the true scholar (2000)

7
The True Scholar Author(s): Robert N. Bellah Source: Academe, Vol. 86, No. 1 (Jan. - Feb., 2000), pp. 18-23 Published by: American Association of University Professors Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40252331 Accessed: 05/10/2010 14:30 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aaup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Association of University Professors is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Academe. http://www.jstor.org

Upload: miodrag-mijatovic

Post on 23-Jan-2016

19 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Robert N. Bellah

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: The True Scholar (2000)

The True ScholarAuthor(s): Robert N. BellahSource: Academe, Vol. 86, No. 1 (Jan. - Feb., 2000), pp. 18-23Published by: American Association of University ProfessorsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40252331Accessed: 05/10/2010 14:30

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unlessyou have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aaup.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

American Association of University Professors is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extendaccess to Academe.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: The True Scholar (2000)

The True Scholar

In the Age of Money, self-interest dominates the academy. But it may not explain how

the world works. Perhaps it's time to reconnect

scholarship to morality.

By Robert N. Bellah

"THE TRUE SCHOLAR" AS A TITLE MAY sound rather quaint in modern academic dis- course. Yet on occasion, and perhaps unreflect-

ingly, we still use the expression. When we say of someone that he or she is a true scholar, or a true scientist, we mean not only that he or she

is knowledgeable or skillful, though we do mean that, but that the person has a character, or a stance toward the world, that is clearly normative or ethical, not merely cognitive. In our common use, then, though not in our reigning philosophies, the true and the good are not two different things, but aspects of one thing. This essay is an effort to make that commonsense

perception more conscious and defensible in the argument about what scholarship in its multiple meanings, including teaching, is all about.

Let me turn to that cantankerous but

highly intelligent philosopher, Alasdair Mac-

Intyre, to open my argument. In 1991 in

Robert Bellah is Elliott Professor of Sociology emeri-

tus at the University of California, Berkeley, and

coauthor of Habits of the Heart (1985) andThe

Good Society (1992).

"The Mission of a Dominican House of Studies in Contempo- rary North America," an unpublished manuscript, he wrote:

What contemporary universities have characteristically lost, both in their practice and in their theorizing, is an adequate grasp of the relationship between the intellectual and the moral virtues. . . . For while the university thinks of itself as a

place of enquiry, it happily rejects the thought that such en-

quiry should be envisaged as having any one overall telos or

good and that that good might itself be adequately intelligi- ble only as an ordered part of the human good. What goods enquiry is to serve and how they are to be envisaged is instead to depend upon the choices and preferences of the

enquirers and of those who supply their material resources. For academic freedom on a liberal view of it requires that rival beliefs about the human good, including denials that there is such a good, should be encouraged to coexist in a

university which is itself to be uncommitted. What enquiry needs from those who practice it is not moral character, but

verbal, mathematical and problem-solving skills. A few quali- ties of character are of course highly valued: industriousness, a show of deference to one's professional superiors and to the academic system, cheerful collegiality, and sufficient

l8 ACADEME January-February 2000

Page 3: The True Scholar (2000)

1

< <

ACADEME January-February 2000 19

Page 4: The True Scholar (2000)

minimal honesty to ensure reliability in reporting research

findings. For these are qualities of character functionally necessary, if skills are to be successfully put to work. But there is no overall end to be served by those qualities or those skills, no agreed or presupposed ultimate good in view. What is the outcome?

It is fragmentation, so that by and large what goes on in one area of enquiry has little or no connection with what

goes on in other areas.

The fragmentation that Maclntyre accurately points out is

perhaps the result not so much of the lack of a notion of the human good as of the presence of an idea of the human good that is left undiscussed. I will return to this matter.

