the incorporeality of god' context and implications of origen's position

Upload: manticora-mvtabilis

Post on 12-Oct-2015

6 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • Religion (1983) 13, 345-358

    THE INCORPOREALITY OF GOD

    CONTEXT AND IMPLICATIONS OF ORIGEN S

    POSITION

    Gedaliahu Stroumsa

    Among second century Middle-Platonists, apophatic language seems to have

    been a most common way of expressing God's transcendence. Apuleius,

    Maximus Tyrius, Celsus, Numenius, the Chaldaean Oracles, all develop, in

    rather similar ways, the Platonic doctrine of God's ineffability . )

    One of the attributes which can in no way be predicated of God is cor-

    poreality. In the tenth chapter of the Didaskalikos, for instance, Albinus seeks to

    demonstrate that the simplicity, the perfect unity of God, implies his incor-

    poreality . 2

    In this absolute denial of God's corporeality, the Middle Platonists were not

    only pursuing a centuries-long argument with Stoicism. They were also the

    heirs of a long chain of philosophical, rationalist criticism of traditional

    religion-which contested, in particular, anthropomorphic conceptions of the

    Gods . 3

    When the Christian theologian Origen asserts, in the first half of the third

    century, the incorporeality of God, he is therefore in no way original . Parallels

    between him and Albinus, in particular, have long been noted . 4 Earlier

    Christian writers, such as Justin, Athenagoras, Tatian and Clement of

    Alexandria, had already made use of the word asbmatos . Yet, with the exception

    of Clement, these writers had not used this term in a rigorous way . Clement's

    Platonism is more cogent : God is noetos, and therefore asSmatos . 5

    What is peculiar to Origen, and deserves, I think, more attention than it

    thus far has been given, is the context in which Origen develops his view, and

    the central role that God's incorporeality plays in the overall structure of his

    thought .

    I shall attempt to show that Origen here faces a major tension (one might

    almost say an antinomy) inherent within biblical tradition, a tension which

    leads to the double temptation of anthropomorphism and dualism . Origen's

    0048-721 X/83/040345 + 14 $ 0 2 .00/0 1983 Academic Press Inc

    . (London) Ltd .

  • 346 G. Stroumsa

    solution to this tension succeeded to resolve the implicit conflict between the

    personal creator God and his absolute incorporeality; it has had momentous

    implications upon subsequent Christian exegesis, theology and mysticism .

    Those implications hopefully will be enlightened by an analysis of the place of

    God's incorporeality in Origen's thought .

    Origen deals with the problem in various places : in the Contra Celsum, in his

    Homilies on Genesis, 6 and in particular in his Commentary on John . 7 Yet nowhere

    do its context and implications appear as clearly as in the Peri Archon, and it

    might be legitimate to focus the analysis on this last text . Written before 230,

    the Peri Archon is both one of Origen's first works, and no doubt his major

    theological opus . It has no known literary predecessors;$ contemporary

    philosophers did seek the essence of the archai 9-which the Academy, in

    opposition to the Stoa, affirmed to be incorporeal . On this issue, of course,

    Origen stands on the side of the Academy, and his works-especially the

    Contra Celsum-contribute much to our doxographic evidence on Stoic

    doctrines .10

    The whole orientation of Origen's system, however, is fundamentally

    different from the inquiries peri archo"n of contemporary pagan philosophers .

    For it is a Christian system, in which the only arche, essentially, is God-in his

    three aspects, but mainly as the Father."

    The Pen' Archon opens with a polemic against anthropomorphicropomorphic conceptions

    of God :

    I am aware that there are some who will try to maintain that even according to our

    scriptures God is a body, since they find it written in the books of Moses : "Our

    God is a consuming fire" (Deut4:24), and in the Gospel according to John : "God is

    spirit, and they who worship him must worship in spirit and in truth" (In 4:24) .

    Now these men will have it that fire and spirit are body and nothing else . 12

    Although Origen does not explicitly name his opponents here, they are,

    obviously, Christians (quoniam inueniunt scriptum esse apud Moysen) . Moreover,

    they do not seem to be those unsophisticated anthropomorphists whom

    Origen calls the akeriotatoi, or simpliciores, whose opinions he attacks elsewhere .

    Rather, it is Christians influenced by Stoic conceptions-'des Chretiens

    stoicisants', as it has been suggested to call them 13-whom he has in mind,

    and this assertion can be easily proven . Indeed, it is in consequence of the

    saying `God is Spirit' Un 4:24) that these people think God to be a body . Now

    the Stoics' corporealism has been mentioned above . For them, there can be no

    incorporeal being, since existence is defined by the body . God, therefore, being

    a spirit, is only the purest of all bodies . As Celsus says, when the Christians

    `say God is spirit, there is in this respect no difference between [them] and the

    Stoics among the Greeks who affirm that God is spirit that has permeated all

    things and contains all things within himself .' 14 To which Origen replies that

  • The Incorporeality of God 347

    `the oversight and providence of God does permeate all things, but not like the

    spirit of the Stoics', for whom `the first principles are corporeal', and `the

    supreme God himself destructible'

    .15

    Had Origen sought, in the Peri Archon, to confront individuals, rather than

    trends, we could have seen in its first chapter an answer to the rhetorical

    question of Tertullian, the best known exponent of Stoic influences among the

    Fathers: 'Quis enim negabit deum corpus esse, etsi dens spiritus est? spiritus enim corpus

    sui generis in sua effigie .'

