the father of all things - university of...

72
The Father of All Things? Hypotheses on the Effects of War on Democracy Prepared for Presentation at the International Studies Association Annual Convention San Diego, CA March 2006 Ronald R. Krebs Assistant Professor Department of Political Science University of Minnesota [email protected] *** PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE OR CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION***

Upload: others

Post on 30-Sep-2020

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

The Father of All Things? Hypotheses on the Effects of War on Democracy

Prepared for Presentation at the International Studies Association Annual Convention

San Diego, CA March 2006

Ronald R. Krebs Assistant Professor

Department of Political Science University of Minnesota [email protected]

*** PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE OR CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION***

Page 2: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

What effect do war and crisis have on the quality of democracy? Must polities choose

between security and liberty? How can they safely exercise emergency powers, addressing their

vital needs while preserving core democratic freedoms and the rule of law? These questions

loom large as Western governments, confronting the threat of terrorist attacks, have, in the name

of national security, claimed emergency powers and passed special legislation that have

expanded executive authority and increased the capabilities of intelligence agencies and the

police. Leaders with less dedication to liberal democracy, such as Russia’s President Vladimir

Putin, have exploited conflicts to undermine their countries’ already-shaky commitment to

liberal norms.

These matters, although obviously pressing today, have, with but few exceptions, failed to

penetrate political scientists’ research agendas. Western publics and politicians have since the

attacks of September 11, 2001, debated which liberties and whose liberties may be abridged and

which expanded. The U.S. Congress has recently renewed (and made permanent) the USA

Patriot Act, passed just weeks after September 11. Britain, Italy, and other European countries

have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention, and permissible speech as they

have become increasingly sensitive to the threat posed by militant Muslims at home. As these

developments mount, our discipline has been, with notable exceptions among scholars of public

law and political theory, strikingly silent. Students of international relations, comparative

politics, and American politics remain today as generally uninterested in exploring the domestic

(and even the international) consequences of war as in the past.1 This is puzzling, however, for

1 In recent decades, scholars of international relations have decried the lack of attention paid to the consequences of war, but with little apparent impact on the subfield or the discipline. See Rasler and Thompson 1992; Stein and Russett 1980; Thompson 1993. For a similar complaint about American politics, see Mayhew 2005.

Page 3: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 2

making sense of war’s effects, particularly its long-term effects, is of immense theoretical,

historical, and practical importance.2

Although political scientists have been slow to consider whether and how war exerts long-

run consequences on domestic societies and especially democratic governance, scholars rooted in

the disciplines of law, sociology, and history have long inquired into the domestic ramifications

of war. This article thus ranges broadly across disciplines to explore what questions have been

asked, how well they have been answered, and what silences persist. This interdisciplinary

dialogue reveals a number of well-established patterns, notably the positive impact of high levels

of war mobilization on democratic participation (expansion of voting rights, creation of

representative legislatures) and the negative impact of crisis and emergency on democratic

contestation (expansion of arbitrary executive power, diminution of civil liberties). Even more

striking, however, is how little we know about war’s long-term consequences, both empirically

and theoretically. Academic lawyers have devoted sustained attention to these questions, but

their central concern with formal law often misses critical informal forces; they have often drawn

lessons from the US case alone, missing potentially important variation; and their research,

notwithstanding its strengths, is often undertheorized, leaving crucial causal dynamics

underspecified and unexplored. Historical sociologists such as Charles Tilly have highlighted

how war mobilization has, in the European context and elsewhere, compelled governmental

authorities desperate for material and human resources to bargain with their populations. This is

an important insight, but it is only part of the story. Political scientists should have much to

contribute to a research area in which so much still remains to be learned.

2 If war were to have purely short-term effects on democracy, the findings would be less compelling. Variation in short-run effects might still call for explanation, but that task would seem to be of secondary importance.

Page 4: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 3

This article proceeds in six parts. The opening discussion speculates on why political

scientists have devoted so little attention to these questions. The second section presents two

traditions of thought on the consequences of war, and the third and fourth sections delve into

what existing research has to say respectively about the short-run and long-run ramifications of

wars for democratic participation and contestation. The fifth part advances a research agenda that

aims to address the lacunae within the existing literature. It lays out a series of hypotheses and

arguments about how the nature of the war, the character of the rights restrictions or expansions,

and features of the democratic regime—all factors that do not figure in existing accounts—may

shape the degree and persistence of wartime effects. It further argues that our causal accounts are

incomplete without theorizing the processes of rhetorical contestation that effectively frame a

crisis as such, that establish “national security” as a compelling justification for war-related

measures, that fix the nature and meaning of a given war, and that shape war’s effects on the

gendered political economy. The article concludes by discussing some policy implications.

The Consequences of War: The Lay of the Literature

“War,” wrote Arthur Stein and Bruce Russett in 1980, “is a major agent of change but a

neglected one” (Stein and Russett 1980, 399). Such neglect is not quite as pervasive today, but

one could hardly characterize the study of war’s consequences as a vibrant research program.

The reason does not lie in the subject’s lack of importance: few would deny that wars have often

served as “critical junctures” that transformed the participant societies’ economies, cultures, and

politics in ways that shaped their future development.3 One German veteran vividly depicted

World War I as “a gash [that] goes through all our lives. … With a brutal hand, it has torn our

lives in two. … Behind everything is the war. We will never be free of it” (Whalen 1984, 181- 3 On path dependence, see, among others, Mahoney 2000; Pierson 2004.

Page 5: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 4

82). Whether this conventional wisdom regarding individuals’ military experiences is accurate is

open to debate,4 but few would assert that large-scale wars are not capable of exerting such an

impact on the participant societies and polities.5

At least three explanations might be advanced to account for such relative neglect, but the

last is most persuasive. First, it has been suggested that assumptions about both the nature of war

and the purpose of social science may have combined to make the study of war’s consequences

seem fruitless at best and inappropriate at worst. War has widely been characterized, often

implicitly, as an episodic phenomenon, rather than as a regular process embedded in and

potentially transforming social life. Since positivist social science has generally concerned itself

with explaining regularities, it could contribute little to the understanding of so singular an event

as war, and the larger social scientific enterprise would make little progress by funneling

scholarly resources toward such research (Kasza 1996; Thompson 1993, 126). This explanation

may have some merit, but techniques adapted from the health sciences have boosted social

scientists’ capacity to analyze such rare events (King and Zeng 2001). More importantly, this

implies that social scientists should have refrained from studying the causes of war—an

endeavor to which they have seemed not at all hesitant to devote their intellectual energies.

Second, teasing out the consequences of war has posed daunting methodological challenges,

which may have scared off all but the most intrepid (or perhaps foolish) of scholars. The effects

of war might be temporary or permanent, they might follow directly or indirectly, and they might

display themselves immediately or only after some time. Nor have the effects of war distributed

themselves evenly across domestic populations (Thompson 1993, 125-26). Finally, isolating the

impact of war, as opposed to other events and long-term social processes, is necessarily a

4 For a critical view, in certain respects, see Krebs 2004. 5 See, however, Modell and Haggerty 1991.

Page 6: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 5

difficult task in complex societies: it would be hard to determine whether “wars involve real

discontinuities in historical development or … simply cause ripples in a basically continuous

process … that is fueled by other determinants” (Stein and Russett 1980, 418). Such concerns

may have played a role, but it is hardly clear that establishing the causes of war is any simpler.

Nor is it clear that one can more easily isolate the impact of other public policy choices, from

welfare to macroeconomics to education.

Third, and most convincingly, political scientists’ normative commitments have driven them

to focus on the causes of war, at the expense of research into its consequences. After the terrible

destruction of the two world wars and in the shadow of nuclear war, the overriding concern was

how to prevent a future catastrophe in which millions would again perish. International relations

theory has thus been inextricably linked to the causes of (global or total) war and peace.

Studying war’s consequences not only seemed less important, but also was potentially troubling.

War could most easily be prevented if it were widely viewed as being without any redeeming

value. It was consequently more comfortable to blame mad military leaders or expansionist

capitalist interests or pathological decision-making for seemingly senseless deaths than to

recognize war as a rational policy choice embraced by responsible statesmen. Similarly, the

discovery that war had desirable domestic ramifications—if it turned out to promote economic

growth or expand democratic citizenship—would run counter to the goal of delegitimizing it.6

There are of course important exceptions to this generalization. Across disciplines, scholars

have explored the effects of war on veterans’ economic prospects, social status, psychological

well-being, and even their capacity and will for political action (Mettler 2005; Modell and

Haggerty 1991). Research on defense spending and economic performance was especially

6 David Mayhew (2005) similarly argues that the lack of attention to war as a causal force in American politics was the result of a dominant liberal-Progressive historical narrative.

Page 7: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 6

vibrant as US military budgets climbed, but no clear consensus emerged regarding the net costs

or substantive significance of the defense burden (Sandler and Hartley 1995, 200-20). More

pertinent to this paper’s subject, scholars inspired by the German historian Otto Hintze (Hintze

1975) have, over the last 30 years, developed an impressive corpus on war and European state

formation and, to a lesser extent, the emergence of constitutional democracy (Downing 1992;

Porter 1994; Rasler and Thompson 1989; Tilly 1992), and others have recently explored whether

and how that analytical framework might yield insight into state-building in other regions and at

other times (Centeno 2002; Herbst 2000; Heydemann 2000; Katznelson and Shefter 2002;

Sparrow 1996). Others have examined the effects of war and militaries on the construction of

nations (Centeno 2002; Colley 1992; Krebs 2004; Smith 1981), and research, largely by

historians, has emerged on the role of war in shaping social memory (Blight 2001; Fussell 1975;

Winter 1995; Winter and Sivan 2000). Still more relevant, the relationship between war and

domestic conflict has attracted some concentrated attention, though empirical research remains

largely confined to the United States (Rasler 1986; Stein 1978; Stohl 1976). And, in recent years,

scholars have explored the impact of war on political leaders’ tenure in office (Bueno de

Mesquita and Siverson 1995; Bueno de Mesquita et al. 1992; Chiozza and Goemans 2003;

Goemans 2000). Finally, David Mayhew has recently urged scholars of American politics to

explore how wars have sparked policy change, inspired new issue regimes, shaken up electoral

coalitions, transformed ideological stances, and introduced new causal stories, but it remains to

be seen if others will take up that research agenda (Mayhew 2005).7

7 It is also worth noting that Mayhew’s insightful article hardly speaks about the effects of war on US democracy, outside the important areas of race and gender. Mayhew’s inductive arguments are also undertheorized, which he views as inevitable since “it is probably a mistake to invest in grand schematic explanations of American history that underplay contingency, and wars are hard to beat as bearers of contingency” (Mayhew 2005, 482).

Page 8: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 7

The quality and vibrancy of this scholarship is striking, yet the sheer quantity continues to

pale in comparison to other research programs. No political science department would feel

complete if it did not offer a class on the causes of war, yet few perceive a similar need to teach

courses on the consequences of interstate and intrastate conflict. It is, moreover, revealing that

neither of two prominent critical literature reviews saw fit to devote even a page to the potential

effects of war on democracy (Stein and Russett 1980, 418; Thompson 1993). Yet it is this topic

that has exercised scholars and pundits in the United States and around the world since the

terrorist attacks of September 11, 2001.

Two Traditions

While the postwar social sciences have in general devoted meager resources to exploring the

effects of war and war mobilization on liberal democratic structures and processes, these matters

have been, across the ages, a central concern of political thinkers, who have arrayed themselves

into two camps with views that are seemingly opposed.

1. The Garrison State. The “garrison state” tradition views liberal democracy as a luxury

afforded only by those living in relatively peaceful international environments. For Otto Hintze,

it was hardly accidental that the early democratizers, Great Britain and the United States, were

surrounded by water and weak neighbors and were relatively isolated from European great

power politics. The more threatened a state, the more powerful was its military and the more

absolute was its form of government; Prussia, surrounded by powerful states, was the epitome of

the militaristic authoritarian regime (Hintze 1975). Harold Lasswell famously argued during the

Second World War that constant war mobilization would exert similar effects in the twentieth

century. Even as formal democratic procedures and structures were retained, real power would

Page 9: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 8

increasingly lie in the hands of the technocratic managers of violence. The democratic republic

would be replaced by the “garrison state” (Lasswell 1941).8

From this perspective, war, particularly large-scale or total war, upsets two equilibria that lie

at the heart of liberal democracy: (1) the “balance” between state authority and national security,

on the one hand, and individual liberty, on the other; and (2) the “balance” among contending

state interests, functions, and branches. Especially since the American and French Revolutions,

ambivalent statesmen, scholars, and citizens have wrestled with the problem of executive power.

Republican thinkers recognized that the executive was, despite his title, more than a mere agent

of the people and that “necessity” would at times require that he be endowed with the power to

stretch the limits of law and on occasion even act outside it. They sought to design constitutional

arrangements that would give the executive enough authority to meet those pressing needs—and

no more (Mansfield Jr. 1989). During and especially in the wake of “emergency”—when the

executive openly seizes powers normally wielded only secretly, if at all, and often either

oversteps its bounds or proves hamstrung to the point of ineffectiveness—debates over the limits

of executive authority and appropriate constitutional design are rekindled. Such moments also

revive debates over the appropriate balance between security and liberty and over what kinds of

political and legal institutions would be best suited to discovering and maintaining that balance.9

As long-dormant disputes sprang up in the United States and elsewhere after September 11, they

revealed how little consensus has been forged.

The “garrison state” view has, since September 11, dominated academic, and, to an extent,

popular discourse. Supporters of the aggressive counterterrorist measures enacted in the United

8 Lasswell was of course wrong: despite his fears and despite the pressure of the Cold War, the United States did not become a “garrison state.” See Friedberg 2000. 9 See, among others, Breyer 2003; Ignatieff 2004a. For analyses of whether tradeoffs are actually necessary, see Donohue 2005a; Hardin 2004; Waldron 2003.

Page 10: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 9

States and Europe have argued that the attacks that day and since revealed that transatlantic

societies needed to revise those balances in light of Islamist threats from within and from

without. Opponents of such steps suggested, in a similar but more pejorative vein, that

democracies tend to abandon their own principles in times of crisis. As one scholar concludes,

“Experience shows that when grave national crises are upon us, democratic nations tend to race

to the bottom as far as the protection of human rights and civil liberties, indeed of basic and

fundamental legal principles, is concerned. Emergencies suspend, or at least redefine, de facto, if

not de jure, much of our cherished freedoms and rights” (Gross 2003a, 1019). Such accounts

typically draw persuasively on American history: the Alien and Sedition Acts, Lincoln’s

suspension of habeas corpus, restrictions on speech during and after World War I and the Red

Scare, the wartime interment of Japanese aliens and Japanese-Americans, McCarthy-era loyalty

oaths and investigations, and FBI activity during the Vietnam War. Machiavelli encouraged the

prince to foster an atmosphere of crisis so as to loosen conventional restraints (Mansfield Jr.

1989, 135-36), and the Left has similarly accused the Bush administration of manipulating the

politics of fear to seize unprecedented power (Robin 2004).

2. War and the Foundations of Democracy. In seemingly stark contrast, a second tradition,

rooted in historical sociology, portrays war, particularly total war, as a driver of democracy. The

turn to the mass army in nineteenth-century Europe required regimes to bargain with their

populations for human and material resources (military conscription and taxes), and the price for

their compliance (and even consent) was political representation and, in some cases, an extensive

welfare state. Intense war mobilization in the age of nationalism may be credited with the

creation of representative assemblies and the extension of citizenship (Dolman 2004; Mann

Page 11: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 10

1998; Tilly 1992; Titmuss 1969 [1958]).10 Stanislav Andreski famously argued that the “military

participation ratio”—what portion of the population was under arms—was the best predictor of a

country’s form of government: the higher the MPR, the more democratic the regime (Andreski

1954). Although these sociologists were inspired by Otto Hintze’s “bellicist” approach, the core

insight directly contradicted Hintze’s expectations, as he had suggested that maritime powers,

which had a relatively low MPR, were more hospitable to democratic governance, while land

powers, which had a relatively high MPR, were more likely to embrace authoritarianism (Hintze

1975, 214-15).

A related mechanism also points to the pro-democratic import of a high MPR. Western

norms, whose roots stretched back to ancient republican Greece and which had been preserved in

medieval militias, depicted military service as a sign of full membership in the political

community as well as evidence of worthiness for membership: military service thus made

available a categorical claim upon the state (Feld 1977; Janowitz 1976).11 As disenfranchised

populations invoked their participation in the armed forces, citizenship would broaden.

Substantial democratic advances consequently would not necessarily require high participation

ratios, but the higher the MPR, the more broadly available this rhetorical mode. Ironically, this

mechanism too could be traced to Hintze, who had argued that “whoever puts himself in the

service of the state must logically and fairly be granted the regular rights of citizenship” and thus

that universal service in particular was conducive to constitutional government and political

representation (Hintze 1975, 211). The mass army appears today to be in terminal decline in the

West, but the norm nevertheless continues to command rhetorical assent. In July 2002, as

10 Martin Shaw, however, argues that the consolidation of parliamentary democracy in the West came only after World War II and rested on state coercion and the international balance of power more than on the strength of domestic forces. Because the United States and its allies marginalized or defeated left-wing movements across Europe, postwar reform and reconstruction proceeded with little input from popular initiatives (Shaw 1988). 11 For more on the operation of this mechanism, see Krebs 2006.

