what deficit? legitimacy and accountability of regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal ›...

22
Jan Biela, University of Lausanne/London School of Economics and Political Science What deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory Agencies Paper prepared for the 42 nd ECPR Joint Sessions, Salamanca, 10-15 April 2014. Workshop: Administrative Organization and the Welfare State: Wicked Issues and the Challenges of Accountability, Legitimacy and Coordination *** Work in progress. Please do not cite without author’s permission. *** Abstract The paper addresses the accountability and legitimacy of regulatory agencies (IRAs). IRAs’ relevance has risen substantially in the past decades, which has led to debates on their legitimacy and accountability. First, it is frequently claimed that democratic institutions have lost terrain vis- à-vis non-majoritarian institutions, due to resource restrictions and policy complexity. Second, literature detects a dilemma in so far, as accountability is seen as the primary mechanism to legitimize these agencies, but at the same time interferes with desired independence. This paper’s main contribution is a theoretical review of the concepts of legitimacy, independence, and accountability, arguing that both accountability and democratic institutions remain more important than conventionally expected. It then applies a regime approach to agency accountability, which make use not only of de jure accountability rights, but also of de facto powers of accountability fora. Finally, it outlines tentative empirical results on accountability regimes in Switzerland and Germany, which largely support theoretical premises. Even though the empirical analysis has to be developed further, it can be concluded that deficits of accountability (and hence, of agency legitimacy) are rather an empirical than a theoretical matter. Acknowledgements This work has been possible by the support of the Swiss National Science Foundation both within the National Centre for Competence in Research (NCCR) Challenges to Democracy in the 21st Century, and a Doc.Mobility scholarship, providing me with the opportunity to discuss my ideas with scholars from the Utrecht School of Governance, and the London School of Economics. I thank Mark Bovens, Kutsal Yesilkagit, and in particular Thomas Schillemans and Mark Thatcher for dealing with my topic in such depth.

Upload: others

Post on 25-Jun-2020

1 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

Jan Biela, University of Lausanne/London School of Economics and Political Science

What deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory Agencies

Paper prepared for the 42nd ECPR Joint Sessions, Salamanca, 10-15 April 2014. Workshop:

Administrative Organization and the Welfare State: Wicked Issues and the Challenges of

Accountability, Legitimacy and Coordination

*** Work in progress. Please do not cite without author’s permission. ***

Abstract

The paper addresses the accountability and legitimacy of regulatory agencies (IRAs). IRAs’relevance has risen substantially in the past decades, which has led to debates on their legitimacyand accountability. First, it is frequently claimed that democratic institutions have lost terrain vis-à-vis non-majoritarian institutions, due to resource restrictions and policy complexity. Second,literature detects a dilemma in so far, as accountability is seen as the primary mechanism tolegitimize these agencies, but at the same time interferes with desired independence. This paper’smain contribution is a theoretical review of the concepts of legitimacy, independence, andaccountability, arguing that both accountability and democratic institutions remain moreimportant than conventionally expected. It then applies a regime approach to agencyaccountability, which make use not only of de jure accountability rights, but also of de factopowers of accountability fora. Finally, it outlines tentative empirical results on accountabilityregimes in Switzerland and Germany, which largely support theoretical premises. Even thoughthe empirical analysis has to be developed further, it can be concluded that deficits ofaccountability (and hence, of agency legitimacy) are rather an empirical than a theoretical matter.

Acknowledgements

This work has been possible by the support of the Swiss National Science Foundation both withinthe National Centre for Competence in Research (NCCR) Challenges to Democracy in the 21stCentury, and a Doc.Mobility scholarship, providing me with the opportunity to discuss my ideaswith scholars from the Utrecht School of Governance, and the London School of Economics. Ithank Mark Bovens, Kutsal Yesilkagit, and in particular Thomas Schillemans and Mark Thatcherfor dealing with my topic in such depth.

Page 2: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

2

1. Introduction

Regulatory agencies are more and more relevant in many sectors of today’s politics. Their

increasing importance is in conflict with the restricted democratic control due to their

independence, representing a challenge for their legitimacy. Accountability is widely seen as the

main feature to ensure agency legitimacy. However, much of the literature detects a trade-off

between accountability (and hence, legitimacy) on the one hand, and independence on the other.

Accordingly, accountability is assigned a limited role, in order not to interfere with agency

independence, which has become a core value of regulatory institutional design. At the same

time, it is doubted that democratic institutions in general have kept the power to play a major role

in holding agencies to account.

The paper argues that the differences to other kinds of agencies are frequently overestimated and

that, from a theoretical perspective, both accountability and democratically elected accountability

fora (DEAF) are less limited in their role than regularly expected. It does so by reassessing

theories of agency legitimacy, accountability and independence, finding only limited differences

between IRAs and “ordinary” agencies. Moreover, it is argued that accountability regimes, built

upon cooperation between DEAF and holders of horizontal accountability, may be able to

overcome resources limitations and provide effective accountability structures. The paper uses

then a proposal for the empirical assessment of agency accountability (Biela/Papadopoulos

forthcoming) to identify specific weaknesses in sets of accountability relations or accountability

regimes. First results strengthen the argumentation of the paper, but as well underline the fact that

effective accountability is a matter of empirical investigation.

The paper proceeds as follows: The next section introduces independent regulators and the

rationales for their rise, while section three reviews the literature on the effect of IRAs’

independence on legitimacy and accountability. Sections 4 and 5 depict the theoretical arguments

on the role of accountability in the case of IRAs and of democratically elected accountability fora

(DEAF) in particular. Section 6 provides an empirical approach and tentative results on four

agencies from Switzerland and Germany. Section 7 concludes.

2. The rise of independent regulators

The last decades faced important changes in the organization of the state, which severely reduced

the role of national governments and parliaments, while (international as well as domestic, public

Page 3: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

3

as well as private) non-elected actors have gained power. Political power in the last decades has

shifted away from parliament and other classical democratic institutions, and particularly towards

„non-majoritarian institutions” (Majone, 2001; Vibert, 2007; Maggetti, 2010). That „rise of the

unelected” (Vibert, 2007) took place at international and supranational level (“upwards

denationalization” to e.g. the European Commission, international organizations such as OECD,

WHO, WTO, or international networks) but also at domestic level (“sideward” and “downwards

denationalization”). Independent central banks come into play, expert and private bodies,

agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent regulatory authorities (Vibert, 2007; Héritier

and Lehmkuhl, 2011: 51). The above-mentioned developments have inspired several authors to

write of a shift “from the positive to the regulatory state” (Majone, 1997) or of “regulatory

capitalism” (Levi-Faur, 2005).

One of the most visible effects of that phenomenon is the increasing number and importance of

independent regulatory agencies (IRAs) since the 1980s. (Thatcher and Stone Sweet, 2002; Coen

and Thatcher, 2005; Levi-Faur, 2005; Maggetti, 2007; Gilardi, 2008). An IRA defined as:

“an unelected body that is organizationally separated from governments and

has powers over regulation of markets through endorsement or formal

delegation by public bodies” (Coen and Thatcher, 2005: 330).