    16

    As a Platonist, Origen strongly contests this conception : there is no possi-

    bility of conceiving a non-material body . Therefore any attribution of cor-

    poreality to God implies his materiality and his corruptibility :

    And if God is declared to be a body, then, since every body is made of matter, we

    shall find that God is made of matter too ; and if so, then, since matter is

    undoubtedly corruptible, God will according to them be corruptible . 17

    Moreover, the corporeality of God also implies his divisibility as Origen

    notes in the Peri Euches:

    in order to remove a mean conception of God held by those who consider that he is

    locally "in heaven", and to prevent anyone from saying that God is in a place after

    the manner of a body (from which it follows that he is a body)-a tenet which leads

    to the most impious opinions, namely, to suppose that he is divisible, material,

    corruptible. For every body is divisible, material, corruptible . 18

    The corporeality of God, Origen says, is thus not simply a mistaken con-

    ception, it is, in a very basic sense, dangerous for the Christian faith . In his

    Commentary on John (XIII .2 1), the Stoic tenet is condemned because it misleads

    simple Christians . Indeed, it can give a theoretical support to those who are

    capable of only a literal reading of the Bible (kata ton recon), which would imply

    that God has not only a body, but also wings!

    19

    Origen understandably opposes such tendencies, which would deny any

    intellectual respectability to Christianity . Even so, the Peri Archon opens

    precisely with a polemic against those Christians who admitted with the Stoics

    that God, being a Spirit, had a body-this striking fact demands our

    attention . 20

    For, if the system developed in the Peri Archon is established like so many

    other theological patristic works-upon a polemical basis, it is mainly a

    polemic against dualism . 21 Although some passages seek to refute specific

    Valentinian or Marcionite doctrines, Origen usually speaks of the `heretics',

    meaning the Gnostics in general, 22 also referring to `Marcion, Valentinus and

    Basilides', en bloc . 23 It is the very foundations upon which Gnostic dualist

    thought is established that Origen seeks to confront and overthrow .

    Now the Gnostics partake, with Origen, in the basic Platonic conception of

  • 3 48 G. Stroumsa

    the archai as incorporeal. Moreover, I think it can be shown-and I have tried

    to do so elsewhere24-that the urge to avoid a literal reading of the biblical

    anthropomorphisms, which would attribute them to God-was a significant

    factor in the origins of dualist Gnosticism .

    Textual evidence confirms that the various gnostic trends held a lofty

    conception of the Deity, beyond body, and even essence . The Gnostics, like the

    second-century Platonists, used apophatic language when they spoke about

    the supreme Deity . On this, the Nag Hammadi texts support descriptions of

    Patristic heresiologists ; 25 for our purposes, a few quotations will suffice .

    In the tractate Marsanes, the Spirit, i .e . the unbegotten one, `does not have

    being'. It is also said to be incorporeal . 26 The Apocryphon of John goes even

    further, in declaring that the invisible Spirit is `completely perfect, illimitable,

    . . . unsearchable immeasurable, invisible, . . ineffable, . . . not corporeal

    [nor] incorporeal .' 27 Such a theologia negatiua is attested further by other new

    texts, like Zostrianos28 orAllogenes, 29 or the Tripartite Tractate. 30 Prior to the Nag

    Hammadi discovery, the strongest known Gnostic proponent of apophatic

    language was Basilides-who denied of God even existence . 31

    Now according to Origen's testimony, it is the Gnostics' emphasis on the

    invisibility of God-a doctrine different from, but, as we shall see, closely

    related to his incorporeality-which is at the source of their rejection of the

    Old Testament God :

    But since the supporters of this heresy are sometimes wont to beguile the hearts of

    very simple people by certain fallacious sophistries, I think it is not unreasonable to

    bring forward the points raised in their arguments and to refute their deceit and

    falsehoods . They say that it is written : "No man hath seen God at any time" (John

    1 :18); yet the God whom Moses proclaims was seen by Moses himself and before

    that by the patriarchs, whereas the God who is announced by the Saviour has been

    seen by no one at all .32

    This text shows that the Gnostic heretics reject the God of the Old Testament

    on the basis that he can be seen-which cannot be said of the true God . In

    other words, they insist on a literal reading of such biblical verses which

    describe God as visible .

    Elsewhere, Origen states that the heretics slander the God of the Old

    Testament, when they attribute to him literally the passions mentioned in

    Scripture .33

    In Origen's view, therefore, the transcendent middle-Platonist theology of the

    Gnostics is not less dangerous for the simple believers than Stoic corporealism .

    Both conceptions, while they lead simple minds to basically different theo-

    logical errors, do so on the basis of the same principle : taking the biblical

    anthropomorphisms literally . In this respect, both attitudes are wrong, and

    dangerous, because they refuse to exegete the biblical text-or, more precisely,

    its anthropomorphic passages .

    In both attitudes, the lack of an exegetical approach leads to the confron-

  • The Incorporeality of God349

    tation between scripture and philosophy-a confrontation in which one

    element is necessarily subdued : philosophy for the anthropomorphists, and

    scripture for the Gnostics . In any case, both attitudes can lead to the same

    theological problems .

    The prolation (probole) of the Son by the Father, for instance, a typically

    gnostic doctrine, developed in order to emphasize the complete distinction

    between God and all creatures, implies, according to strict logic, that both the

    generator and generated one be bodies . 34 Similarly, any conception of God's

    corporeality implies His divisibility-and therefore, here too, the Father

    generates the Son in a pro bole. Origen unhesitantly opposes such a position,

    which implies a dangerous mythologisation of Christian thought, and there-

    fore leads to heresy .