Page 12: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 11

President George W. Bush announced that the thousands of non-citizens serving in the US armed

forces would immediately be eligible for naturalization, he proclaimed military service “the

highest form of citizenship.”12

A Synthesis? These two traditions are often cast as competing, but they are in fact

complementary. One solution might be to link them serially: David Rousseau and Bruce

Newsome thus suggest that political rights are reduced in wartime (a la the first tradition) but

expand in the postwar long run (a la the second tradition) (Rousseau and Newsome 2004). This

move is appealing, but its theoretical logic is unclear. Lasswell, for one, was more concerned

about war mobilization than war itself, and the emergence of the garrison state did not hinge on

the actual eruption of war.13 The resource-extraction model, meanwhile, would predict the

expansion of political rights during war, not afterwards: with the war’s conclusion, the state’s

resource needs would decline and so too would the pressure that the politically excluded could

muster.

The two traditions are in fact not as opposed as they seem at first glance, because they focus

on different dimensions of democracy. Democratic theory suggests that regimes might be

usefully viewed as lying along two continuums: (1) contestation: the extent to which political

opposition and competition is sanctioned and even protected, among those permitted to

participate in governance; and (2) participation: what proportion of the population can

meaningfully engage in contestation, however that system may be designed (Dahl 1971). Liberal

democracies (or what Robert Dahl calls “polyarchy”) rank high along both dimensions, illiberal

democracies allow many to participate in the political system but restrict the scope of their

involvement and impact, liberal authoritarian regimes observe the rule of law and permit

12 Address, 4 July 2002, www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2002/07/20020704-3.html, accessed 14 July 2004. 13 Lasswell foresaw that the twentieth century would be dominated by intensive and regular preparation for war, but was agnostic as to whether war would break out.

Page 13: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 12

relatively high degrees of political contestation but impose strict limits on who may participate,

and despotic regimes rank low along both dimensions.14 The garrison-state tradition captures

war-inspired limits on contestation, while the resource-extraction approach accounts for war-

driven expansions of participation. It is entirely conceivable that war and war mobilization might

have positive effects on one of these dimensions and negative effects on the other.15 These

processes need not move in tight lock-step. To cast war as entirely inimical or entirely beneficial

to democracy is, therefore, too simple.

Both traditions suffer from a common flaw, however. Clearly not all wars have equally

negative effects on participation and equally positive effects on contestation. The critical variable

in both accounts is the scale of war, with the greatest impact coming when war is total and war

mobilization extensive. As William Thompson summarizes the conventional wisdom: “The

impacts of war are primarily a positive function of the extent of societal mobilization, population

losses, and war duration and a negative function of distance from the battlefield” (Thompson

1993, 126-27).16 But to think that large effects are the product only of large causes is a classic

fallacy of causal reasoning (Fischer 1970, 177). Large consequences may emerge from more

modest beginnings, as social scientists informed by both complexity theory and path dependence

have argued (Jervis 1997; Pierson 2004, 18-19). System-altering wars often have been limited in

their stakes, intensity, and duration, and large-scale wars have sometimes had modest

international consequences (Bueno de Mesquita 1990; Levy 1990), and this insight should apply

equally to the domestic ramifications of war.17 It is consequently not obvious that the effects of

14 On the distinction between democracy and liberalism, see, among others, Zakaria 2003. 15 It is also conceivable that war might enlarge the zone of contestation or impose new limits on participation. Neither of the two existing approaches seems to allow for these possibilities. 16 Arthur Stein and Bruce Russett (1980, 401) similarly, but more cautiously, conclude: “Typically, it is assumed that larger wars are likely to manifest more consequences and effect more long-term changes.” 17 See Mayhew 2005, 480-81.

Page 14: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 13

total war on democracy are deeper or more pervasive along either or both dimensions. Nor is it

clear that the consequences of total war are longer-lasting: neither tradition cogently theorizes

when wartime policies are sticky, when they deepen, and when they are undone. In fact, I will

suggest below that total wars may have a deep and long-lasting impact on participation but only

a more mixed, and even short-term, effect on contestation; more limited wars, both interstate

conflicts and counterinsurgent/counterterrorist campaigns, may make a greater and more

enduring impression on contestation.

Scale is a powerful explanatory factor, but it is a crude one. By considering separately the

short-run and long-run effects of different kinds of war on these two dimensions of democracy,

participation and contestation, we can develop a more nuanced understanding of war’s effects.

This organizing scheme will guide the following survey of the more specific hypotheses offered

by literature from across several disciplines.

War and Democracy: Short-Run Consequences

Participation. Large-scale wars have, by many accounts, played a key role in opening up

political systems to excluded groups. Across nineteenth century Europe, states preparing to wage

war negotiated with recalcitrant populations to relinquish their hard-earned money to tax

collectors and their young men to the armed forces. The authorities initially employed coercion

to acquire these resources, but, as interstate competition intensified, they found this insufficient.

Governments with greater legitimacy could extract more resources less expensively and thus

compete more effectively on the international stage. Across Europe, more representative

parliamentary institutions were created, and voting rights were bestowed upon lower class males,

having previously been restricted to men of means and property (Dolman 2004; Tilly 1992, 96-

Page 15: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 14

126; Tilly 1995). Large-scale war similarly underpinned the modern welfare state: to secure

populations’ compliance with state demands on their resources, the scope of citizenship was

extended to new arenas of social life (Titmuss 1969 [1958]).18

Population groups whose peripheral status was maintained through gendered, ethnic, or racial

discourses also exploited the state’s dependence on their resources to work their way toward the

center. Women in England and the United States contributed to their national war efforts during

the First World War and won at least some gains in return. Their war work—extending, in

Woodrow Wilson’s words, “upon the very skirts and edges of the battle itself” (Flexner and

Fitzpatrick 1996, 302-03)—precipitated a major shift in public opinion on the suffrage question

in the United States and Britain (Graham 1996, 105, 46; Harrison 1978, 203-05). Similarly,

African-Americans made substantial strides only during and in the wake of large-scale war

(Klinkner and Smith 2000). Finding the Union stretched by the demands of the Civil War,

Abraham Lincoln issued the Emancipation Proclamation in 1863, and thousands of African-

Americans donned Union blue as a consequence; with the end of the war came constitutional

amendments ending slavery, recognizing blacks as citizens, and guaranteeing blacks the vote.

African-Americans, however, made little headway during a minor war against a declining

imperial power (the Spanish-American War) and a global war in which the US role was critical

but short-lived (World War I).

These efforts have born fruit unevenly, however, and they have not necessarily translated

into lasting gains. White American women attained the vote toward the end of World War I, but

they failed to make similar headway in the labor market after either world war. The United States

relied heavily on women’s industrial muscle, but gender nevertheless remained “an organizing

18 On the extension of citizenship’s scope, see Marshall 1950. Others, however, see more extensive public welfare provisions as the product of state initiative, not struggle from below (Shaw 1988).

Page 16: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 15

premise in the distribution of rights and responsibilities” (Ritter 2002, 203). Despite their

contributions during the Great War and despite the suffragists’ impressive prewar strength,

French women were even denied the vote, with motherhood (as a means of addressing wartime

“depopulation”) trumping emancipation (Hause 1987). In their sweeping analysis of African-

Americans’ struggle for rights, Philip Klinkner and Rogers Smith concede that large-scale war

was at most necessary, not sufficient, for African-American progress, and they identify as

equally critical an inclusive wartime rhetoric and an established protest vehicle (Klinkner and

Smith 2000).19

Contestation. The short-run effects of war on democratic contestation are also well-

established. There is little disagreement that wars tend to lead to the expansion of executive

authority, at the expense of other branches of government, and to the diminution of civil liberties.

That the executive branch expands in times of war and emergency, across all sorts of

regimes, is a truism. For Locke, Montesquieu, and the Federalists, “necessity” demanded the

creation of extensive, if always bounded and checked, executive authority. Assuring the state’s

physical security requires immediate action, and the deliberation typical of legislative politics is

a handicap to effective policymaking. It is widely believed that the executive branch is more

capable of acting with dispatch than standard or even accelerated legislative processes and better

capable of designing good policy under temporal and cognitive constraints.20 The intellectual

history of this assumption is imposing (Mansfield Jr. 1989), and it has deeply shaped the

contemporary debate over the prosecution of counterterrorist campaigns.21 The executive has a

19 Yet the “protest vehicle” was by no means as exogenous to the war experience as Klinkner and Smith imply. The NAACP was vastly strengthened by World War II (as it had been by World War I), and it maintained that strength into the late 1940s (unlike after WW I). In contrast, however, the French women’s movement, which had in 1914 gathered half a million to protest for suffrage, emerged from the war a shadow of its former self. 20 For critiques of this presumption, see Scheuerman 2003; Scheuerman 2005. 21 As Michael Ignatieff has recently revealingly written, “Checks and balances work slowly—Congress must deliberate; the courts must review—and meanwhile, the crisis calls out for decisive action. This is why terrorism’s

Page 17: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 16

possible further advantage in times of crisis because she can typically lay claim to the “national

interest” more credibly than can legislators beholden to parochial concerns,22 and the very

malleability of “necessity” as a category allows for its manipulation by executives desirous of

greater authority, as Machiavelli understood (Mansfield Jr. 1989, 135).23 For Carl Schmitt,

however, it was during crises that liberal regimes revealed their fundamental incoherence: as

they invoked emergency powers lodged in the executive, they dramatically demonstrated that

law was not king and that effective rule required domination, no matter how encircled with

formal constraints (Schmitt 1985).

The expansion of executive authority should not by definition be counted as a strike against

liberal democracy, however. Part of the process of constructing state capacity, more powerful

executives are perfectly consistent with liberal-democratic norms. More autonomous and

arbitrary executive power is not. Restraint of executive action hinges on other actors’ capability

for both review and enforcement. In the absence of either, the executive becomes increasingly

despotic. The expansion of arbitrary executive authority may be married to democracy—the

executive in the twentieth century became by some measures both more powerful and more

democratic (Scheuerman 2000, 1884)—but it is contrary to the spirit of liberalism.24 What is less

clear from the existing literature is why democracies do not expand arbitrary executive powers

uniformly in response to similar policy challenges.

chief impact on democracy … has been to strengthen the power of presidents and prime ministers at the expense of legislatures and courts and to increase the exercise of secret government” (Ignatieff 2004b). 22 Early in the Cold War, President Harry Truman and State Department officials were among the few in government pressing for race reform, for they most directly saw how much damage racial discrimination did to US foreign policy interests. See Borstelmann 2001; Dudziak 2000. 23 Interestingly, Stephen Holmes reads Machiavelli as seeing the foundation of the rule of law in the exigencies of war: “To achieve the social cohesion necessary for war, Machiavelli asserts, the elite must renounce its immunity and expose itself to legal challenges. This is how power politics, if the elite is sufficiently prudent, can incubate the rule of law” (Holmes 2003, 37). It should be obvious that political elites have rarely been so prudent. 24 For this understanding of constitutionalism (and liberalism), see Finn 1991.

Page 18: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 17

The most infamous effects of war that impinge on democratic contestation have come in the

realm of civil liberties. Throughout the transatlantic space, countries have revised their civil-

liberties baselines in the years since the September 11 attacks. Geoffrey Robertson, one of

Britain’s leading civil rights lawyers, put it well in July 2005: “It’s always the case that the flame

of civil liberties burns less brightly when surrounded by the smoke from bombed buses and tube

trains” (Lyall 2005).

The existing literature has perceptively explored the different motives and incentives

confronting both political elites who initiate restrictions on civil liberties in the face of threats as

well as mass publics who support these measures. Regarding elite motivations, there are three

notable reasons. First, elites might sincerely believe that restrictions on individual liberties

constitute a rational response to a new or rising threat. Recent British moves to prohibit the

“glorification of violence” may not effectively address young British Muslims’ alienation, but

the policy is clearly intended to silence radical preachers who have given this alienation violent

direction and at least inspired the July 2005 attacks on London’s transportation system. Second,

in the wake of attack, politicians are typically eager to demonstrate to their constituents that

something is being done to protect them. Politicians may care less about whether the resulting

policy bolsters state security than about whether it achieves substantial political benefits at

relatively low cost. Violating civil liberties may not necessarily provide much protection, but it

may bring political gain. This logic explains why politically weak population groups are common

targets of state action (Cole 2003a; Gross 2003a; Stuntz 2002). Perhaps the most salient example

here is the World War II internment of Japanese aliens and Japanese-Americans residing in the

continental United States in the weeks and months after Pearl Harbor. Third, and related,

mounting threats or recent attacks create opportunities to pursue political and institutional

Page 19: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 18

agendas utterly independent of the crisis. The attacks of September 11 opened political space,

less for discrimination against Muslim and Arab Americans, than for federal agencies’ pursuit of

powers long-denied them.25

Regarding public support for sacrificing civil liberties, two categories of causes have been

noted. Supporters of such measures typically portray public acceptance of particular restrictions

as a rational response to new threats. In August 2005 Prime Minister Tony Blair defended

aggressive new proposals by alluding to the previous month’s brutal Underground and bus

attacks: “For obvious reasons, the mood is now different. People do not talk of scaremongering”

(Cowell 2005).26 Opponents generally argue that mass support for emergency measures is rooted

in psychological dynamics, both “cold” cognition and “hot” emotion, especially fear (Gross

2003a, 28-31).27 Experimental research confirms that threat is a determinant of public attitudes

with regard to tolerance (Marcus et al. 1995; Sullivan et al. 1982). One post-9/11 study found

25 Although President Bush’s public rhetoric emphasized respect for Islam, the government conducted more intensive surveillance of Arab and Muslim immigrants, and the number of hate crimes directed at Arabs and Muslims rose dramatically (Gerstle 2003). 26 Academic literature, which tends to be critical of wartime measures, hardly considers this possibility. Observing domestic policies in response to threat that they deem poorly designed, legal scholars have ascribed public support to mass irrationality. Yet mass publics respond more rationally to events, including foreign policy, than traditionally thought (Page and Shapiro 1992; Zaller 1992). Moreover, rational mass publics may produce a policy that is irrational at the national level, since individuals may (rationally) pursue parochial ends. 27 Fear is greatest when confronting risks that are seemingly beyond one’s control and that are randomly distributed, and national security threats generally meet these criteria. Fear heightens the public’s sensitivity to threats, and fearful individuals are attracted to measures that claim to eliminate, rather than just moderate, the threat (Viscusi and Zeckhauser 2003). Fear may also lead individuals to focus on the “badness” of outcomes rather than on their likelihood, contributing to an excessive reaction to low-probability events and a willingness to pay high costs to reduce risks even by small degrees (Sunstein 2003). When fearful, the public is particularly tolerant of measures that restrict the civil liberties of peripheral populations and even of those that impinge on the citizenry as a whole. However, fear, at least in moderate doses, also improves the quality of decision-making, and some thus argue that it can prevent over-reaction and civil liberties violations (Posner and Vermeule 2003, 626-35). Even if this is true, to the extent that anxiety focuses attention and promotes learning, it destabilizes existing norms with regard to civil liberties and paves the way for their reconsideration (Davis and Silver 2004, 30). Moderate levels of fear appear, for good or for ill, to contribute to the revision of civil liberties baselines.

Page 20: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 19

that “each increase in the level of concern about another attack is associated with a 5-percentage

point decrease in support for civil liberties” (Davis and Silver 2004, 35).28

Oren Gross (2003) has, in a seminal article, persuasively argued that four “assumptions of

separation” have underpinned emergency measures.29 A temporal distinction—crisis vs.

“ordinary” times—seeks to assure publics that restrictions on democratic contestation are

temporary and will be rescinded as soon as the crisis has passed. The three other distinctions

emphasize that such measures are directed against “others.” A spatial distinction, distinguishing

between an “anomalous” zone (such as the Occupied Territories or Northern Ireland) and the

territorial state, pledges that such restrictions are confined geographically. A second spatial

distinction distinguishes between foreign territories (such as Guantanamo Bay or Afghanistan)

and domestic territories.30 Finally, a communal distinction dictates that measures be directed at

“them” rather than “us.” Gross observes that “the clearer the distinction between ‘us’ and ‘them’

and the greater the threat ‘they’ pose to ‘us,’ the greater in scope become the powers assumed by

government (with the cooperation of the legislature and frequent acquiescence of the courts) and

tolerated by the public” (Gross 2003a, 1037).31

The observation that one or more of these “assumptions of separation” has typically

undergirded anti-democratic or illiberal emergency measures rings true, but scholars have only

begun to inquire into the social and political conditions that make these assumptions seem

plausible. Gross (2003) has usefully challenged the presumption that these assumptions are

28 Yet this literature on the whole warns against overestimating the import of threats, since beliefs about whether a group is threatening are much less predictive than either an individual’s general tendency to see the world as a dangerous place or her standing commitments to tolerance and democracy (Marcus, et al. 1995). Trust in government, moreover, mediates between threat perception and support for further restrictions on civil liberties: those with greater trust in government are more willing to relinquish their freedoms (Davis and Silver 2004). 29 See also Hussain 2003, 135. 30 These “assumptions” are reflected in the International Law Association’s definition of “emergency”: see Chowdhury 1989, 24-29. 31 This distinction has been widely noted in the literature. See, among others, Cole 2002; Cole 2003a; Heymann 2003, 88-90; Hofnung 1996, 75; Stone 2004; Stuntz 2002.