The reasoning behind this development has been investigated quite extensively (Gilardi, 2005).

First, agencification is claimed to be more efficient, by producing faster and expertise-oriented

decisions (Maggetti et al., 2013). Moreover, the independence of regulators means an increased

policy stability. We can differentiate here two lines of argumentation: The first perspective

borrowed the so called “credible commitment” argument from the literature on independent

central banks (Kydland and Prescott, 1977; Barro and Gordon, 1983b; Franzese, 2002; Keefer

and Stasavage, 2003). In this view, IRAs help to generate a credible commitment to regulatory

policies, unaffected by short-term political interests. This in turn should prevents regulatory

capture (Laffont and Tirole, 1991) and serves the interests of the business sector by reducing

investment risks and promoting growth (Kydland and Prescott, 1977; Majone, 1999; Alt, 2002).

The second line of argumentation rests upon public choice literature predicting the decisions of

governments under the conditions that they are uncertain about their re-election. Under that

uncertainty, politicians have an incentive to delegate authority to independent actors in order to

reduce the effects of an eventual government turnover (Horn and Shepsle, 1989; McCubbins et

al., 1989; Moe, 1990).

Page 4: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

4

3. The “challenge for democracy”: effects of independence on legitimacy and accountability

In sum, these arguments rest upon a rather economic rationale of better outcomes. What has

remained under-investigated in the debate is the impact of the new state structures on democracy

(Christensen and Lægreid, 2011: 140), in particular on legitimacy and accountability. Due to their

‘non-majoritarian’ character (Majone, 2001), questions of IRAs’ democratic legitimacy have

aroused (Majone, 1994; 1999; Feldman and Khademian, 2002; Van Kersbergen and Van

Waarden, 2004; Coen and Thatcher, 2005).

“The key question is whether the increasing dependence of modern

democratic societies on unelected bodies presents a new danger to democracy”

(Vibert, 2007: 1).

The most prominent conceptualizations of legitimacy in the present context have been developed

by Scharpf (1970; 1999), who differentiates between input- and output-oriented legitimacy. Input

legitimacy is based on the responsiveness to citizens‘ preferences (i.e., government “by the

people”), whereas output legitimacy requires acting in the public interest (in other words, “for the

people”). From an input perspective, “[p]olitical choices are legitimate if and because they … can

be derived from the authentic preferences of the member of a community.” In contrast, output

legitimacy is given if and because choices “effectively promote the common welfare of the

constituency in question” (Scharpf, 1999: 6).

Issues scholars have with IRAs’ legitimacy relate both to input as well as to output legitimacy:

First, input legitimacy is said to be weakened in case of IRAs. IRAs enjoy substantially more

discretion (at least in principle) than ordinary bureaucracy (Gilardi, 2008) and operate “at arm’s

length” of government. In cases of strongly pronounced independence, the “democratic deficit

of such institutions is most striking. The European Central Bank is (or at least had been) a case

in point (Gormley and de Haan, 1996; Berman and McNamara, 1999; Elgie, 2002). The

complexity of regulatory tasks and (often multi-level) governance systems (Zürn, 2000;

Papadopoulos, 2003; Curtin et al., 2010) make it difficult to keep pace with for democratic

institutions. Together with the increased power of domestic bureaucracies and international

networks (Rhodes, 1995), it is thus unsure if parliaments and institutions of representative

democracy in general have kept the power and resources to effectively keep pace with their agents

(Pierson, 2004; Rosa, 2005). Moreover, Finally, IRAs are likely to receive selective input based

on resources (Papadopoulos, 2003), thus might be biased in favor of narrow and myopic interests,

Page 5: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

5

and hardly take externalities of their decisions into account (Føllesdal, 2011: 82). Similar applies

to output legitimacy: In contrast to central banks, IRAs face regularly multiple objectives

(Goodhart, 2001; Quintyn et al., 2007) which are moreover quite difficult to measure (Maggetti,

2010). Due to the technical complexity of tasks, extreme information asymmetries make it

doubtful that IRAs can be monitored effectively (Binderkrantz and Christensen, 2009).

As countermeasures for these challenges, foremost two things have been identified: widened

citizen participation (Zürn, 2000; Sosay, 2006), and accountability (Aucoin and Heintzman, 2000;

Flinders, 2001; Mulgan, 2003; Pollitt, 2003; Bovens, 2010). To increase agency accountability,

being widely accepted as crucial to ensure agency legitimacy and to prevent a democratic deficit

(Van Kersbergen and Van Waarden, 2004; Busuioc, 2009), entails also a problem. Busuioc

summarizes it for the EU case:

“Given that the ‘independence of agencies is often seen as the most central

principle of good governance’ and that a large number were established

specifically in order to remedy, through their independence, credible

commitment failures of the Commission, jeopardising this independence

would defeat the very purpose for which they were created” (Busuioc, 2009:

601).

Busuioc states correctly, that most of this perceived trade-off stems from conceptual ambiguities

and an unclear and incomplete understanding of the concept of accountability as a measure of

control (Smith and Hague, 1971; Romzek and Dubnick, 1987). Also more recently, Majone

(2001) stressed the importance of monitoring procedures and transparency, but at the same time

adheres limits to accountability in order not to interfere with agency independence. To solve the

problem of agency legitimacy, he describes the relationship to agencies’ democratic principals as

“fiduciary”, building mainly on trust and peer control (Maggetti, 2010).

From a different perspective, scholars of central bank independence have shown that

accountability does not necessarily hamper independence, but in contrast might even enhance

the performance of the respective agency and is a necessary complement to independence

(Lohmann, 1992; Briault et al., 1995; Eijffinger et al., 2000; Quintyn et al., 2007; Amtenbrink

and Lastra, 2008; Laurens et al., 2009). They thus support Busuioc’s conclusion:

Page 6: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

6

“[T]he dilemma of accountable independence is a myth owing its existence to

lack of conceptual clarity. Independence and accountability can and actually

should co-exist” (Busuioc, 2009: 614).

However, the details of Moe’s ideal that “no one controls the [agency] …, yet it is clearly under

control” (Moe, 1987: 291) are yet to be clarified. Scholars continue seeing accountability and

independence as strongly antagonistic:

“The empirical distinction between the procedures for implementing

independence and accountability is far from trivial and unproblematic. The

two properties might occasionally overlap and thus conflict in practice.”

(Maggetti et al., 2013: XX).

Or, as Busuioc states:

“[I]t has been repeatedly pointed out that one of the central challenges with

regards to non-majoritarian agencies is to strike the right balance between

independence, on the one hand, and control/accountability, on the other.“

(Busuioc, 2009: 601).

From my perspective, most of these views still suffer from an overly narrow view onto

accountability. In effect, the role assigned to accountability in the context of IRAs is too limited.

This holds in particular for accountability to democratically elected actors. This paper’s goal is

thus twofold: Section four shows that accountability plays a larger role in the context of IRAs than

some of the literature expects. The argument is that – explicitly or implicitly – many scholars

understand accountability as a form of control, which runs short of a number of additional

purposes. The next section offers a more differentiated conceptualization from which is derived

that independence interferes with accountability only to a very limited extent. Moreover, if we

take into account accountability regimes and cooperation between actors, DEAF may have a

stronger role than often predicted.

