the lexicalist hypothesis: both wrong and...

22
The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University of Delaware ([email protected]) draft, March 31, 2015; comments welcome Abstract The Lexicalist Hypothesis, which says that the component of grammar that produces words is distinct and strictly separate from the component that produces phrases, is both wrong and superfluous. It is wrong because there are numerous instances where phrasal syntax feeds word formation, and where phrasal syntax can access sub-word parts. It is superfluous because all the facts that are supposed to be accounted for by the Lexicalist Hypothesis follow from any adequate theory of phrasal syntax. The model of grammar that we are led to is then the most parsimonious one: there is only one combinatorial component of grammar that builds both words and phrases. 1 Introduction The Lexicalist Hypothesis, usually attributed to Chomsky 1970, is a foundational hypothesis in numerous current approaches to morphology and syntax, including Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), Lexical Func- tional Grammar (LFG), Simpler Syntax (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005), various versions of the Principles and Parameters and Minimalist models, and others. 1 The basic tenet of the Lexicalist Hypothesis is that the system of grammar that assembles words is separate from the system of grammar that assembles phrases out of words. The combinatorial system that produces words is supposed to use different principles from the system that produces phrases. Additionally, the word system strictly precedes the phrasal system. This has the result that the phrasal system has no access to sub-word units, and in addition, the output of the phrasal system never forms the input to the word system. An alternative view dispenses with the Lexicalist Hypothesis and argues that the phrasal and word formation systems are not distinct (Sadock 1980, Baker 1985, Sproat 1985, Hale and Keyser 1993, Halle and Marantz 1993, Marantz 1997, Borer 2005, among others). If this view is correct, a model of grammar does not need two separate generative components, but only one. This view has the virtue of simplicity: a model of grammar with only one component is simpler than one with two, and is therefore to be preferred, assuming that they are equivalent in their empirical coverage. In the face of this challenge, numerous recent publications have defended the Lexicalist posi- tion, arguing that the empirical facts demand the strict separation of the word and phrasal systems (e.g., Williams 2007, Newmeyer 2009, Müller 2013, Müller and Wechsler 2014). In this paper I make two points. First, the empirical facts indicate that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is fundamen- tally incorrect. There are numerous instances where the output of the phrasal system feeds word formation, and there are also numerous cases where the phrasal syntax must have access to sub-word units. I make this point in section 2. Second, the Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous. The facts that it is meant to account for are already accounted for by any adequate model of phrasal syntax. This is shown in section 3. Since the Lexicalist Hypothesis is both incorrect and unnecessary, it can and should be dispensed with. We only need a single syntactic module in the grammar, one that produces both words and phrases. Theories that assume the Lexicalist Hypothesis need to be rejected, and researchers should put their efforts into building adequate analyses within a theory with only one component for morphology and syntax. 1 This hypothesis is usually referred to as the Lexicalist Hypothesis, after Chomsky (1970). It is occasionally also referred to as the Lexical Hypothesis (e.g., Williams 2007). The more common name seems to be the Lexicalist Hypothesis, so that is the name I will use. The literature on this hypothesis is too vast to cite fully here. References include Jackendoff (1972), Bresnan (1982), Kiparsky (1982), Simpson (1983), Mohanan (1986), Di Sciullo and Williams (1987), and Bresnan and Mchombo (1995). Many other references can be found in the works cited throughout the text. 1

Upload: others

Post on 09-Feb-2020

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous

Benjamin Bruening, University of Delaware ([email protected])

draft, March 31, 2015; comments welcome

Abstract

The Lexicalist Hypothesis, which says that the component of grammar that produces words is distinct and strictlyseparate from the component that produces phrases, is both wrong and superfluous. It is wrong because there arenumerous instances where phrasal syntax feeds word formation, and where phrasal syntax can access sub-wordparts. It is superfluous because all the facts that are supposed to be accounted for by the Lexicalist Hypothesisfollow from any adequate theory of phrasal syntax. The model of grammar that we are led to is then the mostparsimonious one: there is only one combinatorial component of grammar that builds both words and phrases.

1 Introduction

The Lexicalist Hypothesis, usually attributed to Chomsky 1970, is a foundational hypothesis in numerous currentapproaches to morphology and syntax, including Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), Lexical Func-tional Grammar (LFG), Simpler Syntax (Culicover and Jackendoff 2005), various versions of the Principles andParameters and Minimalist models, and others.1 The basic tenet of the Lexicalist Hypothesis is that the system ofgrammar that assembles words is separate from the system of grammar that assembles phrases out of words. Thecombinatorial system that produces words is supposed to use different principles from the system that producesphrases. Additionally, the word system strictly precedes the phrasal system. This has the result that the phrasalsystem has no access to sub-word units, and in addition, the output of the phrasal system never forms the input tothe word system.

An alternative view dispenses with the Lexicalist Hypothesis and argues that the phrasal and word formationsystems are not distinct (Sadock 1980, Baker 1985, Sproat 1985, Hale and Keyser 1993, Halle and Marantz 1993,Marantz 1997, Borer 2005, among others). If this view is correct, a model of grammar does not need two separategenerative components, but only one. This view has the virtue of simplicity: a model of grammar with only onecomponent is simpler than one with two, and is therefore to be preferred, assuming that they are equivalent in theirempirical coverage. In the face of this challenge, numerous recent publications have defended the Lexicalist posi-tion, arguing that the empirical facts demand the strict separation of the word and phrasal systems (e.g., Williams2007, Newmeyer 2009, Müller 2013, Müller and Wechsler 2014).

In this paper I make two points. First, the empirical facts indicate that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is fundamen-tally incorrect. There are numerous instances where the output of the phrasal system feeds word formation, andthere are also numerous cases where the phrasal syntax must have access to sub-word units. I make this point insection 2. Second, the Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous. The facts that it is meant to account for are alreadyaccounted for by any adequate model of phrasal syntax. This is shown in section 3. Since the Lexicalist Hypothesisis both incorrect and unnecessary, it can and should be dispensed with. We only need a single syntactic module inthe grammar, one that produces both words and phrases. Theories that assume the Lexicalist Hypothesis need tobe rejected, and researchers should put their efforts into building adequate analyses within a theory with only onecomponent for morphology and syntax.

1This hypothesis is usually referred to as the Lexicalist Hypothesis, after Chomsky (1970). It is occasionally also referred to as theLexical Hypothesis (e.g., Williams 2007). The more common name seems to be the Lexicalist Hypothesis, so that is the name I will use.The literature on this hypothesis is too vast to cite fully here. References include Jackendoff (1972), Bresnan (1982), Kiparsky (1982),Simpson (1983), Mohanan (1986), Di Sciullo and Williams (1987), and Bresnan and Mchombo (1995). Many other references can be foundin the works cited throughout the text.

1

Page 2: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

2 The Lexicalist Hypothesis is Wrong

I begin by showing that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is fundamentally incorrect in its view of grammar. There arenumerous cases where the output of the phrasal syntax can demonstrably precede word formation. There are alsocases where the phrasal syntax has access to sub-word units, a state of affairs that is strictly banned by the LexicalistHypothesis.

2.1 Phrasal Syntax Can Feed Word Formation

Let us begin with the strict ordering that is part of the Lexicalist position. According to the Lexicalist Hypothesis,word formation strictly precedes phrasal syntax. The output of the word formation component can feed phrasalsyntax, but not vice versa.

2.1.1 Compounding

The most well-known exception to this strict ordering involves compounding. It is common for nominal compoundsto include a phrase as the first member of the compound (Fabb 1984; Lieber 1988, 1992; Spencer 1988, 1991, 413–417):

(1) a. I gave her a don’t-you-dare! look.b. She baked her fiance a sweet I-love-you cake.

In most theories, compounding must be a lexical process; as we will see below, sub-parts of compounds are gen-erally inaccessible to the phrasal syntax (for instance, in extraction). They should therefore not be able to includephrases that are put together by the phrasal syntax.

In fact, however, the phrases that constitute the first member of these compounds must be put together by thesyntax, because they have the form that the syntax requires. They can be imperatives and have the form of animperative, as in (1a), and they can have the form of a declarative, as in (1b). They can also be wh-questionsand exclamatives, as in the examples in (2). In all cases, if the first member of the compound violates rules andconstraints of the phrasal syntax, the result is ill-formed (3):

(2) a. She had that Don’t-you-dare! look.b. She had that I’m-so-proud-of-myself look.c. She had that What-the-hell-are-you-doing?! look.d. She had that What-a-strange-person-you-are! look.

(3) a. * She had that You-don’t-dare! look. (obligatory inversion with negative imperative)b. * She had that Myself-is-so-proud-of-me look. (reflexive bad as subject)c. * She had that You’re-doing-what-the-hell?! look. (obligatory fronting with wh-the-hell; Pesetsky

1987)d. * She had that What-a-strange-person-are-you! look. (no inversion with exclamatives)

If these phrases were not put together by the phrasal syntax but by some other mechanism, that mechanism wouldhave to precisely duplicate the constraints of the phrasal syntax.