Page 21: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 20

warranted or real: supposedly temporary measures have often become permanent, and the

geographic and communal borders meant to contain these measures are at times permeable.

However, explaining the long-run consequences of such measures, which will be taken up later,

must rest in part on explaining how and when the key distinctions between Here and There,

between Us and Them, and between Normal and Crisis Times are effectively established or

dissolved. These “assumptions” might be more productively viewed as rhetorical commonplaces

deployed to build public support for reducing civil liberties and expanding executive authority.

They are established and reproduced through rhetorical work that makes them seem natural, and

they are challenged through rhetorical action that reveals their arbitrariness. These categories are

deployed by some actors and resisted by others, and the ensuing contestation is critical to

whether these labels are successfully attached to people, places, and events. The categories

themselves thus must be problematized, and the political process through which the meaning and

boundaries of these categories are fixed calls for explanation.32

While the literature has usefully drawn attention to these “assumptions of separation,” it has

not systematically accounted for variation in the power and applicability of these commonplaces,

and explanations in given historical cases are at times unsatisfying. Much is often said to turn on

whether targets can plausibly be characterized as the “Other,’ but the criteria for plausibility are

rarely clear. It may seem obvious that so classifying Whig opponents of the Mexican War and

white critics of the occupation of the Philippines would be more challenging than trying to do the

same to ethnically identified German-Americans during the First World War and Japanese-

Americans during the Second (Graber 2005a). But many cases are more problematic. For

32 This is not, however, necessarily to adopt a stance in which everything is collapsed into discourse. One might advance any number of explanations—rooted in institutions, material power, the test of experience, and so on—to account for political outcomes ranging from effective challenge (and the failure to establish discursive hegemony) to silence (and the naturalization of the arbitrary).

Page 22: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 21

example, Geoffrey Stone maintains that the overt and covert repression of Vietnam protest was

relatively mild in historical terms in part because middle-class war protesters could not be easily

portrayed as “Other” (Stone 2003, 239). Yet Sixties protest was wrapped up with the

“counterculture”: the enduring image is that of the hippie, who consciously sought to distinguish

herself from the straight-laced Fifties generation and the “establishment.” There were, therefore,

seemingly sufficient grounds on which to classify Vietnam protesters as “Other.” That such

efforts either failed or were not even attempted requires explanation. The existing literature has

suggested what follows when labels stick, when they become essential to the discourse of the

times. But those consequences are predicated upon a prior process that is not nearly as well

understood—a process through which meaning is fixed and categories ascribed.

War and Democracy: Long-Run Consequences

If the anti-democratic and illiberal short-run consequences of war were delimited in time and

space, if expansions of executive authority and restrictions on civil liberties failed to persist

beyond the crisis, if the enlargement of the zone of democratic participation were short-lived,

then one might conclude, as many implicitly have, that studying the consequences of war and

war mobilization would be of little enduring value. War would then be merely a temporary

deviation from normal patterns. Perhaps not surprisingly, those who have devoted attention to

the study of the consequences of war and crisis have generally not reached this conclusion.

Participation. War may have long-term effects on democratic participation through a variety

of direct and indirect pathways. Findings here tend to be more suggestive than definitive, often

derived exclusively from the US experience and often limited to specific historical moments.

Page 23: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 22

1. Suffrage. Large-scale wars, and the concomitant pressures for resource extraction, have

yielded expansions in democratic participation that are self-reinforcing and thus particularly

persistent. The logic is straightforward and intuitive. When the vote is extended to previously

excluded populations, they acquire a powerful political resource. Ethnic or religious

communities, especially when they vote as a bloc, acquire protectors, have increased access to

publicity, and become a force to be reckoned with. It is obviously easier to refuse the political

rights of citizenship to the politically weak than to divest the recently empowered of those same

rights. Moreover, while liberal discourse can justify denying certain rights to certain groups—

e.g. convicted criminals, children—it is not clear how one might justify stripping large classes,

identified on ascriptive grounds, of rights of which they had previously been deemed worthy. In

this case, big wars do in fact have large and long-standing consequences.

2. Civil Society. Theda Skocpol and her collaborators have argued that large-scale wars boost

civic engagement, and they imply that such wars have the potential to bring large numbers into

the political system. The war’s outcome is seen as playing a crucial mediating role. Victorious

societies (or at least those identified with the winners) come away with renewed energy and will

for cooperation: civil society becomes more vital, and associational memberships rise

dramatically. However, the civic associations of defeated societies, such as the South after the

US Civil War, and of groups allied with the adversary, such as German-Americans after World

War I, stagnate or even decline after war, as members seek to downplay their unsuccessfully

realized identity. In Skocpol’s sophisticated account, the relationship between government and

civil society during war also has important implications for the specifics of the postwar

relationship, and state structure affects what kinds of organizations thrive and which languish.

But the thrust is that the scale and outcome of war are critical: total, victorious war bolsters civil

Page 24: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 23

society and expands democratic participation (Skocpol 1999; Skocpol et al. 2000; Skocpol et al.

2002).33 These conclusions are based only on US data, and very preliminary studies of other

national contexts suggest that they may not have responded in a similar fashion to the scale and

outcome of war (Kage 2005).

An implication of Skocpol’s work is that limited wars exert little impact on democratic

participation, but Bartholomew Sparrow has argued that Americans’ experience with limited war

since World War II, in Korea and Vietnam, had a large negative effect. Sparrow maintains that

these limited wars estranged Americans from government: they led to a decline in the federal

government’s legitimacy, in trust of the authorities, and thus in state capacity as well (Sparrow

2002). This is a provocative claim, but it is not fully persuasive as to the generalizable

consequences of limited war. As Sparrow himself admits, his indicators of declining political

consent may be problematic; some, such as the rising incidence of conscientious objection, may

capture legitimacy less than they do other trends, such as a secular increase in youth’s

willingness to challenge authority, which may be more closely related to economic prosperity.

Even if Sparrow is correct, however, that state legitimacy has suffered since Korea, did the

absence of trust in government derive from the wars’ limited natures or from the fact that the

military and civilian authorities had in Vietnam sought to mislead the public? This image of

duplicitous Washington insiders was reinforced by the Watergate fiasco. Would Americans

would have lost faith in government if those in government had behaved more honorably, no

matter what the war’s outcome? It would seem difficult to dismiss this critical counterfactual.

33 Questions might be raised about Skocpol’s interpretation of the data and whether broader long-terms trends, such as industrialization and economic growth, played a greater role in shaping associational life. Moreover, while Skocpol attributes post–Civil War patterns of associational life in the North and South respectively to victory and defeat, the postwar data are perhaps equally well explained by prewar and postwar levels of urbanization and population density. Finally, while Skocpol’s explanation for these effects of war is explicitly psychological, it is not well grounded in actual psychological dynamics. Nevertheless, the research is suggestive and persuasive.

Page 25: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 24

To be fair, Sparrow does not frame his argument in terms of participation, but one might

reasonably infer that alienation leads to political disengagement. Yet, even if Sparrow is correct,

the effects of the Vietnam War on democratic participation, and on the quality of democracy

more broadly, were complex. The war was a disruptive force, shattering the Cold War consensus,

and perhaps producing alienation among Americans. But the war also thereby created space for

broad-based dissent: it prompted new social movements and allowed new voices into the public

arena. In the late 1960s African-Americans were increasingly frustrated and alienated, and they

embraced violence, but by the mid-1970s most had again turned to more conventional means of

contention, participating within the system. The press grew distrustful of government during

Vietnam—with good reason!—but it also became a more independent force. And the 26th

Amendment to the Constitution extended the vote to all those over the age of eighteen. Given

these cross-cutting effects, it is not at all clear that this limited war was on balance harmful to

democratic participation. Nor is it clear that these effects, positive or negative, inhered in the

limited nature of these wars (structure), rather than in the choices of political actors (agency).

These scholars of American political development have suggested that wartime experiences

have directly affected the quality of civil society in the United States. Insofar as a vibrant civil

society is necessary (but undoubtedly not sufficient) for a healthy democracy, exploring these

connections is a vital task.34 Far more work remains to be done to ascertain what precisely are

the ramifications of the scale and outcome (as well as other features) of war for civil society,

both in the United States and elsewhere.

3. Gender. The introduction of women into the political system in many countries, most

directly by the extension of the vote, has represented the greatest expansion of democratic

34 As Sheri Berman has pointed out, Weimar Germany had a remarkably vibrant civil society, but its anemic democratic institutions failed to weather economic dislocation and easily gave way to Nazi domination (Berman 1997).

Page 26: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 25

participation in the twentieth century in already consolidated democracies. Has this expansion

occurred thanks to war, despite war, or completely independent of war?

War has, for much of human history, been the province of men (Goldstein 2001), and it has

served to sustain a gendered discourse of masculine warriors and female “beautiful souls”

(Elshtain 1987).35 In ancient Greece and then continually over the ages, the performance of

military service has been seen as evidence of civic virtue, and such civic virtue has been proof of

one’s worthiness for membership in the political community and thus for the rights of

citizenship. But those deemed appropriate for the performance of such communal obligations,

and thus deserving of political rights, were men and most often men of “substance.” Where the

discourse of citizenship has been dominated by such a militarized republicanism, war has served

to reinforce women’s peripheral political status. As Linda Kerber has noted with regard to early

America, “The connection between the republic and male patriots—who could enlist—was

immediate. The connection between the republic and women—however patriotic they might feel

themselves to be—was remote” (Kerber 1998, 240). Women’s claims for political and other

rights could be, and were, turned aside as men invoked this citizenship discourse. As a delegate

to the 1879 California constitutional convention put it, “What is political sovereignty? It is the

fruits of the sword,” and women had not taken up weapons in the nation’s defense (Keyssar

2000, 192-93).36

Women have of course hardly been peripheral to war, even when they have been peripheral

to the political system. As Jean Elshtain observes, they have been “drawn into the picture: as

occasions for war; as goads to action; as designated weepers over the tragedies war trails in its

wake; or, in our own time, as male surrogates mobilized to meet manpower needs for the armed

35 There have of course been many exceptions among members of both sexes, yet they have been discursively marginalized. See Elshtain 1987, 163-225; Goldstein 2001, 59-127. 36 For similar arguments, in the British context, see Harrison 1978, 73-78.

Page 27: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 26

forces” (Elshtain 1987, 58). As industrialized societies came to terms with the realities of total

war in the twentieth century, women were called upon to support the war effort, not in their

traditional roles as camp followers, but as members of the industrial work force. In the United

States and the United Kingdom, women’s contributions in World War I imparted new impetus to

their standing suffrage movements,37 and French women, denied the vote after the First World

War, gained it after the Second “by means of their heroic actions in the Resistance, [which]

demonstrated that they could no longer legitimately be considered minors on the political scene”

(Jenson 1987, 279). Overall, however, women’s postwar experiences in the United States and

Europe were bitter, as reality fell short of feminists’ grander aspirations regarding women’s place

in the public sphere and the industrial economy (Chafe 1972). Women were discursively once

again confined to the private sphere—handcuffed to maternal and nurturing roles. Their wartime

sacrifices were treated as emergency measures, aberrations from the usual and normatively

desirable path, and thus women were not able to sustain their wartime gains. More often than

not, war has simply reinforced standing gender norms that shape the distribution of public rights

and responsibilities (Higgonet et al. 1987; Ritter 2002).

Historically, war has rarely played a transformative role with regard to gender roles.38 The

question is whether this is a necessary feature of war or whether war might conceivably act as a

more progressive force. Those who support equality for women in the armed forces often imply

that war and military service can in fact be placed in the service of the feminist cause. Joshua

Goldstein, however, suggests that the masculinization of war has been functional for the creation 37 There is much disagreement about the role World War I played in helping American and British women attain the vote. For the view that the war played a critical role, see Evans 1989, 170-72; Flexner and Fitzpatrick 1996, 278-319; Keyssar 2000, 215-21. Others argue that this undervalues the suffrage movement, which was increasingly well organized during the first two decades of the twentieth century; for this view, see Banaszak 1996; DuBois 1998, 272. 38 Wartime and postwar discourses appear to have reinforced existing gender constructs. But that causal effect has been barely perceptible, because showing that postwar gender roles were more stable or more powerful than prewar gender roles, as the notion of “reinforcement” suggests, is in practice extraordinarily difficult, if not impossible.

Page 28: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 27

of motivated warriors willing to sacrifice themselves (Goldstein 2001, 251-301). Yet even if

Goldstein is correct, it does not foreclose the possibility that the very notion of warriorhood

might be reconceptualized in a gender-free fashion. To pacifists of both sexes, this is of course

anathema, and they decry the increasingly prominent combat or combat-equivalent roles women

are playing in many Western armed forces. Yet discourse changes only very slowly, as the

coverage of Private Jessica Lynch’s capture and rescue in Iraq has revealed.

4. The Welfare State, Inequality, and Economic Growth. Large-scale war, thanks to now

familiar bargaining dynamics, underpinned the formation of the modern welfare state: the scope

of citizenship was extended to new arenas of social life to secure populations’ compliance with

state demands on their resources (Titmuss 1969 [1958]). These new institutions took shape in the

short run, but they had important long-run effects on participation. Programs to provide public

health, public education, and assistance for the impoverished and disabled sought to ensure at

least some minimally acceptable standard of living, but they were also a modest way of

redistributing wealth and reducing economic inequality. The poor and the uneducated participate

less regularly and intensively in democratic politics than do the relatively wealthy and educated

(Schlozman et al. 2005), and the welfare state consequently increased populations’ capacity to

exercise their political voice: it contributed modestly to leveling the economic and, in the long

run, the political playing field. The messages implicit in these programs’ design also had the

potential to shape citizens’ conception of their role in the polity, and these “interpretive” effects

could boost their will to participate in civic institutions (Hacker et al. 2005, 32-57). These

indirect long-run effects appear to be powerful and persuasive, but they depend on the

extensiveness of the welfare state and the corresponding redistribution of wealth.

Page 29: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 28

If there is any systematic relationship between war and economic growth, it may also have

indirect long-term consequences for participation, for related reasons. If high levels of defense

spending (due to arms racing and intensive war preparation) promote growth through spillover

effects,39 then over the long run it may boost participation. If, however, as many contended later

in the Cold War, the cost of defense becomes a net drag on the economy, by crowding out other

forms of investment, it may depress participation. Focusing in turn on demand and supply,

theoretical models have yielded no clear answer, and the empirical findings have been mixed.

One even-handed review concludes that “the net impact of defense on growth is negative, but

small” (Sandler and Hartley 1995, 220), and another, while unsure about the direction of the

effect, agrees that either way it is “relatively modest” (Payne and Sahu 1993, 14).

Even if this ambiguity is resolved, however, and even if the effects are discovered to be

substantively significant, the implications for participation are sure to be marginal. Absolute

levels of growth matter less for participation than does the degree of inequality, and defense

spending, while perhaps important to the former, has little impact on the latter.40 Social policy,

however, which shapes (but hardly determines) the distribution of income and wealth, has the

capacity to diminish or boost participation. For example, the GI Bill, in part by making

vocational training and a college education affordable for millions of middle- and working-class

Americans, created a generation that has been hailed for its impressive commitment to civic

endeavors (Mettler 2005). Economic inequality underpins political inequality, and rising

economic inequality in the United States since the 1970s has undercut the “rights revolution” that

39 For a recent important contribution to this continuing debate, see Ruttan 2006. 40 A related debate focuses on the relationship between economic performance and democracy. Adam Przeworski and various colleagues have claimed that there is no relationship between economic growth and the emergence of democracy; Carles Boix and others have defended this insight into the effects of modernization. Both, however, measure democracy dichotomously and, at least in part due to the limitations of existing data, eschew more subtle claims about the effect of economic performance on the quality of democratic participation and contestation. See Boix 2003; Boix and Stokes 2003; Przeworski, et al. 2000; Przeworski and Limongi 1997.

Page 30: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 29

promised to level the political playing field. Political participation in the United States continues

to be stratified along the lines of race, ethnicity, and gender—in line with patterns of

stratification in education, employment, and income (Hacker et al. 2005; Schlozman et al. 2005).

In short, long-term economic growth would not seem a consequential path by which war and war

preparations affect democratic participation, even over the long run.

Contestation. Whether wartime expansions of executive authority and restrictions on civil

liberties persist beyond the end of the conflict, paving the way for deeper and broader changes in

the future, is among the most intensely debated questions in the existing literature. Little

agreement has emerged regarding either the empirical patterns or the theoretical logic.

Optimists, comprised largely of legal scholars drawing from the US experience, argue that

there is a silver lining to the United States’ history of wartime restrictions on civil liberties: these

experiences have contributed to the development of a rights-protective jurisprudence that has

constrained government in future conflicts.41 These scholars depict American decision-makers

and jurists as undergoing a process of progressive social learning: wartime violations, though

excused at the time, have invariably been viewed afterwards with regret and even disdain, and

wartime cases have served not as precedents for further violations, but rather as cautionary tales,

prime examples of what should not be done (Cole 2004a; Goldsmith and Sunstein 2002;

Rehnquist 1998; Stone 2004; Tushnet 2003; Wood 2003).