    The exegetical methods developed by the ancient Greek grammarians and

    philosophers in order to make decent sense of Greek mythology-and in

    particular of the Homeric writings 35-had been first applied to the biblical

    text by Aristobulos and Philo . In the second and third centuries C.E ., most

    pagan philosophers, who did not hesitate to allegorize mythological texts of

    various origins, still considered the allegorical reading of the Bible to be

    illegitimate . Celsus himself is a good example of this attitude in the second

    century . He refused to the Bible what he readily granted to the myths of other

    nations, and found fault with `those who treat[ed the Mosaic history] allegori-

    cally ' .36

    The only example that Origen is able to bring against Celsus is Numenius

    the Pythagorean :

    In the first book of his work on The Good where he speaks of the nations that believe

    God to be incorporeal, he also included the Jews among them, and did not hesitate

    to quote the sayings of the prophets in his book and to give them an allegorical

    interpretation. 37

    For Porphyry, as for Celsus, allegorical exegesis of the Bible was an

    absurdity, developed by Origen himself-since it is in order to understand

    properly the Greek mysteries that the philosophers had developed this

    method; it is from them that Origen would have learnt it, then applying it

    fraudulently to `foreign fables' . 38

    As we have seen, however, it is at least in good part as a reaction against the

    implications, for Christians, of the Stoic or the Platonic conceptions of God

    that Origen developed his exegetical method . Both conceptions, indeed,

    heighten the immanent double danger of Biblical tradition-which only

    allegorical reading may prevent-anthropomorphism and dualism . The

    principles of this method are specifically stated in the preface of the Peri Archo"n,

    which constitutes one of Origen's most carefully weighed theological state-

    ments, as says H. Chadwick, `perhaps Origen's most important statement

    about the nature of Christian doctrine .. . 139

  • 3 50G. Stroumsa

    In this preface, Origen enumerates the various components of the regulafidei,

    i .e . the beliefs clearly stated in scripture and transmitted by the apostolic

    tradition . 40 By definition, these beliefs are true, and ought not to be discussed .

    There is one, and only one God, both just and good . He created and establi-

    shed all, ex nihilo, gave the Law, and sent to the world, after the prophets, his

    son Jesus Christ, born of Him before all creation . Jesus Christ, although being

    God, took a body similar to our body, suffered and died, then was resurrected

    and rose to heaven .41 Yet, Origen adds, some questions are neither expressly

    stated in scripture, nor dealt with by apostolic tradition . For instance, it is not

    clear whether the Holy Spirit, too, must be considered as a Son of God, or what

    is the exact nature of the Devil and his angels.42

    One of the most serious questions not answered by apostolic predication is

    whether God himself (and also the Son and the Holy Spirit) are corporeal or

    not. To this problem Origen devotes a rather long paragraph-usually termed

    `digression' by scholars . The scriptures themselves, Origen observes, do not

    know the word asomatos .

    The passage ends thus :

    Nevertheless, we shall inquire whether the actual thing which Greek philosophers

    call asomaton or incorporeal is found in the holy scriptures under another name . We

    must also seek to discover how God himself is to be conceived, whether as corporeal

    and fashioned in some shape, or as being of a different nature from bodies, a point

    which is not clearly set forth in the teaching .. .43

    Origen does, in due course, come back to this cardinal question, stating his

    opinion (arbitror) that corporeal beings are called by scripture visible, whereas

    the incorporeal and substantial powers it calls invisible (for instance in Col

    1 :16 f .) . 44 It is this equivalence, throughout the book, between biblical

    invisibility and philosophical incorporeality which constitutes the core of

    Origen's exegetical system . According to this system, theological research

    should investigate points upon which the apostolic tradition is silent,45

    exegeting biblical passages in the light of philosophical concepts . Here is the

    great intellectual achievement of Origen, which demarcates between him and

    the earlier Fathers .'

    The principles of the rule of faith themselves, however, should not be

    investigated; Origen, therefore, does not raise the problem of the Incarnation

    in philosophical terms . These principles Origen compares (Praef. 10) to the

    foundations of the whole building which is `the body of doctrine' . 47

    We see now that the question-raised by modern scholarship since

    the days of de Faye and Volker-whether Origen is principally a systematic

    thinker or a biblical exegete, is a mistaken one . 48 Origen builds a daring, and

    completely new system of Christian thought established upon biblical exegesis ;

    allegorical exegesis is the ultimate criterion of true Christianity . On the other

  • The Incorporeality of God 3 5 1

    hand, the common ground of heresies (together with Judaism) is their rejection

    of exegesis, their literal reading of the biblical text-or, rather, of Old Testament

    anthropomorphisms. Towards the end of the Peri Archon, Origen states :

    Now the reason why all those we have mentioned (i .e . the Jews and the Gnostics)

    hold false opinions and make impious or ignorant assertions about God appears to

    be nothing else but this, that scripture is not understood in its spiritual sense, but is

    interpreted according to the bare letter . ..49

    It may be worth noting that this bare letter (to psilon gramma) Origen often

    calls the corporeal (somatikon) sense of scripture50-following in this a well-

    established tradition of Alexandrian exegesis . 51 Beyond this, however, Origen

    may be seeking to emphasize the fact that it is the lack of ability to see the real,

    spiritual sense of the revealed texts which is at the root of the attribution of

    corporeality to God .52

    We have seen how Origen took those verses (such as Jn 1 :18) which mention

    the invisibility of God to indicate His incorporeality . But what does Origen do

    with those other verses, which seem to have played a crucial role in the Gnostic

    rebellion, and which implied in some sense, God could be seen (for example

    Ex. 33 :23 : `You will not see my face, but my back')?53

    Origen states that seeing can apply only to bodies . Since God is absolutely

    incorporeal, one cannot see him with one's physical eyes, but one can know him

    and such is the meaning of the verb `to see' when used about God (or, rather,

    the Trinity) :

    . . . what is called `seeing' and `being seen' in the case of bodily existences is with

    the Father and the Son called `knowing' and `being known' through the faculty of

    knowledge and not through our frail sense of sight.54 .