Additionally, as we will see in section 3.3, elements that contribute to word formation cannot generally affectthings that are adjuncts to the elements they combine with. They generally only affect semantic arguments. Incompounding, however, the first element can include various kinds of adjuncts, including adverbial clauses:

(4) She had her usual How-many-times-do-I-have-to-call-[before-you’ll-answer]? look.

Moreover, according to Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) and Williams (2007), the word formation system obeysdifferent principles from the phrasal system, such that the word system is head-final while the phrasal system ishead-initial, in English (there are numerous counterexamples; see section 3.4). If the phrasal part of a compoundwere built by the word system, it should then be head-final, but this is not true:

2

Page 3: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

(5) a. She baked her fiance a sweet I-love-you cake.b. * She baked her fiance a sweet I-you-love cake.

The only conclusion can be that the phrases that appear in compounding are put together by the phrasal syntax.Yet they create units—nominal compounds—that otherwise act like words in the phrasal syntax that they are em-bedded within. For instance, in all of the examples above, they follow determiners and adjectives to form a nounphrase, just like any simple noun. They can also be followed by relative clauses, just like simple nouns, and canappear in any NP position, for instance subject position:

(6) The sweet I-love-you cake that he baked really didn’t taste very good.

They can also be wh-phrases and undergo wh-movement, on the pattern of NPs generally:

(7) Which of these sweet I-love-you cakes are you going to try making?

Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) argue that the phrases that appear in compounds are not counterexamples to theLexicalist Hypothesis. According to them, phrases have to be “lexicalized” to be imported into compounds. Theonly way I can interpret this claim is that apparently a phrase is built by the phrasal syntax, but then becomes somekind of frozen unit in the lexicon, akin to a noun. It can then be used to form a compound.

There are two problems with this. First, allowing this possibility is equivalent to giving up the Lexicalist Hy-pothesis. If phrases can be “lexicalized” and then form an input unit to the word formation component, then there isno sense in which word formation strictly feeds phrasal syntax. The phrasal syntax can feed word formation, sim-ply by building phrases that become lexical units. The Lexicalist Hypothesis has been circumvented and renderedvacuous.

Second, the empirical evidence that Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) give for their claim that compound phrasesmust be “lexicalized” is less than convincing. Using phrases in compounds is completely productive, as the exam-ples above and new product ads show. The fact that non-English can be used, as in a Heil Hitler skinhead (Bresnanand Mchombo 1995, 194, (22)), does not show that these compounds are not put together by the phrasal syntax,since non-English phrases can regularly be manipulated in the phrasal syntax. Postal (2004, chapter 6) discussesthis phenomenon at length. One can say all of the following, in English:

(8) a. He stepped out and yelled Heil Hitler at us.b. Is Heil Hitler German, or French?c. Which part of Heil Hitler do you not understand?

Non-English phrases can be used as objects of verbs and as subjects and even undergo subject-auxiliary inversion.They can also be part of a wh-phrase and undergo wh-movement. Since the phrasal syntax can manipulate non-English phrases, the fact that they can appear in compounds is not evidence that compounds are not using thephrasal syntax. They clearly are.

Compounding, then, is an instance of the ordering that is not supposed to be allowed by the Lexicalist Hypoth-esis: phrasal syntax provides the input to word formation.

2.1.2 Adjectival Passives

Other examples of this situation are not hard to find. Bruening (2014) shows that adjectival passive formation canbe fed by raising to object, a process that many theories regard as syntactic (but not all; see below). Adjectivalpassive formation then feeds further word formation, for instance un-prefixation, as in the following examples withraising to object verbs:

(9) (Bruening 2014, 372, (30))a. . . . his mind is unsound because it starts from premises that are undemonstrated to be true and that

he has no reason to accept as true.

3

Page 4: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

b. [That] remains unestablished to be of any significance at all.c. We are against fad diets and questionable supplements that are unproven to be either safe or effective.d. . . . presence of silicon in bedding plant species previously unreported to be accumulators,. . .e. . . . such studies are important as they may uncover genetic variants in genes previously unsuspected

to be related to the phenotype under study. . .f. No character page should have art that is a) fanmade b) unverified to be that character or c). . .

Again, this is a clear violation of the Lexicalist Hypothesis: a process of phrasal syntax feeds word formation.(See below on viewing raising instead as a lexical process.)

2.1.3 Resultatives

As Müller (2006) shows, the same occurs with resultatives and caused motion constructions. As is well known,objects can be added to verbs that do not select objects in certain constructions, for instance in resultatives:

(10) a. They fished the pond empty.b. * They fished the pond.

(11) a. She danced her shoes bloody.b. * She danced her shoes.

In most Lexicalist theories, word formation processes can only act on semantic arguments of a morpheme. So,if a word formation process were to apply to fish or dance, it would be unable to include an object that is licensedonly by the resultative. As Müller (2006) shows, however, these resultatives quite regularly participate in adjectivalpassive formation and nominalization in German. Corresponding to fish the pond empty is the nominalizationLeerfischung, ‘empty fishing’ (Müller 2006, 868). Corresponding to dance her shoes bloody is the adjective in(12b):

(12) (Müller and Wechsler 2014, 32, (33))a. Er

hetanztdances

diethe

Schuheshoes

blutigbloody

//

ininto

Stücke.pieces

b. diethe

ininto

Stückepieces

//

blutigbloody

getanztendanced

Schuheshoes

c. * diethe

getanztendanced

Schuheshoes

As (12c) shows, the resultative is crucial to forming the adjectival passive, since Schuhe is not an argumentof the verb without it. In most theories, however, resultatives must be part of the phrasal component, since theymanipulate units larger than words. (Müller’s own approach is to assign resultatives to the lexical component; seeimmediately below.)

2.1.4 Raising in Nominalizations

Further examples include many that have been cited as ungrammatical in the literature. For instance, according toChomsky (1970), nominalizations may not include raising to subject or raising to object. These examples are citedagain by Newmeyer (2009) as crucial evidence for the Lexicalist Hypothesis.

(13) a. John was certain/likely to win the prize.b. * John’s certainty/likelihood to win the prize (Chomsky 1970, 189, (8b))

(14) a. We believe God to be omnipotent.b. * our belief of/in God to be omnipotent (Chomsky 1970, 201, (32b))

4

Page 5: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

According to Chomsky and Newmeyer, the Lexicalist Hypothesis rules out raising to subject and raising to objectin the input to nominalization, because they are rules of the phrasal syntax.

However, raising to subject and raising to object do take place in nominalizations. I for one have always found(13b) reasonably acceptable. Numerous examples can be found on the internet, including ones where the genitiveis inanimate, ruling out the genitive being the holder of the psychological state of certainty in the case of certainty:

(15) If that is an accepted premise, the same concept should apply to the net neutrality debate and its certaintyto increase consumer bills.(http://www.foxnews.com/politics/2014/11/17/fcc-official-warns-obama-backed-net-neutrality-plan-will-bring-backdoor-tax-on/)

(16) . . . that the Black Panthers were eager to start a civil war despite its certainty to cause a bloodbath.(blackpanthercivilrights.blogspot.com/)

(17) . . . refused to consider the underlying patent litigation, and its certainty to be a bitter and prolongedprocess.(https://www.wsgr.com/WSGR/Display.aspx?SectionName=publications/PDFSearch/AntitrustWire_0405.htm)

Raising to subject inside a nominalization is even more widespread with likelihood:

(18) Sadly a species’ name affects its likelihood to survive.(https://twitter.com/meeurotaru/status/552744000651001856)

(19) But in this case whether or not a man was in a committed relationship had no influence on his likelihoodto sexually harass.(https://books.google.com/books?isbn=1555536387)

(20) However, if a peer tells the student his joke is “silly” or “stupid” he will be punished by telling the joke andhis likelihood to tell another joke is greatly decreased.(en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Self-control)

Raising to object also seems to be well-attested inside of nominalizations:

(21) do not trust this person or company unless you get proof of them to be different.(http://www.thumbtack.com/wa/bellevue/movers/moving-services)

(22) If anyone got proof of them to be involved in the attack they should take them into the court.(https://www.facebook.com/NationalMartyrs)

(23) . . . again what you are telling us is no proof of them to be hackers.(http://www.kongregate.com/forums/291-yu-gi-oh-bam/topics/379107-new-hack)

(24) The same kind of features she shared with Shakiiya were the only proof of them to be a mother anddaughter, . . .(https://www.fanfiction.net/s/10668250/4/Athélèrn-Ithilrim)

(25) This indicates his acceptance of them to be ministers in his church, at all levels.(https://books.google.com/books?isbn=1602666024)

(26) . . . for true confession consisteth in the general, in a man’s taking to himself his transgressions, with theacknowledgment of them to be his,. . .(The Pharisee and the Publican By John Bunyan)

(27) . . . and how I may be erroneous in my demonstration of them to be consistent with my argument.(http://orthodoxbridge.com/is-the-protestant-church-fragmented-a-response-to-pastor-doug-wilson-1-of-2/)

Unlike raising to subject above, I find the above examples of raising to object unacceptable, like Chomsky andNewmeyer. However, there are so many attested examples that the only conclusion can be that there are signifi-cant numbers of English speakers who accept them. Raising to object must be allowed inside nominalizations inprinciple.