In each successive crisis, these scholars argue, US performance with regard to civil liberties

and executive authority has improved. Regretted restrictions on freedoms have never been

repeated, and arbitrary executive authority has gradually been tamed. In wartime US authorities

have increasingly relied on statute rather than unlegislated executive powers, turned to the courts

41 It is generally presumed that powerful precedent is normatively desirable. But legal hurdles might also be set too high, and a government careful to observe legal norms would find its hands tied—with potentially disastrous results.

Page 31: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 30

rather than administrative justice, and refrained from overt suppression of criticism and dissent

(Rehnquist 1998, 219-21). From this perspective, the Bush administration’s actions since

September 11 have been restrained by historical standards. As Jeffrey Rosen concludes, “Perhaps

the real story after Sept. 11 is that America hasn’t yet come close to abandoning any immutable

principles or its national identity” (Rosen 2001). Post-9/11 measures were not as severe as

initially feared, and more ambitious administration initiatives provoked a bipartisan chorus of

criticism, rather than the usual acquiescence (Spiro 2005). Some credit evolving social attitudes

protective of individual liberty (Goldsmith and Sunstein 2002), others the power of judicial

precedent to shape cultures of liberty and support freedom’s organizational advocates (Cole

2004a, 2582-84), and others international constraints (Spiro 2005). But, despite disagreements as

to particular causes, there is agreement with regard to the trend lines.

Critics, however, maintain that the United States has made the same mistakes, broadly

speaking, in each successive crisis (Bollinger and Stone 2002, 8; Brennan Jr. 1987, 1; Cole

2003b, 5). More cynically, David Cole has argued that past experience has taught governing

authorities an important lesson: how to evade future constraints (Cole 2003a, 88-158; Cole and

Dempsey 2002, 71-89).42 A quantitative study of US Supreme Court decisions found no

evidence for the alleged “ameliorative” trend (Epstein et al. 2005). Moreover, even if this

optimistic narrative were true of the United States, it is not clear that the US experience is

generalizable.43 The United States has been exceptionally fortunate to have faced no serious

home-grown competitors in its hemisphere and to have endured no foreign threats to its survival

42 Oddly, however, Cole has elsewhere hailed the power of judicial precedent as a constraint on government policy and articulated the optimistic narrative. See Cole 2004a; Cole 2004b. 43 In fairness, these scholars have not suggested that the US experience is typical. Since these works are generally light on theory, it is not clear on what basis one could or could not extend their arguments to other countries.

Page 32: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 31

since at least the middle of the nineteenth century. Similar studies regarding other states’

wartime and postwar experiences and jurisprudence are few and far between.

At the theoretical level, many aspects of the optimistic narrative are underdeveloped. First,

the optimists display a mysterious attitude toward the power of precedent. On the one hand, they

are implicitly unconcerned about pusillanimous wartime judicial rulings, since these will have no

long-term negative effect on rights jurisprudence. Justice Robert Jackson famously warned

during World War II that wartime opinions would lie about like a loaded gun, waiting to be fired

at some unsuspecting and innocent soul. Yet, as the optimists point out, the infamous Korematsu

decision upholding the internment of Japanese-Americans, from which Jackson was dissenting,

has not been cited as guiding precedent in the over 60 years since it was handed down.44 On the

other hand, their argument is in fact predicated on normatively desirable precedent proving so

powerful that it constrains decision-makers confronted with imposing threats.

Second, the optimists claim that rights restrictions are not self-reinforcing but rather can

touch off a backlash,45 but the conditions under which such path-dependent processes occur are

left unspecified. In fact it is strongly suggested that such processes always occur, at least in the

United States, after war or crisis. Yet the evidence to the contrary, in the United States and

elsewhere—as emergency laws remain on the books or are approved as permanent legislation, as

new means are found to violate old freedoms—is too great to sustain a case for invariance.

Third, and related, the process by which a postwar consensus emerges critical of wartime

policy and protective of the violated rights is never spelled out. Some, true believers in the

judicial faith, imply that it is largely the product of judges calmly reflecting upon history in their

44 While the optimists do appear to have a point with regard to the well-known Korematsu decision, the more obscure case of Quirin, regarding the dispensation of military justice against Nazi saboteurs during World War II, has been cited in support of the Bush administration’s policy on military tribunals. 45 On such processes in general, see Mahoney 2000, 526-35; Pierson 2000, 85-86.

Page 33: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 32

chambers (Cole 2004a). Yet so apolitical a process ignores the competition waged in the public

sphere to impart meaning to events, and it particularly overlooks the role that both an outraged

civil society and the state have played in forging social memory. The story of increasing

American rights consciousness cannot be told without reference to the American Civil Liberties

Union. That example itself suggests the possibility of a backlash against government over-

reaching, for the ACLU was founded in direct response to World War I and the Red Scare

(Murphy 1979). Yet what promotes or inhibits such mobilization against wartime practice? A

causal account more sensitive to both variation and politics would seek to address this question,

but the optimists do not.

In contrast, pessimists argue that the exception is hardly exceptional, that there is a marked

tendency for the “assumptions of separation” to break down and for emergency to “bleed” into

normal politics. War and crisis, by this account, cast an exceedingly long shadow. The evidence

on behalf of the pessimists’ account, particularly with regard to emergency powers that in many

countries have grown nearly permanent, is overwhelming. But such accounts are less satisfying

when it comes to explanation in general and to explanation of variation in particular.

Emergency powers are sustained by the distinction between “ordinary” and “crisis” times,

yet the reality of protracted crisis has rendered the distinction meaningless (Chowdhury 1989,

43-55; Finn 1991, 134; Gross 2003a). Israel has, since its founding, operated under an effectively

permanent state of emergency (Hofnung 1996). In the United Kingdom, the Prevention of

Terrorism (Temporary Provisions) Act was rushed through Parliament in 1974 and renewed

annually with little controversy until 1998, when permanent legislation of a similar nature was

easily passed (Finn 1991; Sim and Thomas 1983). In Sri Lanka, the temporary too has become

permanent (Coomaraswamy and Reyes 2004). Even in the United States, the Church

Page 34: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 33

Commission famously warned in 1974 that “emergency government has become the norm,” that

citizens were scarcely aware of the nearly continuous emergency regime that had supplied key

aspects of governance since 1933 (Relyea 1974). Finally, the bulk of the USA Patriot Act was

rendered permanent less than five years later, after the addition of only slight, and by many

accounts ineffective, civil liberties protections.

Emergency powers thus seem to display positive feedback (Mahoney 2000, 515-26; Pierson

2004), but explanation requires that we identify the mechanisms through which these institutions

are reproduced (Thelen 1999, 390-92). As Amy Bridges suggests, “we need to problematize

stability, not assume it. How do institutions or regimes sustain themselves? Some regimes and

institutions have more staying power than others” (Bridges 2000, 110). Understanding the

mechanisms of reproduction is essential for explaining variation, which is a notable weakness of

the existing literature on emergency powers.46

The literature suggests, but does not sufficiently develop, two mechanisms. First, Oren Gross

(2003, 1093) has noted that governments rarely willingly part with their new powers and that the

temptation to apply emergency regulations and legislation to non-emergency situations is

immense. Indeed, in Israel in the 1970s, as legislative deadlock prevented formal legislation to

reform the economy or control labor upheaval, emergency provisions were regularly employed,

without any legislative involvement and in clear violation of their intent, to manipulate rates of

exchange and contain labor disputes (Hofnung 1996). While Gross presents this only as an

empirical claim, implicit is that emergency powers often create new institutional interests in their

perpetuation. This is certainly consistent with approaches emphasizing that institutions tend

toward stability because they mirror the distribution of social and material power (Mahoney

46 An exception here is Laura Donohue’s insightful discussion of how and when temporary emergency powers became permanent with regard to Northern Ireland (Donohue 2001, ch. 7). The discussion of this question is the next section draws in part on Donohue’s analysis, while placing it within a broader analytical framework.

Page 35: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 34

2000, 521). If restrictions on civil liberties tend to fall disproportionately on the politically weak

and marginal, it is hardly surprising that such restrictions tend to reproduce themselves. Far-

sighted politicians might recognize the virtues of sunset clauses in compelling regular

reconsideration of such measures, but the pervasiveness of short time horizons and the potential

for political pain make it unlikely that politicians will deem it worth their while to conduct a

searching review—unless the balance of power changes and the previously marginalized have,

against all odds, climbed into positions of relative influence.47

Second, temporary institutions might become permanent if these new institutions came to be

seen as legitimate (Mahoney 2000, 523-25). Students of emergency powers have often claimed

that the public “renormalizes,” that it grows less critical over time as these powers have a

“tranquilizing” effect. Oren Gross thus forecasts increasing “dosages” of emergency power, and

Andrew Arato perceives cycles resulting in increasingly authoritarian emergency regimes (Arato

2002; Gross 2003a). Indeed it is clear that “normalizing the extraordinary” is something to which

governments eager to extend their reach often aspire. The Bush administration has tried to make

new surveillance, intelligence-gathering, and arrest powers appear as just another “mode of

governance” (Shapiro 2002, 63). Leading administration figures, including Secretary of Defense

Donald Rumsfeld and Vice President Dick Cheney have thus cast the post-9/11 period as “the

new normal.”48 It is also clear that sometimes this has in fact worked. During a rare debate in the

House of Commons on renewal of the Prevention of Terrorism Act, one MP noted that “the

power to detain suspects, which produced a shock on both sides of the House in 1974, now

hardly causes an eyelid to flutter” (Sim and Thomas 1983, 75).

47 It is, therefore, possible to explain why rational law-makers might not insert sunset provisions without relying on the psychology of fear—pace Posner and Vermeule (2003, 616-618). 48 For examples, see Lawyers Committee for Human Rights 2003.

Page 36: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 35

What is less clear is the theory underlying such renormalization. Gross’ (2003) reliance on a

medicinal metaphor (dosage, tranquilizer) suggests some sort of physiological reaction that is

obviously not at work. Even more troubling, he further implies that such efforts work uniformly

(which they do not), that efforts to legitimate new powers go uncontested (which is sometimes,

but often not, the case), and that the targets of rhetorical appeals are passive and manipulated

receivers (which deprives the audience of any meaningful agency). One possible mechanism is

psychological: the need to resolve cognitive dissonance suggests that individuals bring their

beliefs, expectations, and even desires into accord with their behavior. This would also support

the intuitive hypothesis that renormalization is more likely the longer the restrictive legislation

and regulations have been on the books. Yet the imperative to reduce cognitive dissonance vastly

overpredicts renormalization, and it cannot account for the very real post-crisis revulsion

identified by the optimists. Pessimists must persuasively explain why adaptive preference

formation is more likely than contrarian preference formation (Posner and Vermeule 2003, 619-

20), and the optimists must do the reverse. Without a well-developed theory, neither can. It

would be foolish to deny the possibility (or reality) of either renormalization or backlash, and

thus what is needed is an analytical framework that allows for both.49

Similar problems bedevil the pessimists’ observation that the promises of authorities—what

goes on over there, in the anomalous zone, will not affect the liberties over here, in the national

territory; what is done to “them,” at home or abroad, will not be done to “us”—are often broken.

49 It is of course also possible that temporary institutions might become permanent as the product of a rational cost-benefit assessment, yet this possibility is not well explored in the existing literature, perhaps because scholars have (without justification) presumed that the pre-crisis status quo is optimal. However, whenever institutions entail large fixed costs, lead to higher returns from continuing use, exhibit positive network externalities, and produce adaptive expectations, path dependence kicks in (Pierson 2004, 24). Thus the perceived efficacy of counterterrorism legislation in Britain paved the way for its effortless renewal and eventual replacement by parallel permanent law. The legislation’s conformity with existing legal norms—it generally imposed increased penalties, based on motive, for crimes already prohibited—implied increased benefits at little additional cost (Donohue 2001, 308-16). In Israel, emergency provisions have become so intertwined with primary legislation and are so essential to the everyday legal system that dispensing with them would invite legal chaos (Hofnung 1996, 49-50).

Page 37: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 36

Specific violations of non-citizens’ freedoms have a tendency to travel across physical

boundaries and, sooner or later, are applied to citizens as well (Cole 2003a, 85-179; Gross 2003a,

1085). What is done to resident aliens or peripheral citizens today is a dangerous precedent for

what can and will be done to the core citizenry tomorrow (Cole 2002; Gross 2003a). Examples

include the application of the 1798 Enemy Aliens Act to US citizens of Japanese descent during

World War II, of techniques used against alien radicals during the first Red Scare to victims of

McCarthyite witch-hunts, and of military tribunals in the current war on terror to US citizens as

well. The right to silence, of which residents of Northern Ireland alone were initially deprived in

terrorist cases, was eventually lost to citizens in mainland Britain as well. Along similar lines, an

Arab Knesset member warned, in protesting the mistreatment of Israel’s Arab citizens,

“Restrictions on the rights of a national minority will come to harm the democracy and the

freedom of the state’s residents. It is impossible to divide democracy and freedom” (Osatsky-

Lazar 2002, 116).

Bleeding across spatial and communal boundaries has clearly occurred in the past and is of

much concern for the future.50 Yet the literature does not go nearly far enough to specify the

conditions under which such spillover occurs. Certainly US authorities had many opportunities

between 1798 and 1942 to apply the Enemy Aliens Act to citizens, but they did not. For the

causal claim to be persuasive, such lags and the many opportunities foregone must be explained.

A Research Agenda: Or, What Political Scientists Can Teach Lawyers—and Vice Versa

In part, simply more empirical research is needed on the effects of war on democracy in

particular countries: the existing literature focuses excessively on the US, British, and, to a lesser

extent, Israeli cases. That literature also does not take sufficient note of variation among even 50 For a skeptical view, however, see Tushnet 2003, 297-98.

Page 38: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 37

these countries, and thus more empirical research of a truly comparative nature is also required.

Finally, as the preceding discussion has emphasized, the legal literature also suffers from

inadequate theorization and specification. This portion of the essay advances possible answers to

many of the questions raised in the preceding sections and thus seeks to guide future empirical

research. The discussion proceeds in four parts, each focusing on a set of variables or processes

that has not received sufficient attention in the existing literature.

1. Features of the War: Scale, Duration, Nature, Meaning

a) Scale and Duration. The existing literature does of course consider one critical feature of

the war: scale. Large-scale, or total, wars are expected to lead to more liberty-restrictive policies,

and such wars are at the same time expected to produce the most pronounced progressive effects

on participation. More limited wars entail less extraction and thus less democracy-promoting

bargaining, but they also generate less pressure on governments to limit freedoms.

These claims seem intuitive when limited to the short run, but in the long run, the effects of

scale point in different directions. Increases in democratic participation tend to be self-

reinforcing, and thus the pro-democratic impact of total wars tends toward lock-in. However,

because total wars are also explicitly framed as deviations from the norm, their discourse

accentuates the boundaries between wartime and peacetime, delivering an advantage to those

who would, upon war’s conclusion, demand a return to prewar norms. Their case is further

strengthened by the fact that high levels of mobilization are not indefinitely sustainable and are

markedly distinct from peacetime levels, imparting a relative clarity to the end of war and the

return of peace. Total wars thus entail substantial long-run benefits for participation and fewer

long-run costs for contestation. It is, therefore, not accidental that the optimistic narrative is most

compelling with regard to America’s total wars: the Civil War and World War II. After the

Page 39: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 38

cannons had fallen silent, the response to wartime restrictions, within the legal community and

society at large, was swift and overwhelmingly critical.

In limited wars, in contrast, the line dividing wartime from peacetime is not nearly as bright.

Because these wars entail more limited mobilization, restrictions on civil liberties may not be as

extensive as under conditions of total war, but they are more likely to persist. Advocates of civil

liberties will find it harder to mobilize potential supporters to roll back violations, and, facilitated

by a discourse that blurs the boundaries between war and peace, government authorities can

more credibly argue that the conditions that gave rise to these measures continue to hold. Less

extensive societal mobilization can be sustained for longer periods, and the end of war, along

with the return of peace, can be dated with less certainty. The often protracted nature of limited

war makes possible a society in which wartime civil-liberties standards become the new norm.

The US experience during the “cold war”—a protracted period of mobilization—is certainly

illustrative of this dynamic. If limited war is necessary for the “normalization” of the exception,

it is certainly not sufficient. The decade-long US involvement in Vietnam had exactly the

opposite effect on regnant norms of executive authority and civil liberties, as the government’s

conduct yielded a backlash against the “imperial presidency,” limits on intelligence agencies, and

the emergence of a more rights-protective legal and normative regime. As the example of

Vietnam suggests, other variables and processes figure as well.

