Else's edition:

    ?7

    yap rpaycoba

    f(LjAur0zT

    -TLV

    OVK

    aVBpco7TCV

    AXa

    lTpaicv

    KaL

    LOV

    KaL EvoaL.uoVL'as [

  • 8/10/2019 Spoudaios and Teleology in the Poetics

    19/19

    176 George F. Held

    whole much better than

    does my own interpretation.My arguments

    against t have been based

    rather n the belief that t is inconsistent ith

    Aristotle's sage of

    o-7roviao0S

    lsewhere n his corpus.One should keep

    in mind, however, that,

    even as traditionally nterpreted,Aristotle's

    definition

    oes

    not

    fit

    he

    genre as a whole, forthe action of some

    Greek

    tragedies s not serious t all. Every definition f tragedy

    which triesto

    distinguish

    what is distinctly ragic and which rises above the mere

    tautology hat a tragedy s a play by a tragedianproduced

    on the tragic

    stage,

    will

    necessarily

    have a somewhat limited applicability and

    practicality. ristotle'sheory s I interprett, however,

    s very practical

    in one very mportant espect:

    t succeeds in distinguishing

    hat makes

    the mosttragiccharactersmost tragic.The term tragic" an be applied

    intelligibly o a Creon,64

    Medea, or a Jason,but the

    term, as most

    people

    use it and understand t, applies much

    better o

    an

    Antigone,

    n

    Oedipus,

    or

    a

    Socrates.

    Why do the latter trike

    us as

    more

    fully ragic

    than

    the former? he reason cannot lie in the pathos

    which they uffer,

    for

    some of the latter sufferno more than

    some of the former.The

    reason must lie

    in

    the

    o-rovb

    which they manifestgenerally n their

    actions and especially in

    those actions which

    lead directly

    to

    their

    respective catastrophes.The example of Socrates is most noteworthy

    because his

    death,

    n

    Plato's account of

    it,

    nvolves ittle

    or no

    pathos

    at

    all (cf. Phd. 117B3-7),

    and

    yet

    strikes

    many

    of us as

    exceedingly ragic.

    It can do

    so only

    because

    the

    tragic

    effect f

    a

    catastrophe

    s

    in

    direct

    proportionnot only

    to

    the pathos suffered,

    ut also

    to

    the

    a-7rov8w7

    manifested by

    the sufferers. hat this should

    be

    so is

    implied

    in

    Aristotle's heory

    s

    I

    interpret

    t. That

    theory,

    herefore,

    s I

    interpret

    it,

    is

    not

    impractical,

    hough

    ts

    practicality

    s

    of a different rder than

    as traditionally nterpreted.

    There

    is,

    I

    suppose,

    the

    possibility

    hat

    a7rovbaZ0s

    in thedefinitionf tragedy s ambiguous, hat, onsciously r

    not, Aristotle

    chose

    to use it there because

    it can

    carry

    both the

    teleological

    onnotations

    which attribute

    o it

    and

    a

    more

    general sense,

    approximating

    he

    English

    "serious."

    To

    hold

    this

    possibility

    o be

    an

    actuality

    s

    a convenient

    way

    of

    making

    most

    ense out

    of

    his

    definition,

    and

    my arguments

    n

    favor

    of my

    own

    interpretation,

    s far as I

    can

    see,

    pose

    no

    absolute

    obstacle

    to

    the

    adoption

    of

    such

    a view.

    64

    As Karl

    Reinhardt,

    Sophocles,

    transl.

    Hazel and David

    Harvey

    (Oxford

    1979)

    93,

    observes,Creon's fate in Antigone is "empty,"Antigone's full." By my interpretation,

    Aristotle's efinition

    f tragedy

    mpliesthat

    the

    fate of Antigone

    s

    more appropriate

    for

    representation

    n tragedy

    than that

    of Creon.

    That Antigone's

    actions

    are

    0a7rovbaZat,

    Creon's largely

    4aiAat, should

    be evident

    from he fact

    that hers

    are

    in

    accordance

    with

    nature

    while his are

    not, as

    I have shown

    in

    "Antigone'sDual

    Motivation

    for theDouble

    Burial," Hermes

    111 (1983)

    197-201.