symposium part 3 william p. fisher, jr, phd with over...

29
SYMPOSIUM PART 3 The Role of Care in Bringing Human and Social Capital to Life in Nursing William P. Fisher, Jr, PhD with over 25 years professional experience, Dr. William P. Fisher, Jr. has developed a complementary array of skills focused on improved information quality and systems in health care and education. He is internationally recognized for contributions to both ends of the theoretical-philosophical to practical-analytic spectrum. Dr. Fisher's recent work explores possibilities for and projects likely consequences of equating tests and surveys measuring the same constructs, so that all instruments in an area measure in the same unit of comparison and with known uncertainty characteristics. Jane F. Sumner, Ph.D, RN, APRN, BC has been investigating caring in nursing for many years because of her varied experiences in practice over 48 years. Her original nursing education was in New Zealand and her 3 university degrees are from the US. For the last 19 years she has been a nurse educator.

Upload: truongdiep

Post on 15-May-2018

215 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

SYMPOSIUM

PART 3

The Role of Care in Bringing Human and Social Capital to Life in Nursing

William P. Fisher, Jr, PhD with over 25 years professional experience, Dr. William P. Fisher, Jr. has developed a complementary array of skills focused on improved information quality and systems in health care and education. He is internationally recognized for contributions to both ends of the theoretical-philosophical to practical-analytic spectrum. Dr. Fisher's recent work explores possibilities for and projects likely consequences of equating tests and surveys measuring the same constructs, so that all instruments in an area measure in the same unit of comparison and with known uncertainty characteristics.

Jane F. Sumner, Ph.D, RN, APRN, BC has been investigating caring in nursing for many years because of her varied experiences in practice over 48 years. Her original nursing education was in New Zealand and her 3 university degrees are from the US. For the last 19 years she has been a nurse educator.

1

Theory, Care, and Nursing:

The Capital Value of a Practical Synthesis

William P. Fisher, Jr., Ph.D.

Jane F. Sumner, Ph.D, RN, APRN, BC

University of California, Berkeley and Lousiana State University, New Orleans

[email protected], [email protected]

Abstract

In the history of science, predictive theories enabling accurate and confident innovations

typically emerge only after phenomena can be represented and reproduced consistently in

standardized forms. These technological forms are structural transformations of the original

forms of life from which meaning was poetically and metaphorically abstracted. A new basis for

theoretical and practical developments in caring in nursing follows from close consideration of

the experience of physis, spontaneously self-organizing natural processes. The physis of a wide

array of nursing constructs exhibits consistencies likely to lend themselves to standardized

technological representations. If they do, new horizons should emerge for theory development

and innovation around nursing’s human and social capital. Probabilistic Rasch models making

use of sufficient statistics and requiring separable parameters will be of significant value. How to

retain a close connection with the original meaning-giving sources in physis will be a matter of

ongoing concern.

2

Framing the Problem

Background. “There is nothing so practical as a good theory” (Lewin, 1951, p. 169). Good

theory provides explanatory power, predictive control, efficiency, and confidence that a

phenomenon is as thoroughly understood as it needs to be for practical purposes. In the history of

science, good theories almost always emerge from social networks sharing standardized

technology and instrumentation (Bijker, Hughes, and Pinch, 2012; Bud and Cozzens, 1992;

Daston and Galison, 2007; Hankins and Silverman, 1999; Ihde, 1991, 1998; Latour, 1987, 2005;

Wise, 1995). Historically, scientific productivity is maximized when phenomena can be

consistently reproduced for controlled study, and information is shared within a community of

practice in standardized terms, images, and metrics. It seems that individual and group learning

and innovation often depend extensively on opportunities to engage with others in the repetitive

play of structured games (Barab, Scott, Siyahhan, Goldstone, Ingram-Goble, et al., 2009; Crease,

1993; Wise, 1995). This behavioral and cognitive orientation persists even when the rules of the

games played are not well defined, and winning becomes less associated with the desired

outcomes of scientific or economic advancement than with secondary outcomes presenting mere

appearances of new learning and productivity (Bakker, van Dijk, Wicherts, 2012; Gertler, 2010).

The creative power of social networks in technological, business, political, and artistic

innovation is very much of contemporary cultural interest globally. The exercise of that power,

however, is nothing new, as it has driven industrial, scientific, and democratic revolutions for

centuries. Innovation has always been a team sport in some respects, but its team characteristics

have become of increasing relevance as the technology for networked communications has

proliferated (Degen, 2009). One of the most important lessons of technology’s ubiquitous

presence is that generalizable creativity depends on systemically shared and complementary

3

moral, economic, and scientific values (Schaffer, 1992; Zak, 2008), taking these as both guides

to right thinking and acting, as well as standardized numeric metrics and common currencies.

A fundamental barrier to the conceptualization and formation of shared values is the

assumption that qualitative and quantitative data and methods entail paradigmatically distinct

philosophical commitments (Bryman, 2007; Moffatt, White, Mackintosh, and Howel, 2007). On

the contrary, "a good implicit phenomenology is often concealed in the most objectivistic

sciences” (Ricoeur, 1967a, p. 219). The apparent ontological divide between qualitative and

quantitative methods may then be only an artifact of unnecessary assumptions, and not an

inherent structural feature of the scientific landscape (Fisher, 2003a, 2003b, 2004, 2010; Fisher

and Stenner, 2011). Nursing, of course, attends to human care needs, and accordingly has to

account for a complex array of physical, chemical, biological, psychological, and social factors

not easily reduced to a simple, standardized model. Theory development has been

characteristically more qualitative, hermeneutic and phenomenological (Benner, 1994, 2001;

Dunlop, 1986; Sumner, 2001, 2006; Watson, 1999) and has understandably, then, not proceeded

in nursing as it did in physics.