This suggestion runs counter to the view, expressed notably by former US Supreme Court

Justice William Brennan, that sees great virtue in protracted conflict. Episodic crises, Brennan

argued, came too infrequently to call forth sustained attention. In contrast, the Israeli experience

taught, in Brennan’s view, that “prolonged and sustained exposure to the asserted security claims

may be the only way in which a country can gain both the discipline necessary to examine

Page 40: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 39

asserted security risk critically and the expertise necessary to distinguish the bona fide from the

bogus” (Brennan Jr. 1987, 7). Baruch Kimmerling has similarly concluded that Israel’s

protracted state of war has had little impact, positive or negative, on social change: conflict has

become routinized, and war has become merely a “social interruption,” regulated through

institutional mechanisms (Kimmerling 1985). In short, “adversity,” Brennan maintained, “may

yet be the handmaiden [of] liberty” (Brennan Jr. 1987, 8).51

Even on empirical grounds, however, the opposite position seems more persuasive. If the

constant threat of war permitted Israel to “preserv[e] its openness, flexibility, and democratic

rules of the game” (Kimmerling 1985, 191), that applied only to the state’s Jewish citizens—not

to Arab citizens, at least for several decades, and not to the Arab residents of the Occupied

Territories. Moreover, Israeli society was deeply shaped by the ever-looming interstate menace,

and Israel’s democracy was highly confined: the rhetoric of national security operated as a

trump, the Israel Defense Forces were rarely questioned, freedom of the press was (informally)

restricted, decision-makers had little patience for the rule of law, and, until recently, even Israeli

jurists excused violations of the law in light of harsh realities. The terrorist threat, which

intensified in the 1970s even as the interstate threat declined, fueled this fire (Dowty 1998;

Kimmerling 2001; Lahav 1988-1989). Nor is the Israeli experience unusual: Sri Lanka’s efforts

to combat the long-standing Tamil insurgency have by no means had the liberalizing effects that

Brennan might have predicted (Coomaraswamy and Reyes 2004).

b) Nature. Wars are distinguished not only by their scale and duration but by their

fundamental nature. Most critical to democratic contestation is how particular types of war

challenge or reproduce the statist discourse that underpins the international order (Gottmann

1951). This discourse draws clear distinctions between inside and outside, between domestic and 51 For this argument, see also Tribe and Guthridge 2004, 1815-16.

Page 41: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 40

international politics, between a hierarchical zone of order and peace and an anarchic zone of

chaos and conflict (Walker 1993). Perhaps paradoxically, the more a given war challenges statist

discourse, the greater the imperative for state authorities to reimpose a state-based geography

premised on identity and difference (Gottmann 1952, 516). Interstate wars, regardless of the

level of mobilization they entail, not only do not challenge the regnant statist discourse but in

fact reproduce it—by granting legitimate combatant status only to uniformed soldiers from

recognized states and refusing to accord others legitimacy. Such wars offer opportunities and

even generate pressure to reduce contestation, but there is no corresponding pressure to

emphasize anew the territorial basis of international life.

In contrast, insurgents and terrorists threaten the very distinction between inside and outside

that sustains the modern nation-state. Terrorism, writes James Der Derian, implies a feudal world

system, “a post-modern simulacrum of the Middle Ages,” and thus challenges the legitimacy of

the statist international order (Der Derian 1992, 117, 80-81).52 States undertaking

counterinsurgent and counterterrorist campaigns on their own territory respond in part by

asserting their territorial identity, reflected in policies that tighten borders and clamp down on

domestic threats (Coleman 2004, 88-93). Regardless of the level of “objective” menace, COIN

and CT wars are constituted by a statist logic that swings the needle from individual liberty

toward national security. Such wars also have an unfortunate tendency to become entrenched and

protracted, and the combination of their inherent nature with a lengthy duration is one that is

particularly deadly for democratic contestation.

Finally, wars may also be imperial in nature—Algeria (France), Vietnam (United States),

Lebanon and the Occupied Territories (Israel), Afghanistan (USSR), arguably Iraq today (United

States). In all of these examples, and perhaps in imperial wars in general, states are engaged in 52 For this view of terrorism, see also Keohane 2002.

Page 42: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 41

COIN and CT campaigns on foreign ground.53 Their adversaries are typically nationalist

insurgents, not the representatives of internationally recognized state units. As such, they

threaten the Westphalian order, but they do so abroad, exerting less pressure on the imperial

power to reassert its territorial identity by imposing restrictions on contestation at home.

Yet, in the long run, imperial wars tend to produce a backlash that strengthens and even

extends contestation. The objects of imperial projects are typically represented as uncivilized or

immature, and the imperial power legitimates its domination by promising to educate and

enlighten the savage, debased, infantile, or even inhuman subject population—the familiar

mission civilatrice, white man’s burden, modernization, and, in today’s idiom, spread of

democracy. Civilization is equated with the values of the imperial power, and thus this

instructional project seeks to transform the inferior Other into a copy of the superior Self.54

Imperial war follows when the target population resists these refined values. Its insurgency not

only suggests that the educative efforts have failed, but, more importantly, challenges the

metropole’s identity as a superior state embodying more advanced values, institutions, and

practices—and all the more so when the insurgency achieves some success. This in part explains

why imperial powers often expend extensive resources on areas seemingly of secondary interest:

resistance calls forth redoubled efforts to inscribe the metropole’s identity on the recalcitrant

population as a way of reaffirming the former’s status.

Combating insurgency, however, is often quite costly and requires brutal methods. As the

imperial power turns to barbaric tactics in the effort to save civilization, it only deepens the

contradiction. The mounting cruelty and costs of the imperial war typically provoke domestic

53 However, the boundaries between metropole and periphery, between home and foreign, are contested and flexible. See Lustick 1993. 54 The seminal work on such representational practices is Said 1978. The literature on colonialism, racism, and the civilizing mission is immense. For examples, see, among many others, Doty 1996; Hunt 1987; Karnow 1989.

Page 43: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 42

dissent.55 Imperial powers have then generally embraced the expedient measure of limiting

contestation, but this only adds to the escalating contradictions, in the long run lending strength

to political forces that seek to end the imperial war and to save democracy at home. Thus the

Vietnam War led to restraints on executive authority and intelligence agencies and to a less

pliant news media; the Afghan War ultimately contributed to the fall of the authoritarian Soviet

regime; and Israel’s occupation of Lebanon and of the Occupied Territories ushered in a more

liberal political culture protective of individual freedoms.

c) Meaning. Separate of the scale, duration, and even inherent nature of the war is the more

contingent question of war’s cultural meaning—of how a given conflict is publicly represented.56

This process is critical to both democratic participation and contestation in the short run and in

the long run. The United States fought the First World War in racialized terms, against the

vicious Huns, and thus the effort did not require a substantial rethinking of the racial lines

dividing American society. Although the discourse of the Pacific theater during World War II

remained deeply racialized, Allied leaders regularly contrasted their liberal values with the racist

values of the Axis (Gerstle 2001, 192-201). This wartime rhetoric created opportunities for

African-Americans to trap US statesmen in their own liberal commitments. Whether gains can be

wrung from authorities after war also depends on the construction of that conflict in the social

memory and the consequent postwar rhetorical possibilities (Krebs 2006).

Similarly, not all and not everyone’s civil liberties have been abridged in wartime.57 The way

in which, during wartime, leading figures frame the adversary has had substantial implications

for contestation, yielding both the extent of wartime restrictions and the identity of its targets.

55 Such dissent has often led to the imperial power’s eventual withdrawal. See Merom 2003. 56 Of course even “the inherent nature of the war” must be publicly represented, and thus no war can be separated from the process of representation. 57 This point is also made by Graber 2005a; Graber 2005b; Tushnet 2003, 278; Wood 2003, 460-61.

Page 44: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 43

Wartime rhetoric may generate the spirit of an “aversive” constitutionalism that drives

authorities to protect certain values and certain populations, even contrary to realist

considerations (Scheppele 2003).58 The fascistic oppressiveness and nationalism of the Nazi

regime led to protections even for those who refused to salute the flag, and the Nazis’ open

religious bigotry led to increased calls for religious tolerance. The due process revolution in the

United States, expanding the rights of the accused, took shape in explicit reference to the

communist Soviet adversary (Graber 2005a, 103-09). In sum, when wartime rhetoric is in line

with social realities and practices, it serves to reproduce them. But when it sits in tension with

social realities and practices, it creates space for reform.

If the cultural meaning imparted to war is of signal importance for democratic participation

and contestation, that raises the question of who is imparting such meaning and how. Because

the public representation of war has implications for actors’ concrete interests, the process is

inherently political and typically contested. While the existing literature has not ignored the

import of wartime and postwar discourse, it has not drawn attention to, nor has it theorized, how

such discourses takes shape. The framing of the war is treated as exogenous. Problematizing

representation is essential, however, and it will be taken up at the end of this section.

2. Features of Rights-Restrictive Policies: Formal vs. Informal

Among the central puzzles which demand explanation is why some rights-restrictive wartime

policies persist into peacetime and others provoke a backlash. Given the prevalence of collective

action problems and the relative power of the governing authorities, mobilization is often

problematic. It depends in the first place on the presence and power of individuals and groups

whose interests have been harmed: if such groups or individuals do not exist, or if they lack any

substantial political resources, mobilization against the status quo is highly unlikely. In contrast, 58 For a related argument, see Klinkner and Smith 2000.

Page 45: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 44

when such individuals and groups acquire unusually substantial political power, revision of the

status quo proceeds unusually smoothly.

The more problematic cases involve groups that can draw on some political resources but

face barriers to mobilization. The “political opportunity structure” has been invoked as a loose

way of summarizing the several features of the political environment that enter into group and

individual calculations (McAdam et al. 2001). Thus I have already argued that how war is

framed, as total or limited, promotes or stifles mobilization. All else being equal, it also seems

reasonable to hypothesize that the form that the rights-restrictive policy takes is important.

Restrictions that are more formal—such as those that that are passed as legislation or reside

in published regulation—are more ripe targets for protest than are restrictions that are more

informal—such as those that are embedded in bureaucratic culture or unpublished regulations.

Formality fosters visibility: rallying potential opponents and attracting media attention is easier

when the sources of grievance are relatively visible than when the measures are hidden from

public view. Consider, as an example, the US rules, during World War II, authorizing the Patent

Office to withhold certification from inventions that might harm US national security, seize the

invention for the government’s use, and impose severe penalties on violators. These rules, which

persisted well beyond the end of the war, were formalized for peacetime in the 1951 Invention

Secrecy Act, but that act did not really come into force until 1979, when the state of national

emergency declared by Truman finally came to an end. The heavy annual use of the secrecy

orders provoked little public outcry between 1951 and 1991 because the public, and even

experts, were hardly aware of the extent of their use. When, however, in response to a Freedom

of Information Act request, this information became public, a brouhaha erupted. But there has

predictably been little complaint about the various informal measures designed to prevent

Page 46: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 45

technologies with national-security implications from reaching the public sphere. Similarly, in

the United Kingdom, where measures to restrict speech and the transmission of information have

tended to be informal, they have operated without much dispute.59

3. Features of the Democratic Regime: Presidential vs. Parliamentary

The existing literature takes surprisingly little note of how the dynamics of crisis and

emergency may function differently in different kinds of democratic regimes. Students of

comparative politics have vigorously debated the relative merits of presidentialism and

parliamentarism and even whether these categories are analytically meaningful. Siding with

those who maintain their utility, I argue that these distinctions between democratic regimes

affect: (a) who participates in defining a crisis as such; and (b) levels of democratic contestation.

Democratic regimes vary enormously in their structures and provisions. The degree of

constitutional authority granted executives varies so widely that, by one account, “some systems

give the president so little power relative to the assembly that they are effectively parliamentary”

(Shugart and Carey 1992, 1-2). Indeed, most democracies established in recent years have been

designed on the semi-presidential (or premier-presidential) model of France, rather than on the

relatively pure models epitomized by Britain and the United States. Nevertheless, presidential

systems are marked by: (1) separation of origin and survival; (2) constitutionally granted

executive authority to execute laws and to check the legislature; (3) composition and

appointment of government/cabinet by the elected executive. Parliamentary systems are

characterized by: (1) fusion of origin and survival; (2) no meaningful executive check on the

legislature; (3) composition and appointment of the government by the assembly (Shugart and

Carey 1992). While real presidential and parliamentary democracies depart from these ideal

types, the very fact of the separation of powers has real consequences: presidential regimes tend 59 For the empirical details, but without this interpretation, see Donohue 2005b, 274-79.

Page 47: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 46

to be less decisive and more resolute, the executive and the legislative majority are marked by

greater inherent “separation of purpose,” and coalitions are costlier to maintain and are less

stable (Samuels 2006).

(a) Defining Crisis. The existing literature has rightly observed that democratic contestation

suffers during wars and national-security crises, but it has failed to question how, when, and by

whom crises are identified.60 When only executives are “securitizing actors”—that is, when only

they can legitimately participate in the national conversation over what constitutes a security

threat61—the path to the declaration of emergency is relatively unimpeded. When, however,

other leading figures, especially legislators, can and do participate in this conversation,

executives are at least somewhat constrained. Features of democratic regimes, notably the

separation of powers and the design of electoral rules, can help explain when legislators have the

capacity and the (potential) will to oppose executives on their march to emergency.

Executives’ declarations of emergency can be challenged only by political actors who can

themselves lay claim to expertise on national security. This may of course derive from personal

experience, such as service in the armed forces or academic training, but electoral rules can also

give politicians incentives to develop such expertise. Systems marked especially by large district

magnitude and less frequent elections are most conducive to “national” debate, and thus

legislators elected under such rules have the greatest incentives to develop expertise and to make

contact with experts in civil society. In contrast, systems with low district magnitude and

frequent elections give politicians incentives to focus on more parochial concerns, allowing

executives to operate with a freer hand (Cox and McCubbins 2001, 37-39; Shugart and Haggard

60 Debates over emergency provisions devote much attention to this question, with some arguing for a substantive definition and others calling for a processual definition of emergency. But this literature does not seek to explain when this process is more or less contested. 61 On “securitization,” see Buzan, et al. 1998, chap. 2; Wæver 1995.

Page 48: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 47

2001, 82-91). Electoral rules shape the capacity of legislators to challenge an executive’s

assertion of a crisis.

Whether regimes are marked by the separation or fusion of powers shapes not only the

capacity but especially the will of legislators to resist the executive. In parliamentary systems,

governments and legislators rise and fall together: as a consequence, party discipline tends to be

tighter.62 In presidential systems, in which legislators’ political fates do not hinge on the

government, party discipline tends to be weaker, and even majority legislators have the capacity

to defy the executive.63 With party discipline weak, legislators also have distinct institutional

prerogatives to resist the executive’s accretions of authority. The separation of origins and

survival is an important source of separation of purpose, regardless of party control over the

branches of government (Shugart and Haggard 2001). The relative independence of the assembly

also gives legislators a separate institutional base in which to conduct hearings, investigate

government practices, and raise questions about the framing of a crisis. Independent legislators

are also more open to interest group involvement in national debate and in public policymaking,

providing those who might oppose the declaration of emergency with a point of access.64

These two dimensions can be combined to yield expectations about when resistance to the

executive’s declaration of emergency is possible (see Table 1). In presidential regimes, marked

62 See Linz 1994. Others contend that parliamentary regimes are not marked by particularly high levels of partisan discipline because minority governments are prevalent and governments often dissolve without early elections (Cheibub and Limongi 2002, 157-62). Nevertheless, presidential democracies have generally seemed to suffer from a lack of party cohesion and from multiple veto players, even when a single party controls all branches of government (Eaton 2000, 361-62). 63 If ballots were fused in presidential systems, then the electoral fates of presidents and members of the president’s party in the assembly would be tightly linked, and separation of purpose would be reduced. But such fused ballots are rare in presidential regimes (Samuels and Eaton 2002). Variation in party discipline in presidential systems has, however, not been insignificant, and a key explanation appears to lie in party control over nominations (ballot access) and campaign funds (Wilson 1986). Nevertheless, there appears to be a distinct tradeoff between executive strength and party strength, and democratic regime type is theoretically and empirically linked to levels of party discipline (Shugart 1998). 64 Eaton (2000, 369) notes, however, that this insight may be particularly true of the United States, where reforms in the 1970s decentralized power in Congress, and less true of other presidential regimes.

Page 49: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 48

by the separation of origins and survival, and in electoral systems that encourage a national

orientation, the combination of legislative independence and incentives to expertise imparts the

capacity and potentially even the will to contest executive assertions of emergency. When

separation is combined with electoral rules that encourage legislator parochialism, the result is

legislators who may have the will but have little capacity: resistance is highly unlikely. When

electoral rules that yield incentives to develop expertise with regard to national matters,

including security, are joined to the fusion of powers, legislators have the capacity to resist but

no will, unless the parliamentary regime is governed by a minority party: resistance is then more

occasional. Finally, when fusion is married to electoral rules that sustain parochialism, legislators

will evince neither the will nor the capacity to resist.

The separation of origins and survival may create a base for resistance, but such regimes are

also characterized by a competitive institutional dynamic. Legislators have certain common

interests across party lines, and they vie with the executive qua executive for power. Executives,

in turn, have incentives to manufacture and exploit crises so as to augment their branch’s relative

position (Arato 2002; Lowi 1969). In parliamentary regimes, characterized by the fusion of

institutional origins and survival, this competitive dynamic is absent, and one might therefore

expect that prime ministers would less often assert crisis, international or otherwise.

(b) Long-Run Effects on Contestation. Once an emergency has been effectively established,

neither parliamentary nor presidential regimes function particularly effectively to constrain the

expansion of executive authority. The more important question is whether a particular

democratic regime type is more likely in the long run to preserve liberal values. It would seem

relevant to distinguish between cases when wartime expansions of executive authority have

sunset clauses, in which case executives later seek to render wartime measures permanent, and

Page 50: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 49

when they have no expiration date, in which case preventing increased arbitrariness would

require undoing the status quo in the wake of the conflict.

