theoretical limitations of consumer policy - practical implications by siya biniza

Upload: siya-biniza

Post on 14-Oct-2015

23 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Theories of consumer behaviour and consumption are key aspects of neoclassical economics. Yet, consumer theory present a very limited understanding of the consumer and the consumed which rests on specific assumptions and an aggregation of consumption across all consumers and goods/services. This is a discussion of some of these limitations and the implications for consumer policy.Therefore, the paper argues that consumers consume for other reasons besides the price of the good, let alone the utility associated with the good. The fact that this does not feature in the logic of consumer policy, which focuses on increasing consumer surplus by offering information about the product, shows the limitation of the narrow neoclassical understanding of consumption as being purely dependent on consistency between preferences and utility – with prices being a quazi measure of utility through the mechanisms of consumer surplus.Thus, consumer policy needs to redress the limitations associated with the neoclassical consumer theory due to these implications. What is needed is a broader understanding of consumption as well as what is consumer, which the neoclassical consumer theory does not allow for due to its very restrictive assumption and universalistic application. Therefore, in order for consumer policy to be more effective, consumer policy needs to refrain from universalistic applications such as the use of the price mechanism in relation to consumer surplus. The specificities of consumption and what is being consumer mean that consumer surplus is unevenly distributed through complex contradictory logics of what is the strongest consideration being made when consuming different products.

TRANSCRIPT

  • Theoretical Limitations of Consumer Policy: Practical Implications Written by Siyaduma Biniza 1

    Neoclassical consumer theory is at the base of consumer policy. Consumer policy is

    the set of policies devised to protect consumers against adverse results from their

    choices in the market. So the idea is that consumers make decisions about what

    goods to consume based a set of options however, there are various challenges in

    exchange which either disadvantage the consumer thereby diminishing consumer

    surplus or there are various market conditions which lead to the same thing. The

    challenges in exchange pertain to conditions that undermine to the neoclassical

    assumption of complete information; the inimical meanwhile market conditions

    relate to the concentration of firms and its implication of raising the price of goods

    thereby diminishing consumer surplus.

    Consumer or producer surplus are the added benefits to consuming or supplying

    goods, this is a notion based on the reserve price of the consumer or producer in

    relation to the market. So the idea is that consumers enjoy a surplus when the

    price of the goods they consumer is much lower than they reservation price which

    is the price the consumer is willing to pay for a product. An example of this is a

    price discount which increases the benefit accrued to the consumer based on this

    principle of surplus being the difference between the market price and the

    consumers reserve. Obviously the market will not always be above the consumers

    reservation price but the logic is that as the market price decreases in relation to

    the reservation price, consumers gain more surplus. Similarly, suppliers realise

    their surplus when the price of their goods is much higher than their reservation

    selling price. So the idea is that when the producer increase, all thing equal, they

    will realise more producer surplus. The idea of surplus is based on the neoclassical

    consumer theory.

    Consumer theory defines all consumers as having the same behaviour yet facing

    different sets of constraints while acting in the same way. Contemporary

    neoclassical economics is a result of the Marginalist Revolution which mainly

    sought to make economics a science. Consumer theory is underpinned by three

    axioms: completeness, reflexivity and transitivity which define consumer

    behaviour. These axioms define preferences and the logic of consumer theory

    regarding consumption and how we make choices generally. This can be expressed

    as ( ) ( ) iff ( ) ( ); which captures a unidirectional

    1 Corporate Strategy and Industrial Development Research Programme, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, South Africa and masters fellow at the Public Affairs Research Institute and Economic Research Southern Africa.

    [email protected] | [email protected] Scribd | Linkedin

  • causality of preferences making them determined by utility (Varian, 2010). The

    definition of utility is very specific but unclear in consumer theory. Utility is

    something gained through consumption and represents some measure of the

    satisfaction gained from consuming goods, but it is unclear whether utility gained

    is determined by ones preferences or whether ones preference are based on

    utility. Nonetheless utility can be considered as a criterion for choice, such that

    individuals only choose to consumer goods that have the highest utility given the

    options available to them (Fine, 2010). Therefore the axioms constitute the idea

    that consumer preferences are logically consistent with the utility gains embodied

    by consumption bundles; such that the consumer strictly prefers a particular

    consumption if, and only if, that bundle has higher utility gains.

