the metaphysics of personhood

13
The Question of Personhood The concept of individual rights and responsibilities is the basis of the Western democratic tradition. Nowadays, we take the oft-cited phrase from the US Declaration of Independence “All men are created equal” to include all adults in society, including women, blacks, and other minorities.  However, the historic battles of suffrage and civil rights activists to secure equal rights for non-white, non-male citizens shows that the question of personhood is far from self-evident.  The question of to whom the law applies is equally, if not more fundamental than the actual content of the laws themselves, since laws are meaningless unless they apply to someone.  With the prospects of human cloning, stem cell research, and hybridized DNA creations on our doorstep, we must again call the Question of Personhood into the foreground of legal and ethical debate. What is a person?  Is personhood dependent on DNA, or is the ability to think a better criterion for personhood status?  What is thinking?  Is there a particular kind of thinking that distinguishes persons from non-persons?  Is such a strict delineation even possible or should personhood be thought of as a scale of degrees instead of a yes/no dichotomy?  If indeed artificial persons are worthy of personhood status, how does the law apply to them? The first part of my argument will show that the question of personhood must be anthropologically- neutral because our current method of following sexual lineage is inadequate since biotechnological creations are not grounded in the same genetic framework as regular humans, both in terms of physical origin and genetic composition.  In order to properly and objectively consider the general Question of Personhood, it is necessary to step outside the particular personhood within which we find ourselves.  Next, I will show why Alan Turing’s famous criterion for sentience fails to capture the essence of personhood, but that by incorporating Heidegger’s concept of Dasein into the formula, we can arrive at a definition of personhood that is much more robust and satisfying.  If we define a sentient being as a Dasein, one with the potential for ontological questioning, we retain the ability to assign personhood status based upon behavior rather than physical constitution and yet still can reject mere symbol-manipulati ng apparatuses such as Searle’s Chinese Room. Lastly, I will draw upon Orson Scott Card's 'Hierarchy of Exclusion' to sketch a method of classifying personhood and then attempt to place particular real and hypothetical creatures within it.   A being’s place within the hierarchy determines the degree to which it is subject to the protections and responsibilities accorded to persons under the law. The Case for Anthropological Neutrality The concept of equality is implicit in Western democracy and law; it seems to be the epitome of injustice if the Law were t o apply to certain members of society and not others.  I n certain exceptional circumstances such as war or emergency we may grant immunity or far-reaching powers to particular individuals, but in general the principle of equality means that the law of the land applies equally to all citizens of the state.  However, history shows that the interpretation of the phrase “All men are created equal” is far from self-evident.  The original framers of the US Constitution weren’t too sure black men were ‘men’, and they certainly weren’t going to let women be ‘men’, either.   The struggle for racial and sexual equality under the law has essentially been a battle over the definition of personhood.  Although the original US formulation of personhood was more or less gender- and race-specific, it has since been re-interpreted to include all adult members of the human species.  Our modern perspective makes it difficult to imagine a time when “All men

Upload: eric-lee-brx

Post on 10-Apr-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 1/13

The Question of Personhood

The concept of individual rights and responsibilities is the basis of the Western democratic tradition.

Nowadays, we take the oft-cited phrase from the US Declaration of Independence “All men are created equal”

to include all adults in society, including women, blacks, and other minorities.  However, the historic battles of 

suffrage and civil rights activists to secure equal rights for non-white, non-male citizens shows that the

question of personhood is far from self-evident.  The question of to whom the law applies is equally, if not

more fundamental than the actual content of the laws themselves, since laws are meaningless unless they

apply to someone.  With the prospects of human cloning, stem cell research, and hybridized DNA creations on

our doorstep, we must again call the Question of Personhood into the foreground of legal and ethical debate.

What is a person?  Is personhood dependent on DNA, or is the ability to think a better criterion for personhood

status?  What is thinking?  Is there a particular kind of thinking that distinguishes persons from non-persons?  Is

such a strict delineation even possible or should personhood be thought of as a scale of degrees instead of a

yes/no dichotomy?  If indeed artificial persons are worthy of personhood status, how does the law apply to

them?

The first part of my argument will show that the question of personhood must be anthropologically-

neutral because our current method of following sexual lineage is inadequate since biotechnological creations

are not grounded in the same genetic framework as regular humans, both in terms of physical origin and

genetic composition.  In order to properly and objectively consider the general Question of Personhood, it is

necessary to step outside the particular personhood within which we find ourselves.  Next, I will show why Alan

Turing’s famous criterion for sentience fails to capture the essence of personhood, but that by incorporating

Heidegger’s concept of Dasein into the formula, we can arrive at a definition of personhood that is much more

robust and satisfying.  If we define a sentient being as a Dasein, one with the potential for ontological

questioning, we retain the ability to assign personhood status based upon behavior rather than physical

constitution and yet still can reject mere symbol-manipulating apparatuses such as Searle’s Chinese Room.

Lastly, I will draw upon Orson Scott Card's 'Hierarchy of Exclusion' to sketch a method of classifying personhood

and then attempt to place particular real and hypothetical creatures within it.   A being’s place within the

hierarchy determines the degree to which it is subject to the protections and responsibilities accorded to

persons under the law.