It may, however, be worthwhile to consider the problems of simplification and theory

development from a fresh point of view. Recent studies of model-based reasoning processes in

the history of science (Nersessian, 2002, 2008) illustrate the productive use of analogies by

James Clerk Maxwell, for instance, in the development of electromagnetic theory. Metaphor has

been found ubiquitous in discourse, including in science and engineering, with the effect of

rendering discovering and invention poetic (Black, 1962; Brown, 2003; Lakoff and Johnson,

1980). This kind of research suggests that nursing may harbor phenomena not previously

examined in terms of their viability as objects of study amenable to analogical models and

4

processes for validating them. In fact, because its primary raison d’etre centers on care and

caring, which are characteristic of a quintessentially human mode of being, nursing may have an

opportunity to make a particularly unique and powerful contribution to the development of a new

kind of art and science.

But what are the unexamined phenomena nursing could more productively focus on? What

kind of theoretical developments are possible that are not yet on the record or being pursued?

How are the relevant phenomena to be identified? It may help to look to the history of science

for a starting point. A source for an analogical perspective is provided by de Solla Price (1986, p.

240), who observed,

Historically, we have almost no examples of an increase in understanding being applied to

make new advances in technical competence, but we have many cases of advances in

technology being puzzled out by theoreticians and resulting in the advancement of

knowledge. It is not just a clever historical aphorism, but a general truth, that

'thermodynamics owes much more to the steam engine than ever the steam engine owed to

thermodynamics.'

An instance of supporting evidence is provided by Kuhn (1977, p. 90), who noted that seven of

the nine theoreticians who succeeded at least partially in quantifying energy conversion

processes were engineers or were working directly on engines when they made their

contributions to the physics of energy conservation.

In nursing, care is a primary focus of both practice and theory. Nursing theoreticians tend

to be practicing nurses with firsthand experience in observing the association of care with

healing. Other nursing theoreticians may be practicing teachers who routinely observe the effect

of their care and attention on the progression of learning in students. There is, however, of course

5

nothing like a care engine that mechanically functions in a physically predictable way, and that

could be experimentally studied and manipulated in accord with engineering principles. But this

literal analogy could be subtly configured in terms of a more ontologically appropriate metaphor

drawn from the ancient Greek concept of physis.

In nursing, physis is understood in terms of the natural and spontaneous healing and

growth experienced as a result of good nutrition, sleep, and hygiene (Wynn, 2006). The term is

also taken to refer to the satisfaction a nurse can experience in the knowledge of having provided

effective quality care (Sumner, 2010). As a philosophical concept, however, physis concerns

natural processes of coming into and going out of existence. Physis is the unsought, poetically

emergent creation and destruction of beings, something that comes from within these beings

themselves, in the manner of a flower, blooming. Physis stands in clear contrast with the ready

availability of technological devices and methods for the automatic, effortless production and

consumption of commercial goods (Heidegger, 1977, p. 10; Glazebrook, 2000, pp. 164-165).

There is a tendency in the modern world to assume that technology defines existence, and

that all important problems have been or will be solved by means of technology. Art, poetry,

music, handicrafts, and natural wilderness are often experienced as reminders of a lost

connection with the earth or a spiritual realm, and they also often convey the feeling that there is

little or nothing that can be done to restore what has been lost.

But awareness of physis and the methodical application of technique both nonetheless

follow from a concern with care. To the extent that one engages in dialogue and negotiation

instead of violence and domination, consideration for another’s human vulnerability has been

shown, a choice in favor of caring has been made, and at least some trace of an experience of

physis is obtained (Gadamer, 1991, p. 61; Habermas, 1995; Heidegger, 1962; Irigaray, 1984;

6

Ricoeur, 1967b). Even in the context of contemporary nursing practice, which can at times seem

awash with technological fixes and immutable control mechanisms, high quality care is still a

goal and is often achieved (Locsin, 2005; Sumner, 2008).

Despite the persistent evidence of physis in nursing, the fundamental value of nursing care in

creating and increasing human and social capital is elusive and remains largely unaddressed

(Royal, 2012). Though an artful apprehension of the value of physis in nursing care (Wynn,

2006) is of great value for symbolizing the safeguarding of care, there is a longstanding and

increasingly urgent need for a poetic crafting of a new root metaphor that resonates with and

captivates the imaginations of everyone providing and affected by that care. Most pointedly,

instead of remaining uncritically rooted in assumptions of what it means to assign value

methodically in nursing practice, in nursing education, or in a nursing research study, those

methods must themselves be broken down to their own authentic expressions of physis and then

reconstructed to meet the needs for new representations (Sumner, 2001, 2006, 2008; Sumner and

Fisher, 2008). Put more directly, cynical games played with meaningless, locally varying ordinal

scores and underpowered p-values as means to the ends of publication and promotion (Bakker, et

al., 2012) must be replaced with authentic play involving meaningful, globally invariant interval

measures and substantively significant, reproducible outcomes.

