voting and social choice

37
Voting and social choice Looking at a problem from the designers point of view

Upload: ogden

Post on 23-Feb-2016

53 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Voting and social choice. Looking at a problem from the designers point of view. Voting over alternatives. voting rule (mechanism) determines winner based on votes. >. >. Can vote over other things too Where to go for dinner tonight, other joint plans, …. >. >. Voting (rank aggregation). - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Voting and social choice

Voting and social choice

Looking at a problem from the designers point of view

Page 2: Voting and social choice

Voting over alternatives

> >

> >

voting rule (mechanism)

determines winner based on votes

• Can vote over other things too– Where to go for dinner tonight, other joint plans, …

Page 3: Voting and social choice

Voting (rank aggregation)• Set of m candidates (aka. alternatives, outcomes)• n voters; each voter ranks all the candidates

– E.g., for set of candidates {a, b, c, d}, one possible vote is b > a > d > c– Submitted ranking is called a vote

• A voting rule takes as input a vector of votes (submitted by the voters), and as output produces either:– the winning candidate, or– an aggregate ranking of all candidates

• Can vote over just about anything– political representatives, award nominees, where to go for dinner

tonight, joint plans, allocations of tasks/resources, …– Also can consider other applications: e.g., aggregating search engine’s

rankings into a single ranking

Page 4: Voting and social choice

Example voting rules• Each voter gives a vector of ranked choices.• Scoring rules are defined by a vector (a1, a2, …, am); being

ranked ith in a vote gives the candidate ai points– Plurality is defined by (1, 0, 0, …, 0) (winner is candidate that is

ranked first most often, only first choice votes are counted)– Veto (or anti-plurality) is defined by (1, 1, …, 1, 0) (winner is candidate

that is ranked last the least often)– Borda is defined by (m-1, m-2, …, 0)

Page 5: Voting and social choice

Nanson (Borda variant)

• Candidate with the lowest Borda score is eliminated, then we re-compute Borda counts and continue.

Page 6: Voting and social choice

Runoff voting rulesproceeds in stages

• Plurality with (2-candidate) runoff: top two candidates in terms of plurality score proceed to runoff; whichever is ranked higher than the other by more voters, wins

How would you describe the idea behind a runoff?• Single Transferable Vote (STV, aka. Instant Runoff): candidate

with lowest plurality score drops out; if you voted for that candidate (as your first choice), your vote transfers to the next (live) candidate on your list; repeat until one candidate remains

• Similar runoffs can be defined for rules other than plurality

Page 7: Voting and social choice

Pairwise electionsselect pairwise comparison from complete list

> >

> >

>

> >

two votes prefer Obama to McCain

>

two votes prefer Obama to Nader

>

two votes prefer Nader to McCain

> >

Page 8: Voting and social choice

Pairwise electionsselect pairwise comparison from complete list

>

two votes prefer Obama to McCain

>

two votes prefer Obama to Nader

>

two votes prefer Nader to McCain

> >

2

2 2

May careabout numbers of voters or

only winner

Page 9: Voting and social choice

Pairwise elimination

• Candidates given a schedule of pairwise competitions

• Loser is eliminated at each stage.• Winner goes on to compete at next round• Like a single elimination athletic event (but

no parallel competitions)• Not every pair is considered

Page 10: Voting and social choice

Sensitivity to agenda setter: order of elimination matters

35 agents a > c > b33 agents b > a > c32 agents c > b > aWho is the winner in the following pairings?(a,b) c(a,c) b(b,c) a

Page 11: Voting and social choice

Condorcet• Condorcet winner of an election:

– A candidate who wins every pairwise election

• Condorcet methods are named for the eighteenth-century French mathematician and philosopher Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas Caritat, the Marquis de Condorcet (took their title from the town of Condorcet in Dauphine) Wikipedia Oct 2010

• Clearly, there may not be a Condorcet winner

• Condorcet condition: if there is a Condorcet winner, he must be the winner.

Page 12: Voting and social choice

Condorcet cycles

> >

> >

>

> >

two votes prefer McCain to Obama

>

two votes prefer Obama to Nader

>

two votes prefer Nader to McCain

?

Page 13: Voting and social choice

Condorcet cycles

>

two votes prefer McCain to Obama

>

two votes prefer Obama to Nader

>

two votes prefer Nader to McCain

?

2

22

Page 14: Voting and social choice

Condorcet cycles 500 voters

>

251 votes prefer McCain to Obama

>

400 votes prefer Obama to Nader

>

330 votes prefer Nader to McCain

?