    God, indeed, cannot be seen-but he can be known ; he is incorporeal, but

    not agnostos as the Gnostic God is . Origen reached this solution to the problem

    of God's incorporeality in his first major treatise . It remains, obviously, of

    central importance for a proper understanding of his later writings, and

    mainly his exegetical and homiletical works . By his acceptance of a main tenet

    of Platonism and its integration into a basically Christian epistemology,55

    Origen was thus able to develop what could be called an intellectualist

    mysticism-for which any oisio of God is a cognitio, the incorporeal soul

    knowing, by nature, its likeness, the incorporeal God .56

    Like Clement, Origen knew that revealed truth needed philosophical

    vocabulary in order to be meaningfully expressed . Yet, unlike Clement, he also

    knew that the relationship between philosophy and scripture was inherently

    problematic, and that equations between the two could not be made at

    random, or at will . More deeply than Clement, he recognized that the accept-

  • 352 G. Stroumsa

    ance of even the best of Greek philosophies, Platonism, could lead to the most

    severe deformations of Christian truth, if unchecked by strict hermeneutical

    rules. This is why Origen's Platonism remains limited within the frame of

    dogma which he himself carefully draws .

    I have hinted above that this qualified Platonism permitted Origen to do

    much more than to offer an ad hoc solution to occasional opponents . Rather, it

    empowered him to confront and overcome a basic antinomy-or a permanent

    double temptation-of biblical monotheism .

    In order to support this claim, we may cast a brief glance at Augustine's case

    against Manichaean dualism . According to his trustworthy testimony, exten-

    sive use of anti-anthropomorphic arguments was made by Manichaean

    propaganda in fourth-century North Africa . We may quote here, at some

    length, from the Confessions :

    For, other than this, that which really is I knew not; and was, as it were, through

    sharpness of wit, persuaded to assert to foolish deceivers, when they asked me :

    `Whence is evil?', `Is God bounded by a bodily shape (et utrum forma corporea deus

    finiretur), and has hair and nails?' . . .

    I, in my ignorance, was much troubled, and, departing from the truth, seemed to

    myself to be making towards it ; because as yet I know not that evil was nothing but

    a privation of good . . . And I know not God to be a spirit, not one who hath parts

    extended in length and breadth, or whose being was bulk . . . And what that should

    be in us by which we were like to God, and might in Scripture be rightly said to be

    `after the Image of God', I was altogether ignorant. 57

    To Augustine's own avowal, therefore, he had been deeply impressed by the

    Manichaean arguments against the anthropomorphism of the Biblical God,

    because he was, in his own words `unable of conceiving another substance

    than that which is visible to our eyes' . 58 It is only his encounter with Latin

    translations of the Platonists' writings-in Milan, under the influence of

    Ambrosius'-which permitted him to break the spell of Manichaean

    argumentation. Only after he had discovered, in these writings, the possibility

    of a purely spiritual-i .e. totally immaterial invisible and incorporeal-being,

    only then could he recognize the Scriptures as true .59 For him, as for Origen,

    vision meant knowledge .

    60

    As he movingly tells in a famous chapter of the Confessions, only on one

    point-albeit a central one-did Platonic metaphysics disagree with biblical

    teaching: the incarnation of the Logos . 61 (Let us remember here that in the Peri

    Archon, similarly, Incarnation which is part of the regula fidei, is not to be

    discussed in philosophical terms .)

    It is this conception of a purely incorporeal being which permitted

    Augustine to reject at once Manichaean dualism and simplistic anthro-

    pomorphism. Such an anthropomorphism, which he says he had always

  • The Incorporeality of God 353

    instinctively rejected 62 could still be encountered among contemporary

    Christians . He mocked those people who could not conceive of allegorical

    language in the Bible . 63 Yet, he adds, these carnal men do, in a sense,

    recognize a dignity in God . The Manichaeans, who claimed to criticize the

    anthropomorphism of the Biblical God, failed lamentably to offer a spiri-

    tualized God . Indeed, Augustine insists, one should laugh, too, at their

    mythological conception of a God essentially limited in space (by the kingdom

    of the prince of evil), and therefore unable to transcend matter . 64

    Augustine adds that of the two evils, anthropomorphism is the lesser one :

    simple people-who did not leave the Catholic church-can still be educated

    and understand that biblical anthropomorphisms, when properly allegorized,

    do not refer to God himself, but to his attributes . Manichaean dualists, on the

    other hand, are unable to offer a spiritual interpretation of their myths, since

    Mani himself presented his teaching as the final, and complete, exegesis of

    former revelations .

    The striking parallel between Origen's and Augustine's confrontations with

    both anthropomorphism and anti-anthropomorphic dualism illustrates the

    fact that Origen's selective use of Platonism opened the way to a major trend of

    Christian spirituality, which could very broadly be called intellectualist

    mysticism . 65 Of this great chain of mystics, such towering figures as Evagrius

    and the Pseudo-Dionysius, after the Cappadocians, were the early theoreti-

    cians . One may note, in particular, that the aniconic conception of the Deity

    affirmed, in the wake of Origen, by Eusebius, had some bearing upon the

    origins of the iconoclastic controversy .66

    This type of intellectualist, aniconic mysticism has been characterized by G .