Pure Reason Versus Ethics

A MAJOR SOURCE OF OUR PROBLEM IS THE IRON CURTAIN drawn by Immanuel Kant between the cognitive and the ethical, between, in his terms, pure reason and practical reason. Accord-

ing to Kant, an unbridgeable gap separates the two realms. We cannot get to one from the other, but each requires a beginning from scratch on its own terms. As a result, our modern quasi- Kantian university has decided to commit itself to cognitive in-

quiry and to push ethical inquiry to the margins as a subfield in

philosophy or something the professional schools can worry about. The quasi-Kantian university actually carries a much more substantive ethical message than it admits to, but before

going into that, I want to explore alternative possibilities. While for Plato the Good, the True, and the Beautiful had an

ultimate unity, Aristotle saw a clear distinction between the in- tellectual and the moral virtues. And it was Aristotle more than Plato who influenced the subsequent tradition in the West. So,

long before Kant, we had a problem with how the two sets of virtues were to be related. But Aristotle, unlike Kant, perceived a

relationship. While from one point of view wisdom, sophia, was the highest virtue, from another point of view the governing virtue was phronesis, inadequately translated as prudence or prac- tical reason. Let me interpret phronesis as judgment, remember-

ing that this is judgment only in an elevated sense of the term. One could say, pushing Aristotle just a bit, that judgment is the most intellectual of the practical virtues and the most practical of the intellectual virtues. In other words, it is the place they come

together. Judgment in this use of the term involves a sense of

proportion, of larger meaning, of what a situation requires, at once cognitively and ethically.

When we say that an action or a person is "truly human" we are

using phronesis, judgment. We mean simultaneously that this ac- tion or this person is such as humans can be and such as they ought to be. Similarly, when we call something inhuman, like eth- nic cleansing, we are saying that it falls below not only the level of what humans ought to do, but what we expect them to do.

We use judgment in this sense all the time and not only in the humanities and the social sciences; we could not conduct the

scholarly enterprise without it. Thus we rely not only, as Mac-

lntyre claimed, on the "functional virtues" supportive of a lim- ited view of scholarship, but also on judgment, which, as I am

using it, is one of the highest virtues. But Maclntyre's criticism

is correct insofar as we do not take

responsibility for what we are doing. We claim devotion to pure cognitive inquiry without any other intent, and we argue that the only norma- tive basis for our inquiry is freedom; we do not take conscious responsibil- ity for the fact that freedom without

judgment would lead to self- destruction.

No Higher Purpose IN THREE RIVAL VERSIONS OF Moral Enquiry, Maclntyre describes three notions of what the university is today. Adapting his terminology, I will call these notions traditional,

positivist, and postmodernist. The traditional is of course where we came from: the tradition of liberal education with its strong ties to the classics and, in America, to theology. Beginning in the last decades of the nineteenth century, the traditional was gradually displaced by the posi- tivist model of untrammeled inquiry, which embraces subjects never in- cluded in the older curriculum and throws off the narrow conception of what a classical and Christian educa- tion ought to be. But it also, in part inadvertently, dismisses any defensi- ble notion of phronesis or judgment that might have held the enterprise together in the face of positivism's penchant for fragmentation. Quite recently, postmodernism has arisen

partly as a criticism of what its pro- ponents see as the false cognitive neutrality of the positivist university. Postmodernists have argued, not without evidence, that the university

exists only to support existing structures of power, particularly in the areas of class, race, and gender. But postmodernism rejects tradition just as readily as it discounts positivism, perceiving tra- dition as yet another form of power play. In so doing, it fails to

bring back any notion of judgment as a governing virtue. In- deed, it rejects the idea of a governing virtue altogether.

But changes in the university, and therefore in scholarship, over the last hundred years have not come about only because of altered intellectual understandings. Changes in the relationship between the university and society have also played a part. The

university has never been a place devoted solely to the formation of character or to pure inquiry. The university has always been an avenue of social mobility. One's life chances are enhanced by attaining a university degree - about that plenty of empirical evi- dence exists as far back as one can go.

Our

modern

quasi- Kantian

university has

decided to

commit

itself to

cognitive

inquiry and to

push ethical

inquiry to the

margins.

2O ACADEME January-February 2000

Page 5: The True Scholar (2000)

Mobility aspirations have long placed pressures on universi-

ties, but for much of that time, they were gentle pressures. By and large, the university's authority to tell upwardly mobile

young men, and later young women, what they needed to know was not basically challenged. And the liberal arts, as a central core of the curriculum, continued to draw students even after the positivist model of the university had gained dominance. But in recent decades, students have begun more and more to tell us what they want to know. The fact that a much higher percentage of the population goes to college accounts for part of this

change, as do shifts in our culture. But the phenomenon has drastic consequences for the curriculum, hiring, and scholarship, which I will describe in a moment. In a world of consumers, consumer students now make the decisions, for better or for worse, that were once made by faculty.