5

Page 6: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

Moreover, the Lexicalist literature is inconsistent on this point. Chomsky (1970), Newmeyer (2009), andWasow (1977) considered the lack of raising to subject and object inside nominalizations and adjectival passivesto be crucial evidence for the Lexicalist Hypothesis. However, Bresnan (1982) and more recently Müller (2006)and Müller and Wechsler (2014) analyze raising to object, raising to subject, resultative formation, and so on, aslexical rules. As such, they can feed other lexical rules and form new words. On this view, nominalizations arefully expected to be fed by raising to subject and raising to object.

Notice that the criterion for deciding whether a rule is lexical or syntactic in this approach is not whether itmanipulates units larger than words, but whether it can feed word formation or not. Müller and Wechsler (2014,32) explicitly state that this is the deciding criterion, following Dowty (1978, 412) and Bresnan (1982, 21). Bythis logic, however, all of phrasal syntax must be lexical rules, because of compounding, above. We saw abovethat compounds can include subordinate clauses, wh-movement, subject auxiliary inversion, and various otherphenomena. All of these would have to be lexical rules, according to the logic in Müller (2006) and Müller andWechsler (2014). In other words, following their logic we again end up with a single generative component ofgrammar, not two that are strictly separated.

Here is my reading of history: The Lexicalist Hypothesis was originally motivated by the apparent lack ofphrasal processes feeding word formation. Since that time, however, more and more instances of this have cometo light. The response has often been to reassign those phrasal processes to the word formation component. Whatthis history shows, however, is that the original motivation was incorrect. Phrasal processes can and frequently dofeed word formation. If all phrasal processes that can feed word formation are reassigned to the word formationcomponent (as lexical rules), then the phrasal component disappears altogether. Alternatively, word formation pro-cesses should be reassigned to the phrasal component. Either way, the strict separation between a word formationcomponent and a phrasal syntax component that is envisioned by the Lexicalist Hypothesis is incorrect.

2.2 Phrasal Syntax Has Access to Sub-Word Units

The Lexicalist Hypothesis is also incorrect in its assertion that the phrasal syntax has no access to sub-word units.In fact, numerous processes can target both phrases and sub-word units.

2.2.1 Coordination/Ellipsis of Word Parts

It has long been noted that coordination of word parts is widespread (Nespor 1985, Booij 1985):

(28) a. infra e ultrasuoni (Italian, ‘infra- and ultra-sounds’; Nespor 1985, 201)b. Freund- or Feindschaft (German, ‘friendship or hostility’; Booij 1985, 152)c. Pre- and post-revolutionary France were very different from each other. (Chaves 2008, 264, (10))

Chaves (2008) argues strongly that this phenomenon is actually not coordination of sub-word parts, but co-ordination of phrases accompanied by word-part ellipsis. Among the arguments is the fact that plural agreementis possible in (28c), as is antecedence of the reciprocal each other. The subject in (28c) must actually be Pre-revolutionary France and post-revolutionary France, with deletion of repeated material in the first conjunct.

Regardless, ellipsis is generally regarded as a phrasal process. Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) include it in theirlist of processes that cannot target sub-word units (see section 3.9). Obviously, it can. One response is to view thistype of ellipsis as different from phrasal syntax ellipsis; for instance, Chaves (2014) treats it as a process that targetslinearized strings, not syntactic phrases. Note, however, that this ellipsis process cannot break up morphemes thatare not easily segmentable, even when the same string can be stranded in a different morphological context:

(29) a. pro-choice and -gun control (Chaves 2008, 263, (6e))b. * (both) pro-gressive and -fessionalc. * Because he is pro-fessional and -management, he is a valuable member of our team.

(30) a. You can pre- or re-mix it.b. * They produce cranber- and dai-ry products.

6

Page 7: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

(31) a. Bing and Sydney Crosby (are not related).b. * The room was full of bing- and bon-go players.

(32) a. red- and black-banded mothsb. * red- and ind-olent

(33) a. bi- and a-sexualb. * the Bi- and A-cre Lane Campaigns (the Biker Lane Campaign and the Acre Lane Campaign)

(34) a. bi- and a-sexualb. birth- and adopted sonsc. * bi- and ma-son paraphernalia (bison paraphernalia and mason paraphernalia)

In (34), for instance, we see that the strings bi- and a- can stand alone, as can the string son. But (34c) does notwork, because in these particular words bi-, ma- (similar in sound to a-), and son are not distinct morphemes.

It is true that this type of ellipsis is sensitive to prosody (Booij 1985), but it is also true that the constraintsholding of it cannot be stated solely in terms of prosody (Chaves 2008, 2014). Rather, this process of ellipsismakes crucial reference to morphology. This means that it has access to sub-word parts.

Chaves (2008, 2014) also argues that the ellipsis process at work here is the same one that we see operatingon phrasal units in right node raising and coordinate ellipsis. Corresponding to deletion of the left member of thesecond coordinate in word-part ellipsis is what is sometimes regarded as non-constituent coordination:

(35) a. [half-brothers] and [half-sisters]b. Mary [caught a fish on Monday with a fly rod] and [caught a fish on Tuesday with a spear]. (Dowty

1988, (62)).

And corresponding to deletion of the right member of the first conjunct is right node raising:

(36) a. [over-application] and [under-application]b. The break-in on Monday was a [rare breach of royal security] but [not unheard-of breach of royal

security]. (Chaves 2014, 839, (11e))

As these examples show, these two ellipsis processes can target units larger than words, namely, phrases. Atthe same time, however, this process must also have access to sub-word morphemes. That is, it can see both unitslarger than words and units smaller than words. This is a clear violation of the Lexicalist Hypothesis: the wordformation system is supposed to be encapsulated from everything that deals in units larger than the word. Thereshould be no process that can target both phrases and morphemes. Yet this type of ellipsis does exactly that.

2.2.2 Adverbs

Other phrasal processes are also known to be able to target sub-word units. One is adverbial modification withagain (von Stechow 1995). Consider the following examples:

(37) a. Sally woke up sad for no reason. In the afternoon, she cheered up, but then a news report saddenedher again.

b. Sally discovered a large opening in the side of the hill. Over a period of weeks it shrank, so sheenlarged it again.

In these examples, the scope of again is not sadden or enlarge, since nothing had saddened Sally before or enlargedthe opening before. Rather, the scope of again is just sad and large, sub-word parts of their respective words.According to Williams (2007, 355–356), this should not be possible, since again is an adverb that only takesphrases as its scope.

von Stechow (1995) and Beck and Johnson (2004), among others, argue that modification with again requireslexical decomposition in the syntax. That is, the syntax needs access to sub-word units. A German example from

7

Page 8: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada (2012) illustrates this point further. German, like many languages, permits an NPwith an oblique case to be added to a clause, and this NP is interpreted as being psychologically affected by theevent denoted by the VP. In German the case this NP receives is dative:

(38) LisaLisa.Nom

zerbrachbroke

MartinMartin.Dat

dasthe.Acc

Puzzle.puzzle

‘Lisa broke the puzzle on Martin.’

Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada (2012) propose that the dative NP is introduced in the specifier of a head Aff(ect).They also adopt Kratzer’s (1996) hypothesis that the external argument of the verb is not actually an argument ofthe verb, but is an argument of a higher head Voice. AffP crucially occurs in between Kratzer’s Voice head and theVP (word order abstracted away from here):

(39) VoiceP

NP

Lisa Voice AffP

NP

MartinAff VP

Vzerbrach

NP

das Puzzle

The Aff head introduces a semantics that says that the event of its VP sister matters psychologically to the NP inits specifier (for details see Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada 2012).

Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada (2012) support this syntactic analysis with facts regarding possible interpreta-tions of wieder, ‘again.’ When wieder is added to the above sentence, only three of the four logically possibleinterpretations are permitted (Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada 2012, 1216, (78)):

(40) LisaLisa

zerbrachbroke

MartinMartin.Dat

dasthe

Puzzlepuzzle

wieder.again

‘Lisa broke the puzzle on Martin again.’

1. The puzzle was broken before (cause irrelevant, perhaps it came that way, and this didn’t necessarilymatter to Martin), and now Lisa has broken it again and this matters to Martin.

2. The puzzle broke or was broken on Martin before, and now Lisa broke it on him again (she did not doit the first time).

3. Lisa had broken the puzzle on Martin before and now she did it again.

4. *Lisa had broken the puzzle before and now she broke it again but for the first time on Martin.

According to Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada (2012), reading 1 corresponds to wieder adjoining to VP. It says thatthe eventuality denoted by its sister, here just the VP ‘broke the puzzle’, happened before. Reading 2 correspondsto wieder attaching to AffP. Again, the eventuality denoted by the sister of wieder happened before: the puzzlebeing broken and that affecting Martin. Reading 3 corresponds to wieder modifying the entire VoiceP. Reading 4 isnot permitted because there is no constituent consisting of the verb and the internal and external arguments, whileexcluding the dative.