A hermeneutic and phenomenological approach to this deconstruction and reconstruction of

method begins from attentive care for the object of the conversation as the essential factor in

creating an authentic science. Work of this kind pursued in relation to the natural sciences

(Crease, 1993; Heelan, 1983, 1998; Ihde, 1998, 2012; Glazebrook, 2000) has been extended and

brought to bear in the social sciences (Fisher, 2003a, 2003b, 2004, 2010; Fisher & Stenner,

2011). Method in this sense playfully appropriates the experience of physis (Gadamer, 1989;

7

Ricoeur, 1981, pp. 182-193). The unexamined phenomena nursing needs to advance the theory

and practice of care reside in the physis that can be found and created in the repeated self-

organization of regular patterns in data recorded as responses to questions on patient surveys,

student tests, and clinical assessments. These questions can be intentionally designed, so far as

possible, to reveal or construct reproducible patterns interpretable as evidence that the construct

measured exists as an identifiable entity in the world. Once established as persisting as

repeatedly identifiable objects of conversations, these patterns could form the basis for a new

technological embodiment of the physis of caring, which in turn could provide a context in which

the nursing profession could collectively puzzle out improved theories of caring.

Method here recovers its root sense of following along after (meta-) the object of inquiry on

the path (odos) it takes up of its own accord. Hence, Gadamer (1989, p. 460) points out that in

method, properly understood, "what thought experiences is the movement of the thing itself." He

continues, observing that

The Greeks...did not conceive understanding as a methodic activity of the subject, but as

something that the thing itself does and which thought 'suffers.' This activity of the thing

itself is the real speculative movement that takes hold of the speaker. We have sought the

subjective reflection of it in speech. We can now see that this activity of the thing itself, the

coming into language of meaning, points to a universal ontological structure, namely to the

basic nature of everything toward which understanding can be directed. Being that can be

understood is language. The hermeneutical phenomenon here projects its own universality

back onto the ontological constitution of what is understood, determining it in a universal

sense as language and determining its own relation to beings as interpretation. (pp. 474-475)

8

Physis can be methodically apprehended, appropriated, and embodied in a technique, however,

only to the extent that "The first concern of all dialogical and dialectical inquiry is a care for the

unity and sameness of the thing under discussion" (Gadamer, 1991, p. 61; original emphasis).

Thus, the focus of physis-oriented research on patient care needs, on student care instruction, and

on nursing care competency begins from the identification of constant patterns stable enough to

be repeatedly recreated across different local conversations involving different people at

different times and places asking different questions that nonetheless still all pertain to a single

construct.

Establishing the existence of these patterns of invariant regularity is, however, only the

beginning of this kind of research. A new paradigm for nursing research and practice based in

careful attention to the physis of care cannot simply rework existing concepts of validity and

reliability; it must begin with a fresh orientation to goals not previously pursued in systematic

ways. The overarching methodological framework must be phenomenological, but in the

existential sense of focusing on the cycle of reduction, application, creative destruction, and

return to reduction described by Heidegger (1982, pp. 19-23, 320-330; Marion, 1998; also see

Fisher, 2010; Fisher and Stenner, 2011).

Though they are necessary to the advancement of knowledge, the identification and local

study of these patterns of invariance are not sufficient in themselves to the task. Stopping with

this reductive moment in the movement through the method is a failure to follow through with

enough care for the physis experienced to extend it to others for application. As Ricoeur (1967b)

puts it, to cut off the conversation in this way commits the violence of the premature conclusion.

Most research employing factor analysis or statistical analysis of ordinal scores makes untenable

assumptions about the meaning of the numbers studied, and more importantly fixes the meaning

9

of the results in relation to the particular questions asked and the particular persons answering

them. This inability to leave the question open, in the sense of supporting transparent

comparability with other studies of the same construct, is the fundamental shortcoming of what

passes for quantitative methods in most mainstream research in nursing employing test, survey,

and assessment data. Science is supposed to be an accumulation of aggregate knowledge, but

even when results are comparable across samples and instruments, researchers usually fail to

make those comparisons (Fisher, 1997, 1999).

To arrive at a place from which the collective intelligence of the field of nursing can be

focused and harnessed—to meet the challenges of advancing theory and practice—standards are

essential. Everyone involved must be able to know when they are experiencing the phenomenon

they intend to experience, and they must be able to see how much of it there is. Standardized

terms, images, and metrics must be devised for the things themselves to be brought into language

as shared objects in the real world. The universality of scientific phenomena is not spontaneously

and effortlessly created from the experience of physis. Things do not automatically pop into

language in some self-initiated and instantaneous way. As Gadamer says, being that can be

understood is language, but that does not mean things come into language all by themselves.

Rather, quite significant resources must be invested in standardization to give a tangible, material

form to the otherwise unenculturated phenomena apprehended when an invariant pattern first

presents itself (Hunter, 1980; Latour, 1987, p. 251).

Standardization makes it possible for observers of the phenomenon to use the same

language in referring to it, reducing the opportunities for confusion that arise when different

words, images, and numbers are used to refer to the same thing. Persistent quantitative patterns

can be fixed in standard metrics to which all instruments measuring the construct are linked. In

10

the history of science, metrological networks have been a means by which communities of

research and practice have united themselves in common purpose and have achieved

extraordinary results (Latour, 1987, pp. 247-257, 2005; Hunt, 1994; Kuukkanen, 2011; Wise,

1995). In the context of the phenomenological method’s careful sensitivity to appropriating the

experience of physis, it is essential to set up metrological systems that distribute the media of a

shared frame of reference to everyone interested in participating in it. Existing examples of such

media for shared frames of reference include clocks, rulers, thermometers, weight scales,

speedometers, etc.