But consumer students are not the only pressures that univer- sities have faced. Universities, and so scholarship, have been seen as serving external purposes, above all those of the state and the economy. By far the most influential outside purpose deriving from the state has been the pressure to contribute to war efforts. The university was mobi- lized, if briefly, during World War I; more totally during World War II; and even more thoroughly dur-

ing the long twilight period of the Cold War lasting until just about a decade ago. Universities grew accustomed to large government research grants, not only in the natural sciences, but in the hu- manities and the social sciences as well for fields such as area studies. Since the end of the Cold War, the most important external pur- pose the university is supposed to serve has been the economy, though economic usefulness has been a university purpose to some

degree at least since the founding of land-grant colleges in the nine- teenth century. I wrote of these

pressures in the January-February 1999 issue of Academe \ so I won't elaborate further here.

Age of Money IT MIGHT BE HELPFUL TO LOOK at evidence of changes in the uni-

versity relative to my theme,

namely, that the true scholar re-

quires a true university, or at least

something like one. I have sug- gested that the very notion of a true university depends on the sur- vival of what Maclntyre means by traditional inquiry: inquiry in

Universities, and so

scholarship, have

been

seen as

serving external

purposes, above all

those

of the

state and

the

economy.

which the link between the intellectual and the moral virtues is not entirely broken, in which something like judgment has at least a degree of influence. In the current understanding of the

university, the humanities, even though they are at the moment rent by civil war, are closest to this understanding.

In the May-June 1998 issue oi Harvard Magazine, James Engell and Anthony Dangerfield published a survey of trends in the humanities titled "The Market-Model University: Humani- ties in the Age of Money." Here are some of the most important findings:

• The humanities represent a sharply declining proportion of all undergraduate degrees.

• Between 1970 and 1994, the number of B.A.'s conferred in the United States rose 39 percent.

• Among all bachelor's degrees in higher education, three

majors increased five- to tenfold: computer and informa- tion sciences, protective services, and transportation and material moving.

• Two majors, already large, tripled: the health professions and public administration.

• Business administration, already popular, doubled. • English, foreign languages, philosophy, religion, and his-

tory all suffered absolute declines.

In addition, the authors point out that

Measured by faculty salaries - a clear sign of prestige and clout - the humanities fare dismally. On average, humanists receive the lowest faculty salaries by thousands or tens of thousands of dollars; the gap affects the whole teaching pop- ulation, regardless of rank.

Humanists' teaching loads are highest, with the least amount of release and research time, yet they're now ex-

pected, far more than three decades ago, to publish in order to secure professorial posts.

Humanists are also, more than others, increasingly com- pelled to settle for adjunct, part-time, nontenured appoint- ments that pay less, have little or no job security, and carry reduced benefits or none.

There's even more, but I don't want to be too depressing. Per- haps these trends cannot be found everywhere, but the article cites my own alma mater. It shows that the trends have occurred at Harvard. It would seem that few schools have entirely escaped them.

Having observed that "the humanities' vital signs are poor," the authors seek an explanation and find it in what they call the Age of Money:

When we termed the last thirty years the Age of Money, we were in part referring to the dollar influx of research grants, higher tuitions, and grander capital improvements. But there's another, more symbolic, aspect to the Age of Money, and one not less powerful for being more symbolic. The mere concept of money turns out to be the secret key to

"prestige," influence, and power in the American academic world.

ACADEME January-February 2000 21

Page 6: The True Scholar (2000)

They argue that there are "Three Criteria for the power of

money in academia, whose rule is remarkably potent, uniform, and verifiable. Academic fields that offer one (or more) of the Three Criteria thrive; any field lacking all three languishes."

In the Age of Money, they continue, the royal road to success is to offer at least one of the following:

• A Promise of Money. The field is popularly linked (even if

erroneously) to improved chances of securing an occupa- tion or profession that promises above-average lifetime

earnings. • A Knowledge of Money. The field itself studies money,

whether practically or more theoretically, i.e., fiscal, busi- ness, financial, or economic matters and markets.

• A Source of Money. The field receives significant external

money, i.e., research contracts, federal grants or funding support, or corporate underwriting.