The Case for Anthropological Neutrality 

The concept of equality is implicit in Western democracy and law; it seems to be the epitome of 

injustice if the Law were to apply to certain members of society and not others.  In certain exceptional

circumstances such as war or emergency we may grant immunity or far-reaching powers to particularindividuals, but in general the principle of equality means that the law of the land applies equally to all citizens

of the state.  However, history shows that the interpretation of the phrase “All men are created equal” is far

from self-evident.  The original framers of the US Constitution weren’t too sure black men were ‘men’, and

they certainly weren’t going to let women be ‘men’, either.   The struggle for racial and sexual equality under

the law has essentially been a battle over the definition of personhood.  Although the original US formulation

of personhood was more or less gender- and race-specific, it has since been re-interpreted to include all adult

members of the human species.  Our modern perspective makes it difficult to imagine a time when “All men

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 2/13

are created equal” was meant to apply, implicitly or explicitly, only to white males, but the reality of ongoing

apartheid and genocide around the world suggests that our Western definition of personhood is not so clearly

a given assumption as we might believe.

Let us politically correct ourselves then and say that “All persons are created equal”, so as to include all

members of the human species.  However, we must not forget the caveat that children under the age of 

majority face additional limitations (e.g. driving an automobile, buying alcohol) and protections (e.g. the YoungOffenders’ Act, inability to give consent) under the law.  We tolerate age-based personhood discrimination

because we recognize that a certain level of experience and guidance is required to make proper decisions.  A

person who is not yet fully formed needs protection from dangerous situations that they themselves may not

recognize, and society as a whole needs protection from children who may not comprehend the consequences

of their actions.  Most people under the age of majority who commit crimes in Canada are tried under the

Young Offenders’ Act1.  The rationale for this is that young people who do not yet realize the full gravity of their

actions should be treated more leniently than someone with the ability to distinguish right from wrong.

However, in particularly vicious cases such as murder and sexual assault, the court can override the Young

Offenders Act and try sixteen-year-olds as adults.  On the other hand, adults with psychological or

developmental problems can be given special consideration and leniency by the court in order to recognizetheir limited or impaired ability to understand the consequences of their actions.   This indicates that the

concept of maturity and status as a fully-formed person is more dependent on behavior than age, with age

being used as a guideline rather than an absolute limit.

The idea that personhood is dependent on behavior rather than physical characteristics is a logical

consequence that follows from the extension of civil rights towards people with different skin tones and sex

organs.  We haven’t bothered to update our species-chauvinist ways because determining personhood has

always been phenotypical: if it comes out of a female person, it’s a person!   The prying open of the human

code by human hand, eye, and machines infuses us with a confident sense of ourselves.  We have discovered

and decoded the actual formula for ourselves and we hold it in our hands.  The precise specification of geneticlineages, inherited diseases and fatherhood is now taken for granted, which makes the question of personhood

seem like a relic of a bygone era.  While on the one hand we possess the unprecedented ability to identify and

classify, at the same time we inherit the ability to manufacture, create, and shape the building blocks of nature

and ourselves.  The fusion of science and actual human material opens up the question of personhood in ways

that we must prepare to deal with, but we are dazzled by the glimmering light of our technological

achievements.  We don’t bother asking about personhood because the answer seems simple: check the DNA

test!  However, we haven’t yet devised a way to delineate the limits of personhood from the standpoint of 

acceptable deviation from the norm, and it seems doubtful whether a DNA test for personhood makes sense.

It seems a rather simple process to establish certain parameters that would serve as a genetic outline

for the human race.  The problem with this is that such parameters may assign personhood to a wider range of 

beings than is prudent.  If a person is anything with human DNA, what about stem cells and embryos?  We still

need to draw a line between what constitutes a person, and what we consider to be a part of person, or a not-

yet person.  The idea of hybridized organisms, the correction of genetic diseases, and the idea of parents

selecting characteristics of their children makes the question more difficult to ascertain.  How much

modification is tolerable within the genetic parameters?  Would an otherwise ‘normal’ person found to be

outside the acceptable DNA limits be stripped of their personhood status?  What would they then become?

1 Young Offenders Act in Canada.  Http://www.lawprotector.ca/youth-criminal-justice.html

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 3/13

I believe a more adequate and common-sense solution is to consider the question of personhood from

a behavioral rather than a genetic point of view.  The possibility of encountering entirely new and strange types

of human beings is a prospect that Western culture hasn’t had to deal with since the opening up of the New

World in the sixteenth century.  We recognize the colonial injustices done and we continue to see the

repercussions of the violent first encounter between First Nations peoples and Europeans in North America,

yet we still haven’t formulated a proper account of what went wrong and what we would do again in a similar

situation.  If we examine the question from both sides of the conflict, as conquerors and as conquered, we will

recognize that our perception of the genetic ‘others’ as somehow less human is a trap that leads to violence

and war.  Surely a new formulation of the question of personhood must take into account the atrocities caused

by our past inability to consider personhood from an objective, universal standpoint.  If we are prejudiced by

our own biology, we will be forced to admit that no alien species, no matter how intellectually, ethically, or

technologically superior could ever be worthy of the same respect we grant to our own geno-comrades.

Anthropomorphism prevents us from asking the general question of what it means to be a person because it

doesn’t allow us to get outside of our own communities, cultures, countries and genetic composition to a

universal perspective.