One view would straightforwardly argue that policy stability is in part a function of the

number of veto players, both institutional and partisan (Tsebelis 2002).65 All else being equal,

presidential regimes tend toward “indecisiveness” and “resoluteness”: policy change is less

frequent and tends to be gradual (Cox and McCubbins 2001; Samuels 2006).66 One might

therefore expect that extending wartime powers set to expire would be particularly difficult in

presidential regimes, as would undoing wartime patterns of executive authority.

However, this argument applies most persuasively with regard to issues without inherent

institutional significance. The accretion of greater executive authority, however, is not equivalent

to other “major policies”: it occupies a place of unusual importance, for it threatens to redefine

the very essence of the regime. Efforts by presidents to arrogate power permanently can call

forth cross-party legislative coalitions to defend their branch’s prerogatives: the separation of

origins and survival fosters the separation of purpose that underpins legislative resistance.

Consequently, undoing wartime patterns of executive authority remains possible in presidential

regimes, contrary to what the conventional logic might suggest. It is also possible in

parliamentary regimes, though it is highly unlikely in the case of majority government: those in

power are rarely likely to wish to roll back executive authority, and the prevalence of strong

party discipline makes initiatives in the assembly unlikely. Rendering wartime executive powers

permanent is not likely in presidential systems, but it is possible in parliamentary regimes,

65 Tsebelis (2002) would add that major policy change is also less likely when major institutional and partisan veto players are separated by greater ideological distance and marked by greater internal cohesion. 66 There is a large literature on the alleged tendency of presidential regimes to policy deadlock and regime breakdown. See Cheibub and Limongi 2002; Cheibub, et al. 2004; Haggard and McCubbins 2001; Linz 1994; Mainwaring and Shugart 1997; Shugart and Carey 1992, chap. 3.

Page 51: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 50

especially in the case of majority government. If these hypotheses are correct, presidential

regimes are in fact more conducive to preserving liberal values in the long run.

Presidential systems also tend to render policy decisions in a more transparent fashion (Eaton

2000, 363-65; Tsebelis 2002, 74). Simply the friction between the branches will produce public

information about actors’ policy positions, and, if the assembly has well-developed watchdog

institutions for investigating and publicizing executive wrongdoing, they can be a powerful force

constraining executive authority.67 The separation of powers also provides lobbyists and interest

groups with greater access into the system. In presidential regimes, aggrieved outside actors may

be encouraged to mobilize and may act more effectively, and legislators can more aggressively

court them without risking the fall of the government (Samuels and Eaton 2002). In

parliamentary regimes, in contrast, outside actors have fewer access points through which to

challenge illiberal developments. Moreover, in parliamentary systems, bureaucracies tend to

have broader portfolios and greater independence; because designing monitoring systems is more

difficult under the separation of powers, presidential systems tend to have more elaborate and

intrusive oversight mechanisms (Moe and Caldwell 1994). Thus in parliamentary systems, policy

is more often made hidden from public view (Ceaser 1986; Eaton 2000, 370-71).68 The greater

transparency and access typical of presidential regimes provides outside actors with more

information and with greater opportunities for overturning illiberal policies driven by war and

threat.

4. The Dynamics of Rhetorical Contestation

67 The strength of the president’s legislative powers is an important countervailing factor, however. The more extensive his executive decree authority, the less transparent the policymaking. See Carey and Shugart 1998; Shugart and Carey 1992, chap. 7. 68 Thus in the United States speech has, on the whole, received greater protection than in Britain, where a culture of secrecy has historically prevailed. Where the United States has done a poorer job protecting speech, the reason has much to do either with bureaucratization (e.g. scientific information, or “knowledge-based speech”) or with an inherent lack of transparency (e.g. measures with a secondary effect on speech) (Donohue 2005b).

Page 52: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 51

Explaining the dynamics and outcomes of rhetorical competition lies at the heart of critical

unanswered questions about the effects of war on democracy, yet this process has not figured in

the explanations offered in the existing literature. For example, the introduction of “national

security” into public debate can powerfully shape who may participate in that conversation and

what policy measures seem warranted. It has, most importantly, facilitated public tolerance of

extraordinary measures, for the very existence of the crisis or emergency is made possible

through rhetorical action that identifies an existential threat (Buzan et al. 1998, 21-24). In some

contexts, national security discourse operates as a trump, in others it is dismissed as a red

herring. In some contexts, only a limited few may participate in the debate on security; in others,

the range of legitimate “securitizing actors” is large.

Several other mechanisms also hinge on the process by which actors effectively set the terms

of debate, particularly in the face of alternative frames and narratives. These include the public

representation of the war’s nature, of the extent of mobilization that is warranted, of the war’s

meaning (and hence of what features of the adversary must be averted), and of women’s

contributions to the war effort. Rhetorical contestation, or the lack thereof, regarding all these

critical factors—which, I have argued above, have implications for how deeply democratic

contestation is undermined, whether these wartime extensions of executive authority and

restrictions on civil liberties survive the war, and whose freedoms and which freedoms are

abridged and expanded during war—must be problematized. Even the characterization of the

war’s outcome, as victory or defeat (which, by some accounts, has ramifications for the vibrancy

of postwar civil society), is often not obvious: although Israel won the 1973 war with its Arab

neighbors, the initial setbacks and unusually high casualty rates led Israelis to view this victory

as a failure, and the war touched off dramatic social and political upheaval.

Page 53: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 52

Similar questions might be raised about “renormalization,” which occurs when new social

conventions emerge enshrining as the norm wartime standards on executive authority and civil

liberties. The important mechanism here would appear to be less psychological than rhetorical.

The key lies in reframing the very purpose of the regulations or legislation, in shifting the terms

of political debate onto grounds that compel their retention. In the United Kingdom, for example,

legislation to deal with the Troubles in Northern Ireland was recast as “anti-terrorist,” rather than

“emergency,” legislation. To fail to renew the laws would have signaled surrender to terrorism,

and thus the burden of proof was transferred to those seeking the laws’ repeal. Opponents of

Britain’s counterterrorist legislation consequently had to demonstrate that the threat of terrorism

no longer existed—and that was something they could not do (Donohue 2001, 316-22).

Who wins such rhetorical competitions? Why do actors whom one might expect to raise their

voices in protest remain silent? Space constraints prevent me from advancing a fully-specified

theory of rhetorical contestation,69 but it is worth exploring what insights such an approach might

yield. Many political scientists, particularly those of a realist bent, adopt strictly materialist

answers to these questions, rendering meaning production epiphenomenal. Extreme

postmodernists, in contrast, adopt fully discursive positions in which the production of meaning

is utterly unconstrained. A more balanced position takes inspiration from critical literature that

strikes for a middle ground. Stuart Hall insists, in his reading of Gramsci, that material forces do

not have immediate or necessary consequences, but they do “define the terrain on which

historical forces move – they define the horizon of possibilities” (Hall 1996 422). Articulations

gain mass traction, Hall suggests, when they touch upon the everyday experiences of mass

publics: Margaret Thatcher’s law-and-order rhetoric tapped into “the direct experience, the

69 For some not-fully-specified steps in that direction, however, see Krebs 2006; Krebs and Jackson 2006; Krebs and Lobasz 2006.

Page 54: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 53

anxieties and uncertainties of ordinary people” who had lived through the upheaval of the late

1960s (Hall 1988, 137). Pierre Bourdieu rightly warns that “legitimating discourses” are not

sufficient as an explanation for domination, for they must be institutionally sustained (Bourdieu

1977, 188).

The production of meaning is located in the conjunction of material factors, institutional

design and position, discursive formations, and experience. To fit the analysis (perhaps

somewhat awkwardly) to causal language, these may be jointly necessary and sufficient.

Discursive Formations. Articulations cannot but draw upon existing discursive formations.

Thus students of transnational activism and social movements have concluded that ways of

framing claims cannot be fabricated out of whole cloth but can at most evolve through “grafting”

(Price 1998). How mass publics and elites respond to the introduction into public debate of the

“national security” commonplace, for example, consequently depends on historical and cultural

narratives that are continually rescripted. In Israel a national narrative crafted around continual

persecution has rendered themes of insecurity particularly resonant (Dowty 1990, 2-3). Yet, very

often, those who oppose the declaration of crisis or emergency will have access to equally

familiar and well rooted commonplaces with very different implications. When that happens, the

terms of the frame will likely not be determinative.

Material and Institutional Factors. The design of institutions is hardly irrelevant to rhetorical

contestation. Executives, and especially presidents, enjoy advantages in rhetorical competition

by virtue of their position, particularly with respect to foreign policy: often the first to speak,

they dominate media coverage, and others must respond to their framings.70 Yet their victory is

not assured. Even motivated presidents have many times failed to mobilize publics for their

70 On positionality, and particularly state elites, in “securitization,” see Buzan, et al. 1998, 31-33; Weldes 1999.

Page 55: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 54

foreign policy goals, instead encountering substantial opposition (Edwards III 2003). The earlier

discussion, highlighting the interaction of democratic regime type with electoral rules, suggests

the power of institutions to shape political actors’ will and capacity to resist.71 Rhetorical mode

matters as well: when policy is justified on pragmatic grounds, opponents can more effectively

counter the executive’s preferred policies than they can when policies are framed in identity-

laden terms (Murphy 1992).72

Experience.73 The everyday experiences of mass publics also differentially empower political

actors and bound sustainable rhetoric. Perceived military fiascoes, such as that of the Israel

Defense Forces in the 1973 war and that of the US armed forces in Vietnam, have often

reworked narratives so as to undermine officials’ claims to expertise. These wars served to

highlight the presence of expertise in civil society and to broaden the range of legitimate

participants in national-security debate. Experience may also prompt speech in a particular

rhetorical mode. The September 11 attacks, for example, called forth a rhetoric that would place

these horrific events in an interpretive context (Murphy 2003). In this epideictic form, dissent

violates audience expectations and is dismissed. In contrast, had President Bush sought to

generate a sense of crisis—rather than respond to events that the mass public, apparently with

little guidance, assimilated into the crisis frame—he would have relied more heavily on

pragmatic argumentation. Such rhetoric in principle permits for a more vocal opposition.

71 The identification of an emergency circumstance is ultimately a political, not a legal, question. Yet the law also can bolster particular institutional roles and strengthen them in political contest. In the United States, for example, the Supreme Court has ruled that, under the authority of the 1795 Militia Act, the declaration of crisis (as the first step toward the imposition of martial law) is the exclusive right of the executive and is not reviewable (Vladeck 2004, 171-72). 72 I allude here to, respectively, the deliberative and epideictic rhetorical genres. For brief useful discussions of the Aristotelian genres, see the relevant entries in Sloane 2001. On epideictic rhetoric, see also Condit 1985. 73 On experience and ideational change, see Legro 2005.

Page 56: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 55

At the core of much of the preceding discussion lies a single critical issue: under what

conditions do elites and mass publics accept new baselines with regard to democratic

contestation, and under what conditions do they resist them? When is the outcome

renormalization (adaptive preference formation), and when is there a backlash (contrarian

preference formation)? Table 2 summarizes the hypotheses elaborated in this section.

Conclusion

The relationship between democracy and war has been much studied in international

relations. Some would say too much, as scholars continue to buzz around the carcass of the

democratic peace. Yet the reverse of that relationship—the effects of war on democracy—though

much debated in times of crisis, has received little systematic attention in either international

relations or comparative politics. In general, we know far more about war’s causes than its

consequences, and that is especially true with regard to democracy. “Pothole” topics—that is,

questions about which scholars have written little—are sometimes potholes for good reason: the

answers may be obvious, trivial, or unknowable. Studying the effects of war on democracy is

methodologically challenging, but it is of unquestionable theoretical and practical import, and

there is certainly a large enough proving ground on which to evaluate hypotheses.

Answering these questions would seem furthermore to be of particular relevance today. We

do not live in a post-Schmittian world in which arguments based on “the exception” are no

longer sustainable (Scheppele 2004, 1069-82): Americans have not become exercised over the

Bush administration’s excesses with regard to domestic eavesdropping, with 54% in February

2006 endorsing the view that it is “generally right” for the government, without first obtaining

court permission, to monitor communications of Americans suspected of having terrorist ties

Page 57: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 56

(Kohut et al. 2006). Polls have shown that the public would support even more extensive

government intrusion as long as national security was deemed to be at stake.74 Despite the

development and spread of international law and human rights norms, we continue to live in an

all-too-often conflictual world of nation-states, and when national security is seen to be

threatened, publics tolerate the suspension of the rule of law.

The penultimate section of the paper advanced a series of claims regarding how and when

features of different wars, rights-restrictive policies, democratic regimes, and processes of

rhetorical competition would affect democratic participation and contestation. Judge Learned

Hand, however, famously warned that such factors may matter only at the margins, for it is the

“spirit of liberty” that saves polities from the dangers of dictatorship. “I often wonder whether

we do not rest our hopes too much upon constitutions, upon laws, and upon courts,” he wrote.

“Liberty lies in the hearts of men and women; when it dies there, no constitution, no law, no

court can save it” (Hand 1977, 190). Much the same might be said about democratic regimes.

“No constitutional framework,” writes Bruce Ackerman, “will suffice to compel the President to

be a statesman if he is determined to play the part of demagogue” (Ackerman 2004b, 1902).75

Political culture and leaders’ normative commitments to individual freedoms may very well

matter more than the scope and duration of war, regime type, and the dynamics of framing in

explaining the severity and persistence of war’s effects on liberal democracy. But the survival of

liberal democracy in rough times may be determined precisely on the margins. It is on the

margins that the difference lies between a democracy that limps along, compromised yet intact,

74 As recently as February 2006, far more Americans thought the government had not gone far enough to protect the country against terrorism (50%) than thought the government had gone too far in restricting civil liberties (33%). These numbers have largely held steady since September 2001, despite media attention to administration overstepping. However, at the same time and in some tension with the preceding finding, decreasing numbers of Americans have seen a need to sacrifice civil liberties in the war on terror. For relevant survey data, see Kohut, et al. 2006; Kohut, et al. 2004. 75 See also Freeman 2003; Gross 2003a, 1129; Rosen 2004, 216.

Page 58: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 57

and one that utterly abandons its heritage. The fate of liberal societies undoubtedly resides in the

hearts of men. But when the love of liberty has taken root, it still needs a nurturing institutional

environment if it is to thrive.

The relationship between institutional and constitutional design, on the one hand, and the

preservation of liberal-democracy in times of emergency, on the other, has been much debated

anew since September 11. Much ink has been spilled on the relative merits of the judicial and

legislative branches in constraining the executive in presidential regimes and on the virtues or

irrelevance of explicit emergency provisions. With regard to the first question, neither judges nor

legislators have done particularly well, at least in the United States, as checks on executive

power in times of crisis. Most acknowledge that “historically, the judiciary has been so

deferential to the executive in wartime as to provide virtually no meaningful check… [I]t would

be a terrible mistake for those who worry about civil rights and liberties to pin too much hope on

the judiciary in times of crisis” (Tribe 2001, 18).76 In the United States, the courts have generally

protected rights only once the war has ended or the crisis has passed, or at best as it has waned.77

They have sought to preserve a congressional oversight, but they have generally followed

Congress’ lead, bolstering it when it has sought to exercise its prerogatives and saying little when

Congress has shown little resistance (Issacharoff and Pildes 2005). The courts have thereby

implicitly acknowledged that only the legislature can resist an ambitious executive. Legislatures

sadly have not done much better in defending civil liberties or even their own prerogatives. They

have tended to overreact in times of crisis, swiftly and without debate passing intrusive and over-

76 This is a widely held view. On the United States, see, among others, Brennan Jr. 1987; Cole 2004a; Epstein, et al. 2005; Gross 2003a, 1034; Kmiec 2003; Rehnquist 1998, 221-22; Rossiter and Longaker 1976. On judicial deference in Israel, see Hofnung 1996. On Sri Lanka, see Coomaraswamy and Reyes 2004. 77 As David Cole (2004, 2591) points out, however, the courts are sometimes the only forum realistically available for publicizing grievances, particularly for the politically weak.

Page 59: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 58

reaching legislation (Cole 2004a, 2589-91).78 If legislators lack the willpower to resist the

executive, it is typically because they sense little concern among their constituents, as Learned

Hand would have feared.