If this picture of the contemporary university is accurate, and it would be hard to argue that it does not contain at least some

truth, then our life together in the university is governed by nei- ther the intellectual nor the moral virtues but by a vice, namely, cupidity, acquisitiveness, or just plain avarice, the same vice that dominates our society as a whole in the Age of Money. To the extent that this is true (and I do not believe it is the whole

truth), it has come about more through default than by inten- tion: it is the result of many small decisions made by administra- tors and faculty concerned to keep their institutions afloat in a

changing society. Yet insofar as we are dominated by one of the classic vices rather than the intellectual and moral virtues, we have ceased to be a true university, which makes it increasingly difficult for us to be true scholars.

Rational Choice Theory IN AMERICA, AND TO SOME DEGREE THROUGHOUT THE

world, we seem to have returned in the past thirty years to some-

thing from the last decades of the nineteenth century, that is, unconstrained laissez-faire capitalism. And just as the theory of social Darwinism mirrored the strident capitalism of the late nineteenth century, so the rise of rational choice theory reflects the emergence of neo-laissez-faire capitalism in the last thirty years. Rational choice theory is more subtle, more technically sophisticated than social Darwinism, but it is still an offspring of the same lineage, one that ultimately goes back to utilitarianism, the commonsense philosophy of the Anglo-American world since at least the eighteenth century. (Rational choice theory as- sumes that social life can be explained principally as the outcome of the rational choices of individual actors, who typically base their actions on what they perceive to be the most effective means to their goals.)

Rational choice theory is now taken as a given in economics and has spread out into many neighboring disciplines: political science, sociology, law, even religious studies. If the theory is

true, we need to admit not only that acquisitiveness is the funda- mental human motive, but also that, as it was put in the 1980s,

"greed is good." And we must also concede that we were mis- taken all these years, in all the religions and philosophies of

Insofar as

we are

dominated

by one

of the

classic

vices

rather

than the

intellectual

and moral

virtues, we have

ceased to

be

a true

university.

mankind, in. thinking cupidity a vice instead of our chief virtue. We are

only beginning to see the full impli- cations of such thinking in our soci-

ety and our universities today. Yet a powerful argument can be

mounted against rational choice the-

ory as an adequate explanation of the human condition, one that gives us

hope that all is not lost in the de- fense of the intellectual and moral virtues. Let me briefly outline the

history of rational choice theory, based on the as-yet-unpublished work of S. M. Amadae, who has

completed a brilliant and illuminat-

ing dissertation on its history titled "Rational Choice Theory in Eco-

nomic, Political, and Policy Science, 1944_1975: A New Chapter in Eco- nomic and Political Liberalism."

Surprisingly, Amadae's is the first at-

tempt to write a history of this influ- ential movement.

Do you know the institution pri- marily responsible for the emergence of rational choice theory after World War II? The Rand Corporation.

Rand began in 1946 with an initial infusion of $10 million from the

Army Air Force. It was meant to maintain the collaboration of scien-

tists, scholars, and the military after the end of World War II in a quasi- governmental, quasi-private institu- tion. In the 1950s the corporation be- came closely associated with the Ford Foundation and engaged with - that

is, employed, gave short-term fellow-

ships to, or consulted with - virtually every major contributor, in no matter what field, to the emergence of ratio- nal choice theory. To quote Amadae

directly: "Locating the development of the conceptual apparatus for rational choice theory within the national security environment counters a basic myth frequently perpetuated about the origin of rational choice theory."

The myth, she says, has two parts: (1) that the idea of the ra- tional actor in the rational choice sense was always at the heart of

economics, and (2) that rational choice theory involves the ex-

port of economic models to other disciplines. The recognition of the importance of Rand, however, allows for a correct under-

standing. Amadae writes:

This lineage [that is, the origin of rational choice theory in

Rand] reveals two crucial facts which are otherwise hope- lessly obscured. The conceptual framework for rational choice theory was developed to solve strategic, military

22 ACADEME January-February 2000

Page 7: The True Scholar (2000)

problems and not problems of economic modeling. Fur-

thermore, this idea set was developed to inform policy deci-

sions, not merely retrospectively to analyze behavior as the social sciences often claim of their own methodology. . . . The theory of rational action had interlocking descriptive, normative, and prescriptive components, and was devel-

oped to inform action re-

specting nuclear strategy and complex questions of

weapons procurement.