    Quispel as a Seinsmystik . 67 Side by side with it, Quispel adds, there is a long

    Christian tradition of a Gestaltmystik. For this kind of mysticism, God indeed

    does have a body (as the `simple' anthropomorphists claim) but this body is

    visible only to the mystic . This mystical anthropomorphism is already attested

    in the Pseudo Clementine Homilies (17 .7) : God has a morphe which only the pure of

    heart can see. The similarity of the doctrine of God's body in the Sht ur Qomah

    fragments or in the Hekhalot Zutreti (where the mystic R. Aqiba is presented as

    their proponent) strongly suggests a Jewish origin for this Gestaltmystik . 68 It

    seems, indeed, that mystical anthropomorphism may have been an alternative

    solution to the above-mentioned antinomy between `simple' anthro-

    pomorphism and dualism-for a religious thought which did not, as did

    Alexandrian Christianity, encounter Platonism .

    The corporeality or incorporeality of God indeed seems to occupy a central

    place in the structure of Late Antique thought; it delineates a fundamental

    demarcation among basic religious attitudes, as well as among major philoso-

    phical schools .69

    As is well known, Origen's stand on this issue was to encounter strong

  • 3 54G

    . Stroumsa

    opposition .Those monks who fought Origenism so violently in the fourth

    century Egyptian desert are known as 'anthropomorphists' . By scholarly

    consensus, they are considered to have been primitivefellahin, who understood

    thebiblical anthropomorphisms literally . 70 Further research, however, might

    investigate the possibility that they rather were, like the above-mentioned

    Palestinian rabbis, the bearers of mystical conceptions of God's morphe.

    An earlier version of this paper was read at the Symposium on Philosophy and Religion in

    Late Antiquity, held at the Israel Academy of Sciences and Humanities, Jerusalem,16-18

    March 1981 . I wish to thank the Very Reverend Prof. Henry Chadwick for kindly

    reading and commenting upon this paper .

    NOTES

    1 See mainly A. J. Festugiere, La Revelation d' Hermes Trismegiste, IV : Le Dieu inconnu et

    la gnose (Etudes Bibliques ; Paris: Gabalda, 1954), p . 94 ff. Cf. also H . A . Wolfson,

    `Albinus and Plotinus on Divine Attributes', HTR 45 (1952), pp . 115-30, and, id.,

    `Answers to Criticisms of my Discussions of the Ineffability of God', HTR 67

    (1974), pp. 186-90. In `Negative Attributes in the Church Fathers and the Gnostic

    Basilides ;' HTR 50 (1957), pp . 145-56, Wolfson notes that, dealing with God, both

    Albinus and Plotinus (as well as Gregory of Nyssa), use the term aphairesis as the

    equivalent of apophasis. (p . 148) .For the continued use ofapophatic terminology in

    Origen's time and later, see M . Harl, Origin et la fonction revelatrice du Verbe incarne

    (Patristica Sorbonensia, 2 ; Paris : Le Seuil, 1958), pp . 88-90, esp . p . 89, n . 77 .

    2 This chapter has been translated and studied by Festugiere, op. cit., pp . 95-102.

    See also the analysis ofJ . Dillon, The Middle Platonists (Ithaca, N.Y . : Cornell Univ .

    Press, 1977), pp. 282--85, who notes that this chapter is one of the most original

    parts of the work (p. 268) . For an edition and translation of the whole text, see P.

    Louis, Albinus, Eisagoge-Didaskalikos (Paris : Les Belles Lettres, 1945) .

    3 See the very useful article of Harold W. Attridge, `The Philosophical Critique of

    Religion under the Early Empire',Aufstieg and Niedergang des romischen Reiches 16 .2

    (Berlin : De Gruyter, 1980), pp . 45-78.

    4 See mainly H. Koch, Pronoia and Paideusis: Studien uber Origenes and sein Verhaltnis zum

    Platonismus (Arbeiten zur Kirchengeschichte, 22 ; Berlin-Leipzig : de Gruyter,

    1932), pp. 256-58, esp. p. 258 .

    5 See R . P. Casey, `Clement ofAlexandria and the Beginnings ofChristian Platonism',

    HTR 18 (1925), pp. 39-101, esp. pp. 78-80 .

    6 Hom Gen 1 .13, 56 Doutreleau (SC7 bis) . The context there is `the image ofGod' (Gen

    1 :26) . In Peri Archon (= PA) 1 .2 .6, Origen says he intends to deal with the image

    and the likeness of God in his commentary on Genesis, now lost for the main part . I

    shall quote the PA according to Crouzel and Simonetti's edition, translation and

    commentary (SC 252-253 : books I and II, and SC 268-269 : Books III and IV) .

    Here: vol. I, p. 120 (SC 252) . Cf. N. de Lange, Origen and the Jews: Studies in

    Jewish-Christian Relations in Third Century Palestine (Cambridge: University Press,

    1976), 126 . Unfortunately, de Lange does not pay sufficient attention to the

    polemical context (against Jewish views) in which Origen formulates its opposition

    to any corporeality of God. See G. Stroumsa, `The Hidden Closeness : On the

    Church Fathers and Judaism', Mehkarei Yerushalaim be-Mahshevet-Ysrael 2 (1982),

    pp. 170-175(in Hebrew) .

    7 In Joh. XIII .21 .123-22.131 (C . Blanc, ed ., trans ., tome III ; SC 222, pp .94f).

    See

    also Contra Celsum VI, 63; VII, 27 ; Dialogue with Heraclides (p . 81 Scherer) .