Consider now a lexical rule approach to affected datives in German. In a lexical theory, the verb zerbrechenwould take two arguments, an internal argument and an external argument. A lexical rule can apply to a verb and

8

Page 9: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

add a dative argument in addition, which will be interpreted as psychologically affected. There is no obvious wayin this theory to account for the possible and impossible readings of wieder. In particular, I see no way to permitreadings 1 and 2 while excluding reading 4. If wieder is allowed access to sub-parts of the argument structure ofthe derived verb, then reading 4 should also be allowed. More importantly, in a lexicalist theory, wieder should notbe allowed access to sub-parts of the derived verb; this violates the Lexicalist Hypothesis.

2.2.3 Wh-Questions

Another example of phrasal adverbs modifying word-parts, not previously recognized to my knowledge, has awh-word questioning a sub-word morpheme. The following are attested examples pulled from the internet:2

(41) a. How “pre” is prehypertension? (http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/17519120)b. How ‘post’ does ‘postcolonial’ have to be before it ceases to be a—or the—primary determinant in

the way Irish writing is read, and reads itself? (Irish Poetry Since 1950: From Stillness Into Historyby John Goodby, p319)

c. Just How Sub Is Subprime? (http://online.barrons.com/articles/SB117409608947340293?tesla=y)

However these types of examples are analyzed, the fact is that the wh-phrase is semantically picking out a singlemorpheme in a multimorphemic word. This is again a violation of the Lexicalist Hypothesis.

2.2.4 Focus

It is also well-known that focus can target sub-word units (Selkirk 1984, 271, Wennerstrom 1993, Artstein 2004):

(42) a. That poet is from the POST-colonial era, not the PRE-colonial one.b. That type of action indicates an A-moral viewpoint, not an IM-moral one.c. That individual is TRANS-sexual, not BI-sexual.d. Sex-IST, not sex-Y!

Since focus can also target phrases, this is again an example of a process that makes no distinction between phrasaland sub-word units (Artstein 2004).

2.3 Summary

In this section we have seen that the main tenet of the Lexicalist Hypothesis is simply incorrect. There is no strictseparation of the component of grammar that produces words and the component that produces phrases. Phrasalsyntax can feed word formation processes, and there are numerous processes that can target both phrasal units andsub-word units.

One response to some of these facts has been to reassign processes from the phrasal component to the lexicalcomponent. However, every phrasal process seems to be able to feed compounding; this strategy then necessitatesreassigning everything from the phrasal component to the lexical one. The conclusion is clear: the grammar is notstrictly separated into word and phrase components, there is only a single component that puts together both wordsand phrases.

2A wh-phrase can also replace a word-part in an echo question (Artstein 2004):

(i) This is a stalag-what? (A: stalagMITE; Artstein 2004, 7, (13a))

However, this type of questioning is insensitive to morpheme boundaries, and can replace any string (or prosodic unit), as in He’s a presti-what? (prestidigitator) or It’s a capy-what? (capybara). This phenomenon is probably just asking to repeat some phonological string, andso is not relevant to the Lexicalist Hypothesis.

9

Page 10: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

3 The Lexicalist Hypothesis is Superfluous

I now show that we do not need the Lexicalist Hypothesis to account for the facts that it is meant to account for. Wesaw in the last section that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is wrong in numerous ways, but there are other cases where itdoes seem to capture something. That is, there are cases where phrasal elements cannot target sub-word units, andthere are cases where sub-word units seem to behave differently from their phrasal correspondents. I show here thatthese facts already follow from most theories of phrasal syntax, with no need to invoke the Lexicalist Hypothesis orthe Principle of Lexical Integrity (Bresnan and Mchombo 1995). All we need is a distinction between elements thatselect heads and elements that select phrases, along with the commonly assumed principle that elements strictlymodify their sister (the element they merge with). Since most syntactic theories already distinguish heads fromphrases and already limit combination to sisterhood, they already account for these differences, with no need forthe Lexicalist Hypothesis.

3.1 Phrasal Elements That Cannot Target Sub-Word Units

According to Williams (2007), we need the Lexicalist Hypothesis in order to account for the inability of wh-questioning to target part of a word, as in the following:

(43) (Williams 2007, 354, (1))a. How complete are your results?b. * How completeness do you admire? (intended: [how complete]-ness do you admire)c. What degree of completeness do you admire?d. How complete a record do you admire?

In (43b), how cannot modify just the complete part of the noun completeness. The examples in (43c–d) are meantto show that there is nothing semantically ill-formed about this question.

The obvious question to ask is whether the syntax independently rules out (43b). It does, in fact. How as anadverb does not combine with nouns (*how man, *how liberty). Of course, we need to rule out the bracketing in(43b), where it combines with what would be an adjective before the suffix -ness turns it into a noun. For this, andin fact for all of the cases brought up by Williams and discussed in this and subsequent subsections, we just needa difference between items that select heads and items that select phrases. The principle that elements combinestrictly with their sister then derives the facts. Any syntactic theory that distinguishes heads from phrases thereforecaptures the facts that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is thought to be needed for.

In this particular case, how as a phrase modifier selects phrases, and cannot select heads. It strictly combineswith phrasal constituents headed by As and Vs. For the sake of exposition, I use adjunction to AP:

(44) AP

AdvP

how

AP

Acomplete

How cannot adjoin to a head, as would be required in (43b):

(45) * N

A

AdvP

how

Acomplete

N-ness

10

Page 11: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

The facts that Williams argues follow only from the Lexicalist Hypothesis in fact follow from any syntactictheory that distinguishes heads from phrases. Appealing to the Lexicalist Hypothesis is unnecessary.

Similarly, Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) say that the Lexicalist Hypothesis and their Principle of LexicalIntegrity are needed to account for the inability of adverbs to modify sub-word parts:

(46) (Bresnan and Mchombo 1995, 192, (17))a. [A happy]-nessb. * [AP quite happy]-nessc. * [AP more happy [than sad]]-ness

Put differently, phrases like APs cannot form the input to word-formation rules like -ness suffixation.3

This restriction follows in exactly the same way as wh-questions, above. Like how, quite and more selectphrases, not heads. In contrast, -ness selects heads, not phrases. The bracketing in (46b–c) is impossible because-ness cannot combine with a phrase. Additionally, quite cannot adjoin to the NP headed by happiness and modifyjust the adjective happy, for two reasons: first, as an adverb, quite does not select NPs; and second, if quite couldattach to happiness, that is what it would modify, by the principle that elements combine strictly with their sisters.It could not modify just a sub-part of its sister.

All of these restrictions are ones we independently need in phrasal syntax; nothing more needs to be said. Thereis simply no need for the Lexicalist Hypothesis or the Principle of Lexical Integrity.

3.2 Strict Locality of Affixes Versus Phrases

Williams (2007) also points to the strict locality that is observed with affixal self- as opposed to phrasal self as amotivation for the Lexicalist Hypothesis. Phrasal self may take a long-distance antecedent, so that in the followingexample himself does not need to relate the internal argument of destruction to the external argument of destruction;instead the destroyer can be unspecified:

(47) John told stories about the destruction of himself. (Williams 2007, 354, (2))

In contrast, self-destruction strictly requires coreference between the destroyed and the destroyer. An example like(48b) cannot instead relate the destroyed with the teller of stories. This means that, in contrast with (47), (48a) isunambiguous, and must mean (48b), not (48c):

(48) (Williams 2007, 354, (3))a. John told self-destruction stories. (unambiguous)b. John told stories about one’s destruction of oneself.c. John told stories about the destruction of himself.

According to Williams, such facts show that “the lexical system has no delayed resolution, but the phrasal systemdoes” (Williams 2007, 355).

Again, we do not need the Lexicalist Hypothesis to account for such facts, all we need is the difference betweenheads and phrases. If affixal self- is a head that selects heads, not phrases, then it will strictly operate on its sister,the head it attaches to. This particular affix has the effect of making the head it attaches to reflexive, so that twoarguments of that head are covalued. In self-destruction, self- will covalue the destroyer and destroyed argumentsof destruction. There is no “delayed resolution” because elements combine strictly with their sisters.

The same is true, though, of phrasal elements: they also combine strictly with their sisters. The only differenceis that their sisters are phrases. In (47), of himself combines strictly with destruction to fill the internal argumentrole of destruction. The NP himself needs an antecedent, but, as is well-known, inside NPs reflexives are free to

3Actually, this is not entirely true, either. There are examples like stick-to-itiveness and unputdownable, as well as phrases that usezero-derivation, like a pick-me-up, the once-over, a do-over, a know-it-all. While these might be dismissed as exceptional, they are stillquite common and help to make the point that there is no strict separation between the phrasal system and the word system.

11

Page 12: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

find an antecedent based on perspective or other principles (Pollard and Sag 1992, Reinhart and Reuland 1993). Ifhimself were to occur as the object of the verb destroy, it would again require covaluation between it and anotherargument of the verb. (The syntax does have numerous instances of long-distance relations, like variable bindingand extraction, but this is not one of them.)

Once again, the facts that are taken to motivate the Lexicalist Hypothesis simply fall out from any syntactictheory that distinguishes heads from phrases.