4. The theoretical perspective: Functions of accountability

Accountability is a tricky concept: While the term accountability has been in use for a long time

in social sciences, it has gained more attention in the past years (Lindberg 2013: 203). However,

there is still no consensus in the literature about the content and limits of the concept of

Page 7: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

7

accountability (Bovens, 2010). It is conceptualized in many different ways, and almost every

author used his or her own definition and understanding of accountability (Curtin et al., 2010).

Over time, more elements have been classified as part of accountability, turning it into an “ever-

expanding concept” (Mulgan, 2000). As a pattern behind the expanded use of the notion, the

underdeveloped distinction between its normative and descriptive contents has been identified:

Bovens argues that in the understanding of some scholars, “being accountable” has become a

kind of “virtue” of organizations. Accountability studies from that tradition hence often focuses

the “actual and active behavior of public agents” in order to assess the legitimacy of public officials

and public organizations (Bovens, 2010: 947-8).

In contrast, another strand of literature treats accountability rather as a descriptive mechanism,

and “employ a restricted definition of accountability that focuses on the mechanisms with which

actors in public administration are hold accountable” (Schillemans, 2011: 389).1 In this sense,

accountability is understood as a social relation between two actors – an actor and a forum

(Bovens, 2007; 2010), an accountor and an accountee (Pollitt, 2003), or a principal and an agent

(Pratt and Zeckhauser, 1985; Lupia, 2003)– that “involves an obligation to explain and justify

conduct” (Bovens, 2010: 951). This strand of literature does not deal with the question “whether

the agents have acted in an accountable way, but whether they are or can be held accountable ex

post facto by accountability forums” (Bovens, 2010: 948). To follow that second understanding

of accountability implies to acknowledge that accountability can be used to maintain or increase

control over an agent, but as a neutral instrument, it can be used also for other purposes.

Reviewing literature, accountability is seen to serve two broad purposes: a) to prevent the misuse

of power (e.g. Thomas, 1998) and b), to ensure adequate performance (Peters, 2007).

Misuse of power is mainly prevented by ensuring agents to behave according to the public will

and in compliance with law. The first one is widely called responsiveness; the second one is

known as compliance, or with Peters “responsibility”. Responsibility here means “ensuring that

the behavior of officials corresponds to (is responsible to) the law or a code of ethics in office”

(Peters, 2007: 16). Responsibility can be assured by a superordinate institution, such as a board

or a parent ministry, or by courts. In contrast, “the idea of responsiveness is that the good civil

servant is one who is willing to take direction from above, to attempt to serve the public, and,

1 While Bovens (2010) associates the normative strand with US, and the descriptive one with European scholars,Philp (2009) contrasts normative law-based and descriptive economics-based approaches.

Page 8: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

8

insofar as possible, to provide the public with what it wants” (Peters, 2007: 16). The idea to

generate responsiveness through accountability is widespread:

“Accountability is a broad and rather stretched concept that reflects a range of

understandings rather than a single core paradigm. In democratic polities, it

also appears intimately related to electoral representation, reflecting a looped

relationship between authorization of parties and their governments through

ex-ante mandates, on the one hand, and, on the other, the evaluation of their

performance in office through ex-post controls (Andeweg 2003), with the

ultimate sanction being the capacity to ‘throw the rascals out’” (Curtin et al.,

2010: 930).

Building upon the idea of retrospective voting (Fiorina, 1978), a large strand of literature on

electoral accountability has been developed (for an overview, see Ashworth, 2012). At least

equally prominent is the idea of accountability with regard to public administration. Agency

theory (Pratt and Zeckhauser, 1985; Lupia, 2003) sees the relation between a democratically

elected politician and a bureaucrat as a delegation of power from a principal to an agent that

occurs because of limitations of the principal with regard to expertise and resources (Gilardi and

Braun, 2002). The delegation hence implies an asymmetric distribution of information. Given

their preferences diverge, the agent can pursue his preferences on the cost of the principal’s ones.

The principal accordingly aims to establish structures to monitor the agent’s actions, e.g. via

reporting requirements (McCubbins and Schwartz, 1984). In sum, the main task of accountability

from this perspective is to delimit the gap between agency outputs and the wider public’s will. It

thus contributes rather to the input dimension of legitimacy.

The other basic purpose, performance, is in contrast strongly linked to output legitimacy. It is

often argued that accountability is a necessary condition for good performance (Aucoin and

Heintzman, 2000; Shah, 2007; Gasmi et al., 2009). This notion can be derived from two quite

different arguments: Agency theory stresses the effect of sanctions: In anticipation of severe

consequences ex post, agents show higher efforts than if this is not the case. In contrast, other

approaches see the political decision-making as an iterated process of learning and adaption

under uncertainty. From that perspective, accountability is a mechanism that provides some

feedback information on previous decisions and provides additional information for further

improvement (cf. Sabel, 2004). In any way, the claimed positive effects of accountability on

Page 9: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

9

performance) are disputed. In contrast, “accountability overloads” (Schillemans and Bovens,

2009) and “multiple accountability disorders” (Koppell, 2005) might lead to demotivation

(Ossege, 2012) and symbolic action (Bovens, 2010: 957; Flinders, 2011).

A last purpose of accountability can be subsumed under the aspect of efficiency. Efficiency in a

very wide sense is also the main issue of classical agency theory, assuming that insufficient

monitoring ends up in the agent pursuing his own goals. These goals are not necessarily policy-

oriented (this case has already been dealt with in the paragraph on responsiveness), but can

characterized by the maximization of budget (Niskanen, 1971), the minimization of effort (Migué

and Bélanger, 1974) or the maximization of “slack” (Wyckoff, 1990) in the sense of spare

resources that can be used for anything in the agent’s interest.

I have outlined that from a theoretical perspective, accountability serves not only to exercise

control, but has other functions as well. I am now going to reassess the arguments in favor of

agency independence and show that accountability is only affected by these arguments in two

respects. As mentioned in the outset, independence of regulators is mainly based on an argument

known as “credible commitment”, which has first been applied to central banks (Barro and

Gordon, 1983a; b; Keefer and Stasavage, 2003). The argument models the monetary policy as

being subject to time-inconsistent preferences. Time inconsistency means that an actor interested

mainly in short-term advantages takes decisions, which entail negative effects in the long run.

Applied to monetary policy, politicians might favor lower interest rates that in the short run reduce

unemployment (and improve their chance of being reelected), while in the long run that interest

rate means a (welfare-decreasing) rise of inflation rates. Similarly, in the case of regulation, it is

argued that politicians’ short-term orientation (in gains from state-owned ex-monopolists) and

high uncertainty created by eventual government turnovers might hamper private investments.

From that perspective, the establishment of an IRA is an instrument to solve that “principal’s

moral hazard” (Miller, 2000).