A Modified Turing Test +Dasein

The need to step outside of our genetic prejudices necessitates examining the question of personhood

from a behavioral rather than a physical perspective.  Alan Turing's Turing Test is a convenient point of 

departure to imagine what a behavioral model of personhood might look like2.  Turing asks whether a system

of machine-based logic could ever be considered to possess intelligence, with the implication that, given

enough computing power, a machine capable of thought would require us to rethink our conception of 

sentience and personhood, and possibly extend these concepts to include artificial intelligence.  The Turing

Test is a modified version of ‘The Imitation Game’, a simple party game where an interrogator and two players,

one male and one female, are isolated from each other, with the sole method of interaction being written

communication, e.g. a pen and a pad of paper or a computer terminal.  The interrogator asks questions toplayers A and B in order to ascertain which player is the male and which is the female.  One of the players

attempts to trick the interrogator into making a false identification (by pretending to be the other sex), while

the other player tries to aid the interrogator.  In the Turing Test, the male and female participants are replaced

by human and computer roles, with the computer attempting to fool the interrogator into thinking that it is a

human.  Turing argues that if the success rate of an interrogator playing the modified human vs. computer

Imitation Game is equivalent to their success rate playing the original male vs. female version, then there are

grounds to believe that the computer exhibits intelligence.  It is interesting that Turing's attempt to define the

mind from a strict materialist perspective (as opposed to a dualist perspective, with the belief that aspects of 

the human mind cannot be described in physical terms, i.e. the soul) leads him to define intelligence by

behavior rather than physical constitution.

One problem with Turing's conception of intelligence is raised by John Searle in his famous 'Chinese

Room' response3.  Searle imagines a computer program that is able to pass the Turing Test, and in this case it

has the ability to speak fluent Chinese.  Since the program follows a set of computer-language instructions to

2Oppy, Graham and Dowe, David.  The Turing Test.  Stanford Encyclopedia of  Philosophy,

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/turing-test/, 2008.

3Hauser, Larry.  Chinese Room Argument.  Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,

http://www.iep.utm.edu/chineser, 2005.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 4/13

perform this task, it would be possible (if not practical) to print out these formal rules in English on a set of 

cards and give them to an ordinary person who does not speak Chinese.  This person is placed in a room, and

told to follow the instructions on the cards upon receiving input.  A person outside the room feeds input, i.e. a

question in Chinese, into the room through a slot in the door.  The person inside the room follows the

instructions on the cards in order to produce output data, i.e. a response in Chinese, which is sent back through

the slot to the other side.  The Chinese Room would pass the Turing Test for intelligence, since, from the

outside, the system appears to speak fluent Chinese.  Searle asks, is there any part of the system that actually

understands Chinese?  Certainly the man inside the room doesn’t understand Chinese, and neither do the cards

or the room itself!  Searle’s point is that while the ability to manipulate symbols may indicate intelligence,

without an understanding of what it is processing, of what it is doing, a system really doesn’t possess

intelligence in the same way that humans do.  Any criterion for intelligence that only takes into account the

correct manipulation of symbols fails because it doesn’t encompass the way our own minds have intentionality,

the realization that thoughts are about some thing or another.

Despite its flaws, the Turing Test has some features that are useful in our discussion of the question of 

personhood.  The most interesting aspect of the Turing Test is its universality.  The test takes a strictly

functional or behaviorist approach to the question of intelligence, since its aim is to determine whether amachine, i.e. a non-human, could ever possess intelligence.  Alan Turing's theory of mind attempts to break

away from anthropomorphism.  The problem with anthropomorphic theories of mind is that they beg the

question.  If we define ‘intelligence’ only in terms of what ‘intelligent’ beings do, then the answer to our

question is contained in the premise itself!  Even the Turing Test falls somewhat into the trap of 

anthropomorphism.  Although it attempts to be neutral with respect to physical constitution, it still defines

‘intelligence’ in terms of how well a machine emulates human behavior and human intelligence, rather than

intelligence in general .  Often human behavior isunintelligent, and it is ironic that some computers fail the

Turing Test because interrogators notice a lack of typing errors.  On the other hand, some intelligent behavior

is not human, such as the computation of large numbers, so machines in the Turing Test must make sure not to

appear to be more intelligent than a regular human.

It is interesting that Turing chose the use of language as the criterion for intelligence.  Certainly, the

ability to communicate and discuss one's thoughts, feelings, and desires is one aspect of the human

experience, but is that sufficient?  Exactly what are suitable topics for conversation?  If one chooses to engage

in dialogue that is heavily dependent upon slang, idioms, and specialized vocabulary, I doubt most regular

people would be able to carry on such a conversation, let alone a machine carrying out a set of instructions.

Would we then be forced to say that those people fail the Turing test and thus lack intelligence?  If not, why do

machines face a higher standard for 'intelligence' than humans?  Should we demote persons who lack

interpersonal skills and promote charming computers?  The use of language is one step towards the kind of 

intelligence we are discussing, but merely being able to communicate is insufficient for the question of personhood since many animals already possess this ability but are not treated as persons.  Thekind of 

conversation is critical here.  Although apes can be taught to communicate using sign language, we intuitively

feel that there still exists a gap between us and them.  They are certainly sentient, and thus deserving of 

respect, i.e. we must not inflict unnecessary pain on them, but their mental faculties are certainly not on the

same level as our own.  Are the deficiencies of animal intelligence simply a matter of their brains being

underpowered?  Would a simple upgrade of processing speed, and thusmore of the same kind of thinking ever

satisfy our criterion for personhood?  Would having the ability for more animal-level thoughts per second ever

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 5/13

allow them to jump to the level of thinking that is peculiar to humans?  What kind of thinkingis peculiar to

people alone?