  • The Incorporeality of God 355

    8 See G. Dorival, "La forme du Peri Archon", in Origeniana (Quaderni di Vetera

    Christianorum, 12 ; Bari : Istituto di Letteratura Cristiana Antica, 1975), pp. 33-45 .

    9 See for instance Albinus, Didaskalikos, VIII, 1 .

    10 For Origen's criticism of the Stoic corporealist conception of the archai, see C . Cels .

    VI . 71 ; cf. VII . 37 . In respect with Stoic doctrine, it may be more precise to speak of

    corporealism than of materialism . See E . Weil, "Remarques sur Ie materialisme

    des Stoiciens", in L'Aventure de l'Esprit, Melanges A . Koyre, II (Paris : Hermann,

    1964), pp. 556-572 .

    The best analysis of Origen's polemic against Stoicism is that of H . Chadwick,

    'Origen, Celsus and the Stoa',JTS, N .S. 48 (1947), 34-49 . As Chadwick notes, the

    corporeality of God is one of the two main Stoic doctrines criticized by Origen, the

    other being the doctrine of heimarmene. On Origen's rejection of Stoic terminology

    on the soma, see also E . Elorduy, S . J ., `El Influjo estofco en Orfgenes', Origeniana,

    pp. 277-288, esp. p . 279 .

    11 See B. Steidle, 'Neue Untersuchungen zu Origenes' zrepi &pX&v', ZNW 40 (1941),

    pp. 236-243 . Steidle argues that in the title of his work, Origen directly refers to its

    main opponents, the Marcionites, who, as is known, used to speak of the two (or

    three) archai . See references there, p. 240 . See also the discussion of E . von Ivanka,

    Plato Christianus (Einsiedeln: Johannes Verlag, 1964), p . 110 ff., as well as J .

    Rius-Camps, 'Origenes y Marcion Caracter preferentemente antimarcionita del

    prefacio y del segundo ciclo del Peri Archon, Origeniana ; 297-312 ; and R. Cadiou,

    Introduction au systeme d'Origene (Paris : Belles Lettres, 1932), p . 95 fl:, on Marcionism in

    Origen's time. Clement, who stated the First Principles, the archai, to be un-

    demonstrable (Strom. 11 .4 .13-14) never realized his intention of discussing them at

    length (Strom . 111 .13 .1 ; 21 .2 ; IV .2 .1 ; V .140 .3 ; VI .4 .2 ; Quis dives 26) . Chadwick,

    who refers to these texts, suggests that 'Origen may have wished to fill the gap

    when he wrote his own fateful treatise "On First Principles"' . . . (Early Christian

    Thought and the Classical Tradition, p . 72 .

    12 PA 1 .1 .1 (1, 91 Crouzel-Simonetti) . I quote Butterworth's translation (reprint New

    York: Harper and Row, 1966) . On the meaning ofpneuma/spiritus in early Christian

    literature, see A . H . Armstrong, `The Self-Definition of Christianity in Relation to

    Later Platonism', in E . P. Sanders, ed ., Jewish and Christian Self-Definition, I

    (London: SCM Press, 1980), p. 89 ff.

    13 By A. Beckaert, `L'evolution de l'intellectualisme grec vers la pensee religieuse et la

    releve de la philosophic par la pensee chretienne', Rev . Et . Byz . 19 (1961), p . 59. The

    classic work on the topic, M . Spanneut, Le Stoicisme des Peres de l'Eglise (Patristica

    Sorbonensia ; Paris : Le Seuil, 1957) does not pursue its systematic investigation

    beyond Clement of Alexandria .

    14 C. Celsum VI.71 I quote Chadwick's translation (Cambridge : Cambridge

    University Press, 19803 ), p. 385 .

    15 Ibid., ibid . Cf. ibid ., 1 .21, or IV.1 .4 : ` . . . the God of the Stoics, in that He is

    corporeal . . .' See also ibid . VIII.49, in finem, and Origen, Peri EuchIs 27 .8, to be

    read in parallel with C. Cels . 111 .47, according to which the Stoa, which regards

    `material and corporeal things as fundamental', and asserts `that all ultimate

    realities are corporeal' is implicitly condemned, and belongs (together with

    Epicureanism) to `the wisdom of the earth' (I Cor 1 :26-29) .

    16 Adv. Prax . 7 . Tertullian similarly considers the soul to be corporeal-he calls it `an

    inner man' (De Anima IX.7-8) ; see Spanneut's analysis, op . cit., p . 164 f Tertullian,

    of course, is not fully conscious of the extent of Stoic influences upon his thought,

    and occasionally attacks Stoicism, together with the other philosophical schools-

  • 356 G. Stroumsa

    even claiming that it is from Stoic tenets that Marcion developed his own con-

    ceptions (Praescr. Haer. VII .6) .

    17 PA 11 .4 .3 (I, p . 284 Crouzel-Simonetti) .

    18 Peri Euches 23 .3 . I quote Chadwick's translation in Alexandrian Christianity, ed . J . E . L.

    Oulton and H . Chadwick (Philadelphia: Westminster,1954) .

    19 As implied, for instance, in Ex 19:4. C. Cels . IV .37 . Here again, Origen reflects an

    accusation made by Celsus upon Christians in general .

    20 Indeed, incorporeity is not an independent question, distinct from that of the

    scriptures,as

    Harl remarks ("Structure et coherence du Peri Archon", Origeniana,

    24, n. 38) against Chadwick . The strategic place of the discussionsofGod's incorpo-

    reality in the Peri Archon has been duly noted by M. Alexandre, `Le statut des

    questions concernant la matiere dans le Peri Archon', Origeniana, pp. 63-81,

    esp . p .