    Completeness is the axiom that choices require a comparison of the available

    options (Varian, 2010). So completeness requires that we are able to compare any

    two bundles of goods in order to define preferences. This simply means that an

    individuals preferences for any two goods, or bundles of goods, are based on a

    comparison of the bundles. For example an individuals preference, between two

    bundles of goods, say 6 apples and 3 pairs of jeans (bundle A) as opposed to 12

    apples and 6 pairs of jean (bundle B), are only complete if these bundles can be

    compared using an ordinal or cardinal scale. A cardinal scale means that an

    individuals preferences can be quantitatively expressed based on a comparison of

    the optional bundles. So for argument sake, using a cardinal scale, we could say

    the consumer prefers bundle A twice as much as bundle B. In contrast, we can

    qualitatively compare bundle A and B using an ordinal scale for example John

    prefers bundle A over bundle B. But this axiom does not require strict preference

    but also allows weak preference and indifference. Weak preference is the idea

    that, even though the individual prefers bundle A over bundle B, the preferred

    bundle is at least as good as the less preferred bundle, i.e. .

    Thus given that all bundles of goods are either distinct or identical, the consumers

    preferences will only be complete if we can compare the consumption bundles.

    This axiom is plausible since a requirement of choice is that we need to be able to

    make a comparison of the options available to us (Gendin, 1996). But since this

    axiom is applied to all consumption (choice); it requires an objective or common

    way of comparing consumption bundles (options). If our comparison was based on a

    context-specific criterion completeness would not always hold and there would be

    instances when our preferences are associated with incomparable consumption

    bundles. However, it is possible to object this and assert that consumption is often

    based on incomparable consumption bundles as is captured by the maxim of

    comparing apples and oranges. Nevertheless it is permissible that our preferences

    are based on some comparison of the consumption bundles or choices we have.

    Completeness requires that consumption bundles be comparable based on their

    associated utility. The implication of this is that the object of preferences is only

  • the utility of consuming a specific consumption bundle; and that consumption

    bundles are intrinsically characterised by their utility only. In other words our

    preferences are only related to the utility associated with the goods consumed;

    such that we cannot have preferences which reflect a comparison of physical or

    abstract qualities of a consumption bundle. Also consumption, or choices, are only

    characterised by the utility associated with the consumption bundle. So, even

    though we can differentiate bundles according to the combination of goods that

    form that bundle, the only important distinguishing factor of each consumption

    bundle is the utility gained from it (Fine, 2010). However, the utility is determined

    by our preferences, which makes consumer theory a solely preference-based, or

    utility-based, theory of choice.

    In this regard it is assumed that all the options are fully known by the consumer.

    This brings us to consumer policy and competition policy which partly intend to

    make increase the choices that individuals know by avoiding market imperfections

    such as asymmetric information, non-existence of markets and incomplete

    markets. Consumer policy tries to deal with issues of coercion of consumers,

    asymmetry of information which result in adverse choices by consumers and any

    disgruntlement that occurs after the purchase (Vickers, 2003). In South Africa, this

    is body of policies is referred to as the Consumer Protection Act. Competition

    policy on the other hand is broader and aimed a different set of objectives such as

    fostering a competitive market economy, promoting international competitiveness,

    industrial development and economic growth (Black & Roberts, 2008). Initially

    competition policy in South Africa was aimed at regulating the size of firms and

    prohibit collusive behaviour which results in higher prices, such as the case of

    collusion by bread producers in 2007 (Black & Roberts, 2008). But competition

    policy has evolved to stretch beyond just prohibiting monopolistic by firms.

    Therefore, competition policy can be understood as dealing with the market

    conditions that diminish consumer behaviour, whilst consumer policy deals with

    challenges in exchange

    However consumer policy is based on the neoclassic consumer theory which does

    not differentiate between products, goods, services, career decision etc. (Fine,

    2010). This is the first limitation of consumer policy because of this limited

    understanding of the consumed it cannot adequately deal with the nuanced

    different information or market failures that pertain to specific products. So for

    instance applying for loan is considered to be given by the same consumption laws

    as consuming a meal for lunch. However, different products face different sets of

    informational imperfects, different sets of market constraints and other challenge

    which pertain to their consumption. For instance, although the specific

    characteristics might be clear upon physical inspection i.e. one can see the

    ingredients to their hotdog and could easily read the terms and condition of a loan

    before deciding to consume either of these goods. But are nuanced differences

    that could impact the experience of consumption before or after, for instance

  • even though terms might be clearly defined in the loan contract, certain prior

    knowledge limits the ability of the consumer to understand the implication of what

    is contained in the terms and conditions. This is less of a problem to someone

    consuming a hotdog.