In light of the functions of accountability outlined before, the commitment argument exclusively

relates to responsiveness. In order to fulfil their tasks, central banks or IRAs should be isolated

from shortsighted political influence. This applies foremost to every-day decision-making of

agencies and banks: Much of the central bank literature refer to Debelle and Fischer’s (1994)

differentiation between goal and instrument independence. Quintyn et al. (2007) use the term

“operational independence”. It can be derived from the literature that, while instrument

independence is economically useful in the case of central banks, goal independence is not

Page 10: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

10

(Briault et al., 1995). Since goals are normally fixed in regulatory law, we can transfer this insight

to our typology of accountability functions by stating that rather than responsiveness,

responsibility (which is compliance with rules) is a core function of accountability in the context

of IRAs. Responsibility is regularly ensured by judicial review, peer and expert monitoring, and

other mechanisms (Majone, 1998; 1999; Van Kersbergen and Van Waarden, 2004). Also,

performance measures as an aspect of output legitimacy remain an undisputed function of

accountability (Majone, 2001).

In sum, applying theoretical argumentation in favor of independence to the typology of

accountability functions developed, two qualifications have been identified: First, responsiveness

is not a desirable goal in the context of IRAs. Second, accountability can still serve to ensure

effectiveness, efficiency, and responsibility of agencies. As a restriction, the latter one should not

be ensured by the government, but by judicial or expert bodies.

5. The empirical perspective: Accountability regimes as strengthening factors

We have now argued that accountability is a core mechanism to ensure democratic legitimacy of

IRAs. There are only two differences compared to ordinary bureaucracy. However, according to

the literature, IRAs are challenging democracy in a second aspect: the claimed reduced

importance of democratically elected accountability fora (DEAF). I argue that a more integrated

empirical assessment of accountability, taking into account the various mechanisms of

cooperation and information-sharing existing in reality, can possibly remedy the stated

weaknesses, which are mostly based on a lack of resources and expertise. First, I reassess common

definitions of accountability in order to depict the development of a broadened understanding of

accountability. Second, I present theoretical and empirical arguments from literature indicating

an increasing complexity of accountability relations, referred to as accountability networks and

accountability regimes. In sum, these findings suggest that, in order to assess agency accountability

correctly, it is necessary to take into account cooperation between DEAF and e.g. expert bodies

or stakeholders, which is done in the following section.

Classical approaches, mainly from the strand of agency theory (see for overviews Bendor et al.,

2001; Gilardi and Braun, 2002; Miller, 2005), model the relation between a principal and an

agent as a delegation of power from the principal to the agent. The delegation in turn implies the

problem of adequate control mechanisms, since the principal has to assure the agent acts in her

interest. These approaches have in common that they assume a linear, hierarchical relationship

Page 11: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

11

between principals) and agents, mainly characterized by mechanisms of monitoring, control, and

sanctioning. Strom (2000) speaks in this context of a “chain of delegation” from voters to

members of parliament, a government head, government ministers, and bureaucrats.

In line with this, accountability has been used in political science for a long time primarily in two

contexts: a) accountability of democratically elected politicians to their electorate, and b)

accountability of bureaucrats to their administrative and political leaders. The former is generally

labelled as political or electoral accountability, the latter one as administrative or bureaucratic

accountability. However, this classical understanding of accountability makes increasingly less

sense, and has been proven too narrow (Roberts, 2001): “Traditional measures of accountability

that rely upon line or top-down measures do not necessarily provide a good guide to the

accountability culture as a whole.” (Considine, 2002: 37).

Consequently, the understanding of accountability has been widened: A court, for instance, is no

one’s principal (the court has no powers to delegate) but nevertheless can held other bodies to

account. In fact, ombudsmen, accountors (Mainwaring and Welna, 2003; Moreno et al., 2003),

judicial review, as well as professional peers (Papadopoulos, 2007) and civil society (Smulovitz

and Peruzzotti, 2000) play an important role in holding political bodies to account. Table 1

depicts the differences between several accountability definitions.

Definition entails … Group 1 Group 2 Group 3… the right to access certain information No Yes Yes… the right to request specific information No Yes Yes… the right to enforce information requests Yes Yes Yes… the right to pose sanctions for agency conduct Yes Yes No… the ability to pose sanctions based on de facto power(non-institutionalized accountability)

No Yes No

… accountability with regard to any aspect of conduct No Yes YesTable 1: Simplified summary of accountability definitionsNote: Group 1: Romzek and Dubnick (1998), or Fearon(1999); Group 2: Bovens (2007), Schedler (1999) or Grantand Keohane (2005); Group 3: Lindberg (2013) and Philp (2009).

Group 1 entails agency theory inspired approaches, which define fora rights-based, focus on

performance, and sanctions. The second group consists mainly of scholars who aimed to widen

the understanding of accountability. They include also non-institutionalized fora (e.g., the media)

and define fora rather power-based, than rights-based. Moreover, these scholars explicitly add an

information dimension to accountability. This widened understanding is seen critical by the

scholars of the third group, which consider formal rights to get informed as the decisive aspect of

accountability.

Page 12: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

12

Groups 2 and 3 reflect the more recent, non-hierarchical relationships regularly tagged with the

notion “horizontal” or “diagonal accountability”2 as opposed to “vertical accountability” (Bovens,

2007). Vertical accountability is characterized by a hierarchical principal-agent relationship, but

horizontal accountability is not:

‘Horizontal accountability’ refers to mechanisms of accountability that do not

address the political principals of agencies –hierarchical or vertical

accountability – but address other significant stakeholders such as clients,

professional peers, or semi-independent overseeing boards” (Schillemans,

2009: 2).

Some scholars see horizontal accountability as a replacement of more traditional ones (Barberis,

1998), others underline the importance of hierarchical relationships and see horizontal

accountability as complementary (Mulgan, 2003; Papadopoulos, 2007; Schillemans, 2008; 2009;

Héritier and Lehmkuhl, 2011: 136). Schillemans summarizes:

“There are several reasons why horizontal accountability—as it was found to

work—can not be seen as a potential substitute for ministerial responsibility. To

begin with, horizontal accountees do not act as deputies for the minister. …

Furthermore, these new mechanisms do not create an alternative form of

accountability to democratically legitimized accountees. … For these reasons,

horizontal accountability must be considered as something that differs from the

democratic control through ministerial responsibility. What horizontal

accountability adds, however, is that it stimulates the learning capacity of

agencies” (Schillemans, 2008: 190).

The findings on horizontal accountability reinforce the idea that accountability is based on

“cumulative effects of various mechanisms of control“ (Thomas, 1998: 349) and is a product of

complex interactions between actors (Harlow and Rawlings, 2007). As Scott points out:

2 Bovens called diagonal accountability the relationships in which a forum has direct access to information, but hasto rely on a third party to implement sanctions (e.g., an audit office that reports to the parliament).

Page 13: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

13

„The extended mechanisms of accountability in the regulatory state are not

linear … Rather, they are premised on the existence of complex networks of

accountability“ (Scott, 2000: 49-50).