3.3 Differences in How Adjuncts are Treated

The principle that elements combine strictly with their sisters also explains the difference that Williams (2007)points to between affixal re- and phrasal again. Phrasal again may include adjuncts in its scope, but re- may not:

(49) (Williams 2007, 355, (4))a. John re-washed the dishes on Tuesday. (not ambiguous)b. John again washed the dishes on Tuesday. (ambiguous as to whether it includes on Tuesday in its

scope)

According to Williams, a prefix “can have scope only over the arguments of the item it adjoins to in the wordsystem” and not the adjuncts “because the arguments of a lexical item are represented on the item itself in someway, but adjuncts are not” (Williams 2007, 355).

Williams is only sort of right about this (see the discussion of raising and resultatives above), but again we do notneed the Lexicalist Hypothesis. Re- as a head strictly selects heads, and like all syntactic elements operates strictlyon its sister, namely the head it combines with. As Williams notes, adjuncts are not specified in the semantics of ahead, so when re- combines with a head, it cannot include any adjuncts of the head it attaches to in its semantics.In contrast, again is phrasal, and may combine with a very large phrase, one that can include an adjunct.4 Again,there is no need for the Lexicalist Hypothesis, the facts follow from any theory of syntax that includes a differencebetween heads and phrases and the principle that elements combine strictly with their sisters.

3.4 Different Principles?

Williams (2007) lists two other differences that he claims hold between the word system and the phrasal system.The most important one, the claim that the word system provides input objects to the phrasal system and notvice versa, has already been addressed and shown to be wrong. The other is the claim that the word system andthe phrasal system obey different principles, so that, for instance, the word system is head-final in English, butthe phrasal system is head-initial. In fact, the driving intuition behind the syntactic approach to word formationis that this is false: principles of word formation are ones familiar from phrasal syntax (Baker 1985, Hale andKeyser 1993, among numerous others). As for head directionality, it is rather superficial, and there are numerouscounterexamples in both directions in English: words can be head-initial, like pickpocket, cutthroat, know-it-all;and phrases can be head-final, like counterexamples notwithstanding and two years ago. This difference, such as itis, is simply not significant.

What is significant is that we do in fact see the same principles operating. Crucial to the previous two subsec-tions was the principle that elements combine strictly with their sisters. This principle holds of both phrases andmorphemes. Similarly, the constraints on what can form an adjectival passive in English almost perfectly mirrorthe constraints on what can form a verbal passive; where there are differences, they follow from syntactic principles(Bruening 2014).

The recognition that the principles are the same is also implicit in the trend mentioned above to reassign allsyntactic processes to the lexical component. For Bresnan (1982), verbal passives must also be lexical, just likeadjectival passives; for Müller (2006), raising and resultatives must be lexical. If we are reassigning all processesto the same component, those processes must all obey the same principles.

4We saw above (section 2.2.2) that again can also adjoin to very small phrases, and thereby modify sub-word units. It is one of only afew adverbs that is supremely flexible in this way (another is too, see Bruening 2010, 549).

12

Page 13: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

3.5 Idiosyncrasy

One of Chomsky’s (1970) original arguments for a lexical treatment of nominalizations, repeated in Newmeyer(2009), is that they are not completely productive or semantically regular. That is, they show a great deal ofidiosyncrasy. The following list of sample semantic irregularities among derived forms (not just nominalizations)is from Newmeyer:

(50) (Newmeyer 2009, 94, (7))a. profess (‘declare openly’)—professor (‘university teacher’)—profession (‘career’)b. ignore (‘pay no attention to’)—ignorance (‘lack of knowledge’)—ignoramus (‘very stupid person’)c. person (‘human individual’)—personal (‘private’)—personable (‘friendly’)—personality (‘character’)—

personalize (‘tailor to the individual’)—impersonate (‘pass oneself off as’)d. social (‘pertaining to society’; ‘interactive with others’)—socialist (‘follower of a particular political

doctrine’)—socialite (‘member of high society’)

There are also nominalizations that have no corresponding verb that they could be derived from, for instancemotion (*mote), tuition (*tuit). The same is true of other derived forms (social, *soci).

In order for this undeniable fact to be an argument for a split between a phrasal system and a word-formationsystem, we have to assume that there is a qualitative difference between lexical rules and phrasal rules in regularity.Indeed, Chomsky (1970) assumed just that: that rules of the phrasal component are completely productive andsemantically transparent, while lexical rules show numerous irregularities and restrictions.

Since that time, however, this has been shown over and over to be false. Irregularity is not the exclusive provinceof the word formation system, it is pervasive in the combinatorial system generally. There are phrasal idioms, likekick the bucket and the shit hit the fan; there are particle-verb combinations that are interpreted idiosyncraticallyand are not completely productive (throw up, chew out; see Jackendoff 2002); there are obscure limitations ondifferent types of A-bar movement (Sag 2010). Since the assumption is false, the argument does not go through:there is again no difference between the word system and the phrase system, and no reason to treat them differently.In fact, if we want a uniform account of idiosyncrasy, then we have to treat them the same, otherwise we will haveto have two different ways of deriving idiosyncrasy, one for the word system and the other for the phrasal system.

Newmeyer (2009, 105) does ask a pertinent question: In purely syntactic theories of word formation, whereis it recorded which affixes particular roots can combine with? That is, where is it stated that the root destroy(or destruct or whatever its base form is) combines with -ion, while grow combines with -th and criticize formscriticism and not *criticization?

This is an important question, but it is a question to be answered, not an argument. Any theory has to answerthis question, whether it assumes the Lexicalist Hypothesis or not. The Lexicalist Hypothesis does not make givingan answer any easier, since in a Lexicalist theory, root and affix combinations are also done via rule, just as in apurely syntactic theory. The rules just have a different name. Particular roots still have to be specified as undergoingsome rules and not others. The same has to be done in a syntactic theory. The two types of approaches are in thesame boat; the question for all of them is what lexical entries look like, and what information is stored where.

If we give up lexical rules and only have a single syntactic rule component, as I am arguing for here, then allword formation has to be done by the same syntax that builds phrases. We need a way to capture idiosyncrasiesand lack of full productivity. There are two obvious ways:

1. All specifications are stored in the lexical entries of roots. Suppose we have a root SOCI. In the entry for thisroot, it can be recorded that SOCI + -al = ‘pertaining to society’, while SOC + -al + -ist = ‘follower of thedoctrine of socialism’, and so on.

2. Lexical entries include syntactic structure. There is a lexical entry for socialist that includes its structure andits meaning. There is another lexical entry for social that includes its structure and meaning (and its structureis probably a subset of the structure of socialist).

13

Page 14: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

On both views, combinations are memorized as they are encountered. At the same time, language users willgeneralize to some extent and extract commonalities (different individuals may do this to different extents). Thisis not really different from most Lexicalist views; all that is different is the claim that the system that puts wordstogether is the same as the system that puts phrases together.

There are also other possibilities besides the two listed, and I will not commit to any one here. It is an empiricalquestion what the best account is. It seems to me, however, that a uniform account of idiosyncrasy at the wordlevel and at the phrasal level would be desirable, and this is more likely to be successful in a theory that does notdistinguish the two. (See Bruening 2010 on an approach to phrasal idioms where selection is crucial; selectionoperates uniformly throughout the system.)

3.6 Internal Structure

Another of Chomsky’s (1970) arguments for a split between a word system and a phrase system is the claim thatderived words have the phrasal structure of their derived category, and do not have the phrasal structure of thecategory they are derived from. For instance, a deverbal nominalization has exactly the same phrasal syntax as anunderived noun, and does not have the phrasal structure of a verb or a sentence. Newmeyer (2009) illustrates thiswith the following examples:

(51) (Newmeyer 2009, 95, (9))a. the stupid refusal of the offerb. * the refusal stupidly of the offerc. * the not refusal of the offerd. * the have refusal of the offer

(52) a. * She stupid refused the offer.b. She refused the offer stupidly.c. She did not refuse the offer.d. She has refused the offer.

A derived N takes adjectives, not adverbs, and may not have sentential negation or auxiliary verbs that are possiblewith the verb it is derived from. According to Chomsky and Newmeyer, these facts only follow if derived Ns enterthe syntax as unanalyzable Ns.

The claim that Ns derived from Vs do not have phrasal properties of Vs has been argued to be false. Forinstance, Fu, Roeper, and Borer (2001) argue that Ns derived from Vs may have adverbs, while underived onesmay not:

(53) (Fu, Roeper, and Borer 2001, 549, (2))a. The occurrence of the accident suddenly disqualified her.b. * Kim’s accident suddenly on the track disqualified her.

This has been contested by Newmeyer (2009), but all of his examples of putatively underived nouns (p.109, ex-amples 47a–c) are either zero-related to verbs (use, release) or can plausibly be analyzed as derived from a verbalsource that is not actually used (recourse, which is used in the “light verb” construction take recourse). The matterrequires more research to be settled. (Newmeyer’s skepticism of the do so data also offered by Fu, Roeper, andBorer 2001 does appear to be warranted.)