    64 .

    21 This fact is recognized also by scholars who do not go as faras Steidle . See for

    instance Chadwick, op .cit . (n . 10 supra), for whom the Peri Archon consists "in the

    main of an elaborate refutation of gnostic dualism and determinism directed

    against Marcion, Valentine and Basilides, and a pioneer attempt to lay down rules

    for the right interpretation ofthe Bible." See especially A . Le Boulluec, `La place

    de la polem que antignostique clans lePeri Archon d'Origene', Origeniana, pp .

    47-61 : ` . . . la polemique antignostique . . . constitue l'un des axes fondamentaux

    de l'ouvrage' (p. 53) .

    22 Except, may be, in I I1 .3 .3, where 'haereseos principes' might refer to the leaders of

    the philosophical schools, as Le Boulluec thinks (ibid . p . 53). Cf. Crouzel-

    Simonetti, vol . IV, 76, n . 16 . As Le Boulluec notes, moreover, the bearers of

    corporeal conceptions of God are never called heretics (ibid . p . 54) .

    23 For instance in 11 .9 .5.On polemical allusions to Gnostic doctrines in other works of

    Origen, see M. Harl, 'Pointes antignostiques d'Origene : le questionnement impie

    des Ecritures', in R. van den Broek and M . J. Vermaseren, eds

    .,Studies in Gnosticism

    and Hellenistic Religions (EPROER 91; Leiden: Brill, 1981), pp. 205-217 .

    24 See `Le couple de I'Ange et de I'Esprit: traditions juives et chretiennes', RB 88

    (1981), pp . 42-61 .

    25See for instance the apophatic terms used by Marcos the Gnostic about the higher

    God, the Propator, in Iranaeus, Adv. Haer. 1 . 14.1 (1, 129 Harvey) .

    26 NHC X,1 ; 4 :14-19 ; 6 :3-5. Cf. the Teachings ofSilvanus, CG VII,

    4;100 :7 ff.: `For it is

    not right for us to say that God is a body', on which see W. E. Schoedel,

    'Topological Theology and Some Monistic Tendencies in Gnosticism', in M.

    Krause, ed., Essays on the Nag Hammadi Texts in Honour ofA. Bohlig (NHS 3 ; Leiden :

    Brill, 1972), pp. 88-108 .

    27 NHC II, 1 ; 3, passim. The puzzling double negation (1 . 23)

    has been explained. by

    Wolfson, `Answers to Criticisms . . .', p . 190 .See the text in M. Krause-P. Labib,

    Die drei Versionen des Apokryphon desJohannes(Wiesbaden : Harrassowitz, 1962), pp.

    115-116 .

    28 NHC VIII, 1 ; 3:11-13 .

    29 NHC XI, 3; 47 :10-11; 62

    :23.

    30 NHC 1,5; 133 :20-21 .

    31See Wolfson, `Negative Attributes', quoted n . 1 .

    supra .

    32 PA 11.4.3 .

    33 PA IV.2 .1 .

    34 PA IV.4 .1 .

    35 See J. Pepin, Mythe et Allegorie(Paris : Aubier-Montaigne, 1958). Cf. esp

    . Eusebius,

    Praep. Evang. VIII . 10.On Philo's use of allegory, see for instance Wolfson,

    Philo I

  • The Incorporeality of God 357

    (Cambridge, Mass . : Harvard U.P., 1957), pp. 115-137.In

    Immut . 11 .54, Philo

    states that the biblical anthropomorphisms, which must not be taken literally,

    serve for the education of the many .

    36 C. Cels . 1 .17 .Beyond anti Judaism-or anti-Christianity-the reasons for this

    attitude remain unclear. It may have been this self-avowed, nay proclaimed

    historical and anti-mythical character of the Hebrew scriptures which prevented

    the pagan philosophers from applying to them methods developed for mytho-

    logical texts .

    37 Ibid. 1 .15 .On Numenius's theology, see H.-C . Puech, `Numenius d'Apamee et les

    theologies orientales au second siecle', in Puech, En quite dela Gnose I (Paris:

    Gallimard, 1978), pp. 25--54. On Numenius's view ofJudaism, see M

    . Stern, Greek and

    Latin Authors on Jews and Judaism II(Jerusalem: Israel Academy of Sciences and

    Humanities,1980), pp . 206-216 .

    38 Quoted by Eusebius, Hist. Eccl. VI .19.5-8 .

    39 Early Christian Thought, p. 79 .

    40 On this topic, see R.-C . Baud, S . J ., `Les `regles' de la theologie d'Origene', Rev . Sc.

    Rel. 55 (1967), pp. 161-206, and J . Fr. Bonnefoy, `Origene theoricien de la methode

    theologique', Melanges . . . Cavallera(Bibliotheque de 1'Institut Catholique de

    Toulouse, 1948), pp. 87-145. (non vidi) . The concept of a regula fidei also appears,

    as is known, in such early theologians as Irenaeus, Tertullian or Hippolytus . See

    for instance D . van den Eynde, Les normes de l'enseignement chretien (Gembloux, Paris:

    Duculot, Gabalda ; 1553), pp. 281-313 .

    41 PA, Preface,4.

    42Ibid ., 6.