For these networks, the term ‘accountability regime’ has been proposed (Scott, 2000: 55; Bovens

et al., 2008; Schillemans, 2008: 179). The term regime was first used in the context of

international relations (Krasner, 1983: 1). The regime concept has found entrance into the

comparative analysis of political institutions (Kaiser, 2002) as well as into regulatory policy analysis

(e.g. Vogel, 1996). Biela and Papadopoulos (forthcoming) define an accountability regime as the

full set of actors, institutions, norms and rules that are of importance for the accountability of a

given agent.3

To sum up, in the theoretical part of the paper, I have argued that accountability and DEAF play

a larger role for IRAs than conventionally expected. Only minor restrictions apply with regard to

functions of accountability and DEAF, and the latter may have a chance to compensate their

resource restrictions by adequate cooperation with third fora. In the next section, I briefly present

both an empirical approach to agency accountability (Biela and Papadopoulos, forthcoming) that

addresses the above-mentioned criteria and tentative empirical results from four Swiss and

German agencies (Biela, 2014).

6. Agency accountability: A tentative empirical assessment

The conceptual reviews above now provide us with the tools to assess agency accountability and

to check it for potential deficits: We can identify the fora based on clear criteria, differentiate

between three levels of agency action that correspond to the basic purposes of accountability in

the IRA context. For the empirical analysis, we make use of the operationalization in Biela and

Papadopoulos (forthcoming), depicted in table 2.

The approach proposes to distinguish between three levels of agency action: a political, an

operational and a managerial level. Commonly, literature differentiates between managerial and

political accountability (Day and Klein, 1987). The former form is a ‘neutral, technical exercise

involving bookkeeping and arguments about whether what is being done is being done efficiently

and effectively’ (Christensen and Laegreid, 2002: 271). Political accountability, in contrast, is

3 The formulation rests upon Eberlein and Grande, defining a regulatory regime “as the full set of actors,institutions, norms and rules that are of importance for the process and the outcome of public regulation in agiven sector” (2005: 91).

Page 14: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

14

generally understood as political responsiveness to the principals’ preferences. Justified by the

theoretical underpinnings of delegation to regulatory agencies, we add a third level of action,

which includes single-case decisions, and in general application of regulatory instruments by the

agency. Furthermore, the approach focuses not only on the formal rights of accountability fora to

gather information or pose sanctions, but also their de facto ability to use these rights, determined

by their capability to process information and the credibility to use their sanctioning rights. Table

1 summarizes the indicators used for the approach.

Fora Aspects of agency conductAll political or societal actors in a accountability relation withthe agency, i.e., with relevant information and/or sanctioningrights

Political accountability: achievement of statutory goals,outcome

Operational accountability: adequacy and legality of singleregulatory decisions, output

Managerial accountability: Efficient use of resources (staff,funding), throughput

Formal information rights Information capability Formal sanctioning rights Sanctioning credibilityExtensive (+): forum hasdirect access to primarydocuments and forum candemand specific information

Moderate (o): forum has nodirect access to primarydocuments but can demandspecific information

Limited (-): forum hasneither direct access toprimary documents nor candemand specific information

Resources: time, staff,expertise

Cooperation: cross-memberships, informationexchange with third fora orexpert bodies

Severe (+): persistent effect atorganizational level (e.g.,competence withdrawal)

Moderate (o): Situationaleffect at organizational level(e.g., decision overrun) orpersistent effect at individuallevel (e.g. dismissal of staff)

Limited (-): situational effectat individual level (e.g.,disciplinary measures tostaff)

Internal structure of forum:composition, appointmentrule, decision rule,heterogeneity

Coordination between fora:division of competencies,probability of deadlock andblame shifting

Political interest

Table 2: The assessment of agency accountability (Biela and Papadopoulos, forthcoming).

In section four, I concluded that there are three remaining functions of accountability in the

context of IRAs. At the strategic level, accountability is still required to ensure performance and

facilitate learning. Second, operationally, agency decisions still need to be reviewed in terms of

responsibility. Here applies a restriction: Due to agency independence, this has to be done by an

institution independent from the government, frequently an agency board. Moreover, agency

actions have to be subject to judicial review and hence legal accountability. Third, at managerial

level, agencies remain responsible for their internal management and the use of their budget, in

short, for acting efficiently. We can conclude thus that, at least from a theoretical, perspective,

accountability remains crucial also in the case of IRAs. This holds with only a slight restriction

for democratically elected actors such as governments and parliaments.

Page 15: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

15

Moreover, the approach differentiates between formal rights and de facto power to hold an

agency to account (Lægreid and Verhoest, 2010; Gilardi and Maggetti, 2011). The approach

attempts to evaluate a forum’s capacity to gain information and to appraise agency action, based

on the fora’s time, level of expertise, and extent of cooperation with other fora. On the sanctioning

side, it is about the likeliness that the forum actually imposes consequences, taking into account

its internal structure, and the side costs of sanctions (Biela and Papadopoulos, forthcoming). In a

recent working paper, I applied the approach to four agencies from Swiss and German

telecommunications and financial sectors (Biela, 2014). A summary of the findings is depicted in

tables 3 and 4.

Table 3: Overall assessment of accountability regimes (Biela, 2014: 17).

Table 4: Accountability vis-à-vis governments and parliaments (Biela, 2014: 17).

All agencies except the ComCom are subject to at least a reasonable level of accountability.

However, we see both cross-case and cross-level differences: Swiss agencies seem to be less

accountable than their German counterparts are. Biela (2014) assigns that to scarce resources and

less frequent cooperation in the Swiss cases. The comparison of agency action levels proves first,

that accountability indeed varies between levels. The differentiated approach we took thus have

led to additional insights. Second, comparing the overall accountability level (table 3) with

accountability to DEAF, accountability is still present, but its level decreases. The most striking

difference is at the operational level, where accountability to government or parliament is either

weak or non-existent. So far, this is what I expected. On the other hand, DEAF are (with

exceptions) also far from being strong fora at political and managerial levels. This goes beyond

our expectation and has to be corroborated in a sounder analysis. Moreover, there are cases

suggesting either a level specific or even a general deficit of accountability structures. This is most

clearly the case if we look at the Swiss ComCom.

Page 16: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

16

7. Conclusion

This paper argued that the role of accountability and democratic institutions in legitimizing

independent regulators is often seen overly pessimistic. It reviewed concepts of letimacy,

accountability, and independence and argued that despite independence, accountability still can

play a major role. The aim was to show that the power of agency accountability is rather a matter

of empirical investigation than of theoretically argued trade-off. In detail, there are only two

restrictions applying to IRA accountability: First, responsiveness is not a desirable goal. Second,

the compliance with rules has to be monitored rather by fora such as courts and expert bodies,

rather than by parent departments. The second argument was, that democratic instutions have

maintained much more power than often predicted. An empirical approach taking into account

the network or regime structure of accountability can shed light on that fact.

My aim was not to declare all issues with democratic legitimacy of IRAs to be unreasoned. It was

rather to specify the role accountability plays and argue that accountability deficits are a matter of

empirical scrutiny. The analysis has shown that accountability indeed remains strong in many

respects. DEAF keep within their role as important accountability fora, except at operational level

– which is predicted by theory. However, this is only part of the story. DEAF are rarely the

strongest fora, neither at political, nor at managerial levels. Moreover, there are cases where a

anaccountability deficit is indeed likely. Sometimes only at certain levels of agency action, or

regarding a certain kind of fora. In at least one of the four cases under scrutiny, however, the

accountability deficit is quite comprehensive. Thus, the challenge of democracy might be smaller

than often expected, but apparently it is far from nonexistent. The empirical results are rather

tentative, however. Only four cases are covered, and the operationalization has to be improved.