251

330400

Number of voters who areunhappy with ranking or number of winning arcs who are unhappy

Page 15: Voting and social choice

• Preference profile: a tuple giving a preference ordering for each agent

• #(o>o’) is the number of agents who prefer o to o’• Smith set: is the smallest set S O having the

property that o’ S, #(o> o’) #(o’>o) In other words, every outcome in the Smith set is

preferred (by at least half of the agents) to every outcome outside the set.

Page 16: Voting and social choice

What is the Smith set?

35 agents a > c> b >d33 agents b > a > d > c32 agents c >d > b > a

What is the relationship between Smith set and Condorcet?

a

d

b

c

65 (35)

67(33)

68(32)

67(33)

68(32)

68 (32)

Page 17: Voting and social choice

Cumulative voting: Each voter is given k votes which can be cast arbitrarily (voting for any set of candidates he wants). The candidate with the most votes is selected.

Approval voting: Each voter can cast a single vote for as many of the candidates as he wishes; the candidate with the most votes is selected.

Page 18: Voting and social choice

Copeland: candidate gets two points for each pairwise election it wins, one point for each pairwise election it tiesSecond order Copeland: sum of Copeland scores of alternatives you defeat. (once used by NFL as tie-breaker)

35 agents c > a> b >d33 agents b > a > d > c32 agents c >d > b > a

What is Copeland Score?What is second order

Copeland Score?

a

d

b

c

65 (35)

67(33)

68(32)

67(33)

67(33)

68 (32)

Voting rule based on pairwise elections

Page 19: Voting and social choice

Another voting rule based on pairwise elections

• Maximin (aka. Simpson): candidate whose worst pairwise result is the best among candidates – wins. So if there are four candidates and 10 voters and between pairs (me,opponent): (9,1), (10,0), (8,2), and (5,5). If others had a worse pairwise vote than (5,5), I would be the winner.

Page 20: Voting and social choice

• Slater: create an overall ranking of the candidates that is inconsistent with as few pairwise elections as possible– NP-hard! Consider all orders and count inconsistencies.

• An instance of the Slater problem can be represented by a “pairwise election” graph whose vertices are the candidates, and which has a directed edge from a to b if and only if a defeats b in their pairwise election. The goal, then, is to minimize the number of edges that must be flipped in order to make the graph acyclic.

• Cup/pairwise elimination: pair candidates, losers of pairwise elections drop out, repeat

Page 21: Voting and social choice

Slater on pairwise election graphs• Final ranking = acyclic tournament graph• Slater ranking seeks to minimize the number

of inverted edges

a b

d c

a b

d c

pairwise election graph Slater ranking

(a > b > d > c)What about b >d>c>a?

Page 22: Voting and social choice

Even more voting rules…• Kemeny: create an overall ranking of the candidates that has

as few disagreements as possible (where a disagreement is with a vote on a pair of candidates). For each pair of voters (X,Y) count how many times X is preferred to Y. Test all possible order-of-preference sequences, calculate a sequence score for each sequence, and compare the scores. Each sequence score equals the sum of the pairwise counts

that are “honored by” the sequence (a is preferred to b and a precedes b in the sequence). The sequence with the highest score is identified as the overall ranking

– NP-hard!– Similar to Slater – but looks at actual numbers of votes not just result

of pairing.• Bucklin: start with k=1 and increase k gradually until some

candidate is among the top k candidates in more than half the votes; that candidate wins

Page 23: Voting and social choice

Kemeny on pairwise election graphs• Final ranking = acyclic tournament graph

– Edge (a, b) means a ranked above b– Acyclic = no cycles, tournament = edge between every

pair• Kemeny ranking seeks to minimize the total weight

of the inverted edges

a b

d c

2

210

4

42

pairwise election graph Kemeny ranking

a b

d c

2

2

(b > d > c > a)

Page 24: Voting and social choice

So…

• SO… how do we choose a rule from all of these rules?• How do we know that there does not exist another, “perfect”

rule?• Let us look at some criteria that we would like our voting rule

to satisfy

Page 25: Voting and social choice

Condorcet criterion• A candidate is the Condorcet winner if it wins all of its

pairwise elections• Does not always exist…• … but the Condorcet criterion says that if it does exist, it

should win

• Many rules do not satisfy this simple criterion• Consider plurality voting:

– b > a > c > d– c > a > b > d– d > a > b > c

• a is the Condorcet winner, but it does not win under plurality. Explain

Page 26: Voting and social choice

Majority criterion• If a candidate is ranked first by majority of votes that

candidate should win– Relationship to Condorcet criterion?

a > b > c > d > ee > a > b > c > dc > b > d > a > e

• Some rules do not even satisfy this• E.g. Borda:

– a > b > c > d > e– a > b > c > d > e– c > b > d > e > a

• a is the majority winner, but it does not win under Borda (b wins under Borda, right?)