Other facts have been suggested to distinguish derived from underived Ns. For example, Bruening (2013)argues that certain PP adjuncts require verbal structure, and so they are only permitted with Ns that include verbalstructure. Instrumentals are one such. They are allowed with VPs and with derived nouns, but not with (at leastsome) underived nouns (Bruening 2013, 12, (48–52)):

(54) a. The inspector saw the blood with a microscope.

14

Page 15: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

b. The sample was smelled with an electronic nose.c. The danger was sensed by Peter with his spider-sense.

(55) a. the perception of light with a photosensorb. the detection of the sound with an amplifierc. the discernment of God’s will with various omens

(56) a. * the sight of the blood with a microscopeb. * the smell of the sample with an electronic nosec. * Peter’s sense of danger with his spider-sense

Additionally, it is generally true that verbs that select a particular preposition continue to select that samepreposition when they are turned into derived nouns:

(57) a. depend on, dependence on; rely on, reliance onb. apply for, application for; prepare for, preparation forc. believe in, belief in; specialize in, specialization in; succeed in, success ind. commit to, commitment to; refer to, reference to; respond to, response toe. approve of, approval of; acquit of, acquittal off. agree with, agreement with; collide with, collision with

While this is not inconsistent with the Lexicalist Hypothesis, it is not expected by it either. On the Lexicalistposition, we ought to expect more idiosyncratic variation from verb to derived noun.

Now, it is true that, by and large, derived nouns have the phrasal syntax of nouns. However, this follows on anytheory that treats them as nouns, even a theory that derives them from verbs in the phrasal syntax. The verbs havebeen turned into nouns, in every theory, and as such, they are expected to behave as nouns. There is no need toappeal to the Lexicalist Hypothesis to explain this.

It does appear that many of the criticisms that have been voiced concerning syntactic analyses of nominaliza-tions arise from those analyses treating the nominalizing morphemes as attaching to phrases, something like thefollowing:5

(58) NP

N-ion

VP

Vdestruct-

NP

the city

In this type of analysis, the nominalizing head selects a phrase as its complement, but combines with the head ofthat phrase morphologically, usually by head movement (see, e.g., Marantz 1997, Alexiadou 2001, Borer 2003,Roeper 2005).

Note, however, that it is also possible to analyze nominalization as a nominalizing head attaching directly tothe verbal stem, before it projects any phrasal structure:

(59) N

Vdestruct-

N-ion

5These criticisms include Williams (2007), Wechsler (2008), Newmeyer (2009), Müller (2013), Müller and Wechsler (2014). See moreon this in the conclusion.

15

Page 16: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

Both options are available in a purely syntactic approach to word formation. Which is correct is an empiricalquestion. If the bulk of the evidence suggests that nominalizations do indeed include verb phrase structure, thenperhaps the phrasal approach is correct. If the evidence indicates that they do not, then the pure head approachmight be called for.

There are also other possibilities. In any case, a theory that does without the Lexicalist Hypothesis is perfectlycapable of capturing the facts. This means, again, that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is superfluous.6

3.7 Frozen Structure

The last argument offered by Chomsky (1970) and repeated by Newmeyer (2009) is the claim that we do not seetransformational syntax inside of derived words. This was already discussed above and shown to be false (section2.1). As was shown above, two of the phrasal phenomena discussed by Chomsky, raising to subject and raising toobject, do occur inside derived nominals. Others do, as well, like “particle shift”; the very examples that Chomskycited as ungrammatical are accepted by numerous speakers as at least marginally acceptable (Larsen 2014):

(60) a. ? his looking of the information up (cited as ungrammatical in Chomsky 1970, 193, (14a))b. ? his defining of the problem away (cited as ungrammatical in Chomsky 1970, 193, (14b))

Similarly, Bruening (2014) showed that some instances of “dative shift” occur inside adjectival passives, contraWasow (1977) and much other work:

(61) (Bruening 2014, 401, (102a), (103a))a. The Victoria was unspared the horrors of World War II. . .b. . . . he struggled with his identity, cast as a sex symbol for 1950s America but unafforded a private

life outside the limelight.

Bruening (2014) shows that this is allowed just with certain double object verbs like deny, spare, afford. It is notallowed with alternating verbs like give, send, etc. Bruening (2014) explains this difference in terms of phrasalsyntax, and suggests that the phrasal syntax is the right place to look for constraints on what may appear in phrasesheaded by derived words (pp411–412).

This means, again, that the Lexicalist Hypothesis is not only wrong, but it is also unhelpful in explaining whatrestrictions do exist. The phrasal syntax can explain these restrictions better than the Lexicalist Hypothesis can,since the Lexicalist Hypothesis has nothing specific to say about different classes of double object verbs. It alsohas nothing to say about the difference between adjectival passives, which allow double object verbs of the denyand spare class, and agentive -er nominalizations, which do not (Bruening 2014, 412). Not only is the LexicalistHypothesis superfluous, it is useless in helping us to understand why some syntactic phenomena can appear insome derived words but others cannot.

3.8 “Lexical Integrity”: Extraction

I turn now to the arguments that Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) give for their Principle of Lexical Integrity. Thisprinciple says that word parts are inaccessible to the syntax, as would follow from the Lexicalist Hypothesis. Wesaw in section 2 that this is incorrect in many instances, but in others it does seem to be true.

The first argument involves extraction. According to Bresnan and Mchombo (1995), word parts are inaccessibleto extraction:

(62) * It’s American history that they’ve been [— teachers] for years. (modified from Bresnan and Mchombo1995, 187, (3b))

6One argument presented against syntactic accounts of nominalizations is that they can be coordinated with underived nouns and sharearguments (Wechsler 2008, Müller and Wechsler 2014). In section 3.9 I suggest that all apparent coordination of heads is actually coordi-nation of phrases. If this is correct, the possibility of coordination of derived and underived nouns is not problematic for any theory.

16

Page 17: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

As we did above regarding adverbs, we should ask whether the phrasal syntax independently rules out such attemptsat extraction. It does, in numerous ways. The most important is that this sort of extraction (A-bar extraction) mayonly target phrases, and not heads:

(63) a. It’s [a dedicated teacher] that she’s been — for years.b. * It’s teacher that she’s been [a dedicated —] for years.

(64) a. As [justifiably proud of your daughter] as you’ve been — over the years,. . .b. * As proud as you’ve been [justifiably — of your daughter] over the years,. . .

Neither of these illicit instances of extraction is ruled out by the Principle of Lexical Integrity. Obviously, weneed some constraints in the phrasal syntax. The most important one is that A-bar extraction only targets phrases,and not heads. Once we have this constraint, however, the inability of A-bar extraction to target sub-word unitsfollows: they are not phrases.7 There is no need to have a Principle of Lexical Integrity in addition. It is entirelysuperfluous.

The same constraint operates on A-extraction, too. Raising to subject and passivization may not target a head,even in a case like the pseudopassive where a subpart of the argument of the verb—the complement of the Pcomplement of the V—can be extracted:

(65) a. The wealthiest candidate is likely — to win.b. * Candidate is likely [the wealthiest —] to win.

(66) a. Only the softest bed will be slept [in —].b. * Bed will be slept [in [only the softest —]].

Both A- and A-bar extraction are constrained to operate on phrases, not heads; and it therefore follows that theycannot target sub-parts of words, because those are not phrases.

Some Lexicalist theories treat raising and passive as lexical rules (e.g., Bresnan 1982, Müller 2006). As such,they should in principle be able to target sub-parts of words, yet they cannot:

(67) a. * American history is likely [a(n) — teacher] to win Teacher of the Year.b. * American history was hired [a(n) — teacher].

Some other principle must block this. Whatever that principle is makes the Principle of Lexical Integrity superfluouseven within a Lexicalist theory. The Principle of Lexical Integrity does no work whatsoever, even in a theory thatassumes its correctness.

Extraction, then, does not require the Lexicalist Hypothesis or the Principle of Lexical Integrity. The factthat extraction cannot target sub-parts of words follows from independent principles. The Lexicalist Hypothesis issuperfluous.

3.9 “Lexical Integrity”: Conjunction and Ellipsis

According to Bresnan and Mchombo (1995), conjunction and ellipsis are phrasal processes and so cannot targetparts of words. We saw above that this is false. Word parts can be conjoined and elided. Above we saw that allinstances of conjunction of word parts might actually be ellipsis, however, so it may well be that conjunction cannottarget word parts. If this is correct, do we need a Principle of Lexical Integrity to explain it?

The answer is no. Again, all we need is the recognition that some syntactic processes may only target phrasesand not heads. Conjunction may be such a process. Of course, conjunction does seem to be able to operate onheads, as in the following examples:

7We saw above that the first member of a compound can be a syntactic phrase. Such phrases still cannot be extracted by A-bar movementprocesses, however. This is because, as also shown above, these phrases when combined with the second member of the compound forma noun as far as the phrasal syntax they are embedded within is concerned. Extraction processes operating on larger phrases will treat theentire compound as a single noun, that is, as a head.

17

Page 18: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

(68) a. They can and will arrest you.b. They shot and killed the suspect.

There are some indications that coordination of heads is illusory, however, and is probably always phrasalcoordination. For instance, coordination of modals can include phrasal elements like adverbs:

(69) They can and probably will arrest you.