Further versions of the paper will have to extend that part.

References

Alt, James E. (2002), 'Comparative Political Economy: Credibility, Accountability, and Institutions' in Ira Katznelsonand Helen V. Milner (eds), Political Science: The State of the Discipline. New York: W. W. Norton, pp.147-171.

Amtenbrink, Fabian and Rosa M. Lastra (2008), 'Securing Democratic Accountability of Financial RegulatoryAgencies - A Theoretical Framework' in R. V. De Mulder (ed), Mitigating Risk in the Context of Safety andSecurity. How Relevant is a Rational Approach? Rotterdam: Erasmus School of Law & Reearch School forSafety and Security (OMV), pp. 115-132.

Ashworth, S. (2012), 'Electoral Accountability: Recent Theoretical and Empirical Work', Annual Review of PoliticalScience, Vol 15, Vol. 15, No., pp. 183-201.

Page 17: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

17

Aucoin, P. and R. Heintzman (2000), 'The dialectics of accountability for performance in public managementreform', International Review of Administrative Sciences, Vol. 66, No. 1, pp. 45-55.

Barberis, P. (1998), 'The new public management and a new accountability', Public Administration, Vol. 76, No. 3,pp. 451-470.

Barro, R. J. and D. B. Gordon (1983a), 'A Positive Theory of Monetary-Policy in a Natural Rate Model', Journal ofPolitical Economy, Vol. 91, No. 4, pp. 589-610.

-- (1983b), 'Rules, Discretion and Reputation in a Model of Monetary-Policy', Journal of Monetary Economics, Vol.12, No. 1, pp. 101-121.

Bendor, J., A. Glazer and T. Hammond (2001), 'Theories of delegation', Annual Review of Political Science, Vol.4, No., pp. 235-269.

Berman, S. and K. R. McNamara (1999), 'Bank on democracy - Why central banks need public oversight', ForeignAffairs, Vol. 78, No. 2, pp. 2-+.

Biela, Jan (2014), ' Governance, Accountability, and Legitimacy of Regulatory Agencies: Comparative Case Studiesfrom the Telecommunications and Financial Sectors in Germany and Switzerland', paper presented atNational Centre of Competence in Research (NCCR) Challenges to Democracy in the 21st Century.Working Paper No. 71, Zurich.

Biela, Jan and Yannis Papadopoulos (forthcoming), 'The empirical assessment of agency accountability: A regimeapproach and an application to the German Bundesnetzagentur', International Review of AdministrativeSciences, Vol., No., pp.

Binderkrantz, A. S. and J. G. Christensen (2009), 'Delegation without Agency Loss? The Use of PerformanceContracts in Danish Central Government', Governance-an International Journal of Policy Administrationand Institutions, Vol. 22, No. 2, pp. 263-293.

Bovens, M. (2007), 'Analysing and assessing accountability: A conceptual framework', European Law Journal, Vol.13, No. 4, pp. 447-468.

-- (2010), 'Two Concepts of Accountability: Accountability as a Virtue and as a Mechanism ', West European Politics,Vol. 33, No. 5, pp. 946-967.

Bovens, M., T. Schillemans and P. t'Hart (2008), 'Does public accountability work? An assessment tool', PublicAdministration, Vol. 86, No. 1, pp. 225-242.

Briault, Clive B, Andrew G Haldane and Mervyn A King (1995), 'Independence and Accountability', paperpresented at Seventh International Conference of the Institute for Monetary and Economic Studies, Tokyo,26-27 October.

Busuioc, M. (2009), 'Accountability, Control and Independence: The Case of European Agencies', European LawJournal, Vol. 15, No. 5, pp. 599-615.

Christensen, J. G. and P. Laegreid (2002), 'New Public Management - Puzzles of Democracy and the Influence ofCitizens', Journal of Political Philosophy, Vol. 10, No. 3, pp. 267-296.

Christensen, Tom and Per Lægreid (2011), 'Democracy and administrative policy: contrasting elements of NewPublic Management (NPM) and post-NPM', European Political Science Review, Vol. 3, No. 01, pp. 125-146.

Coen, D. and M. Thatcher (2005), 'The new governance of markets and non-majoritarian regulators', Governance-an International Journal of Policy and Administration, Vol. 18, No. 3, pp. 329-346.

Page 18: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

18

Considine, Mark (2002), 'The End of the Line? Accountable Governance in the Age of Networks, Partnerships, andJoined-Up Services', Governance: An International Journal of Policy, Administration, and Institutions, Vol.15, No. 1, pp. 21-40.

Curtin, D., P. Mair and Y. Papadopoulos (2010), 'Positioning Accountability in European Governance: AnIntroduction', West European Politics, Vol. 33, No. 5, pp. 929-945.

Day, Patricia and Rudolf Klein (1987), Accountabilities: five public services. London and New York: Tavistock.

Debelle, Guy and Stanley Fischer (1994), 'How Independent Should a Central Bank Be?' in Jeffrey C. Fuhrer (ed),Goals, Guidelines, and Constraints Facing Monetary Policymakers. Boston: Federal Reserve Bank ofBoston, pp. 195-221.

Eberlein, B. and E. Grande (2005), 'Beyond delegation: transnational regulatory regimes and the EU regulatory state',Journal of European Public Policy, Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 89-112.

Eijffinger, Sylvester, Marco Hoeberichts and Eric Schaling (2000), 'A Theory of Central Bank Accountability', CEPRDiscussion Paper 2354, accessed

Elgie, R. (2002), 'The politics of the European Central Bank: principal-agent theory and the democratic deficit',Journal of European Public Policy, Vol. 9, No. 2, pp. 186-200.

Fearon, James D. (1999), 'Electoral Accountability and the Control of Politicians: Selecting Good Types versusSanctioning Poor Performance' in Adam Przeworski, Susan C. Stokes and Bernard Manin (eds),Democracy, Accountability, and Representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 55-97.

Feldman, M. S. and A. M. Khademian (2002), 'To manage is to govern', Public Administration Review, Vol. 62, No.5, pp. 541-554.

Fiorina, M. P. (1978), 'Economic Retrospective. Voting in American. National Elections: A Micro-Analysis',American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 22, No. 2, pp. 426-443.

Flinders, Matthew (2001), The Politics of Accountability in the Modern State. London: Ashgate.

-- (2011), 'Daring to be a Daniel: The Pathology of Politicized Accountability in a Monitory Democracy',Administration & Society, Vol. 43, No. 5, pp. 595-619.

Føllesdal, Andreas (2011), 'The Legitimacy Challenges for New Modes of Governance: TrustworthyResponsiveness', Government and Opposition, Vol. 46, No. 1, pp. 81-100.

Franzese, Robert J. (2002), Macroeconomic policies of developed democracies. Cambridge, UK ; New York:Cambridge University Press.