In Being and Time, Martin Heidegger sets out to uncover the fundamental question of Being, the

property of the universe that allows specific instances of Being, or beings, to exist 4.  Being is to existence as

light is to vision.  In the same way that we see light only when it illuminates some thing, we see Being only

through beings that exist.  He believes that philosophers throughout history have missed the big question of Being because they have been preoccupied with describing the properties of specific beings, and thus never get

deep enough to reach the question of Being in general.  If we want to describe a forest, we cannot simply stare

at individual trees but must be able to stand outside of it.  Our attempt to describe Being faces the same

difficulty: how can we, as beings necessarily stuck within the forest of Being, ever attain a perspective outside

of Being-ness that would allow us to describe this fundamental property of ourselves?  Heidegger believes that

the realization of the question of fundamental Being, as opposed to individual instances of being, signifies a

paradigmatic shift in mental development.  Why is the question of Being a problem at all?  For Heidegger, the

reason that this problem exists is because we are capable of asking it!  Humans are unique on Earth in that we

are the sole creatures who possess the ability to pose questions about the fundamental nature of ontology,

with the implication that we alone may somehow be capable of answering it.  Instead of trying to find someexceptional state of non-Being from which to answer the question of Being, Heidegger believes that insight

must be gained from understanding regular, everyday ontological questioners, i.e. ourselves.  For Heidegger,

every being in the world is necessarily embedded within the fundamental nature of Being, and we are thus

completely 'thrown' into a universe which shapes us completely.  If we are going to understand Being, we need

to recognize that, first and foremost, we belong to the realm of existence, we are necessarily 'there' in the

world.  Heidegger uses the word Dasein (literally, 'being-there', or 'being-in-the-world') to signify the

ontological questioner, i.e. ourselves, for whom the general question of Being is an issue of importance.

The fundamental quality of Dasein that distinguishes it from other beings in the universe is its ability to

formulate questions of ontology, rather than simply ontics.  This distinction between ontology and ontics willhelp illuminate and overcome the struggle to find a functionalist definition of intelligence that doesn't get

tripped up by the Chinese Room dilemma.  One of the main problems with ontological inquiry is that we have a

tendency to lapse into ontics; we treat Being as something within the category of Being, and thus its general

description remains vague.  It is like trying to describe the general concept of 'dog' by talking about spaniels or

poodles.  If you can only tell me about a specific type of dog or a certain mode of existence, you aren't really

talking about the general category 'Dog', or 'Being'.  Another way to think of ontology vs. ontics is to imagine a

serene fall landscape.  If you asked a regular person to describe the scene, they would probably use broad

terminology, e.g. "The wind is blowing", "The leaves are changing color", "The air has a cool, fresh scent".  On

the other hand, a computer would probably use precise details to talk about the scene, e.g. "The temperature

is 12 degrees", "45 percent of the foliage has fallen to the ground", "It is the 8th of November".  In both cases,we receive information about the scene, but the two categories of description appeal to different levels of 

understanding.  If we only consider Being ontically, i.e. using precise details like a computer would, we are

stuck with describing specific instances of Being, i.e. beings, rather than Being itself.  If we fall into the trap of 

treating ontological questions ontically, we will end up acting "as if they concerned one entity amongst others,

and could be sufficiently explained by 'telling a story' (as in a 'history of philosophy') and tracing them 'back in

4 Heidegger, Martin.  Being and Time.  Harper and Row Publishers, Inc., New York, 1962, 2008.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 6/13

origin to some other entities, as if being had the character of some possible entity'"5.  We must be careful not

to allow our consideration of ontology, i.e. the nature of Being, to stray onto the path of ontics, i.e. the nature

of specific beings.

The ontologic / ontic distinction is crucial to answering the question of personhood.  In a very intuitive

sense we feel that the Turing Test is inadequate; there is an aspect of human intelligence that a symbol-

manipulating system like the Chinese Room lacks, namely, ontological understanding.  As Searle's responseshows, a computer possesses ontic knowledge, i.e. it can properly relate certain symbols to other symbols and

thus carry out a conversation, but it lacks ontological knowledge, i.e. what the symbols actually mean.  Searle's

Chinese Room could define a Chinese character in terms of other Chinese characters, but it could never step

outside of those symbols and define them in terms of something else.  If we ask the machine "What does A

mean?", it must respond by saying that "A means B."  If we continue and ask, "Well, what does B mean?", the

computer might respond with another synonym, "B means C".  Although the computer may be able to continue

like this for some time, at some point it will run out of synonyms and have to circle back to the beginning of the

inquiry, by saying that "C means A".  The program's lack of meta-understanding, of its being unable to step

outside of the formal logic of its machine language, shows that it cannot conceive of the Chinese characters in

terms of something other than other Chinese characters.  It is an ontic wizard, yet it is completely void of ontologic understanding, which is one of the key aspects (I will argue the key aspect) of personhood.

Dasein is an appropriate way to characterize personhood for a number of reasons.  First, it satisfies our

need for an anthropologically-neutral definition, in that "when we designate this entity with the term 'Dasein',

we are expressing not its "what" (as if it were a table, house or tree) but its Being" (Heidegger p 67).  In order

to approach the larger question of Being, one must first take into account the nature of the entity who poses

the question of Being.  The difficulty for Dasein lies in the fact that the deeper question of its ontology, i.e.

what it means to Be or to exist, has historically been passed over in favor of questions concerning its ontics, i.e.

the history of its being throughout the ages.  The real question of Being remains obscure, and it "is rather

conceived as something obvious or 'self-evident' in the sense of the Being-present-at-hand of other createdThings" (Heidegger, p 75).  The essence of Dasein is therefore not the ability to trace a linear causality further

and further back in time, but rather the ability to speculate on the nature of Being or existence itself.