This may sound like a high standard to achieve, and it is. Achieving it would be an

unprecedented accomplishment in the human and social sciences. It is true that data exhibiting

invariant patterns of the kind described here are commonly produced in high stakes tests and

research in education, psychology, and health care employing a variety of probabilistic models

(Rasch, 1960, 1977; Andrich, 1978, 2004; Bezruzcko, 2005; Bond and Fox, 2007; Fisher and

Wright, 1994; Wilson, 2005; Wright, 1977, 1999). Nursing has a fairly extensive history of

research and licensure applications employing models requiring data exhibiting the

characteristics of physis (Fox, 1999; Hagquist, Bruce, & Gustavsson, 2009; Holm & Kavanagh,

1985; Lee and Fisher, 2002; O’Neill, Marks, and Reynolds, 2005; Smith, Conrad, Chang, &

Piazza, 2002; Sumner & Fisher, 2008), though the possibilities for capitalizing on physis in this

context has not been generally appreciated for its particular value (Strickland, 2002).

The local definitions of invariant constructs described in some instances of measurement

research and practice do not make their full value evident because nothing is done to link results

together in a shared framework of common standards. Even when multiple separate calibrations

of different instruments measuring the same thing, or of the same instrument calibrated on

11

different samples, are available in the published literature of a field, comparing or equating the

available metrics is rare (Fisher, 1997, 1999). It seems as though the idea of science as an

accumulated compendium of learning has been lost.

The full value of local instrument calibrations can be realized only if and when the invariant

patterns identified are represented systematically in an interconnected network of point-of-use

applications unified by standards (Fisher, 2012; Fisher, Harvey and Kilgore, 1995: Fisher,

Harvey, Taylor, Kilgore, and Kelly, 1995; Stenner and Smith, 1982; Stenner and Stone, 2010).

Of course, to arrive at a new system of that sort, existing systems of research and practice that

are not organized around coordinated expressions of physis must be replaced using the processes

of creative destruction deployed in the third moment of the phenomenological method. Those

conversations will not be likely to occur until dissatisfaction with the anomalies and

inconsistencies of the existing paradigm coalesce into a broad movement in which firm

conceptions of the first two moments are in place.

Ontological Midwifery of Care

Situating caring in a “transpersonal framework of conscious intentionality,” Watson (1999,

pp. 237, 243-259) notes that postmodern analyses and concepts often fail to move beyond critical

evaluations of failed philosophies or methods to new ways of constructing possibilities for

healing environments. If, following Watson, nurses are to be able to assume roles as “ontological

architects” designing and inhabiting healing spaces, they will need (a) a more tightly interwoven

and systematic integration of ontology and method, and (b) a new science of ontological research

and development to support them.

Ontology, as the logic of existence and of how things come into being, becomes

methodological when the physis of a form of life is captured or recorded, and is made routinely

12

repeatable. The ontology of care is, however, specifically focused on living being, as opposed to

mechanical building materials. Architectural space is an apt metaphor for the configuration of

attitudes, skills, and relationships needed to create a healing environment. The metaphor falls

short, however, in its implications as they are pursued into the details of nursing practice.

Consistent methodological principles follow more directly from the metaphor of the Socratic

midwife than they do from the mixed metaphor of “ontological architects.”

Socrates’ dialectical method was intended to ensure that his students’ and colleagues’

conceptual offspring would be born with the metaphoric equivalents of good eyes, straight noses,

and ten fingers and toes (Plato, 1961, pp. 853-856, or 149 ff. in standard Stephanus pagination).

So, too, must nursing attend to the midwifery of both caring practitioners able to take on lives of

their own as professionals, and of caring processes and outcomes able to bring patients back to

their productive, interdependent lives.

How can ontological midwifery be systematically focused on caring in nursing? There

would seem to be an almost unspannable breach between the ontological assumptions of

contemporary measurement practice in nursing and the qualitative depiction of the practical

demands experienced in managing care, as is described in other contexts by Bryman (2007) and

Moffatt, et al. (2007). Recent texts (such as Watson, 2009) on measuring caring in nursing show

that nursing has not yet recognized or adopted to a significant degree relevant advances in

measurement theory and practice made over the last several decades, though there are some

exceptions (Fox, 1999; Hagquist, Bruce, & Gustavsson, 2009; Holm and Kavanagh, 1985; Lee

and Fisher, 2002; O’Neill, Marks, and Reynolds, 2005; Smith, Conrad, Chang, & Piazza, 2002;

Sumner & Fisher, 2008). A significant and unaddressed challenge then concerns how to better

13

inform nursing’s ontological aspirations with improved methods that remain authentically

connected with its caring mission.

Husserlian phenomenology became the method of ontology and of scientific philosophy in

Heidegger’s (1982) critical synthesis, though Husserl himself contributed more to that synthesis

than has generally been recognized (Marion, 1998, pp. 43-51, 143-146). Heidegger, like many

who came later in 20th

century Continental philosophy, focused extensively on the third,

creatively destructive or deconstructive moment in the ontological method, to the near exclusion

of the other two moments, reduction and construction. As Heidegger (1982, pp. 19-23, 320-330)

and Derrida (2003, p. 62) recognized, however, engagement with the processes of reduction and

construction is unavoidable in that writing itself reduces infinite potentials to a limited text, and

inherently involves the positive intention to express some kind of meaning (Caputo, 1997, p. 80;

Fisher, 2010; Ruin, 2011, p. 80).