    Secondly, the nature of axioms or assumptions of consumer theory also limit the

    efficacy of consumer policy. Firstly, completeness requires that the consumer have

    known and observable preferences. It is an acceptable requirement that choice

    requires individuals to compare their available options. But the assumption that

    this comparison is based solely on utility is qualitatively parsimonious and dubious

    as a definition of preferences and choice. Similarly the use of the price mechanism

    to determine the surplus which either accrues to consumers or producers is a

    narrow definition for comparing the desirability of choices. This overlooks

    alternative theories of consumption such as Veblens institutional approach to

    what he terms conspicuous consumption. Conspicuous consumption is the idea that

    certain institutions exist which undermine the logic of consumer surplus and utility

    associated with it such that the individual would gain more utility when the price

    of the good increases because this becomes a form of social differentiation with

    the consumer gaining benefit from the fact that very few consumers can afford the

    goods consumed. Therefore, although the preferences might be known to the

    consumer i.e. they prefer social differentiation they preferences might not

    always be observable if we accept that the logic of consumer surplus does not

    always coincide with the price mechanism. The case of conspicuous consumption

    undermines the pursuit of increase consumer surplus which is the object of

    consumer policy, and in fact a higher price would lead to higher utility according

    to the logic of conspicuous consumption.

    This highlights the fact that consumers consume for other reasons besides the price

    of the good, let alone the utility associated with the good. The fact that this does

    not feature in the logic of consumer policy, which focuses on increasing consumer

    surplus by offering information about the product, shows the limitation of the

    narrow neoclassical understanding of consumption as being purely dependent on

    consistency between preferences and utility with prices being a quazi measure of

    utility through the mechanisms of consumer surplus. This brings us to the

    limitations associated with transitivity and reflexivity.

    Consumer theory requires that preferences are only defined by the utility

    associated with each consumption bundle; such that we most prefer the bundle

    that yields the most utility. And consumption, which is symbolic of all our choices,

    is reduced to preferences based on the criterion of utility gains. This is explicitly

    supported by the reflexivity axiom, which states that a bundle, or single goods, is

    at least as good as itself. This means that identical bundles are at least equally

    preferred implying that goods have fixed utility or that our preferences are fixed.

    Therefore utility is an intrinsic and at least fixed endowment of every good (Fine,

  • 2010). Preferences are contextually fixed and the only thing changing is the

    consumption bundle and the utility associated with it. However, this cannot

    accommodate the issue of diminishing utility post-consumption.

    For instance, one might decide to take a loan now but due to changed life

    circumstances ends up regret the purchase because terms of the loan were met by

    personal life situation. For example a married couple might decide to take a home

    loan which they can bought afford because they are both employed. However the

    couples life might change when one partner is no longer employed or when the

    couple divorces. Then the consumers would not be able to afford their loan and

    thus face the typical challenges that the consumer policy tries to address post-

    exchange. Reflexivity requires that each bundle maintain its utility in such a way

    that the bundle offers at least the same utility as itself. But this is not the same in

    reality, because as my example shows the same loan with the same consumer

    offers very different utility based on alternative life factors which also influence

    the gains from consumption. As such, consumer policy can only deal with the

    changing nature of utility associated with goods in so far as the consumers

    preferences change and not due to other social factors. What my example is meant

    to show is that, even though consumers preferences might not change their utility

    from consumption changes due to other social considerations.

    This overlooks various other criteria for comparison between bundles of goods such

    as religion, political ideology or culture. For instance, even though a bundle might

    offer greater utility an individual might choose a bundle that offers lower utility do

    to their prescribed culture. For example, in a culture than criticises obesity, an

    individual might choose to eat less even though they would gain more utility from

    eating more simply because the dominant culture. In this example, it is plausible

    to argue that, culture is a characteristic that more strongly determines

    consumption choice than utility based on preferences. So it is dubious to assert

    that utility is the only criteria for comparison between consumption bundles.

    Nevertheless, neoclassical consumer theory requires that an individual be able to

    compare bundles of goods based utility which is derived by an individuals

    preferences. The use of utility as the only criterion of comparing preferences, and

    preference-based decision-making, is a dubious and parsimonious definition of

    consumption and individual choices. This is because consumption is complex and

    that the reasons for consuming a certain good or services cannot be reduced to the

    price level because consumers also other considerations in their decisions to

    consume. So consumer policy that deals with ensuring greater consumer surplus

    based on the neoclassical consumer theory cannot adequately deal with the needs

    of every consumer adequately.