The explicit provision of constitutional emergency powers may, however, bolster legislators,

and this may be the strongest argument on their behalf. Some maintain that war should be waged

within standard constitutional limits and with conventional democratic oversight (Breyer 2003;

Cole 2004a); others argue that wartime measures must be explicitly extraconstitutional so as to

avoid tainting law in ordinary times (Gross 2003a; Tushnet 2003); still others have proposed

various models of accommodation (Gross 2003a, 1058-69), among them a set of constitutional

procedures for the effective, but legally constrained, employment of emergency powers (Rossiter

1948).79 The legal constraints on emergency powers rarely prove binding, for they are violated

when necessity seemingly calls. But this fact of political life does not mean that emergency

powers are irrelevant. Their greater virtue may lie less in their specific provisions than simply in

their existence. Explicit emergency powers provide both government and public with a set of

legal standards to which adherence is expected. Deviations from those norms require

explanation, thus undercutting the executive’s potential for arbitrariness and hence despotism

(Finn 1991). If the legislature wishes to be a rubber stamp, no formal provisions can compel it to

be something more. But if the legislature wishes to be a meaningful check on the executive, a

formal oversight process, which is essential to even the most minimal regulated emergency

powers, can serve as the springboard for resistance.80

78 For a more optimistic view of the congressional role since 9/11, however, see Rosen 2004, ch. 4. 79 For recent variations on Rossiter’s theme, see Ackerman 2004a; Arato 2002; Ferejohn and Pasquino 2004; Scheuerman 2006. 80 Empirical studies of the efficacy of explicit constitutional provisions are rare. This is a major theme in Rossiter’s classic work (1948). One study has found that most specific features of emergency powers have no statistically significant impact on the levels of human rights abuse (Keith and Poe 2004). On the variety of constitutional emergency provisions, see Gross 2003b.

Page 60: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 59

The heated contemporary debates over the necessity and costs of post-9/11 measures often

make grand claims based on limited empirical data and weak theoretical foundations. Citizens

must indeed be ever vigilant against assertions of state power, but research that identifies the

circumstances in which executive authority is expanded most greatly and civil liberties restricted

most severely, and in which these wartime measures tended to permanence and other forms of

“bleeding,” could help civil libertarians pick their battles more carefully. It could help leaders

committed to liberal democracy understand better the ramifications of expanding executive

authority. It could help identify the institutions and constitutions conducive to the procurement

and preservation of both security and the rule of law. Such research is, in short, vital if we are to

balance security and liberty in an anxious age.

Table 1. Presidentialism, Parliamentarism, and National Security Debate

Origin and Survival

• legislative dependence (discipline)• no incentive to expertiseNo willNo capacityNo Resistance

• legislative independence (little discipline)• no incentive to expertiseWill (potential)No capacityNo Resistance

Parochial Orientation

• legislative dependence (discipline)• incentives to expertiseNo will (caveat: minority government)CapacityResistance Rare

• legislative independence (little discipline)• incentives to expertiseWill (potential)CapacityResistance Possible

National Orientation

FusionSeparation

• legislative dependence (discipline)• no incentive to expertiseNo willNo capacityNo Resistance

• legislative independence (little discipline)• no incentive to expertiseWill (potential)No capacityNo Resistance

Parochial Orientation

• legislative dependence (discipline)• incentives to expertiseNo will (caveat: minority government)CapacityResistance Rare

• legislative independence (little discipline)• incentives to expertiseWill (potential)CapacityResistance Possible

National Orientation

FusionSeparation

Electoral Rules And Political Debate

Page 61: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 60

Table 2. Democratic Contestation, Normalization, and Backlash

Relevant Factors Normalization Backlash Scale and Duration of War limited

total & shor war

Nature of War counterinsurgency/counterterrorist

imperia

Meaning of War

wartime rhetoric in line with

reality/social practices

wartime rhetoric in tension with reality/social practices

Rights-Restrictive Policies

informal

formal

Democratic Regime

a) fusion of powers;

b) separation of powers & electoral rules fostering

parochial orientation (see Table 1)

separation of powers & electoral rules fostering

national orientation (see Table 1)

Rhetorical Mode

epideictic

deliberative

Experience

victory

defeat

& protracted war

t

l

Page 62: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 61

References

Ackerman, Bruce. 2004a. "The Emergency ." Yale Law Journal 113 (???):1029-. -----------. 2004b. "This Is Not a War." Yale al 113 (8):1871-907. Andreski, Stanislav. 1954. Military Organization and Society. Berkeley: University of alifornia

Press. Arato, Andrew. 2002. "The Bush Tribunals ecter of Dictatorship." Constellations 9

(4):457-76. Banaszak, Lee Ann. 1996. Why Movements Succeed or Fail: Opportunity, Culture, and the

Struggle for Woman Suffrage. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Berman, Sheri E. 1997. "Civil Society and the Collapse of the Weimar Republic." Wo Politics

49 (3):401-29. Blight, David W 001. Race and Reunion: The Civil War in American Memory. Cambridge:

Belknap Press. Boix, Carles. 2003. Democracy and Redistribution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Boix, Carles, and Susan C. Stokes. 2003. "Endogenous Democratization." World Politics

55:517-49. Bollinger, Lee C., and Geoffrey R. Stone. 2002. "Dialogue." In Eternally Vigilant: Free Speech

in the Modern Era, edited by Lee C. Bollinger and Geoffrey R. Stone. ChicagoUniversity of Chicago Press.

Borstelmann, Thomas. 2001. The Cold War and the Color Line: American Race Relations in the Global Arena. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Brennan Jr., William J. 1987. The Quest to Develop a Jurisprudence of Civil Liberties in Times of Crisis.

Breyer, Stephen G. 2003. Liberty, Security, and the Courts. Bridges, Amy. 2000. "Path Dependence, Sequence, History, Theory." Studies in American

Political Development 14 (1):109-12. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce. 1990. "Big Wars, Little Wars: Avoiding Selection Bias."

International Interactions 16 (3):159-69. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and Randolph M. Siverson. 1995. "War and the Survival of Political

Leaders: A Comparative Study of Regime Types and Political Accountability.Political Science Review 89 (4):841-55.

Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, et al. 1992. "War and the Fate of Regimes: A ComparativeAnalysis." American Political Science Review 86 (3):638-46.

Buzan, Barry, et al. 1998. Security: A New Framework for Analysis. Boulder: Lynne Rienner. Carey, John M., and Matthew S. Shugart, eds. 1998. Executive Decree Authority. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press. Ceaser, James W. 1986. "In Defense of Separation of Powers." In Separation of Powers--Does It

Still Work?, edited by Robert A. Goldwin and Art Kaufman. Washington, D.CAmerican Enterprise Institute for Public Policy.

Centeno, Miguel. 2002. Blood and Debt: War and the Nation-State in Latin America. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

Constitution Law Journ

and the Sp

C

rld

:

" American

.:

. 2

Page 63: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 62

Chafe, William H. 1972. The American Woman: Her Changing Social, Economic, and Political Roles, 1920-1970. New York: Oxford University Press.

Cheibub, José Antonio, and Fernando Limongi. 2002. "Democratic Institutions and Re e Survival: Parliamentary and Presidential Democracies Reconsidered." Annual Review of Political Science 5:151-79.

Cheibub, José Antonio, et al. 2004. "Government Coalitions and Legislative Success Under Presidentialism and Parliamentarism." British Journal of Political Science 34 (4):565-87.

Chiozza, Giacomo, and Hein Goemans. 2003. "Peace Through Insecurity: Tenure and International Conflict." Journal of Conflict Resolution 47 (4):443-67.

Chowdhury, Subrata Roy. 1989. Rule of Law in a State of Emergency: The Paris Minimum Standards of Human Rights Norms in a State of Emergency. New York: St. Martin's Press.

Cole, David. 2002. "Enemy Aliens." Stanford Law Review 54. -----------. 2003a. Enemy Aliens: Double Standards and Constitutional Freedoms in the War on

Terrorism. New York: New Press. -----------. 2003b. "The New McCarthyism: Repeating History in the War on Terrorism

Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review 38:1-30. -----------. 2004a. "Judging the Next Emergency: Judicial Review and Individual Righ n Times

of Crisis." Michigan Law Review 101 (8):2565-94. -----------. 2004b. "The Priority of Morality: The Emergency Constitution's Blind Spot." Yale

Law Journal 113 (8):1753-800. Cole, David, and James X. Dempsey. 2002. Terrorism and the Constitution: Sacrificing Civil

Liberties in the Name of National Security. 2nd ed. New York: New Press. Coleman, Mat. 2004. "The Naming of 'Terrorism' and 'Evil Outlaws': Geopolitical Place-Making

After 11 September." In 11 September and Its Aftermath: The Geopolitics of Terror, edited by Stanley D. Brunn. London: Frank Cass.

Colley, Linda. 1992. Britons: Forging the Nation, 1707-1837. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Condit, Celeste M. 1985. "The Functions of Epideictic: The Boston Massacre Orations as Exemplar." Communication Quarterly 33 (4):284-99.

Coomaraswam Radhika, and Charmaine de los Reyes. 2004. "Rule by Emergency: Sri Lanka's Postcolonial Constitutional Experience." International Journal of Constitutional Law 2 (2):272-95.

Cowell, Alan. 2005. "Blair is Seeking to Curb Radicals Who Preach Hate." New York Times. Cox, Gary W., and Mathew D. McCubbins. 2001. "The Institutional Determinants of Economic

Policy Outcomes." In Presidents, Parliaments, and Policy, edited by Stephan Haggard and Mathew D. McCubbins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Dahl, Robert A. 1971. Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Davis, Darren W., and Brian D. Silver. 2004. "Civil Liberties vs. Security: Public Opinion in the Context of the Terrorist Attacks on America." American Journal of Political Science 48 (1):28-46.

Der Derian, James. 1992. Antidiplomacy: Spies, Terror, Speed, and War. Cambridge: Blackwell. Dolman, Everett Carl. 2004. The Warrior State: How Military Organization Structures Politics.

New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

gim

."

ts i

y,

Page 64: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 63

Donohue, Laura K. 2001. Counter-terrorist Law and Emergency Powers in the United Kingdom, 1922-2000. Dublin: Irish Academic

-----------. 2005a. "Security and Freedom on the Fulcrum." Terrorism and Political Vi 17:69-87.

-----------. 2005b. "Terrorist Speech and the Future of Free Expression." Cardozo Law Review 27 (1):234-341.

Doty, Roxanne Lynn. 1996. Imperial Encou eapolis: University of Minnes Press. Downing, Brian M. 1992. The Military Revolution and Political Change: Origins of Democracy

and Autocracy in Early Modern Europe ton: Princeton University PressDowty, Alan. 1990. "Emergency Powers in Devaluation of Crisis." In Coping With

Crises: How Governments Deal With Emergencies, edited by Shao-chuan Leng. Lanham: University Press of America.

-----------. 1998 he Jewish State: A Centur rkeley: University of Californi ress. DuBois, Ellen Carol. 1998. Woman Suffrage and Women's Rights. New York: New York

University Press. Dudziak, Mary L. 2000. Cold War Civil Rights: Race and the Image of American Democracy.

Princeton: Princeton University Press. Eaton, Kent. 2000. "Parliamentarism versus Presidentialism in the Policy Arena." Comparative

Politics (3):355-76. Edwards III, George C. 2003. On Deaf Ears: The Limits of the Bully Pulpit. New Haven: Yale

University Press. Elshtain, Jean Bethke. 1987. Women and War. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Epstein, Lee, et al. 2005. "The Supreme Court During Crisis: How War Affects Only Non-War

Cases." New York University Law Review 80 (1):1-116. Evans, Sara M. 1989. Born for Liberty: A History of Women in America. New York: Free Press. Feld, Maury. 1977. The Structure of Violence: Armed Forces as Social Systems. Beve y Hills:

Sage. Ferejohn, John, and Pasquale Pasquino. 2004. "The Law of the Exception: A Typology of

Emergency Powers." International Journal of Constitutional Law 2 (2):210-39. Finn, John E. 1991. Constitutions in Crisis: Political Violence and the Rule of Law. New York:

Oxford University Press. Fischer, David Hackett. 1970. Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought. New

York: Harper & Row. Flexner, Eleanor, and Ellen Fitzpatrick. 1996. Century of Struggle: The Woman's Rights

Movement in the United States. Cambridge: Belknap Press. Freeman, Michael. 2003. Freedom or Security: The Consequences for Democracies U ng

Emergency Powers to Fight Terror. Westport: Praeger. Friedberg, Aaron L. 2000. In the Shadow of the Garrison State : America’s Anti-statism and its

Cold War Grand Strategy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Fussell, Paul. 1975. The Great War and Modern Memory. New York: Oxford University Press. Gerstle, Gary. 2001. American Crucible: Race and Nation in the Twentieth Century. Princeton:

Princeton University Press. -----------. 2003. "Pluralism and the War on Terror." Dissent 50 (2):31-38. Goemans, Hein. 2000. "Fighting for Survival: The Fate of Leaders and the Duration of War."

Journal of Conflict Resolution 44 (5):555-79.

Press. olence

ota

.

a P

nters. Minn

. PrinceIsrael: The

y Later. Be. T

32

rl

si

Page 65: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 64

Goldsmith, Jack, and Cass R. Sunstein. 2002. "Military Tribunals and Legal Culture: What A Difference Sixty Years Makes." Constitutional Commentary 19 (1):261-90.

Goldstein, Joshua S. 2001. War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gottmann, Jean. 1951. "Geography and International Relations." World Politics 3 (2):153-73. -----------. 1952. "The Political Partitioning of Our World: An Attempt at Analysis." World

Politics 4 (4):512-19. Graber, Mark A. 2005a. "Counter-Stories: Maintaining and Expanding Civil Liberties in

Wartime." In The Constitution in Wartime: Beyond Alarmism and Complacencby Mark Tushnet. Durham: Duke University Press.

-----------. 2005b. "Voting Rights and Other 'Anomalies': Protecting and Expanding Civil Liberties in Wartime." In At War with Civil Rights and Liberties, edited by Thomas E. Baker and John F. Stack Jr. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

Graham, Sara Hunter. 1996. Woman Suffrage and the New Democracy. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Gross, Oren. 2003a. "Chaos and Rules: Should Responses to Violent Crises Always Be Constitutional?" Yale Law Journal 112:1011-134.

-----------. 2003b. "Providing for the Unexpected: Constitutional Emergency Provision " Israeli Yearbook on Human Rights 33:13-44.

Hacker, Jacob, et al. 2005. Inequality and Public Policy. Washington, D.C.: Task Force on Inequality and American Democracy, American Political Science Association.

Haggard, Stephan, and Mathew D. McCubbins, eds. 2001. Presidents, Parliaments, and Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hall, Stuart. 1988. The Hard Road to Renewal: Thatcherism and the Crisis of the LeftVerso.

-----------. 1996. "Gramsci's Relevance for the Study of Race and Ethnicity." In Stuart Hall: Critical Dialogues in Cultural Studies, edited by David Morley and Kuan-Hsing Chen. London: Routledge.

Hand, Learned. 1977. The Spirit of Liberty: Papers and Addresses of Learned Hand. 3rd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Hardin, Russell. 2004. "Civil Liberties in the Era of Mass Terrorism." Journal of EthicHarrison, Brian H. 1978. Separate Spheres: The Opposition to Women's Suffrage in B ain.

London: Croom Helm. Hause, Steve C. 1987. "More Minerva than Mars: The French Women's Rights Campaign and

the First World War." In Behind the Lines: Gender and the Two World Wars, edited by Margaret Randolph Higgonet, et al. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Herbst, Jeffrey. 2000. States and Power in Africa: Comparative Lessons in Authority and Control Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Heydemann, Steven, ed. 2000. War, Institut cial Change in the Middle EasBerkele ity of California P

Heymann, Philip B. 2003. Terrorism, Freedom, and Security: Winning Without War. mbridge: MIT Press.

Higgonet, Margaret Randolph, et al., eds. 1987. Behind the Lines: Gender and the Two World Wars. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Hintze, Otto. 1975. "Military Organization and the Organization of the State." In The Historical Essays of Otto Hintze, edited by Felix Gilbert. New York: Oxford University Press.

y, edited

s.

. London:

s 8:77-95. rit

. ions and Soress.

t.

Cay: Univers

Page 66: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 65

Hofnung, Menachem. 1996. Democracy, Law and National Security in Israel. Dartmouth: Aldershot.

Holmes, Stephen. 2003. "Lineages of the Rule of Law." In Democracy and the Rule of Law, edited by José María Maravall and Adam Przeworski. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hunt, Michael H. 1987. Ideology and U.S. Foreign Policy. New Haven: Yale University Press. Hussain, Nasser. 2003. The Jurisprudence of Emergency: Colonialism and the Rule of Law. Ann

Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Ignatieff, Michael. 2004a. The Lesser Evil. Princeton: Princeton University Press. -----------. 2004b. "Lesser Evils." New York Times Magazine. Issacharoff, Sa uel, and Richard H. Pildes. 2005. "Between Civil Libertarianism and Executive

Unilate lism: An Institutional Process Approach to Rights During Wartime." In The Constit in Wartime: Beyond Alarmism and Complacency, edited by Mark Tushnet. Durham Duke University Press.

Janowitz, Morris. 1976. "Military Institutions and Citizenship in Western Societies." Armed Forces and Society 2 (2):185-204.

Jenson, Jane. 1987. "The Liberation and New Rights for French Women." In Behind the Lines: Gender and the Two World Wars, edited by Margaret Randolph Higgonet, et al. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Jervis, Robert. 1997. System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Kage, Rieko. 2005. "Defeat and Reconstruction: Explaining the Rise of Civic Engagement in the Wake of Wars." Ph.D. diss., Department of Government, Harvard University.

Karnow, Stanley. 1989. In Our Image: America's Empire in the Philippines. New York: Random House.