If we modify Turing's criterion for intelligence to encompass the qualities of Dasein, we have a much

more robust theory of personhood.  First, it is anthropologically neutral.  It allows for the possibility that

machines, animals, and alien beings could be considered intelligent persons, which I believe is the most

valuable aspect of the Turing test.  If behavior (rather than genetics) is what distinguishes people from lower

forms of life, we can escape from the circular logic of 'Humans are intelligent, therefore intelligence requires

human DNA', and we can avoid the unenviable task of having to first establish arbitrary genetic limits of 

personhood and then having to enforce those criteria.   Secondly, we can overcome the Chinese Room problem

by having the ability to distinguish between mere symbol-manipulating entities and entities that possess higher

levels of understanding.  If our criteria for personhood is simply the ability to use language, we face two

problems.  First, the topic of conversation is arbitrary.  Many clearly intelligent humans could not carry on a

conversation about the World Series or about the latest fashion trends out of Paris.  Would these folks

therefore lack intelligence?  I don't think so.  It is necessary to define what the topic of conversation should be

if we expect to have a consistent, fair method of evaluation.  The second problem is that symbol-manipulating

5Monk, Ray and Raphael, Frederic.  The Great Philosophers: From Socrates to Turing.  Weidenfeld and

Nicholson, London, 2000, p. 298.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 7/13

apparatuses with no intentionality could pass the test.  If we augment the criterion for personhood from simply

'the ability to converse' to 'the ability to converse about the question of Being', we now have a definition that

includes humans and excludes Searle's Chinese Room and, presumably, other animal species.  One of the

strengths of defining personhood in terms of Dasein is that it leaves the door open for the discovery of animal,

machine, and alien Daseins, even though at present, we know of only one type of Dasein, ourselves.  One may

object that my definition excludes human embryos, infants, and the mentally impaired: Are they not persons as

well?  To this, I should clarify that Daseins aren't constantly questioning Being; even the most intelligent people

are able to immerse themselves and become lost for a while in the simple pleasures of life.  Daseins are beings

with the potential ability to question Being.  Thus undeveloped or unrealized Daseins are still Daseins, in the

same way that a monarch caterpillar still belongs to the same family of organisms as the monarch butterfly,

even if the caterpillar dies before it undergoes metamorphosis.

Working up the Hierarchy of Exclusion

A further property of Dasein is that the "...Being which is an issue for this entity in its very Being, is in

each case [its own]"6.  In other words, Dasein arrives at the general question of Being through first questioning

the riddle of its own existence.  When it finds allontic or causal explanations to be insufficient, it turns to the

ontological issue of the nature of existence itself.  These 'big questions' about one's own existence and about

existence itself are what separates the intelligence of persons from the thought processes of lower forms of 

life, i.e. animals and symbolic machine logic.  However, this leads us to ask: What exactlyare ontological

questions, anyway?  If an animal, machine or alien began to ask these questions, how would we react?  Would

we have to grant them personhood status?  Would we be allowed to kill them?  How can we classify sentient,

pre-sentient, and non-sentient life forms, and how should the law apply to them?

The point of Searle's Chinese Room response to the Turing Test is to illustrate how our common sense

notions of personhood cannot be ignored in the discussion.  After all, weare persons, and one of our key

features is the ability to recognize intelligence in others.  A criterion for personhood that doesn't make sense to

most people is probably a failure.  Although a system with only the ability to manipulate symbols seems

insufficient to deserve personhood status, how would the argument change if the criterion for passing the

Turing Test were extended to include the character of Dasein?  If the same initial conditions were preserved,

i.e. a man in a closed room with a set of instructions to follow, and somehow this system began outputting

questions about the nature of Being, would we still agree with Searle that the Room lacks true intelligence?  If 

an animal, machine, or alien began to ask 'big' questions, like 'What happens when I die?', 'Where does the

Universe come from?' or 'What is outside of the Universe?', it would certainly be disturbing, and would likely

cause us to call into question whether the being we are conversing with is merely mimicking human behavior

or has stepped towards full human intelligence.

I will not attempt to spell out the full range of what constitutes an ontological question, other than to

say that we seem to feel the weight of these questions more so than regular ones.  When we try to fathom

concepts like the edge of the Universe, time before the Big Bang, Nothingness or Infinity, we experience a

feeling of existential vertigo, an overwhelming sense that our lives are insignificant and meaningless within the

vastness of the void of space.  Historically, we have dealt with these questions by appeal to supernatural

deities, gods and spirits who control various aspects of the world we live in.  Religion and spirituality reflect

Dasein's quest for ontological understanding, they are ways of plugging the dam to hold back the existential

6 Heidegger, Martin.  Being and Time.  Harper and Row Publishers, Inc., New York, 1962, 2008, p. 67.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 8/13

pressure of Being from flooding our rational minds with its unanswered (and unanswerable) questions.  As

Dasein becomes more aware of its world through science and exploration, it has less of a need to appeal to

supernatural causes, but as Kurt Godel's Incompleteness Theorem demonstrates, the logical impossibility of 

knowing everything means that one can never fully free oneself from superstitious and untestable hypotheses7.