Similarly, coordination of verbal heads (here nominalized) acts like coordination of word parts in permittingplural agreement and antecedence of reciprocals (see above and Chaves 2008):

(70) a. Their shooting and killing (of) the suspect were unrelated to each other. (the suspect was woundedby the shooting last year, and then they killed him with a knife this year)

b. Her offering and making me an espresso usually take place on different days.

It is plausible, then, that all instances of apparent head coordination are actually all phrasal coordination withellipsis.

If apparent coordination of heads is always coordination of phrases, then coordination is just one of manyprocesses (like extraction above) that only targets phrases, and not heads. This is a restriction in the phrasal syntax,but it has the result that the coordination of word parts is banned, with no reference to the Lexicalist Hypothesisor the Principle of Lexical Integrity. Once again, all the work of the Lexicalist Hypothesis is already done by thephrasal syntax.

3.10 “Lexical Integrity”: Inbound Anaphoric Islands

Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) also cite “inbound anaphoric islands” as evidence for their Principle of LexicalIntegrity. Following Postal (1969, 213-214), they note that words may be formed from referential nouns, but notfrom pronouns:8

(71) McCarthyite, *himite

Other types of pro-forms also cannot appear inside words:

(72) a. * People who smoke like other do-so-ers. (Postal 1969, 217, (69a))b. * We need a truck but not a one-driver. (cf. We need a truck but not a driver of one.)

It is not exactly clear how this would follow from the Principle of Lexical Integrity. According to Simpson(1983), coreference is part of the sentence grammar (the phrasal system), so a pronoun could not receive its refer-ence within a word, since the sentence grammar has no access to sub-words parts. As Ward, Sproat, and McKoon(1991) note, this would then have nothing to say about cross-sentential anaphora, which is also ruled out. Bresnanand Mchombo (1995) themselves explain the facts in a way that makes no reference to Lexical Integrity: “indexicalpronouns, though they do have intrinsic lexical content and can appear word-internally, lack the appropriate lexicalcontent to serve as morphological bases for semantic derivatives” (p192). In other words, pronouns have very littlesemantic content, and that is what stops them from forming words like *himite and *do-so-er. In attested wordswith pronouns like he-man and she-male, the pronouns are used just for their gender features, which is the onlyreal semantic content that they do have. If this is correct, then inbound anaphoric islands have nothing to do withthe Principle of Lexical Integrity and everything to do with the paucity of content in pro-forms.

A different explanation is offered by Sproat (1988). According to Sproat, pro-forms are always maximalprojections. Pronouns are actually NPs, do so is a full VP, and so on. Word formation processes never operateon maximal projections. As discussed above, suffixes like -ite and agentive -er strictly select heads, and may notcombine with phrases. This rules out formations like *himite and *do-so-er. It does not rule out pro-forms in

8Postal (1969) also discusses “outbound anaphoric islands,” but these are not considered by Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) to be evidencefor Lexical Integrity, since they were shown by Ward, Sproat, and McKoon (1991) to be regulated by pragmatics.

18

Page 19: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

compounds, since, as we saw above, the first member of a compound can actually be phrasal. As we would thenexpect, phrasal compounds actually can include pro-forms, including fully referential ones:

(73) a. The dog gave me an accusing you-like-her-better-than-me look.b. She gave me her easily recognizable I-love-flowers-but-you-always-buy-me-ugly-ones look.c. She gave him her patented I-love-to-dance-but-I-won’t-do-so-alone look and he dutifully stood and

accompanied her to the dance floor.

These examples are not expected by Bresnan and Mchombo (1995), who claim that phrases in compounds are“lexicalized” (see above). If they are lexicalized then they would be expected to behave like words, and be inboundanaphoric islands.

Additionally, Bresnan and Mchombo (1995) themselves cite numerous counterexamples to the inbound anaphoricisland constraint, where in some languages a derived word form can include pronominal agreement affixes. Harris(2006) similarly shows that Georgian word-formation processes can include fully referential pronouns. This meansthat inbound anaphoric islands are not observed in some languages (or in compounds in English), a state of affairsthat should be impossible if they really follow from the putatively universal Principle of Lexical Integrity.

Inbound anaphoric islands, then, follow the pattern we have seen throughout this paper: there are numerouscounterexamples to what the Lexicalist Hypothesis requires, and where there are restrictions, they follow fromother considerations.

3.11 Summary

This section has gone through numerous cases from the literature where some phenomenon has been claimed torequire the Lexicalist Hypothesis and/or the Principle of Lexical Integrity. In every case, the Lexicalist Hypothesisis superfluous: all of the data are already accounted for by any adequate theory of phrasal syntax. All we have torecognize is that some elements are limited to operating on phrases while others are limited to operating on heads.Additionally, we need a strict principle of locality, such that elements combine semantically only with the node thatthey combine with syntactically. All of this is routine in theories of phrasal syntax, even theories that also have aseparate component of lexical rules.

4 Conclusion

The Lexicalist Hypothesis was a reasonable hypothesis about the organization of the human language faculty. Itcould have been correct that the human grammar has distinct word formation and phrasal syntax components.However, all of the evidence reviewed here indicates that it does not. The first part of this paper showed that thereare numerous phenomena where phrasal syntax provides the input to word formation, and numerous phenomenawhere phrasal operations have access to sub-word units. The second part of the paper showed that where thereare facts to be explained, they follow from any adequate theory of phrasal syntax, without the need to refer to theLexicalist Hypothesis. The Lexicalist Hypothesis is entirely redundant and superfluous. More generally, all weneed is a single combinatorial component for both words and phrases.

If some hypothesis is both incorrect and does no work, the obvious action to take is to discard it. In this case,doing so leads to the kind of theory that considerations of parsimony would also prefer: a theory where there isonly one combinatorial system putting together both words and phrases, not two distinct systems. As noted inthe introduction, a theory with only one component is simpler than and therefore preferable to a theory with twocomponents, all other things being equal. This paper has shown that all other things are equal: the LexicalistHypothesis does no work, and so has no empirical advantage to outweigh the parsimony consideration. In fact, itseems to be at a disadvantage, since it gets numerous empirical facts wrong.

I conclude that theories with the Lexicalist Hypothesis as an inextricable part are inadequate theories andshould be abandoned immediately (for instance, LFG and HPSG). The kind of theory we need is one with onlya single combinatorial system for both words and phrases. In fact, this type of approach has been shown to havenumerous advantages. For examples, see Bruening (2014) on novel and correct predictions regarding adjectival

19

Page 20: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

passives; Bruening (2013) on verbal passives; Bruening (2010) on double object constructions (or “applicatives”)and correct predictions regarding possible and impossible idioms, possible and impossible readings with adverbslike again and too, and facts about the deny class of double object verbs; and Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada (2012)on various valence-changing operations that add arguments not selected by the main verb.

One last point that should be made concerns the numerous criticisms that have been offered of particularanalyses within the general syntactic approach to word formation. For example, Williams (2007), Wechsler (2008),Newmeyer (2009), Müller (2013), and Müller and Wechsler (2014) heavily criticize the syntactic accounts ofnominalizations in Marantz (1997), Alexiadou (2001), Borer (2003), Roeper (2005), and others. Many of thesecriticisms are quite valid. However, none of them invalidate the syntactic approach in general. Showing that aspecific analysis encounters problems does not invalidate the general approach that that specific analysis is couchedwithin. To draw an analogy with the theory that Müller (2013) thinks the entire field has converged on, namelyHPSG, no one would think that a later HPSG analysis that argued against an earlier HPSG analysis of the samefacts invalidated HPSG in general.

Put differently, it is almost certainly true that we do not yet have fully adequate analyses of every particularphenomenon, or even any of them. Showing that a particular analysis is inadequate means that we are makingprogress, by having ruled out some analysis that will not work. I believe that the discussion of this paper hascontributed a giant step forward in this vein: we now know that entire classes of theories can be ruled out, becausethey assume an incorrect and superfluous hypothesis (the Lexicalist Hypothesis). We can now concentrate ourefforts on developing better analyses within the most parsimonious class of theories, namely, the ones that assumeonly a single combinatorial system for both words and phrases.

ReferencesAlexiadou, Artemis (2001), Functional Structure in Nominals: Nominalization and Ergativity. Amsterdam/Philadelphia:

John Benjamins.Artstein, Ron (2004), “Focus Below the Word Level.” Natural Language Semantics 12: 1–22.Baker, Mark (1985), “The Mirror Principle and Morphosyntactic Explanation.” Linguistic Inquiry 16: 373–415.Beck, Sigrid, and Kyle Johnson (2004), “Double Objects Again.” Linguistic Inquiry 35: 97–123.Booij, Geert E. (1985), “Coordination Reduction in Complex Words: A Case for Prosodic Phonology.” In Harry van der

Hulst and Neil Smith, eds., Advances in Nonlinear Phonology, Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 143–160.Borer, Hagit (2003), “Exo-Skeletal vs. Endo-Skeletal Explantions: Syntactic Projections and the Lexicon.” In John C.