The iterative cycling through the process of reduction, application, and creative destruction

is not so much a technique, however, as it is the irreducible whole of authentic method itself. The

(Gadamerian) Socratic midwife welcoming the birth of new life and comforting the afflicted is

complemented by the (Derridean) Socratic gadfly afflicting the comfortable by creatively

destroying hidden preconceptions (Risser, 1989). Similarly, Kuhn (1970) distinguishes between

method as it is linearly presented in textbooks and method as it is lived by researchers

experiencing new forms of physis in the laboratory. Tracing the emergence of new methods

through the primary journal literature reveals the process of trial and error through which

phenomena come into the world as new entities.

Gadamer (1989, pp. 101-134) points to play as the most important clue to understanding the

nature of method. Echoing Husserl’s intention to attend to things themselves and Hegel’s

14

arguments against inauthentic externally-imposed methodologies, Gadamer elaborates a sense of

method as following along (meta-) the path (odos) described by phenomena as they are

experienced. The repetitive back and forth of questions and answers, experimental trials and

errors, playfully absorbs the observer into a participatory role and a partner in the creation of

meaningful representations (Toulmin, 1982).

The metaphor of Socratic maiuetics supports and informs nursing’s ontological midwives by

providing a fertile context for conceiving, gestating, birthing, and nurturing living meaning.

Caring in nursing is not only the field’s defining activity, caring is fundamental to human being.

The choice between peaceable negotiation and violent impositions of will hinges on caring

enough to try to create shared meaning, and begins from love (Fielding, 2003; Irigaray, 1984;

Marion, 2007; Ricoeur, 1967b).

Caring as the Midwifery of Living Meaning

For our purposes here, human and social capital are taken to include nurses’ own skills,

motivations, health, and trustworthiness, as well as that of their patients. Though human and

social capital have been a focus of interest of workers in the nursing context (Kritsotakis &

Gamarnikow, 2004; Lauder, Reel, Farmer, & Griggs, 2006; Royal, 2012), little or no attention

has been paid to how the very low efficiency of the respective markets might be improved.

Measurement costs are a primary source of this inefficiency (Barzel, 1982; Benham and

Benham, 2000), as their insurmountably high levels cause most human and social capital

investment decisions to be made on the basis of little, no, or mistaken information (Fisher, 2011,

2012; Goldberg, 2009).

The concept of capital is important to nursing because it focuses close attention on the

varied types of human, social, and economic value created in nursing (Covell, 2008; Gopee,

15

2002; Royal, 2012). Qualitative descriptions and evaluations of human and social capital are

important foundational steps to take toward creating uniform standards for quantifying their

value. Despite the meaning of the term “capital,” however, its application to date to human and

social assets (Becker, ; Coleman, 1988) remains an empty metaphor: amounts of skill,

motivation, health, or trust are not expressed in standard units in the way property and

commodities are, and neither can these forms of capital be associated with a known market

value. If intangible assets are to be priced in accord with their value, if they are to pay

appreciable returns on investment, and if they are to ever be included as significant factors in

economic models, they will have to be quantified. Authentic quantification embodying the

principles of ontological midwifery is one way vigilant attention can be focused on meaningful

representations.

How might caring human and social capital in nursing be conceived, midwifed, and nurtured

to a fuller maturity? The efficiency of capital markets depends on metrological standards like

common currencies and common product definitions well known for their value in reducing the

costs encountered in negotiating even the simplest transactions (Barzel, 1982; Benham &

Benham, 2000). Markets for property and manufactured goods are highly efficient because value

can be readily ascertained via socially sanctioned and scientifically developed universally

uniform standardized measures. Human and social capital, however, are needlessly dysfunctional

in highly inefficient markets because of the common but resolvable difficulties associated with

determining and representing value (Fisher, 2009, 2011, 2012). Better measurement is key to

overcoming these difficulties.

A place to start in exploring possibilities for ontological midwifery in nursing is suggested in

the realization that the physis experienced in the teaching, provision, and management of care

16

could be construed as the living DNA of a meaningful social body and collective intelligence.

Projecting and elaborating models of this kind involve positing abstract mathematical ideals as

heuristic fictions guiding inquiry (Butterfield, 1957; Ihde, 1991; Kuhn, 1961; Nersessian, 2002,

2006). Model-based reasoning processes in science are not qualitatively different from the way

words and concepts are used in everyday language (Nersessian, 2006, 2008; Fisher, 2004).

Models, like words, project unrealistically perfect conceptualizations of relationships between

distinct and separate unitary phenomena. No data or observations ever conform perfectly to the

models’ heuristic fictions. Perfect circles cannot be drawn, there are no mathematical pendula

made of a weightless string and a point-like mass, and there are no ability test data affected only

by the difficulties of the questions asked and the abilities of the persons measured.

Given such models and data that more or less fit them, instruments embody each separate

phenomenon’s perceptual profile and can do so in measuring units that are, first, experimentally

determined to be of a constant size, and, second, can be expressed in a standardized numeric

metric. These determinations of unit size and their standardization are facilitated by the Rasch

measurement models widely employed in educational assessment and professional licensure, that

are increasingly applied in health care research at large, and that have seen some limited use

within nursing research and practice.

Beyond the determination of invariant units, the support Rasch models offer for realizing the

goal of an ontological midwifery in nursing includes

the mapping of qualitative learning progressions and therapeutic continua useful in theory

development and in designing curricula and treatment programs as these are defined by

the invariant order of the item hierarchies established via instrument calibration;

the equating of different instruments experimentally shown to measure the same thing;

17

the adaptive administration of those instruments, such that items may be chosen for use

according to qualitative and/or quantitative criteria without compromising either the unit

or the error of measurement;

the theory-informed modification of existing instruments via the removal or addition of

items, again without compromising the comparability of the unit of measurement;

the removal of rater severity and leniency as factors influencing measures; and

the capacity to estimate measures in a standardized unit on the fly at the point of use, with

no need for data computerization, storage, analysis, and reporting.