Kasza, Gregory J. 1996. "War and Comparative Politics." Comparative Politics 29 (1):355-73. Katznelson, Ira, and Martin Shefter, eds. 2002. Shaped by War and Trade: International

Influences on American Political Development. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Keith, Linda Camp, and Steven C. Poe. 2004. "Are Constitutional State of Emergency Clauses

Effective? An Empirical Exploration." Human Rights Quarterly 26:1071-97. Keohane, Robert. 2002. "The Globalization of Informal Violence, Theories of World Politics,

and 'The Liberalism of Fear'." In Understanding September 11, edited by Craig Calhoun, et al. New York: Social Science Research Council/New Press.

Kerber, Linda. 1998. No Constitutional Rights to be Ladies: Women and the Obligations of Citizenship. New York: Hill & Wang.

Keyssar, Alexander. 2000. The Right to Vote: The Contested History of Democracy in the United States. New York: Basic Books.

Kimmerling, Baruch. 1985. The Interrupted System: Israeli Civilians in War and Routine Times. New Brunswick: Transaction Books.

-----------. 2001. The Invention and Decline of Israeliness: State, Society, and the Military. Berkeley: University of California Press.

King, Gary, and Langche Zeng. 2001. "Explaining Rare Events in International Relations." International Organization 55 (3):693-715.

Klinkner, Philip A., and Rogers M. Smith. 2000. The Unsteady March: The Rise and Decline of Racial Equality in America. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

mraution:

Page 67: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 66

Kmiec, Douglas W. 2003. "The Supreme C s of Hot and Cold War: Learning from the Sounds of Silence for a War on Terrorism." Journal of Supreme Court History 28 (3):270-99.

h Center for the People and the Press.

How It Might." International Security 28 (4):85-124.

al Rhetoric." European Journal of International Relations forthcoming. al

e Road to War in Iraq." Presented at International Studies Association

srael's re." Cardozo Law Review 10:529-60.

Lawyer ecurity ited States. New York: Lawyers Committee for Human

Legro, trategies and International Order.

Levy, Jack S. 1990. "Big Wars, Little Wars, and Theory Construction." International

Linz, Juan J. 1994. "Presidential or Parliamentary Democracy: Does It Make a Difference?" In erican Evidence, edited by Juan J.

Lowi, T : Ideology, Policy, and the Crisis of Public

Lustick ands. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Mahon

ocracy:

Mansfi g the Prince: The Ambivalence of Modern Executive

Marcus rties ess.

Mayhe tics." Perspectives on Politics 3 (3):473-93. McAdam, Doug, et al. 2001. Dynamics of Contention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

ourt in Time

Kohut, Andrew, et al. 2006. Iran a Growing Danger, Bush Gaining on Spy Issue. Washington, D.C.: Pew Research Center for the People and the Press.

-----------. 2004. Foreign Policy Attitudes Now Driven by 9/11 and Iraq. Washington, D.C.: Pew Researc

Krebs, Ronald R. 2004. "A School for the Nation? How Military Service Does Not Build Nations, and

-----------. 2006. Fighting for Rights: Military Service and the Politics of Citizenship. Ithaca:Cornell University Press.

Krebs, Ronald R., and Patrick T. Jackson. 2006. "Twisting Tongues and Twisting Arms: The Power of Politic

Krebs, Ronald R., and Jennifer Lobasz. 2006. "Fixing the Meaning of September 11: RhetoricCoercion and thAnnual Convention, San Diego, CA.

Lahav, Pnina. 1988-1989. "A Barrel Without Hoops: The Impact of Counterterrorism on ILegal Cultu

Lasswell, Harold. 1941. "The Garrison State." American Journal of Sociology 46 (4):455-68. s Committee for Human Rights. 2003. Assessing the New Normal: Liberty and Sfor the Post-September 11 UnRights. Jeffrey W. 2005. Rethinking the World: Great Power SIthaca: Cornell University Press.

Interactions 16 (3):215-24.

The Crisis of Presidential Democracy: The Latin AmLinz and Arturo Valenzuela. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. heodore. 1969. The End of LiberalismAuthority. New York: W.W. Norton. , Ian S. 1993. Unsettled States, Disputed L

Lyall, Sarah. 2005. "Stricter Antiterror Laws in Britain." New York Times. ey, James. 2000. "Path Dependence in Historical Sociology." Theory and Society 29:507-48.

Mainwaring, Scott, and Matthew S. Shugart. 1997. "Juan Linz, Presidentialism, and DemA Critical Appraisal." Comparative Politics 29 (4):449-71.

Mann, Michael. 1998. The Sources of Social Power, Vol. 2: The Rise of Classes and Nation-States, 1760-1914. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. eld Jr., Harvey C. 1989. TaminPower. New York: Free Press. , George E., et al. 1995. With Malice Toward Some: How People Make Civil LibeJudgments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Pr

Marshall, T.H. 1950. Citizenship and Social Class. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. w, David R. 2005. "Wars and American Poli

Page 68: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 67

Merom, Gil. 2003. How Democracies Lose Small Wars. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Mettler, Suzanne. 2005. Soldiers to Citizens: The G.I. Bill and the Making of the Greatest Generation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. , John, and Timothy HaggertModell y. 1991. "The Social Impact of War." Annual Review of

Moe, Tal of

--------- . "'Our Mission and Our Moment': George W. Bush and September 11th."

e Arab h 43:103-32.

of Chicago Press.

." In Defense Spending and Economic Growth, edited by

Pierson rocesses."

--------- ton

. New York: Free Press. w

Przewo et al. 2000. Democracy and Development: Political Institutions and Well-

Rasler, tes, 1890-1970."

Rasler, Karen A., and William R. Thompson. 1989. War and State Making: The Shaping of

---------iorgio Ausenda. San Marino: Center for Indisciplinary Research on Social

Sociology 17:205-24. erry M., and Michael Caldwell. 1994. "The Institutional Foundations of Demcoratic Government: A Comparison of Presidential and Parliamentary Systems." JournInstitutional and Theoretical Economics 150 (1):171-95.

Murphy, John M. 1992. "Epideictic and Deliberative Strategies in Opposition to War: The Paradox of Honor and Expediency." Communication Studies 43 (2):65-78. --. 2003Rhetoric & Public Affairs 6 (4):607-32.

Murphy, Paul L. 1979. World War I and the Origin of Civil Liberties in the United States. New York: W.W. Norton.

Osatsky-Lazar, Sara. 2002. "The Military Administration as a Control Mechanism Over thCitizens: The First Decade, 1948-1958." Mizrah He-Hadas

Page, Benjamin I., and Robert Y. Shapiro. 1992. The Rational Public: Fifty Years of Trends in Americans’ Policy Preferences. Chicago: University

Payne, James E., and Anandi P. Sahu. 1993. "Defense Spending and Economic Growth: An Evaluation of the Overall ImpactJames E. Payne and Anandi P. Sahu. Boulder: Westview. , Paul. 2000. "Not Just What, But When: Timing and Sequence in Political PStudies in American Political Development 14 (1):72-92. --. 2004. Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton: PrinceUniversity Press.

Porter, Bruce D. 1994. War and the Rise of the State: The Military Foundations of Modern Politics

Posner, Eric A., and Adrian Vermeule. 2003. "Accommodating Emergencies." Stanford LaReview 56 (3):605-44.

Price, Richard. 1998. "Reversing the Gun Sights: Transnational Civil Society Targets Land Mines." International Organization 52 (3):613-44. rski, Adam, Being in the World, 1950-1990. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Przeworski, Adam, and Fernando Limongi. 1997. "Modernization: Theories and Facts." World Politics 49 (2):155-83. Karen A. 1986. "War, Accommodation, and Violence in the United StaAmerican Political Science Review 80 (3):921-45.

Global Powers. Boston: Unwin Hyman. --. 1992. "Assessing the Costs of War: A Preliminary Cut." In Effects of War on Society, edited by GStress.

Rehnquist, William H. 1998. All the Laws But One: Civil Liberties in Wartime. New York: Knopf.

Page 69: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 68

Relyea, Harold. 1974. A Brief History of Emergency Powers in the United States. In Special Committee on National Emergencies and Delegated Emergency Powers. Washington,

Ritter, Gretchen. 2002. "Of War and Virtue: Gender, American Citizenship and Veterans'

Robin, ry of a Political Idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

--------- e. New

Rossiteeton University Press.

Rousseau, David L., and Bruce Newsome. 2004. Women, Minorities, and War: The Impact of

t. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Samuels, David. 2006. "Separation of Powers." In Oxford Handbook of Comparative Politics,

d at Conference on

sity Press.

al

--------- ergency: States of Exception and the Temptations of

Scheue "The Economic State of Emergency." Cardozo Law Review 21

-------- Israel Yearbook

-------- lture, Politics: Rethinking 9/11,

-------- rnal of Political

mocracy, American Political Science Association.

overeignty.

D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office.

Benefits After World War II." Comparative Social Research 20:201-26. Corey. 2004. Fear: The Histo

Rosen, Jeffrey. 2001. "The Nation: What Price Security? Testing the Resilience of American Values." New York Times, November 18, 1. --. 2004. The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom in an Anxious AgYork: Random House. r, Clinton L. 1948. Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies. Princeton: Princ

Rossiter, Clinton, and Richard P. Longaker. 1976. The Supreme Court and the Commander in Chief. expanded edition ed. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Wartime Mobilization on Political Rights in Europe, 1900-1955. unpublished ms.: University of Pennsylvania.

Ruttan, Vernon W. 2006. Is War Necessary for Economic Growth? Military Procurement and Technology Developmen

Said, Edward. 1978. Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient. New York: Pantheon.

edited by Susan Stokes and Carles Boix. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Samuels, David, and Kent Eaton. 2002. "Presidentialism and Parliamentarism: The State of the

Literature and an Agenda for Future Research." PresenteConsequences of Political Institutions in Democracy, Duke University.

Sandler, Todd, and Keith Hartley. 1995. The Economics of Defense. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer

Scheppele, Kim Lane. 2003. "Aspirational and Aversive Constitutionalism: The Case for Studying Cross-Constitutional Influence Through Negative Models." InternationJournal of Constitutional Law 1 (2):296-324. --. 2004. "Law in a Time of Em9/11." University of Pennsylvania Journal of Constitutional Law 6 (5):1001-83. rman, William E. 2000.(5-6):1869-94.

---. 2003. "Emergency Powers and the Compression of Time and Space." on Human Rights 33:45-62.

---. 2005. "Rethinking Crisis Government." In Terror, Cuedited by Terry Nardin. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

---. 2006. "Emergency Powers and the Rule of Law After 9/11." JouPhilosophy 14 (1):61-84.

Schlozman, Kay L., et al. 2005. Inequalities of Political Voice. Washington, D.C.: Task Force onInequality and American De

Schmitt, Carl. 1985. Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of STranslated by George Schwab. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Page 70: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 69

Shapiro, Bruce. 2002. "All in the Name of Security." In A Just Response: The Nation on Terrorism, Democracy, and September 11, 2001, edited by Katrina vanden Heuvel. New

Shaw, M ocial Theory of Total War and Peace.

e Constitutional Choices." British Journal of Political

Shugaridge University Press.

niversity Press.

ion." Journal of Law & Society 10 (1):71-84. an

. Fiorina. Washington, D.C. and New

Skocpo nizers: The Institutional Origins of Civic .

---------

Sloane, etoric. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

and Cohesion of Ethnic Communities." Ethnic and Racial Studies 4 (4):375-97. .

--------- ars and the Attenuation of the State: Soldiers, Money, and Political

olitical Development, edited by Ira Katznelson

onstitution in Wartime: Beyond Alarmism and Complacency,

Stein, AStein, A sequences."

Stohl, M

Stone, ime." Journal of Supreme Court History 28

--------- ilous Times: Free Speech in Wartime from the Sedition Act of 1798 to the

Stuntz, rror." Yale Law Journal 111.

York: Thunder's Mouth Press/Nation Books. artin. 1988. Dialectics of War: An Essay in the S

London: Pluto Press. Shugart, Matthew S. 1998. "The Inverse Relationship Between Party Strength and Executiv

Strength: A Theory of Politicians'Science 28 (1):1-29. t, Matthew Soberg, and John M. Carey. 1992. Presidents and Assemblies: Constitutional Design and Electoral Dynamics. Cambridge: Cambr

Shugart, Matthew Soberg, and Stephan Haggard. 2001. "Institutions and Public Policy in Presidential Systems." In Presidents, Parliaments, and Policy, edited by Stephan Haggard and Mathew D. McCubbins. Cambridge: Cambridge U

Sim, Joe, and Philip A. Thomas. 1983. "The Prevention of Terrorism Act: Normalising the Politics of Repress

Skocpol, Theda. 1999. "How Americans Became Civic." In Civic Engagement in AmericDemocracy, edited by Theda Skocpol and Morris PYork: Brookings Institution Press and Russell Sage Foundation. l, Theda, et al. 2000. "A Nation of OrgaVoluntarism in the United States." American Political Science Review 94 (3):527-46--. 2002. "Patriotic Partnerships: Why Great Wars Nourished American Civic Voluntarism." Unpublished ms., Princeton. Thomas O., ed. 2001. Encyclopedia of Rh

Smith, Anthony D. 1981. "War and Ethnicity: The Role of Warfare in the Formation, Self-Images

Sparrow, Bartholomew H. 1996. From the Outside In: World War II and the American StatePrinceton: Princeton University Press. --. 2002. "Limited WCommunication in World War II, Korea, and Vietnam." In Shaped by War and Trade:International Influences on American Pand Martin Shefter. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Spiro, Peter J. 2005. "Realizing Constitutional and International Norms in the Wake of September 11." In The Cedited by Mark Tushnet. Durham: Duke University Press. rthur A. 1978. The Nation at War. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. rthur A., and Bruce M. Russett. 1980. "Evaluating War: Outcomes and Con

Unpublished ms., New York. ichael. 1976. War and Domestic Political Violence: The American Capacity for

Repression and Reaction. Beverly Hills: Sage. Geoffrey R. 2003. "Civil Liberties in Wart(3):216-51. --. 2004. PerWar on Terrorism. New York: W.W. Norton. William J. 2002. "Local Policing After the Te

Sullivan, John L., et al. 1982. Political Tolerance and American Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Page 71: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 70

Sunstein, Cass R. 2003. "Terrorism and Probability Neglect." Journal of Risk and Uncertai(2/3):121-36

nty 26 .

of

Thomp R. 1993. "The Consequences of War." International Interactions 19 (1-

tional Review

Tribe, L

le

Tushne Reflections on Civil Liberties in Wartime."

Viscusi khauser. 2003. "Sacrificing Civil Liberties to Reduce

Vladec 114:149-

Wæver, Ole. 1995. "Securitization and Desecuritization." In On Security, edited by Ronnie

al

Whalen Great War, 1914-1939.

Wilson he Separation of Powers." In Separation of

erprise Institute for Public Policy Research.

ersity Press. tury.

view

Thelen, Kathleen. 1999. "Historical Institutionalism in Comparative Politics." Annual ReviewPolitical Science 2:369-404. son, William2):125-47.

Tilly, Charles. 1992. Coercion, Capital, and European States, AD 990-1992. Cambridge: Blackwell.

-----------. 1995. "The Emergence of Citizenship in France and Elsewhere." Internaof Social History 40 (supplement 3):223-36.

Titmuss, Richard M. 1969 [1958]. "War and Social Policy." In Essays on the "Welfare State". Boston: Beacon Press. aurence. 2001. "Trial By Fury: Why Congress Must Curb Bush's Military Courts." The

New Republic:18-20. Tribe, Laurence H., and Patrick O. Guthridge. 2004. "The Anti-Emergency Constitution." Ya

Law Journal 113 (8):1801-70. Tsebelis, George. 2002. Veto Players: How Political Institutions Work. New York/Princeton:

Russell Sage Foundation/Princeton University Press. t, Mark. 2003. "Defending Korematsu: Wisconsin Law Review 274:273-307. , W. Kip, and Richard J. ZecTerrorism Risks." Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 26 (2/3):99-120. k, Stephen I. 2004. "Emergency Power and the Militia Acts." Yale Law Journal94.

Lipschutz. New York: Columbia University Press. Waldron, Jeremy. 2003. "Security and Liberty: The Image of Balance." Journal of Politic

Philosophy 11 (2):191-210. Walker, R.B.J. 1993. Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press. Weldes, Jutta. 1999. Constructing National Interests: The United States and the Cuban Missile

Crisis. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. , Robert Weldon. 1984. Bitter Wounds: German Victims of the Ithaca: Cornell University Press. , James Q. 1986. "Political Parties and tPowers--Does It Still Work?, edited by Robert A. Goldwin and Art Kaufman. Washington, D.C.: American Ent

Winter, Jay. 1995. Sites of Memory, Sites of Mourning: The Great War in European Cultural History. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ

Winter, Jay, and Emmanuel Sivan, eds. 2000. War and Remembrance in the Twentieth CenCambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Wood, Diane P. 2003. "The Rule of Law in Times of Stress." University of Chicago Law Re70:455-70.

Zakaria, Fareed. 2003. The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at Home and Abroad. New York: W.W. Norton.

Page 72: The Father of All Things - University of Minnesotausers.polisci.umn.edu/~ronkrebs/Publications/Krebs, War and Democ… · have revised their laws on immigration, preventive detention,

Krebs, The Father of All Things? • 71

Zaller, John. 1992. The Nature and Origins of Mass Opinion. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.