Page 27: Voting and social choice

Monotonicity criteria• Informally, monotonicity means that “ranking a candidate

higher should help that candidate,” but there are multiple nonequivalent definitions

Page 28: Voting and social choice

Monotonicity criteria• A weak monotonicity requirement: if

– candidate w wins given the current votes, – we then improve the position of w in some of the votes and leave

everything else the same,then w should still win.

• E.g., Single Transferable Voting does not satisfy this:– 7 votes b > c > a– 7 votes a > b > c– 6 votes c > a > b

• c drops out first (lowest plurality), its votes transfer to a (next candidate), a wins

• **But if 2 votes b > c > a change to a > b > c (we improve a’s ranking), b drops out first, its 5 votes transfer to c, and c wins– 5 votes b > c > a– 9 votes a > b > c– 6 votes c > a > b

Page 29: Voting and social choice

Monotonicity criteria…• A strong monotonicity requirement: if

– candidate w wins for the current votes, – we then change the votes in such a way that for each vote, if

candidate c was ranked below w originally, c is still ranked below w in the new vote

then w should still win.• Note the other candidates can jump around in the vote, as

long as they don’t jump ahead of w• None of our rules satisfy this

Page 30: Voting and social choice

Independence of irrelevant alternatives• Independence of irrelevant alternatives criterion: if

– the rule ranks a above b for the current votes,– we then change the votes but do not change which is

ahead between a and b in each votethen a should still be ranked ahead of b. (The other votes are irrelevant to the relationship between a and b.)

• None of our rules satisfy this

Page 31: Voting and social choice

Arrow’s impossibility theorem [1951]

• Suppose there are at least 3 candidates• Then there exists no rule that is

simultaneously:– Pareto efficient (if all votes rank a above b, then

the rule ranks a above b), Explain use of term– nondictatorial (there does not exist a voter such

that the rule simply always copies that voter’s ranking), and

– independent of irrelevant alternatives

Page 32: Voting and social choice

Weak Pareto efficient

• if there exist a pair of outcomes o1 and o2 such that i o1 >i o2 then C([>]) o2

In other words, we cannot select any outcome that is dominated by another alternative for all agents

Why is it called weak?

Page 33: Voting and social choice

Muller-Satterthwaite impossibility theorem [1977]

• Suppose there are at least 3 candidates• Then there exists no rule that simultaneously:

– satisfies unanimity (if all votes rank a first, then a should win),

– is nondictatorial (there does not exist a voter such that the rule simply always selects that voter’s first candidate as the winner), and

– is monotone (in the strong sense).

Page 34: Voting and social choice

• The Shoham Leyton-Brown text has proofs of the impossibility theorems.

• We won’t go over them – but interested readers should take a look.

Page 35: Voting and social choice

Manipulability• Sometimes, a voter is better off revealing her preferences

insincerely, aka. manipulating• E.g. plurality

– Suppose a voter prefers a > b > c– Also suppose she knows that the other votes are

• 2 voters b > c > a• 2 voters c > a > b

– Voting truthfully will lead to a tie between b and c– She would be better off voting e.g. b > a > c, guaranteeing b wins

• All our rules are (sometimes) manipulatable

Page 36: Voting and social choice

Single-peaked preferences• Suppose candidates are ordered on a line

a1 a2 a3 a4 a5

• Every voter prefers candidates that are closer to her most preferred candidate

• Let every voter report only her most preferred candidate (“peak”)

v1v2 v3v4v5

• Choose the median voter’s peak as the winner– This will also be the Condorcet winner

• Nonmanipulable! Impossibility results do not necessarily hold when the space of preferences is restricted.

Why would you guess this is true?

Page 37: Voting and social choice

Some computational issues in social choice• Sometimes computing the winner/aggregate ranking is hard

– E.g. for Kemeny and Slater rules this is NP-hard• For some rules (e.g., STV), computing a successful

manipulation is NP-hard– Manipulation being hard is a good thing … But would like something

stronger than NP-hardness– Also: work on the complexity of controlling the outcome of an election by

influencing the list of candidates/schedule of the Cup rule/etc.• Preference elicitation:

– We may not want to force each voter to rank all candidates;– Rather, we can selectively query voters for parts of their ranking,

according to some algorithm, to obtain a good aggregate outcome• Combinatorial alternative spaces:

– Suppose there are multiple interrelated issues that each need a decision– Exponentially sized alternative spaces

• Different models such as ranking webpages (pages “vote” on each other by linking)