The tendency for scientists and philosophers to relegate religion to the dustbin of history robs us of the

opportunity to investigate the ontological questioning of various cultures.  Questioning someone's religious

beliefs is an extremely sensitive and tricky thing to do because it releases a torrent of existential uncertainty

upon the one being questioned.  Religion and faith are tools that deflect ontological dilemmas so that one can

escape the terrifying helplessness and meaninglessness that confronts us when we question the nature of 

Being.  Religion is an indicator of humanity's shift from basic biologic intelligence to the ontological intelligence

of Dasein.

The prospect of a computer posing ontological questions is unnerving because it cuts to the very

essence of how we define ourselves.  We have created computers with the ability to learn and to pose

questions.  Is it not fathomable that they eventually work their way to ontological questions?  I believe most

people's feelings about their trusty home computer would change if the computer began asking them 'big'

questions.  Searle's Chinese Room response succeeds against the regular Turing Test, but I'm not sure how wellit would fare against a modified Turing Test incorporating the essence of Dasein.  What about animals?  We

know that higher-level apes have the ability to communicate using sign language, but while they do possess the

ability for self-reflection, empathy and deception, it is doubtful that they ontologize.  However, we have only

scratched the surface of our quest for linguistic communication between humans and animals.  How would our

perception of life on Earth change if we learned that other species, such as dolphins or squids, wonder about

the same 'big' questions as ourselves?  Do animals have religious beliefs?  How can we be sure that it isn'tthey 

who think we are primitive?  One may object that my definition of personhood is too inclusive, that it allows for

the possibility that almost anything capable of thought be considered worthy of personhood.  If zoologists

discover one chimpanzee capable of ontological reasoning, wouldn’t we be forced to concede that personhood

status be conferred to all chimps?  Wouldn’t we then have to consider the possibility that all simians possess

this potential ability?  Where would personhood end?  This leads us to consider that personhood may not be a

'black and white' distinction; there may be degrees of personhood which need to be elaborated.

The idea of degrees of personhood is not as counter-intuitive as it appears at first glance.  We often

humanize animals:  many people speak of their pets as having distinctpersonalities, and many people treat

their pets as members of their families.  On the other hand, we often speak of serial murders in a

dehumanizing way, of them being ‘monsters’ or ‘animals’ without souls, or lacking conscience.  In a very literal

sense psychopaths lack a defining characteristic of human behavior: empathy.   Our laws, in fact, reflect this

personalization and de-personalization.  While it is nothing out of the ordinary for a farmer to kill a cow or

chicken for meat, it is illegal to kill a domestic cat or dog for the same purpose, barring extreme circumstances,of course.  While it is illegal for the state to infringe upon the freedoms of a regular citizens, it is appropriate to

imprison (and in some cultures, execute) citizens who have contravened criminal law.  We assign degrees of 

personhood (or lack of personhood) to animals and people, and this appears to be based on the degree to

which they exhibit ‘humane’ (or inhumane) behavior.   The same person who grieves over the loss of the family

dog with an elaborate burial ceremony may simply flush a dead goldfish down the toilet.  A jaywalker may

experience little to no loss of freedom, while a serial rapist may receive a life sentence or even execution.  This

7 Hofstadter, Douglas.  Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid.  Basic Books, USA, 1979.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 9/13

reinforces the idea that behavior is the determining factor for personhood.

The final section of my discussion will draw upon Orson Scott Card's 'Ender Series', specifically his

'Hierarchy of Exclusion', in order to formulate a basis for a universal criteria for assigning personhood based on

behavior.  The Ender Series begins near the climax of the third and decisive battle between human beings and

the 'Buggers', an alien race with a hive-like mentality controlled by a Queen who communicates

instantaneously across space to her drones8

.  The Buggers have sent a final wave of attacking ships in order tostrike a finishing blow and wipe out humanity.  The protagonist, Andrew 'Ender' Wiggin, is a child soldier who is

unknowingly manipulated into destroying the Buggers' home planet, thus destroying the Buggers, saving

humanity, and becoming a worldwide hero.  After the Bugger War, Ender flees Earth to avoid being co-opted

by the factions on Earth who, now that the threat of alien war is gone, are vying for power and plotting war

against each other.  On a distant planet, Ender discovers the last remaining Bugger Queen, with whom he

learns to communicate9.  Upon hearing the tragic story of the nearly extinct alien race, Ender writes a history of 

the Buggers, or 'Formics', in which he reveals that the war was a grave misunderstanding, where both sides

mistakenly thought the other was hostile and incapable of inter-species communication.

As the true history and nature of the Formics becomes understood on Earth, humankind's attitude

towards the alien species changes and the war is recognized as a tragic error rather than a grand success.

Instead of being worshiped as a hero, the legendary Ender is now reviled as the one responsible for destroying

an entire species of intelligent life, and becomes known as 'Ender the Xenocide'.  The second and third

installments of the Ender series focus on the struggle to establish a system for identifying, classifying, and

interacting with life forms having different degrees of sentience, which becomes known as the 'Hierarchy of 

Exclusion'.  Card's system establishes four main categories of life forms, not including familiar members of 

one's own species and world.  The first two categories, Utlanning and Framling, both designate strangers of 

one's own species, with the first group coming from one's own planet, and the second group coming from

another planet.  From our perspective, an Utlanning would be a human from Earth and a Framling would be a

human from another colonized planet.  The next two categories of life forms, Ramen and Varelse, both includebeings from other species.  Ramen designates those species that are capable of communication and peaceful

co-existence with other intelligent species, while Varelse are incapable of communication with other forms of 

life10.  The distinction between Ramen and Varelse is the philosophical and ethical issue that permeates the rest

of the Ender Series.