Gasmi, Farid, Paul Noumba Um and Laura Recureo Virto (2009), 'Political Accountability and RegulatoryPerformance in Infrastructure Industries: An Empirical Analysis', World Bank Economic Review, Vol. 23,No. 3, pp. 509-531.

Gilardi, F. (2005), 'The institutional foundations of regulatory capitalism: The diffusion of independent regulatoryagencies in western Europe', Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 598,No., pp. 84-101.

Gilardi, F. and D. Braun (2002), 'Delegation aus der Sicht der Prinzipal-Agent-Theorie', PolitischeVierteljahresschrift, Vol. 43, No. 1, pp. 147-161.

Gilardi, Fabrizio (2008), Delegation in the regulatory state: independent regulatory agencies in Western Europe.Cheltenham and Northampton: Edward Elgar.

Page 19: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

19

Gilardi, Fabrizio and Martino Maggetti (2011), 'The Independence of Regulatory Authorities' in David Levi-Faur(ed), Handbook on Regulation. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 201-214.

Goodhart, C. (2001), 'Regulating the regulators - accountability and control' in E. Ferran and C. A. E. Goodhart(eds), Regulating financial services and markets in the 21st century. Oxford: Hart Publishing, pp. 151–164.

Gormley, L. and J. de Haan (1996), ' The democratic deficit of the European Central Bank', European Law Review,Vol. 21, No., pp. 95-112.

Grant, R. W. and R. O. Keohane (2005), 'Accountability and abuses of power in world politics', American PoliticalScience Review, Vol. 99, No. 1, pp. 29-43.

Harlow, C. and R. Rawlings (2007), 'Promoting accountability in multilevel governance: A network approach',European Law Journal, Vol. 13, No. 4, pp. 542-562.

Héritier, A. and D. Lehmkuhl (2011), 'New Modes of Governance and Democratic Accountability', Governmentand Opposition, Vol. 46, No. 1, pp. 126-144.

Horn, M. J. and K. A. Shepsle (1989), 'Administrative Arrangements and the Political Control of Agencies -Administrative Process and Organizational Form as Legislative Responses to Agency Costs - Commentary',Virginia Law Review, Vol. 75, No. 2, pp. 499-508.

Kaiser, André (2002), Mehrheitsdemokratie und Institutionenreform. Verfassungspolitischer Wandel in Australien,Großbritannien, Kanada und Neuseeland im Vergleich. Frankfurt/New York: Campus.

Keefer, P. and D. Stasavage (2003), 'The limits of delegation: Veto players, Central Bank independence, and thecredibility of monetary policy', American Political Science Review, Vol. 97, No. 3, pp. 407-423.

Koppell, Jonathan G. S. (2005), 'Pathologies of Accountability: ICANN and the Challenge of 'MultipleAccountabilities Disorder'', Public Administration Review, Vol. 65, No. 1, pp. 94-108.

Krasner, Stephen D. (1983), International regimes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Kydland, F. E. and E. C. Prescott (1977), 'Rules Rather Than Discretion - Inconsistency of Optimal Plans', Journalof Political Economy, Vol. 85, No. 3, pp. 473-491.

Lægreid, Per and Koen Verhoest eds (2010), Governance of public sector organizations proliferation, autonomy andperformance. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Laffont, Jean-Jacques and Jean Tirole (1991), 'The Politics of Government Decision-Making: A Theory ofRegulatory Capture', The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 106, No. 4, pp. 1089-1127.

Laurens, Bernard J., Marco Arnone and Jean-François Segalotto (2009), Central bank independence, accountability,and transparency a global perspective. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

Levi-Faur, D. (2005), 'The global diffusion of regulatory capitalism', Annals of the American Academy of Politicaland Social Science, Vol. 598, No., pp. 12-32.

Lindberg, Staffan I (2013), 'Mapping accountability: core concept and subtypes', International Review ofAdministrative Sciences, Vol. 79, No. 2, pp. 202-226.

Lohmann, S. (1992), 'Optimal Commitment in Monetary Policy: Credibility versus Flexibility', American EconomicReview, Vol. 82, No. 1, pp. 273-286.

Lupia, Arthur (2003), 'Delegation and its perils' in Kaare Strøm, Torbjörn Bergman and Wolfgang C. Müller (eds),Delegation and accountability in parliamentary democracies. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 33-54.

Page 20: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

20

Maggetti, M. (2007), 'De facto independence after delegation: A fuzzy-set analysis', Regulation & Governance, Vol.1, No. 4, pp. 271-294.

Maggetti, Martino (2010), 'Legitimacy and accountability of independent regulatory agencies. A critical review',NCCR Democracy Living Reviews Vol. 2, No., pp. 1-9.

Maggetti, Martino, Karin Ingold and Frédéric Varone (2013), 'Having Your Cake and Eating It, Too: Can RegulatoryAgencies Be Both Independent and Accountable?', Swiss Political Science Review, Vol. 19, No. 1, pp. 1-25.

Mainwaring, Scott and Christopher Welna (2003), Democratic Accountability in Latin America. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

Majone, Giandomenico (1994), 'The Rise of the Regulatory State in Europe', West European Politics, Vol. 17, No.3, pp. 77-101.

-- (1997), 'From the Positive to the Regulatory State: Causes and Consequences of Changes in the Mode ofGovernance', Journal of Public Policy, Vol. 17, No. 02, pp. 139-167.

-- (1998), 'Europe's Democratic Deficit: The Question of Standards', European Law Journal, Vol. 4, No. 1, pp. 5-28.

-- (1999), 'The Regulatory State and its Legitimacy Problems', West European Politics, Vol. 22, No. 1, pp. 1-24.

-- (2001), 'Nonmajoritarian Institutions and the Limits of Democratic Governance: A Political Transaction-CostApproach', Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, Vol. 157, No., pp. 57-78.

McCubbins, M. D. and T Schwartz (1984), 'Congressional oversight overlooked: Police patrols versus fire alarms.',American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 28, No., pp. 16-79.

McCubbins, Matthew D., Roger G. Noll and Barry R. Weingast (1989), 'Structure and Process, Politics and Policy -Administrative Arrangements and the Political Control of Agencies', Virginia Law Review, Vol. 75, No. 2,pp. 431-482.

Migué, Jean-Luc and Gérard Bélanger (1974), 'Toward a General Theory of Managerial Discretion', Public Choice,Vol. 17, No., pp. 27-43.

Miller, G. J. (2005), 'The political evolution of principal-agent models', Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 8,No., pp. 203-225.

Miller, Gary (2000), 'Above Politics: Credible Commitment and Efficiency in the Design of Public Agencies', J PublicAdm Res Theory, Vol. 10, No. 2, pp. 289-328.

Moe, T. M. (1987), 'Interests, Institutions, and Positive Theory : The Politics of NLRN', Studies in AmericanPolitical Development, Vol. 2, No., pp. 136-299.

-- (1990), 'Political-Institutions - the Neglected Side of the Story', Journal of Law Economics & Organization, Vol. 6,No., pp. 213-253.