Care for the quality, meaning, and practicality of measures is an important way of following

Nightingale’s advice as to putting “the patient in the best condition where Nature can heal”

(quoted in Watson, 1999, p. 258). The non-physical subtleties of energy and mood that must be

coordinated and mediated to create this condition inevitably must involve the matching of caring

skills with caring challenges, matching that could be more efficiently facilitated over the course

of nursing education and practice through the judicious construction of an array of well-tuned

instruments. Properly situated within a problem-focused methodological pluralism (Dawson,

Fischer, & Stein, 2006), care for the unity and sameness of the objects of healing conversations

can nurture the smallest seeds of possibility into fruitful trees of realized productivity.

18

References.

Akkerman, S., van den Bossche, P., Admiraal, W., Gijselaers, W., Segers, M., Simons,

R.-J. et al. (2007, February). Reconsidering group cognition: From conceptual confusion to a

boundary area between cognitive and socio-cultural perspectives? Educational Research Review,

2, 39-63.

Andrich, D. (1978). A rating formulation for ordered response categories. Psychometrika,

43(4), 561-73.

Andrich, D. (2004, January). Controversy and the Rasch model: A characteristic of

incompatible paradigms? Medical Care, 42(1), I-7--I-16.

Bakker, M., van Dijk, A., & Wicherts, J. M. (2012). The rules of the game called

psychological science. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 543-554.

Barzel, Y. (1982). Measurement costs and the organization of markets. Journal of Law

and Economics, 25, 27-48.

Becker, G. (1994). Human capital: A theoretical and empirical analysis with special

reference to education (3rd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Benham, A., & Benham, L. (2000). Measuring the costs of exchange. In C. Ménard (Ed.),

Institutions, contracts and organizations: Perspectives from new institutional economics (pp.

367-375). Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.

Benner, P. (Ed.). (1994). Interpretive phenomenology: Embodiment, caring, and ethics.

Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Benner, P. (2001). The phenomenon of care. In S. K. Toombs (Ed.), Handbook of

phenomenology and medicine (pp. 351-370). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

19

Bezruczko, N. (Ed.). (2005). Rasch measurement in health sciences. Maple Grove, MN:

JAM Press.

Bijker, W. E., Hughes, T. P., & Pinch, T. (Eds.). (2012). The social construction of

technological systems: New directions in the sociology and history of technology. Cambridge,

Massachusetts: MIT Press.

Black, M. (1962). Models and metaphors. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

Bond, T., & Fox, C. (2007). Applying the Rasch model: Fundamental measurement in the

human sciences, 2d edition. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Brown, T. (2003). Making truth: Metaphor in science. Champaign-Urbana, Illinois:

University of Illinois Press.

Bryman, A. (2007). Barriers to integrating quantitative and qualitative research. Journal

of Mixed Methods Research, 1(1), 8-22.

Bud, R., & Cozzens, S. E. (Editors). (1992). SPIE Institutes. Vol. 9: Invisible

connections: Instruments, institutions, and science (R. F. Potter, Ed.). Bellingham, WA: SPIE

Optical Engineering Press.

Butterfield, H. (1957). The origins of modern science. New York: The Free Press.

Caputo, J. D. (1997). A commentary. In J. D. Caputo (Ed.), Deconstruction in a nutshell:

A conversation with Jacques Derrida (pp. 31-202). New York: Fordham University Press.

Coleman, J. S. (1988). Social capital in the creation of human capital. American Journal

of Sociology, 94 (Supplement), 95-120.

Crease, R. (1993). The play of nature. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press.

Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2007). Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

20

Dawson, T. L., Fischer, K. W., & Stein, Z. (2006). Reconsidering qualitative and

quantitative research approaches: A cognitive developmental perspective. New Ideas in

Psychology, 24, 229-239.

Degen, R. J. (2009). Social network driven innovation. NEP: New Economics Papers:

Social Norms and Social Capital, Working Paper No. 47, globADVANTAGE Center of

Research in International Business Strategy, Leiria, Portugal. Retrieved 17 October 2009, from

http://www.globadvantage.ipleiria.pt/wp-content/uploads/2009/10/working_paper-

47_globadvantage.pdf.

Derrida, J. (2003). Interview on writing. In G. A. Olson & L. Worsham (Eds.), Critical

intellectuals on writing (pp. 61-9). Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.

Dunlop, M. J. (1986). Is a science of caring possible? Journal of Advanced Nursing,

11(6), 661-670.

Fielding, H. (2003). Questioning nature: Irigaray, Heidegger and the potentiality of

matter. Continental Philosophy Review, 36(1), 1-26.

Fisher, W. P., Jr. (1997). Physical disability construct convergence across instruments:

Towards a universal metric. Journal of Outcome Measurement, 1(2), 87-113.

Fisher, W. P., Jr. (1999). Foundations for health status metrology: The stability of MOS

SF-36 PF-10 calibrations across samples. Journal of the Louisiana State Medical Society,

151(11), 566-578.

Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2009). Invariance and traceability for measures of human, social, and

natural capital: Theory and application. Measurement, 42(9), 1278-1287.

21

Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2010). Reducible or irreducible? Mathematical reasoning and the

ontological method. In M. Garner, G. Engelhard, Jr., W. Fisher, Jr. & M. Wilson (Eds.),

Advances in Rasch measurement, Vol. 1 (pp. 12-44). Maple Grove, MN: JAM Press.

Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2011). Bringing human, social, and natural capital to life: Practical

consequences and opportunities. Journal of Applied Measurement, 12(1), 49-66.

Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2012). What the world needs now: A bold plan for new standards.

Standards Engineering, 64(3), 1 & 3-5 [http://ssrn.com/abstract=2083975].

Fisher, W. P., Jr., Harvey, R. F., & Kilgore, K. M. (1995). New developments in

functional assessment: Probabilistic models for gold standards. NeuroRehabilitation, 5(1), 3-25.

Fisher, W. P., Jr., Harvey, R. F., Taylor, P., Kilgore, K. M., & Kelly, C. K. (1995,

February). Rehabits: A common language of functional assessment. Archives of Physical

Medicine and Rehabilitation, 76(2), 113-122.

Fisher, W. P., Jr., & Stenner, A. J. (2011). Integrating qualitative and quantitative

research approaches via the phenomenological method. International Journal of Multiple

Research Approaches, 5(1), 89-103.

Fisher, W. P., Jr., & Wright, B. D. (Eds.). (1994). Applications of probabilistic conjoint

measurement. International Journal of Educational Research, 21(6), 557-664.

Fox, C. M. (1999). An introduction to the partial credit model for developing nursing

assessments. Journal of Nursing Education, 38(8), 340-6.

Gadamer, H.-G. (1989). Truth and method (J. Weinsheimer & D. G. Marshall, Trans.)

(Rev. ed.). New York: Crossroad.

Gadamer, H.-G. (1991). Plato's dialectical ethics: Phenomenological interpretations

relating to the Philebus. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press.

22

Gertler, M. S. (2010). Rules of the game: The place of institutions in regional economic

change. Regional Studies, 44, 1-15.

Goldberg, S. H. (2009). Billions of drops in millions of buckets: Why philanthropy

doesn't advance social progress. New York: Wiley.

Glazebrook, T. (2000). Heidegger's philosophy of science. New York: Fordham

University Press.

Hagquist, C., Bruce, M., & Gustavsson, J. P. (2009, March). Using the Rasch model in

nursing research: An introduction and illustrative example. International Journal of Nursing

Studies, 46(3), 380-393.

Hankins, T. L., & Silverman, R. J. (1999). Instruments and the imagination. Princeton,

NJ: Princeton University Press.

Heelan, P. A. (1983, June). Natural science as a hermeneutic of instrumentation.

Philosophy of Science, 50, 181-204.

Heelan, P. A. (1998, June). The scope of hermeneutics in natural science. Studies in

History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 29(2), 273-298.

Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time. New York: Harper & Row.

Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology and other essays. New York:

Harper & Row.

Heidegger, M. (1982). The basic problems of phenomenology (J. M. Edie, Ed.) (A.

Hofstadter, Trans.). Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press.

Holm, K., & Kavanagh, J. (1985). An approach to modifying self-report instruments.

Research in Nursing and Health, 8, 13-18.

23

Hunt, B. J. (1994). The ohm is where the art is: British telegraph engineers and the

development of electrical standards. In A. van Helden, & T. L. Hankins (Eds.), Instruments

[Special issue]. Osiris: A Research Journal Devoted to the History of Science and Its Cultural

Influences, 9, 48-63. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press.

Hunter, J. S. (1980, November). The national system of scientific measurement. Science,

210(21), 869-874.

Ihde, D. (1991). Instrumental realism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Ihde, D. (1998). Expanding hermeneutics: Visualism in science. Evanston, Illinois:

Northwestern University Press.

Ihde, D. (2012). Experimental phenomenology: Multistabilities (2nd Ed.). Albany, New

York: SUNY Press.

Irigaray, L. (1984). An ethics of sexual difference (C. Burke & G. C. Gill, Trans.). Ithaca,

New York: Cornell University Press.

Kritsotakis, G., & Gamarnikow, E. (2004, January). What is social capital and how does

it relate to health? International Journal of Nursing Studies, 41(1), 43-50.

Kuhn, T. S. (1961). The function of measurement in modern physical science. Isis,

52(168), 161-193. (Reprinted in T. S. Kuhn. (1977). The essential tension (pp. 178-224).

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.)

Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and

change. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press.

Kuukkanen, J.-M. (2011). I am knowledge. Get me out of here! On localism and the

universality of science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(4), 590-601.

24

Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago, Illinois: University of

Chicago Press.

Latour, B. (1987). Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through

society. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: An introduction to Actor-Network-Theory.

Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

Lauder, W., Reel, S., Farmer, J., & Griggs, H. (2006). Social capital, rural nursing and

rural nursing theory. Nursing Inquiry, 13(1), 73-79.

Lee, N. P., & Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2002). Evaluation of the Diabetes Self Care Scale.

Journal of Nursing Measurement, 10(3), 171-85.

Lewin, K. (1951). Field theory in social science: Selected theoretical papers (D.

Cartwright, Ed.). New York: Harper & Row.

Locsin, R. C. (1995). Machine technologies and caring in nursing. Image: Journal of

Nursing Scholarship, 3(27), 2101-203.

Locsin, R. C. (2005). Technological competence as caring in nursing, a model for

practice. Indianapolis: Sigma Theta Tau International Honor Society of Nursing.

Marion, J.-L. (1998). Reduction and givenness: Investigations of Husserl, Heidegger, and

phenomenology. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.

Marion, J.-L. (2007). The erotic phenomenon. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Moffatt, S., White, M., Mackintosh, J., & Howel, D. (2007). Using quantitative and

qualitative data in health service research - what happens when mixed method findings conflict?