At this point, you may be wondering what the debate about alien intelligence has to do with life on

Earth.  If we concede that the prospect of artificially-created human beings is immanent, we must recognize

that a potentially new kind of being is on the way.  The Ramen / Varelse distinction applies to life forms of 

another species which thus might include, depending on how modified one's DNA is, genetically modified

humanoids.  Our ability to modify human genotypes takes breeding to an unprecedented level.  Up until now,

we have only been able to select for phenotypes, i.e. the outward characteristics of a being.  Genetic alteration

was bound by the physical realities of animals: trying to mate a tiger and a bumblebee was impossible because

it simply wouldn't work.  Now, the possibilities are limitless.  We have decoded the actual building blocks of 

life, and have the power to stitch together DNA from various sources or even to create entirely new genetic

strands.  The line between what is, in genetic terms, an artificial 'human' and an artificial 'other' has yet to be

8 Card, Orson Scott.  Ender's Game.  Tor Books, USA, 1985.

9 Card, Orson Scott.  Speaker for the Dead.  Tor Books, USA, 1986.

10 Card, Orson Scott.  Xenocide.  Tor Books, USA, 1991.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 10/13

determined.  Biologists consider two animals as belonging to the same species if they can mate and produce

fertile offspring.  If one were to create a genetically modified humanoid that, other than being infertile, was

typically 'human', would they therefore belong to a different species and thus not receive personhood status?

My argument is that a behavioral criterion for personhood is essential because a strictly genetic definition is

inadequate.  Any delineation between species based on pure genetics will not only be flawed by its

arbitrariness, it will be unable to encompass all the potential forms of otherwise 'human' forms of life that

might come about, and it precludes the possibility of non-organic beings to possess intelligence.  The biologist's

definition of species is based on behavior, and our definition of personhood must follow suit.

The distinction between Ramen and Varelse must be clarified.  Simply being able to communicate is

not a sufficiently robust criteria for full 'intelligence', as Searle's Chinese Room argument shows, but the other

aspect of Ramen is its ability for peaceful co-existence with other species.  How can we define one's ability to

peacefully co-exist?  Here is where Dasein returns to the story.  If the essential quality of Dasein is its ability to

ontologize outside of its own ontic history, then part of being a Dasein is the recognition of and respect for

other Daseins, regardless of their physical constitution.  "Dasein's 'average everydayness' can be defined as

'Being-in-the-world which is falling and disclosed, thrown and projecting, and for which its ownmost

potentiality-for-Being is an issue, both in its Being alongside the 'world' and in its Being-with-Others'"11.Dasein's ontological structure as Being-alongside-other-entities-within-the-world leads to the recognition of 

care as its distinctive and essential feature.  For Heidegger, care "embraces the unity of these ways in which

Being may be characterized"12, and thus Dasein's concern for itself necessarily includes a concern for the

welfare of the world within which it finds itself.  Essential to Dasein is its ability to consider other beings whom

it exists alongside as possible Daseins who are therefore worthy of respect and deserving of harmonious co-

existence.  Not surprisingly, humans have a special knack for recognizing intelligent pattern and behavior in

other creatures, artifacts, and phenomena, and the difficulties faced by those who, due to impairments in the

brain, illustrate how essential this skill is in our everyday lives.  We are so enamored of this that we often

ascribe intelligence and intentionality to clearly non-intelligent processes, such as weather and machines, when

we say "The sea is angry" or "My computer is acting crazy".  Our striving to find other sources of intelligence

shows the care of Dasein in action.

Thus Ramen are defined as non-human species who exhibit the qualities of Dasein, while Varelse are

non-human species who exhibit intelligence but do not ontologize.  This definition satisfies the need for

anthropological neutrality and is robust enough to exclude systems that lack intentionality, like the Chinese

Room.  The fundamental question that remains is the problem of observation, for it places an onus of 

responsibility on ourselves to make the effort to detect signs of intelligence and personhood.  According to

Card, "The difference between Ramen and Varelse is not in the creature judged, but in the creature judging.

When we declare an alien species to be Ramen, it does not mean that they have passed a threshold of moral

maturity.  It means thatwe have"13

.  Indeed the aim of this paper is not solely to judge the worth of othercreatures, but to increase our own level of ethical maturity with respect to the beings whom we are in the

process of creating.  Should we not consider the consequences of our actionsbefore we commit them?  A

parent is deemed neglectful if they do not provide the means for their child to live and prosper in the world,

are creations of science not worthy of the same care and respect?  It is vitally important thatwe act as Ramen,

11Heidegger, Martin.  Being and Time.  Harper and Row Publishers, Inc., New York, 1962, 2008, p. 225.

12 Ibid, p. 237.

13 Demosthenes' Letter to the Framlings.  Card, Orson Scott.  Speaker for the Dead.  Tor Books, USA, 1986, p. 1.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 11/13

and not as Varelse, in our dealings with non-human forms of intelligence, whether the beings are humanoid,

animal, machine, or alien.