    43 Ibid ., 9 . The discussion of the meaning of asdmatosbegins in 8 .

    44 PA 1 .7 .1,in finem (vol . I, 208 Crouzel-Simonetti) : sine uisibilia, quae sunt corporalia,

    sine inuisibilia, quae non alia esse arbitror quam incorporeal substantiasque uirtutes. Cf. 11 .3 .6

    in finem . See also C. Cels . VI .64, in finem, about Col 1 :15 : semainetai de ek tis aoratou

    phones ho asomatos.The identification invisibility = incorporeality is already made

    by Philo (Opif. 29) and is found in the Extracts of Theodotos, 47 (p . 159 Sagnard) .

    45 See for instance PA, Preface,4 ; in finem (on the Holy Spirit) .

    46 Such as Irenaeus, for whom `heresy comes of following the itch to speculate where

    scripture has given no clear guidance' (Chadwick,Early Christian Thought, p . 81) .

    Tertullian had established (De Anima 2,4) the new idea of a constant reference to

    the evangelical regula in the relationships between Christianity and Philosophy-

    but his goal was completely different from that of Origen. For Tertullian, this

    reference permitted, in each case, to check the respective positions of the two great

    adversaries . See the analysis of this text by A . Labhardt, 'Tertullien et la philoso-

    phie ou la recherche d'une "position pure",'Museum Helveticum 7 (1950), pp .

    159-180 .

    47 PA, Preface, 10 .

    48 See for instance the partisan attitude of Crouzel,Origin et la philosophie (Theologie,

    52 ; Paris : Aubier, 1962), p. 179 ff

    .

    49 PA, IV.2 .2 . Cf. H. De Lubac, Histoire et Esprit: l'intelligence de l'Ecriture d'apres Origin

    (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1950), pp . 48-49 .

    50 In PA IV.2.8-9 for instance.

    51See already Philo, de migr. Abr. 83-93 ; cf. Clement, Strom. VI .15 .

    52See also Hom Gen 1 .13 (p . 56

    Doutreleau) .

    53 These verses also provided, of course, the scriptural basis for anthropomorphist

    conceptions of God ; see PA 11 .4 .3 (vol . I, p . 286 Crouzel-Simonetti) where Origen

    mocks such conceptions .

  • 358 G. Stroumsa

    54 PA 1 .1 .8 ; cf. ibid. 11 .4.3 and also C. Cels. VII.43 . In their commentary, Crouzel and

    Simonetti note that in practice, Origen does not always make a difference between

    seeing and knowing (vol . II, p. 29, n . 36) .

    55 "Entre le platonisme et Origene, it y a tout I'Evangile", De Lubac, op . cit., p . 238.

    56 This principle comes from Empedocles and Plato . Crouzel and Simonetti state that

    this is the fundamental axioma of Origenian mysticism, and refer to some texts

    (PA, vol . II, 26, n . 29) . For the incorporeality of the soul-as of all created rational

    natures-see PA 1 .7 .1 .Origen notes, however, that only God (the Trinity) can be

    said to be incorporeal in the absolute sense of the word .

    57 Conf. 111 .7. I quote W . Watts' translation, repr. in the LCL edition. Cf. De Gen .

    contr. Man 1 .27 .

    58 Ibid. VII . 1 .

    59 In Epist. 148 (PL 33, 622), Augustine notes that God is incorporeal for Patristic

    tradition .

    60 See the texts quoted by R . Jolivet and M . Jourjon, Six Traites Anti-Manicheens

    (Oeuvres de Saint Augustin, 17 ; Paris : Desclee, 1961), p . 762, note complementaire

    2. Cf. De Civ. Dei X .13, where he states that Biblical mentions of God's visible form

    should be understood as metaphors .

    61 Conf. VII.9; cf. VII .19 in finem .

    62 Conf. VII . 1 .

    63 C. Epist. Fund. XXIII:25. Cf. Haer. 50.

    64 Ibid., ibid .

    65 On this trend in early Christian spirituality see A . J . Festugiere, "Ascese et

    Contemplation", in L'Enfant d'Agrigente (Paris : Plon, 1950), pp. 134-148 and pp .

    185-186 (notes). Cf. A . Louth, The Origins of the Christian Mystical Tradition (Oxford :

    Clarendon, 1981), on which see my review in Numen 29 (1982), pp. 278-282 .

    66 Cf. G. Florovsky, "Origen, Eusebius and the Iconoclastic Controversy", Church

    History 19 (1950), pp. 77-96 .

    67 In "Sein and Gestalt", Studies in Mysticism and Religion presented to Gerschom G . Scholem

    (Jerusalem: Magnes, 1967), pp. 191-195 .

    68 See G. Stroumsa, "Form(s) of God : Some Notes on Metatron and Christ", HTR 76

    (1983), to appear . On early Jewish mystical literature, see I . Grunewald, Apoca-

    lyptic and Hekhalot Mysticism (AGUWJ 14; Leiden-Koln-Brill, 1980) . See esp . p . 148

    on Hekhalot Zutreki .

    69 In his 'Origen, Celsus and the Resurrection of the Body', HTR 41 (1948),

    pp. 83-102 . Chadwick shows that Origen takes over (and slightly adapts) for his

    own purpose (can the resurrected body have a shape?) arguments used by the

    Academy in the polemic against Epicurean anthropomorphism-according to

    which the Gods had a shape (p . 94) .

    70 See for instance A. Guillaumont, Les 'Kephalaia Gnostica' d'Evagre le Pontique et

    l'histoire de l'origenisme chez les Grecs et les Syriens (Patristica Sorbonensia 5; Paris : Le

    Seuil, 1962), p . 59 ff.

    GEDALIAHU STROUMSA teaches in the Department of Comparative

    Religion in the Hebrew University of Jerusalem. He is currently spending a

    period of study leave at Dumbarton Oaks, Washington, D .C .