Moore and Maria Polinsky, eds., The Nature of Explanation in Linguistic Theory, Stanford: CSLI, pp. 31–67.Borer, Hagit, ed. (2005), Structuring Sense: An Exo-Skeletal Trilogy. New York: Oxford University Press.Bosse, Solveig, Benjamin Bruening, and Masahiro Yamada (2012), “Affected Experiencers.” Natural Language and

Linguistic Theory 30: 1185–1230.Bresnan, Joan (1982), “The Passive in Lexical Theory.” In Joan Bresnan, ed., The Mental Representation of Grammatical

Relations, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3–86.Bresnan, Joan, and Sam A. Mchombo (1995), “The Lexical Integrity Principle: Evidence from Bantu.” Natural Lan-

guage and Linguistic Theory 13: 181–254.Bruening, Benjamin (2010), “Ditransitive Asymmetries and a Theory of Idiom Formation.” Linguistic Inquiry 41: 519–

562.Bruening, Benjamin (2013), “By-Phrases in Passives and Nominals.” Syntax 16: 1–41.Bruening, Benjamin (2014), “Word Formation is Syntactic: Adjectival Passives in English.” Natural Language and

Linguistic Theory 32: 363–422.Chaves, Rui P. (2008), “Linearization-Based Word-Part Ellipsis.” Linguistics and Philosophy 31: 261–307.Chaves, Rui P. (2014), “On the Disunity of Right-Node Raising Phenomena: Extraposition, Ellipsis, and Deletion.”

Language 90: 834–886.Chomsky, Noam (1970), “Remarks on Nominalization.” In R. A. Jacobs and P. S. Rosenbaum, eds., Readings in English

Transformational Grammar, Waltham, MA: Ginn, pp. 184–221.Culicover, Peter W., and Ray Jackendoff (2005), Simpler Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

20

Page 21: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

Di Sciullo, Anna-Maria, and Edwin Williams (1987), On the Definition of Word. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Dowty, David (1978), “Governed Transformations as Lexical Rules in a Montague Grammar.” Linguistic Inquiry 9:

393–426.Dowty, David (1988), “Type Raising, Functional Composition, and Non-Constituent Conjunction.” In Richard T. Oehrle,

Emmon Bach, and Deirdre Wheeler, eds., Categorial Grammars and Natural Language Structures, Dordrecht: Rei-del, pp. 153–197.

Fabb, Nigel Alexander John (1984), Syntactic Affixation. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Fu, Jingqi, Thomas Roeper, and Hagit Borer (2001), “The VP within Process Nominals: Evidence from Adverbs and

the VP Anaphor Do So.” Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 19: 549–582.Hale, Kenneth, and Samuel Jay Keyser (1993), “On Argument Structure and the Lexical Expression of Syntactic Rela-

tions.” In Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, eds., The View from Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Honor ofSylvain Bromberger, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 53–109.

Halle, Morris, and Alec Marantz (1993), “Distributed Morphology and the Pieces of Inflection.” In Kenneth Hale andSamuel Jay Keyser, eds., The View from Building 20: Essays in Linguistics in Honor of Sylvain Bromberger, Cam-bridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 111–176.

Harris, Alice C. (2006), “Revisiting Anaphoric Islands.” Language 82: 114–130.Jackendoff, Ray (2002), “English Particle Constructions, the Lexicon, and the Autonomy of Syntax.” In Nicole Dehé,

Ray Jackendoff, Andrew McIntyre, and Susan Urban, eds., Verb-Particle Explorations, Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter,pp. 67–94.

Jackendoff, Ray S. (1972), Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Kiparsky, Paul (1982), “Lexical Phonology and Morphology.” In Seok Yang, ed., Linguistics in the Morning Calm,

Seoul: Hanshin, pp. 3–91.Kratzer, Angelika (1996), “Severing the External Argument from Its Verb.” In John Rooryck and Laurie Zaring, eds.,

Phrase Structure and the Lexicon, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 109–137.Larsen, Darrell (2014), Particles and Particle-Verb Constructions in English and Other Germanic Languages. Ph.D.

thesis, University of Delaware.Lieber, Rochelle (1988), “Phrasal Compounds in English and the Morphology-Syntax Interface.” In CLS 24: Papers

from the Parasession on Agreement in Grammatical Theory, Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 202–222.Lieber, Rochelle (1992), Deconstructing Morphology: Word Formation in Syntactic Theory. Chicago and London: The

University of Chicago Press.Marantz, Alec (1997), “No Escape from Syntax: Don’t Try Morphological Analysis in the Privacy of Your Own Lexi-

con.” In Alexis Dimitriadis, Laura Siegel, Clarissa Surek-Clark, and Alexander Williams, eds., Proceedings of the21st Annual Penn Linguistics Colloquium, no. 4:2 in Penn Working Papers in Linguistics, Philadelphia: Universityof Pennsylvania.

Mohanan, K.P. (1986), The Theory of Lexical Phonology. Dordrecht: Reidel.Müller, Stefan (2006), “Phrasal or Lexical Constructions?” Language 82: 850–883.Müller, Stefan (2013), “Unifying Everything: Some Remarks on Simpler Syntax, Construction Grammar, Minimalism,

and HPSG.” Language 89: 920–950.Müller, Stefan, and Stephen Wechsler (2014), “Lexical Approaches to Argument Structure.” Theoretical Linguistics 40:

1–76.Nespor, Marina (1985), “The Phonological Word in Italian.” In Harry van der Hulst and Neil Smith, eds., Advances in

Nonlinear Phonology, Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 193–204.Newmeyer, Frederick J. (2009), “Current Challenges to the Lexicalist Hypothesis: An Overview and a Critique.” In

William D. Lewis, Simin Karimi, Heidi Harley, and Scott O. Farrar, eds., Time and Again: Theoretical Perspectiveson Formal Linguistics in Honor of D. Terence Langendoen, Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 91–117.

Pesetsky, David (1987), “Wh-in-Situ: Movement and Unselective Binding.” In Eric Reuland and Alice ter Meulen, eds.,The Representation of (In)definiteness, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 98–129.

Pollard, Carl, and Ivan Sag (1992), “Anaphors in English and the Scope of the Binding Theory.” Linguistic Inquiry 23:261–303.

Postal, Paul M. (1969), “Anaphoric Islands.” In Robert I. Binnick, Alice Davison, Georgia M. Green, and Jerry L.Morgan, eds., Papers from the Fifth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago: University ofChicago, Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 205–239.

21

Page 22: The Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and …udel.edu/~bruening/Downloads/LexicalismSuperfluous1.pdfThe Lexicalist Hypothesis: Both Wrong and Superfluous Benjamin Bruening, University

Postal, Paul M. (2004), Skeptical Linguistic Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Reinhart, Tanya, and Eric Reuland (1993), “Reflexivity.” Linguistic Inquiry 24: 657–720.Roeper, Thomas (2005), “Chomsky’s Remarks and the Transformationalist Hypothesis.” In Pavol Štekauer and Rochelle

Lieber, eds., Handbook of Word-Formation, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 1–22.Sadock, Jerrold M. (1980), “Noun Incorporation in Greenlandic: A Case of Syntactic Word Formation.” Language 56:

300–319.Sag, Ivan A. (2010), “English Filler-Gap Constructions.” Language 86: 486–545.Selkirk, Elizabeth O. (1984), Phonology and Syntax: The Relation between Sound and Structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT

Press.Simpson, Jane (1983), Aspects of Warlpiri Morphology and Syntax. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

Distributed by MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, Cambridge, Mass.Spencer, Andrew (1988), “Bracketing Paradoxes and the English Lexicon.” Language 64: 663–682.Spencer, Andrew, ed. (1991), Morphological Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.Sproat, Richard (1985), On Deriving the Lexicon. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Sproat, Richard (1988), “On Anaphoric Islandhood.” In Michael Hammond and Michael Noonan, eds., Theoretical

Morphology: Approaches in Modern Linguistics, Orlando: Academic Press, pp. 291–301.von Stechow, Arnim (1995), “Lexical Decomposition in Syntax.” In Urs Egli, Peter E. Pause, Christoph Schwarze,

Arnim von Stechow, and Götz Wienold, eds., Lexical Knowledge in the Organization of Language, Amsterdam:John Benjamins, pp. 81–117.

Ward, Gregory L., Richard Sproat, and Gail McKoon (1991), “A Pragmatic Analysis of So-Called Anaphoric Islands.”Language 67: 439–474.

Wasow, Thomas (1977), “Transformations and the Lexicon.” In P. Culicover, A. Akmajian, and T. Wasow, eds., FormalSyntax, New York: Academic Press, pp. 327–360.

Wechsler, Stephen (2008), “A Diachronic Account of English Deverbal Nominals.” In Charles B. Chang and Hannah J.Haynie, eds., Proceedings of the 26th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, Somerville, MA: CascadillaProceedings Project.

Wennerstrom, Ann (1993), “Focus on the Prefix: Evidence for Word-Internal Prosodic Words.” Phonology 10: 309–324.Williams, Edwin (2007), “Dumping Lexicalism.” In Gillian Ramchand and Charles Reiss, eds., The Oxford Handbook

of Linguistic Interfaces, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 353–381.

22