Let us now consider how different types of intelligent beings would fit under my ontological criterion

for personhood.  At the risk of appearing species-ist and/or igniting the abortion debate, it seems logical to

posit that all developed and developing humans who possess a full set of DNA, i.e. adults, children, fetuses and

embryos but not egg or sperm cells, have the potential to become ontologizers and thus deserve personhoodstatus.  This supposition is not based upon genetics, but rather the behavioral tendencies of the human

species.  Human cell cultures may possess a complete DNA set but are not in the process of development and

thus are not persons.  Less clear-cut examples may include cell cultures which contain stem cells, and thusdo

have the potential to develop into specialized types of cells, including brain cells.  Although there is room for

debate, I believe that if the cells can be kept from developing further without being killed in the process, then

as long as they remain in their non-realized general state, their potential for becoming a person is under

control and they therefore are not deserving of personhood status.  This distinction has particular

consequences for biologists who are studying ways to replace damaged tissue and organs by growing and

harvesting human stem cell cultures.  As long as the tissue remains in its original state and is unable to progress

beyond being a stem cell, then it is not a person and using it for research is acceptable.  Using humans,humanoids, or modified humans who have human brains would be unacceptable because those beings do have

the potential to exhibit the qualities of Dasein, given the opportunity.

Another area for discussion is hybridized or genetically-modified humanoids.  Here the myriad of 

possible types of organisms necessitates a case-by-case consideration based upon behavior.  It is prudent to err

on the side of caution here, by taking the default position that any being containing traces of human DNA be

considered to be persons, unless thorough observation proves otherwise.  Although it may be determined that

the hybrid animal does not, in fact, possess the potential for ontological questioning, it does not imply that

they are not worthy of any rights, only that the scope of protections extended to them might be lesser than

those conferred to persons.  Imperative in this determination isour willingness to investigate thoroughly and tobe sensitive to attempts by the subject to communicate.  The developmental process of the humanoid may

take as long (or longer) than that of a regular human being, thus such a venture is a serious undertaking that

must be done under strict supervision with the rights of the subject in mind.  If we expect a teenage mother to

adhere to a certain level of care for her child over the course of decades, surely the onus of responsibility of 

professionally trained scientists towards their creations should be much greater!  A scientist who murders a

person should be treated no less leniently than a doctor who kills a patient.

In the case of machine intelligence, it seems doubtful that we would ever legislate against the killing of 

a computer, although if we were ever to encounter an ontologizing machine, it might make us second-guess

our biologic prejudices.  If a machine began asking questions along a line of inquiry like "What happens when I

die?", how might we react?  Could we ever use machines to help us gain insight into the fundamental question

of Being?  If we had a computer (or a computer program) that could do such a thing, would we everwant to kill

it?   At what point would software become its own species?  Computer software already possesses the ability

to self-replicate, to learn, to deceive, and to fight for its own survival, so how different is a computer virus from

a flu virus?  Would computers ever create myths to explain the unexplainable?  At this point, most of these

questions still exist in the realm of speculative fiction, although a time may come when the answers to them

are essential for human existence.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 12/13

Conclusion

The Question of Personhood is vital from a legal, ethical, and existential perspective because it sets the

ground upon which all of these higher concepts apply.  It is absolutely essential to decideto whom the law

applies, not only what the law should be.  We are entering a new paradigm of biotechnological development,

one which will thrust the Question of Personhood to the forefront of public debate.  We must not allow our

ancient prejudices or our modern technological achievements to blind us from the need for a definition of personhood that is based upon neutral, rational principles rather than genetics.  A behavioral criterion for

personhood is essential if we are to prepare our world and ourselves for the new types of humans we are now

capable of creating.  We have the ability to create new species of humanoids, must we not also prepare our

minds and our social system for their arrival?  Dasein provides a useful framework for personhood because it

incorporates the ontological way of thinking that excludes mere animal and discrete-state types of intelligence.

Dasein's fundamental element of care means that it can see the world and itself as necessarily entwined and

demands that Dasein be responsive and respectful to the needs of the beings alongside whom it exists.  There

can be no Dasein without the world, and thus care for oneself entails care for others.  The need to define

others in terms of Dasein and non-Dasein, or Ramen and Varelse necessarily places the onus of responsibility

on the observer to take all necessary steps to reach out towards other forms of intelligence.  It is imperativethat we first examine our own moral maturity before we judge others.  The Question of Personhood requires

us to first look into ourselves in order to discover what makes us what we are, and only then can we properly

reach out to other forms of life with the hopes of welcoming them into our domain.

8/8/2019 The Metaphysics of Personhood

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/the-metaphysics-of-personhood 13/13

Works Cited

Heidegger, Martin.  Being and Time.  Harper and Row Publishers, Inc., New York, 1962, 2008.

Krell, David Farrell.  Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings.  HarperCollins Publishers, USA, 1977, 1993.

Monk, Ray and Raphael, Frederic.  The Great Philosophers: From Socrates to Turing.  Weidenfeld and

Nicholson, London, 2000.

Oppy, Graham and Dowe, David.  The Turing Test.  Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,

Http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/turing-test/, 2008.

Hauser, Larry.  Chinese Room Argument.  Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy,

http://www.iep.utm.edu/chineser, 2005.

Hofstadter, Douglas.  Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid.  Basic Books, USA, 1979.

Card, Orson Scott.  Ender's Game.  Tor Books, USA, 1985.

Card, Orson Scott.  Speaker for the Dead.  Tor Books, USA, 1986.

Card, Orson Scott.  Xenocide.  Tor Books, USA, 1991.