Health Services Research, 6, 28.

25

Nersessian, N. J. (2002). Maxwell and "the method of physical analogy": Model-based

reasoning, generic abstraction, and conceptual change. In D. Malament (Ed.), Essays in the

history and philosophy of science and mathematics (pp. 129-166). Lasalle, Illinois: Open Court.

Nersessian, N. J. (2006). Model-based reasoning in distributed cognitive systems.

Philosophy of Science, 73, 699-709.

Nersessian, N. J. (2008). Creating scientific concepts. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT

Press.

O'Neill, T., Marks, C. M., & Reynolds, M. (2005). Re-evaluating the NCLEX-RN

passing standard. Journal of Nursing Measurement, 13(2), 147-165.

Plato. (1961). Theaetetus (F. M. Cornford, Trans.). In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.),

The Collected Dialogues of Plato, including the Letters (pp. 845-919). Bollingen Series LXXI.

Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

Price, D. J. d. S. (1986). Of sealing wax and string. In Little science, big science—and

beyond (pp. 237-253). New York: Columbia University Press.

Ricoeur, P. (1967a). Husserl: An analysis of his phenomenology (J. Wild, Ed.) (E. G.

Ballard & L. E. Embree, Trans.). Northwestern University Studies in Phenomenology &

Existential Philosophy. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press.

Ricoeur, P. (1967b). Violence et langage (J. Bien, Trans.). Recherches et Debats: La

Violence, 59, 86-94. (Rpt. in D. Stewart & J. Bien, (Eds.). (1974). Violence and language, in

Political and social essays by Paul Ricoeur (pp. 88-101). Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.

Ricoeur, P. (1981). Hermeneutics and the human sciences: Essays on language, action

and interpretation (J. B. Thompson, Ed. & Trans). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University

Press.

26

Risser, J. (1989). The two faces of Socrates: Gadamer/Derrida. In D. P. Michelfelder &

R. E. Palmer (Eds.), Dialogue & deconstruction: The Gadamer-Derrida encounter (pp. 176-

185). Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.

Royal, J. (2012). Evaluating human, social, and cultural capital in nurse education. Nurse

Education Today, 32, e19-e22.

Ruin, H. (2011). Seeing meaning: Frege and Derrida on ideality and the limits of

Husserlian intuitionism. Husserl Studies, 27, 63-81.

Schaffer, S. (1992). Late Victorian metrology and its instrumentation: A manufactory of

Ohms. In R. Bud & S. E. Cozzens (Eds.), Invisible connections: Instruments, institutions, and

science (pp. 23-56). Bellingham, WA: SPIE Optical Engineering Press.

Smith, E. V., Jr., Conrad, K. M., Chang, K., & Piazza, J. (2002). An introduction to

Rasch measurement for scale development and person assessment. Journal of Nursing

Measurement, 10(3), 189-206.

Stenner, A. J., & Smith III, M. (1982). Testing construct theories. Perceptual and Motor

Skills, 55, 415-426.

Stenner, A. J., & Stone, M. (2010). Generally objective measurement of human

temperature and reading ability: Some corollaries. Journal of Applied Measurement, 11(3), 244-

252.

Strickland, O. (2002). Editorial: Subdimensions and subscales in measurement and

instrument development. Journal of Nursing Measurement, 107(3), 167-9.

Sumner, J. (2001). Caring in nursing: A different interpretation. Journal of Advanced

Nursing, 35(6), 926-32.

27

Sumner, J. (2006). Concept analysis: The moral construct of caring in nursing as

communicative action. International Journal of Human Caring, 10(1), 8-16.

Sumner, J. (2008). Is caring in nursing an impossible ideal for today's practicing nurse?

Nursing Administration Quarterly, 32(2), 92-101.

Sumner, J., & Fisher, W. P., Jr. (2008). The moral construct of caring in nursing as

communicative action: The theory and practice of a caring science. Advances in Nursing Science,

31(4), E19-E36.

Toulmin, S. E. (1982). The construal of reality: Criticism in modern and postmodern

science. Critical Inquiry, 9, 93-111.

Watson, J. (1999). Postmodern nursing and beyond. New York: Churchill Livingstone.

Watson, J. (2009). Assessing and measuring caring in nursing and health science, 2nd

Ed.. New York: Springer-Verlag.

Wilson, M. (2005). Constructing measures: An item response modeling approach.

Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Wise, M. N. (1995). Precision: Agent of unity and product of agreement. Part III--"Today

Precision Must Be Commonplace." In M. N. Wise (Ed.), The values of precision (pp. 352-61).

Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

Woolley, A. W., Chabris, C. F., Pentland, A., Hashmi, N., & Malone, T. W. (2010).

Evidence for a collective intelligence factor in the performance of human groups. Science, 330,

686-688.

Woolley, A. W., & Fuchs, E. (2011). Collective intelligence in the organization of

science. Organization Science, 22(5), 1359-1367.

28

Wright, B. D. (1977). Solving measurement problems with the Rasch model. Journal of

Educational Measurement, 14(2), 97-116.

Wright, B. D. (1999). Fundamental measurement for psychology. In S. E. Embretson &

S. L. Hershberger (Eds.), The new rules of measurement: What every educator and psychologist

should know (pp. 65-104). Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Wynn, F. (2006). Art as measure: Nursing as safeguarding. Nursing Philosophy, 7, 36-44.

Zak, P. J. (Ed.). (2008). Moral markets: The critical role of values in the economy.

Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.