Moreno, Erika, Brian F. Crisp and Matthew Soberg Shugart (2003), 'The Accountability Deficit in Latin America' inScott Mainwaring and Christopher Welna (eds), Democratic Accountability in Latin America. Oxford:Oxford University Press, pp. 79-131.

Mulgan, R. (2000), ''Accountability': An ever-expanding concept?', Public Administration, Vol. 78, No. 3, pp. 555-573.

Page 21: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

21

-- (2003), 'One Cheer for Hierarchy- Accountability in Disjointed Governance', Political Science, Vol. 55, No. 2, pp.6-18.

Niskanen, William (1971), Bureaucracy and Representative Government.

Ossege, Christoph (2012), 'Accountability – are We Better off Without It?', Public Management Review, Vol. 14,No. 5, pp. 585-607.

Papadopoulos, Y. (2003), 'Cooperative forms of governance: Problems of democratic accountability in complexenvironments', European Journal of Political Research, Vol. 42, No. 4, pp. 473-501.

-- (2007), 'Problems of democratic accountability in network and multilevel governance', European Law Journal, Vol.13, No. 4, pp. 469-486.

Peters, B. G. (2007), 'Performance-Based Accountability' in Anwar Shah (ed), Performance, accountability andcombating corruption. Washington DC: World Bank, pp. 15-32.

Philp, Mark (2009), 'Delimiting Democratic Accountability', Political Studies, Vol. 57, No. 1, pp. 28-53.

Pierson, Paul (2004), Politics in time : history, institutions, and social analysis. Princeton, N.J. ; Oxford: PrincetonUniversity Press.

Pollitt, Christopher (2003), The essential public manager. Maidenhead and Philadelphia: Open University.

Pratt, John W. and Richard Zeckhauser (1985), Principals and agents : the structure of business. Boston, Mass.:Harvard Business School Press.

Quintyn, Marc, Silvia Ramirez and Michael W. Taylor (2007), 'The Fear of Freedom: Politicians and theIndependence and Accountability of Financial Sector Supervisors', IMF Working Paper 07/25, accessed

Rhodes, R.A.W. (1995), 'From prime ministerial power to core executive' in R.A.W. Rhodes and P. Dunleavy (eds),Prime minister, cabinet and core executive. Basingstoke: Macmillan, pp. 11-37.

Roberts, J. (2001), 'Trust and Control in Anglo-American Systems of Corporate Governance: The Individualisingand Socialising Effects of Processes of Accountability', Human Relations, Vol. 54, No. 12, pp. 1547-1572.

Romzek, B. S. and M. J. Dubnick (1987), 'Accountability in the Public Sector: Lessons from the Challenger Tragedy',Public Administration Review, Vol. 47, No. 3, pp. 227-238.

-- (1998), 'Accountability' in J. M. Shafritz (ed), International encyclopedia of public policy and administration.Boulder: Westview, pp. 6-11.

Rosa, Hartmut (2005), Beschleunigung. Die Veränderung der Zeitstrukturen in der Moderne. Frankfurt a.M.:Suhrkamp.

Sabel, Charles F. (2004), 'Beyond Principal-Agent Governance: Experimentalist Organizations, Learning andAccountability' in E. R. Engelen and M. Sie Dhian Ho (eds), De staat van de democratie. Democratievoorbij de staat. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, pp. 173-196.

Scharpf, F. W. (1970), Demokratietheorie zwischen Utopie und Anpassung. Konstanz: Universitätsverlag.

Scharpf, Fritz Wilhelm (1999), Governing in Europe effective and democratic? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Schedler, Andreas (1999), 'Conceptualizing Accountability' in Andreas Schedler, Larry Diamond and Marc F.Plattner (eds), The Self-Restraining State: Power and Accountability in New Democracies. London: LynneRienner, pp. 13-28.

Page 22: What Deficit? Legitimacy and Accountability of Regulatory ... › filestore › paperproposal › c294ff37-abb7-4aff-8583-8… · agencies, industrial self-regulation, or independent

22

Schillemans, T. and M. Bovens (2009), 'The Challenge of Multiple Accountability: Does Redundancy lead toOverload?' in Melvin J. Dubnick and H. George Frederikson (eds), Accountable Governance: Promisesand Problems. North Castle: M. E. Sharpe, pp. 3-21.

Schillemans, Thomas (2008), 'Accountability in the Shadow of Hierarchy: The Horizontal Accountability ofAgencies', Public Organization Review, Vol. 8, No. 2, pp. 175-194.

-- (2009), 'Horizontal Accountability. A Partial Remedy for the Accountability Deficit of Agencies', paper presentedat 5th Transatlantic Dialogue, The Future of Governance, George Washington University & George MasonUniversity, Washington DC, June 11-13.

-- (2011), 'Does Horizontal Accountability Work? : Evaluating Potential Remedies for the Accountability Deficit ofAgencies', Administration & Society, Vol. 43, No. 4, pp. 387-416.

Scott, C. (2000), 'Accountability in the regulatory state', Journal of Law and Society, Vol. 27, No. 1, pp. 38-60.

Shah, Anwar, Performance accountability and combating corruption,

Smith, B. L. R. and D. C. Hague eds (1971), The dilemma of accountability in modern government: independenceversus control. London: Macmillan.

Smulovitz, C. and E. Peruzzotti (2000), 'Societal Accountability in Latin America', Journal of Democracy, Vol. 11,No. 4, pp. 147-158.

Sosay, Gül (2006), 'Consequences of Legitimizing Independent Regulatory Agencies in Contemporary Democracies:Theoretical Scenarios' in Dietmar Braun and Fabrizio Gilardi (eds), Delegation in contemporarydemocracies 1st publ.. edn. London [u.a.]: Routledge, pp. 171-190.

Strøm, K. (2000), 'Delegation and accountability in parliamentary democracies', European Journal of PoliticalResearch, Vol. 37, No. 3, pp. 261-289.

Thatcher, Mark and Alec Stone Sweet (2002), 'Theory and practice of delegation to non-majoritarian institutions',West European Politics, Vol. 25, No. 1, pp. 1-+.

Thomas, Paul G. (1998), 'The Chaninging Nature of Accountability' in B. G. Peters and Donald J. Savoie (eds),Taking Stock. Assessing Public Sector reforms. Montreal et al.: McGill-Queen's University Press, pp.

Van Kersbergen, K. and F. Van Waarden (2004), ''Governance' as a bridge between disciplines: Cross-disciplinaryinspiration regarding shifts in governance and problems of governability, accountability and legitimacy',European Journal of Political Research, Vol. 43, No. 2, pp. 143-171.

Vibert, Frank (2007), The rise of the unelected: democracy and the new separation of powers. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

Vogel, Steven Kent (1996), Freer markets, more rules : regulatory reform in advanced industrial countries. Ithaca,NY: Cornell University Press.

Wyckoff, P. G. (1990), 'The Simple Analytics of Slack-Maximizing Bureaucracy', Public Choice, Vol. 67, No. 1, pp.35-47.

Zürn, M. (2000), 'Democratic Governance beyond the Nation-State: The EU and Other International Institutions',European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 6, No. 2, pp. 183-221.