    Moreover, even if we agree that utility is the only comparative criteria of choice,

    neoclassical consumer choice theory makes for a parsimonious definition of choice.

    This means that choice is only determined by preferences, which are only defined

  • by utility. In other words the individuals preferences, regardless of anything else,

    are the only considerations we make before choosing. The same parallels exist for

    consumer policy and the price-mechanisms as it relates to consumer surplus.

    Furthermore, this is a preference-based theory of choice and it doesnt leave room

    for any room for social, cultural, political or religious consideration. Physical or

    abstract properties of the options available do not have any place in neoclassical

    consumer theory. Therefore, although an individual might prefer something based

    on their religious views; neoclassical consumers does not allow for this because

    preferences are only defined through utility so choices are simply concerned with

    utility.

    It might be argued that these are trivial consideration that religious, cultural,

    racial or gender-specific factors which impact on consumption can be ignore in

    favour of more common assumptions about consumption. However, this misses the

    point of consumer policy, which is based on constitutional rights and values which

    seek to accommodate all religious beliefs, cultural associations, racial diversity

    and gender equity. Therefore the importance of these socio-political

    considerations is important to ensure complete consumer protection and delivering

    on consumer rights for all.

    Lastly, there is an assumption that a mixture of goods is universally more

    preferable to consumption of one sort of good. However, again this is impractical

    and does not take practical considerations about consumption into account. For

    example, Varian makes the argument that although he enjoyed both olives and ice-

    cream he would not prefer consuming both simultaneously as opposed to one type

    of good (Varian, 2010, p. 47). Consumer policy cannot differentiate according to

    which products are better consumed together and which are not. For example,

    consumer policy cannot suggest that consumers get debt counselling when they

    apply for a loan in order to prevent future challenges associated with post-

    consumption dissatisfaction even though this is a plausible recommendation.

    Therefore, consumer policy cannot bolster its effectiveness by bundling

    consumption of certain goods due to the undifferentiated nature of what is being

    consumed and the assumption that a combination of goods or services is preferred

    to the consumption of one good according to neoclassical consumer theory.

    Also there are issues of collective consumption such as in the case of public goods

    and services. In such cases information about goods would assist with issues

    related to their consumption. However, simply availing information about products

    without considering the impact of class or social formation would undermine the

    provision of consumer rights to all. For example, in the case of water services in

    Johannesburg it has been found that different classes do not have the same access

    to the state or public services (Bawa, 2011). Thus consumption and challenges that

    consumer policy seeks to resolve are also class, gender and race-related. The same

    is not always true privately consumed goods which require more than information

  • about prices or qualities of the goods. This is where advertising fills more or a role

    because it can link the social considerations during consumption with goods

    available on the market. However, in cases of non-existent or incomplete market

    simply sharing information about the goods would not resolve issues that closely

    tied to social class, racial and gender divisions in society.

    Thus, consumer policy needs to redress the limitations associated with the

    neoclassical consumer theory due to these implications. What is needed is a

    broader understanding of consumption as well as what is consumer, which the

    neoclassical consumer theory does not allow for due to its very restrictive

    assumption and universalistic application. Therefore, in order for consumer policy

    to be more effective, consumer policy needs to refrain from universalistic

    applications such as the use of the price mechanism in relation to consumer

    surplus. The specificities of consumption and what is being consumer mean that

    consumer surplus is unevenly distributed through complex contradictory logics of

    what is the strongest consideration being made when consuming different

    products.

  • Works Cited

    Abrams, P., 1988. Notes on the Difficulty of Studying the State. Journal of Historical

    Sociology, 1(1), pp. 58-89.

    Bawa, Z., 2011. Where is the State? How is the State? Accessing Water and the State in

    Mumbai and Johannesburg. Journal of Asian and African Studies, 46(5), p. 491503.

    Black, A. & Roberts, S., 2008. Chapter 8: The Evolution and Impact of Industrial and

    Competition Policies. In: s.l.:s.n., pp. 211-243.

    Fine, B., 2010. Consumers and Demand, s.l.: mimeo.

    Gendin, S., 1996. Why Preference is Not Transitive. The Philosophical Quarterly, 46(185),

    pp. 482-488.

    Varian, H. R., 2010. Chapter 3: Preferences. In: J. Repcheck, ed. Intermediate

    Microeconomics: A Modern Approach. 8th ed. New York & London: W. W. Norton &

    Company, pp. 34-52.

    Vickers, J., 2003. Economics for Consumer Policy. London, British Academy for Humanities

    and Social Science.