Indeed, the first real classic on rational choice theory in econom- ics was Kenneth Arrow's Social Choice and Individual Values, pub- lished in 1951 but written mostly in 1948, when Arrow was at Rand, where he had been, according to

Amadae, "assigned the task of de-

riving a single mathematical func- tion which would predict the col- lective political outcomes for the entire Soviet Union."

I don't dispute that rational choice theory had, by the 1980s, become central in economics, nor that it has had an enormous influence in recent years, particu- larly through the University of

Chicago's economics department, on many other fields, including my own. But I want to set the record straight on the origin of ra- tional choice theory by showing that it did not originate in disin- terested theorizing in some univer-

sity ivory tower. Instead, it

emerged from the very practically oriented Rand Corporation and had, in that context, "interlocking descriptive, normative, and pre- scriptive components," to use Amadae's words. Probably the sin-

gle most important theoretical source of rational choice theory was Von Neumann and Mor-

genstern's Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, published in 1944. Mainstream economists re-

garded the book as unimportant until they finally absorbed Arrow's work.

Fatal Flaw

WHATEVER ONE THINKS OF

game theory, rational choice the-

ory as developed at Rand was pre-

If we

believe

that the

struggle for

strategic

advantage is the

truth about

human

beings, then

we should

realize

that we are

not just

teaching a

scientific

truth;

we are

preaching a

gospel.

scriptive, and it did indeed determine action. Its first great em-

pirical test came when one of its primary devotees, Robert Mc- Namara, who was not a professor but a president of the Ford Motor Company and then secretary of defense, had a chance to use it as the basis for decision making in the Vietnam War. (I won't develop the chain that links McNamara to Rand, but it is a tight one.) I think it is safe to say that McNamara's Vietnam test was not a success. And the reason was that the North Viet- namese would not behave as rational actors are supposed to be- have, because they had absolute value commitments, or ideologi- cal zealotry, or whatever you want to call it, which simply was not explicable in rational-actor terms.

I want to suggest two things from this example. One is that rational choice theory is wrong not because much human action cannot be explained in such terms - much human action can in- deed be explained in rational-actor terms - but because all human action cannot be explained in such terms. For a theory that claims to be total, the existence of exceptions is fatal. They are particularly so when the decisions the theory cannot explain turn out not to be minor cases of unexplained variance, but deci- sions critical to the understanding of human action.

Today, rational choice theory, born in the intense engage- ment of the Cold War as a tool for the prosecution of that war, is now ensconced in the university and taught to students as scientific truth. When Gary Becker writes A Treatise on the

Family to show that choices about marriage and family stem from each individual's maximizing his or her competitive, strategic self-interest, is that a treatise about the True or the Good? Or, indeed, is it about virtue or vice? Is there any way of teaching that book as though it had no practical intent? Even a student who says, "Well, I'm not really like that," will conclude that "if other people are, then I had better behave in

strategic terms or I will be taken advantage of." Let me conclude by recounting an exchange I had with one

of my ablest recent students. He wrote, quoting a well-known French sociologist, that all human action is motivated by a

competitive struggle to increase some form of capital. I said to him, "Is that true of you? Are you just out to increase your cap- ital? How could I ever trust you if that were true?" I don't say he was instantly converted, but my reaction had a sobering ef- fect on him. He responded, "I never thought of applying this

theory to myself." Well, theories do apply to ourselves, and they have tests that

are both empirical and ethical. Often, it is impossible to tell where the cognitive leaves off and the ethical begins. Scholars live in the world, and the world we live in right now is domi- nated by money. If we believe that the struggle for strategic ad-

vantage is the truth about human beings, then we should real- ize that we are not just teaching a scientific truth; we are

preaching a gospel. We have done that before in our intellec- tual history, and we decided that it was wrong. But a lot of

things that we thought had gone away have returned in recent

years. So if we don't think that the struggle for strategic advan-

tage is the whole truth about human beings, then in our schol-

arship and our teaching we should begin consciously to accept that our work is governed by the virtue of judgment, at least in

aspiration. That alone would be an enormous contribution in our present situation. &

ACADEME January-February 2000 23